Defending The Undefendable
Defending The Undefendable
THE
UNDEFENDABLE
CK
LORD
SEUM
ENDER
MONEYL
MILITTERE
WALTER BLOCK
Defending
the
Undefendable
Defending
the
Undefendable
Walter Block
Auburn, Alabama
Copyright © 2008 Ludwig von Mises Institute
Copyright © 1991 Fox and Wilkes
Copyright © 1976 by Fleet Press Corporation
All rights reserved. Written permission must be secured from the publisher
to use or reproduce any part of this book, except for brief quotations in crit-
ical reviews or articles.
Published by the Ludwig von Mises Institute, 518 West Magnolia Avenue,
Auburn, Alabama 36832. Mises.org.
ISBN: 978-1-933550-17-6
This book is dedicated to those who have taught me political
economy and inspired me with a passion for justice :
Nathaniel Branden
Walter E. Grinder
Henry Hazlitt
Benjamin Klein
Ayn Rand
Jerry Woloz
Introduction .xiii
I. Sexual 1
1. The Prostitute • .3
2. The Pimp . • · 9
3. The Male Chauvinist Pig .13
vii
viii Defending the Undefendable
V Financial .97
Index .253
FOREWORD
ix
X Defending the Undefendable
Murray N. Rothbard
COMMENTARY
xii
INTRODUCTION
he people presented in this book are generally consid-
xiii
xiv Defending the Undefendable
upon them. This means only that these activities should not be
punished by jail sentences or other forms of violence. It decid-
edly does not mean that these activities are moral, proper, or
good.
Walter Block
I. SEXUAL
1
THE PROSTITUTE
3
4 Defending the Undefendable
THE PIMP
made.
An initial point requiring clarification is the claim that
pimps use coercion and threats of violence to gather and keep
prostitutes on their payrolls . Some pimps do , but does this fact
justify condemning the profession itself? Is there any profession
that does not have a single practitioner who is not guilty of foul
play? There are bricklayers, plumbers, musicians , priests , doc-
tors, and lawyers who have violated the rights of their fellow
creatures . But these professions are not qua professions to be
condemned in their entirety.
9
10 Defending the Undefendable
ROOMS
YORK
L WONG
L
RESTA LAUNDRY
KE E
U
MAD L
B
الحدادی
MERLT
10 N
rodrigues
13
14 Defending the Undefendable
if friends of the rapist swore they had sexual intercourse with the
victim , she could be characterized as “immoral,” and it becomes
virtually impossible to obtain a conviction . If the victim is a pros-
titute, it is equally impossible to obtain a conviction . The rea-
soning behind the legal inability for a prostitute to be raped is
the ludicrous view that it is impossible to compel a person to do
that which she does willingly at other times .
One ofthe most attractive aspects of the women’s liberation
movement is its support for greater penalties for rape , plus resti-
tution to the victim. Previously people who occupied a compa-
rable position on the political spectrum as do most of today’s
feminists (e.g., liberals and leftists) urged lighter sentences for
rapists and general mollycoddling of criminals . In their view, all
crime, rape included, was caused mainly by poverty, family
breakdown, lack of recreational facilities, etc. And their “solu-
tion” followed directly from this “ insight”: more welfare, more
parks and playgrounds for the underprivileged, counseling, ther-
apy, etc. In contrast, the feminists’ insistence on stiffer jail sen-
tences for rapists and worse—comes like a breath of fresh air.
rapists—and
Although rape is the most striking instance in which the
government acquiesces in coercive actions against women , there
are others . Consider what is implied by the laws against prosti-
tution . These laws prohibit trade between mutually consenting
adults . They are harmful to women in that they prevent them
from earning an honest living. If their anti-woman bias is not
clear enough, consider the fact that although the transaction is
just as illegal for the customer as for the seller, the male (cus-
tomer) is almost never arrested when the female (seller) is .
Abortion is another case in point. Although inroads have
finally been made , abortion is limited by obstructive rules. Both
outright prohibition of abortion and abortion under present
controls deny the great moral principle of self- ownership . Thus,
they are throwbacks to slavery, a situation essentially defined by
the barriers put up between people and their right of self- own-
ership . Ifa woman owns her body then she owns her womb, and
she alone has the complete and sole right to determine whether
to have a child or not.
The Male Chauvinist Pig 15
AE
sodrigues
after “kicking the habit. ” During the addictive period, the addict
is a helpless slave to the drug, willing to enter into any degrada-
tion to secure “one more fix.”
How then can the evil nature of the drug pusher be ques-
tioned ? How can we even presume to look upon him with
favor?
drugs illegally who does more than anyone to mitigate the evil
effects of the original prohibition .
The prohibition of heroin has the devastating effect of forc-
ing the price up to a level which can only be characterized as
astronomical . When a commodity is outlawed, in addition to all
the usual costs of growing, harvesting, curing, transporting,
merchandising, etc. , the costs of evading the law and paying for
the punishments meted out when the evasion fails, must be
added. In the case of bootleg whiskey (during the prohibition
era of the 20s) , these extra costs were not excessive because law
27
28 Defending the Undefendable
enforcement was lax and the legislation did not have widespread
popular support. In the case of heroin, these costs are enormous.
Anti-heroin legislation enjoys wide popular support, with
demands for even stricter laws and penalties. Vigilante groups
and youth gangs in the inner city ghetto areas have inflicted
their own punishment on drug pushers and addicts. These
groups have had the quasi-support of the “law and order” fac-
tion, making it difficult and expensive to bribe the police who
fear the great penalties society would impose on them if they
were caught.
In addition to having to pay costly bribes to the police, the
drug merchants must also pay high salaries to their employees
for the dangers they encounter in smuggling and operating the
factories which prepare the drugs for street sales. They must also
exercise a degree of paternalism in taking care of those employ-
ees who are caught bribing politicians, lawyers, and judges to
minimize the penalties.
These are the factors which account for the high price of
heroin. But for these many extra costs imposed by the prohibi-
tion of heroin, the price would not differ in any significant way
from the price of other crops (wheat, tobacco, soya beans, etc.).
If heroin were legalized, an addict could obtain his daily need
for about the cost of a loaf of bread, according to the best esti-
mates.
Under prohibition, heroin addiction may cost as much as
$100 per day for a mature habit. Depending upon market infor-
mation and alternative sources of supply, the addict spends
about $35,000 per year to support his habit. It is obvious that this
cost is responsible for the untold human suffering usually
blamed on heroin addiction. The typical addict is usually young,
uneducated, and unable to earn a sufficient amount of money by
honest means to support his habit. If he does not seek medical
and psychiatric help, the only choice the addict can make to
secure his “fix” is to enter into a life of crime where he may even-
tually be hunted down by the police or street gangs. Further-
more, the addict criminal is in a far worse position than the non-
addict. The nonaddict criminal can select the most opportune
The Drug Pusher 29
time and place for a robbery. But the addict must commit a
crime whenever he needs a “fix,” and these times usually occur
when his reactions are dulled by his drug deprivation.
In reflecting upon the economics of “fencing” stolen mer-
chandise, it becomes obvious that the addict must commit an
enormous amount of crime to support his habit. To have the
annual amount of $35,000 necessary to buy drugs, the addict
must steal roughly five times that amount (almost $200,000 per
year), since the buyers of stolen merchandise (fences), usually
pay only 20 percent or less of the retail value of what they buy. If
the figure of $200,000 is multiplied by the estimated 10,000
addicts in New York City, the total of $20 billion is the amount
of the total value lost in crimes committed by addicts in the Big
Apple.
It cannot be stressed strongly enough that these crimes are
due to the prohibition of heroin and not the result of heroin
addiction. It is the prohibition that drastically forces its price up
and drives the addict into a life of crime and brutishness which
may end in his own death or that of the victim.
To prove this point, consider the small but significant num-
ber of medical doctors who, having access to heroin, have
addicted themselves. Its price is not prohibitive since their sup-
ply of the drug is not illegal. Their lives are “normal,” useful,
and fulfilling—with just this one difference. Economically
speaking, their lives would not be too different if, instead of
being addicted to heroin, they were diabetics and addicted to
insulin. With either addiction, these doctors would still be able
to function professionally. If, however, their legal supply of
heroin were cut off (or insulin were suddenly declared illegal),
these doctors would be at the mercy of the street pusher, unable
to ascertain the quality of the drugs they purchased, and forced
to pay exorbitant prices for their supply. Under these changed
circumstances the position of the addicted doctor would be more
difficult, but it would not be catastrophic, since most of these
professionals could easily afford the $35,000 annual cost of their
habit. But what of the uneducated addict living in poverty, who
does not have these prospects?
30 Defending the Undefendable
33
34 Defending the Undefendable
THOS EMEREY
MEDICINE
MD
HUBRIS
WALK IN PHARMACEUTICAL
LTD-
"To be honest with you I'm very much satisfied with the
quality ofdrugs from the pharmaceutical house I deal with
now. "
THE BLACKMAILER
41
42 Defending the Undefendable
AUT
GASAVIO
REPAIRS
47
48 Defending the Undefendable
Cafe PAVANE
A ONICK
STR
51
52 Defending the Undefendable
ED
DODD
his views should prevail, and the customer would not have the
right to dismiss him.
“Taxi driver’s freedom ,” would guarantee to drivers the right
to go where they wanted to go, regardless of where the paying
customer wanted to be taken . “Waiter’s freedom,” would give
the waiter the right to decide what you will eat. Why should not
plumbers, waiters, and taxi drivers have a “vocational freedom ”?
Why should it be reserved for academics ?
Basically, the difference which is said to exist between these
vocations and the academics is that the academics require free
inquiry, untrammeled rights of expression , and the right to pur-
sue thoughts wherever they may lead. This claim and this dis-
tinction is, of course, made by the academics. In addition to
being objectionably elitist, this argument also misses an impor-
tant point, one which is not concerned with the question, of
what is involved in intellectual activity. It is the impropriety of
“vocational freedom” in upholding the employee’s “ right” to a
job on the basis of purely formalistic requirements, regardless of
the wishes and desires ofcustomers and employers.
Ifthere is an acceptance of the elitist argument which claims
that the “ intellectual” professions must be granted a freedom
inappropriate to other professions, what of others which qualify
as “intellectual” ? What about “medical freedom” for doctors ,
“legal freedom” for lawyers, “artistic freedom” for artists, etc.
“Medical freedom ” might give doctors the right to perform oper-
ations , regardless of whether the patient approved . Would it pre-
vent patients from firing doctors whose procedures they disap-
proved of? Would “artist freedom” give artists the right to charge
for art which is neither wanted nor appreciated ? Considering
the way “academic freedom” operates , these questions must all
54 Defending the Undefendable
A advertising
is detailed and
entices
seemingly
people,compelling.
forcing themItto
isbuy
claimed
products
that
they would otherwise not buy. It preys on the fears and psycho-
logical weaknesses of people. It is misleading, with its justaposi-
tion of a beautiful woman and a commercial product, implying
that she is somehow part of the deal. It is foolish, what with its
contests, marching bands, and jingles. It is an insult to our intel-
ligence.
The argument is usually capped with an appeal to our self-
ish natures—advertising is very costly. A minute of prime televi-
sion time or a full-page adverstisement in a popular magazine or
newspaper can run into thousands of dollars. The advertising
industry as a whole is a multibillion dollar industry. If we banned
advertising, it is alleged, all of this money could be saved. The
money could then be used to improve the product, or lower its
price, or both. The advertising industry could be replaced with a
governmental board which would present objective descriptions
and ratings. Instead of sexy misleading jingles, we would have
product descriptions, perhaps summarized by a grade level of
“Grade A,” “Grade B,” etc. In any case, the advertisers, who are
57
58 Defending the Undefendable
SCMATZ
DRAFT BEER
SECRE
TA
WARNI DETER RYO
NG: THE MINEDF
INTERI H A
THE O R S MIRA
A OVE GE
THAT THDEANBGERO IS A
US Y
AND IS TO OUR
HEAL
TH
MENT
AL
1For the view that it was not the government that initiated controls of this
type in an effort to regulate business in the public interest, but rather
business in an effort to control the competition of newcomers, see
Gabriel Kolko, Triumph of Conservatism (New York: Quadrangle, 1967).
The Advertiser 61
2This point has been made by Professor Benjamin Klein of the de-
partment of economics, University of California, Los Angeles.
The Advertiser 63
in any case. But if the rights of free speech are to mean any-
thing at all, those who are not in public favor must be
defended. Libertarians anxiously await a defense by the Ameri-
can Civil Liberties Union of the free speech rights of advertisers.
This organization was ominously quiet during the banning of
cigarette commercials from television.
10
IN A CROWDED THEATER
69
70 Defending the Undefendable
TEA Alles
FKO andro
TER
Khavay MA
ESP
ANA RESO
100? ते
TODAY
SPANISH
LANGUAGE
JALNY
ALLESA
terje
S
LM
FI
75
76
Defending the Undefendable
DE
DE
JOO
T AL
LA REE OURN
WA ,ST J
so desired . Under the present system , they do not even have the
choice.
areas, which would be responsible for the extra charges. For the
present, however, the people living in these areas must not be
prohibited from taking the necessary steps to obtain adequate
cab service.
Poor people would benefit as producers, as they set up their
own businesses. They would, of course, have to assume owner-
ship of a car, but the artificial and insurmountable $30,000 bar-
rier would be removed.
There are, however, objections that will be raised to a free
market in taxicabs:
(1) “A free market would lead to chaos and anarchy if medal-
lions were eliminated. Taxis would flood the city and weaken
the capacity of any cab driver to earn a living. So drivers would
leave the industry in droves, and there would be far fewer taxis
available than needed. Without medallions to regulate the num-
ber of taxis, the public would be caught between two unsatisfac-
tory alternatives.”
The answer is that even if there were an initial rush into the
industry, and the market was glutted, only some drivers would
leave the field. The number of cabs, therefore, would not swing
erratically from an horrendous oversupply, to none at all, and
back again. Moreover, the drivers who would tend to leave the
industry would be the inefficient ones whose earnings were low
or those with better alternatives in other industries. By leaving
they would allow the earnings of those who remained to rise,
and thus stabilize the field. One does not, after all, gain any
insurance against the possibility of too many or too few lawyers,
doctors, or shoe-shine boys by fixing an arbitrary upper limit to
the number of people who can enter these occupations. We
depend upon the forces of supply and demand. When there are
too many workers in a field, the relative salaries decrease, and
some will be encouraged to enter other occupations; if too few,
wages and new occupants increase.
(2) The argument that licensing protects the riding public is
one of the most disingenuous arguments for taxi medallions. It
is the same one used by psychiatrists, who strive to “protect” us
The Gypsy Cab Driver 81
scalper is unjust.
Why does scalping exist ? A sine qua non of scalping, a neces-
sary condition for its existence, is a fixed , invariable supply of
tickets. Ifthe supply could increase with increased demand , the
scalper would be totally displaced . Why would anyone patron-
ize a scalper when he could purchase additional tickets from the
theater at the printed list price ?
83
84 Defending the Undefendable
OPENS TODAY!
JASON LIEBAVAN
PRESENTS
L
NEW MUSICAM
BOX R EA
ID EoAf
OFFICE RH
A R
DI
STARRING M
YNIAN POLLY 07700
BUT.
MUSIC BYLAWRE
LYRICS BY *. UTLE
CHOREOGI AP
DIREC
rodigues
fear of a backlash . Many people feel that there is a “fair” price for
a movie ticket, and managers are responsive to this feeling.
Thus, even though they might be able to charge higher than
usual prices for a movie like “The Godfather, ” they choose not
to . They know many people will refuse to patronize the theater
at a later time, feeling that the management “ took advantage” of
the public during the showing of this very popular movie. There
86 Defending the Undefendable
lines. It is more costly for them (in terms of income lost) to take
time off from work than for a member of the lower class. It is
prudent for the member of the middle class to buy his ticket
from the scalper for $45.00 rather than wait in line and lose far
more, which he might have earned had he gone to work. In
short, ticket scalping allows people in the lowest income brack-
ets to serve as the paid agents of people in the middle class, who
are too busy to wait in line for cheap tickets.
Rich people have servants who can wait in long lines for
them and, therefore, do not need scalpers. In one case, however,
the ticket scalper can help even the rich—when the scalper, who
is a specialist, can do the job for less than it would cost the rich
man to use a servant for the task. (It should occasion no surprise
that ticket speculation can benefit all people. The market is not
a jungle where people can only benefit at the expense of others.
Voluntary trade is the paradigm case of mutually beneficial
action.) If the scalper’s profit margin is less than what it would
cost the rich man to use a servant, he can buy the ticket directly
from the scalper, cut out the middleman servant, and save the
extra money.
From another perspective, however, price rationing and
ticket scalping favor the rich, by ensuring that they will find it
easier to purchase tickets at the high market price, while the rest
of the public may find it difficult or impossible. However, this is
the essence of a monetary economy and must be accepted as
long as we wish to reap the benefits only such a system can pro-
vide.
In the chapter on the importer, a defense will be made of a
monetary economy because it enables us to specialize and to
benefit from the division of labor. Imagine the quality of life and
the chances for survival if each of us was limited to what we
could produce ourselves. The spectre is frightening. Our lives
depend on trade with our fellows, and most if not all of the peo-
ple presently living would perish if the monetary system fell.
The degree to which we do not permit money to ration goods,
the degree to which we do not allow the rich to obtain a greater
share of the goods of society in proportion to their monetary
The Ticket Scalper 89
fellow officers .” As Serpico states , “The only oath I ever took was
to enforce the law—and it didn’t say against everybody except
other cops .”
assumption made about the “good guys” and the “bad guys” is
evident. The good guys are Frank Serpico and one or two police-
men who gave him limited aid in his quest for “justice ” and
punishment ofthe grafters . The bad guys were those cops on the
take, and those who protect them from prosecution . It is pre-
cisely this view which should be questioned .
91
92 Defending the Undefendable
THE (NONGOVERNMENT)
COUNTERFEITER
99
100
Defending the Undefendable
reci
recip
recipien
recip
Mr. A
Sec
Four
Thir
pien
First
ient
ond
ient
th
t
there is no one recipient who loses the total value of the com-
modity given up in return for the counterfeit money. But, it is
The (Nongovernment) Counterfeiter 101
S
OM
RO
Y
DA OR
WEEK HOTEL
SE CLAIR
easy to see that there are losses for the counterfeiter has gained
a value , without adding to the store of value of the rest of soci-
ety. Since there are only so many goods in the society at any one
time and the counterfeiter has gained some through fraud , there
must be others who have lost out.
102 Defending the Undefendable
The way the loss is spread out though the society depends
upon the rise in prices caused by the extra money (the counter-
feited money) now in circulation. That prices will rise in
response to the activities of the counterfeiters is a foregone con-
clusion, for counterfeiting increases the amount of money in cir-
culation while the amount of goods and services remains the
same. Prices will not rise all at once, nor will they rise smoothly
and regularly. Rather, prices will rise in waves as does the water
in a pool in response to a stone disturbing the equilibrium. They
will first be driven up in the industry or area of which the first
recipient of the counterfeit money is a member. Prices will be
driven up because the counterfeit money spent in the industry is
“extra”; that is, in the absence of the counterfeiting, it would not
have been spent; therefore the first recipient benefits. He has
received money which would not have been forthcoming but for
the counterfeiting, and he is able to spend this extra money in an
area where prices have not yet risen. The first recipient gains this
incremental difference (though it may be substantial, it is in no
way comparable to the counterfeiter’s gain).
The second recipient also gains, as do all other recipients at
the beginning of the ever-spreading ripple effect. For these peo-
ple all receive the new money before prices have had a chance to
be pushed up by the extra money put into circulation by coun-
terfeiting. However, in time there will be a recipient of the imi-
tation money who will just come out even. He will receive
money at a time when it is still possible to spend part of it in an
area which has not yet had a counterfeit-induced price rise. If he
spends his money in an area which has not yet received a boost
in prices, he will gain slightly from the inflation; if not, he will
lose. On the average, people in this phase of the monetary
expansion will be neither greatly benefited nor greatly harmed
from the counterfeiting.
People receiving the counterfeit money after this stage bear
the losses of the monetary expansion. Before they receive any
extra money, prices will have risen. When the counterfeit money
finally filters down to them they will be net losers. There are
some groups, such as widows and retired people, who will
The (Nongovernment) Counterfeiter 103
1We do not claim a strict, nonoverlapping temporal order for these stages.
They are rather devices to clarify exposition.
106 Defending the Undefendable
THE MISER
111
112 Defending the Undefendable
THE INHERITOR
117
118 Defending the Undefendable
X CE
A AN
T R IT
Gi PLE HE
ve PEO IN
T AX POOR
ThePond T 0
HE 10 %
AN
EQU T
AL FA DE
T S
SHAR CA
E
Kurt Vonnegut, Welcome to the Monkey House (New York: Dell, 1970) .
120 Defending the Undefendable
THE MONEYLENDER
121
122 Defending the Undefendable
$100 now. Unlike Mr. A, who cares much more about present
money than future money, Mr. B would not give up a large
amount of future money for cash in hand. (It should be noted
that a negative time preference does not exist, that is, a prefer-
ence for money in the future over money in the present. This
would be equivalent to saying that there would be a preference
toward giving up $100 in the present, in order to get $95 in the
future. This is irrational unless there are conditions other than
time preference which operate. For example, one might want to
purchase protection for money that is unsafe now, but will be
safe a year hence, etc. Or, one may want to savor his dessert and
postpone consumption until after dinner. “Dessert-before-din-
ner” would then be considered a different good than “dessert-
after-dinner,” no matter how similar the two goods were in
physical terms. There is thus no preference shown for a good in
the future over the same good in the present.)
Although it is not necessary, it is usual for a person with a
high time preference (Mr. A), to become a net borrower of
money, and for a person with a low time preference (Mr. B), to
become a lender. It would be natural, for example, for Mr. A to
borrow from Mr. B. Mr. A is willing to give up $200 a year from
now in order to get $100 now, and Mr. B would be willing to
loan $100 now if he can get at least $102 after one year has
elapsed. If they agree that $150 is to be repaid a year hence for a
present loan of $100, they both gain. Mr. A will gain the differ-
ence between the $200 he would have been willing to pay for
$100 now and the $150 that he will actually be called upon to
pay. That is, he will gain $50. Mr. B will gain the difference
between the $150 that he will actually get a year hence and the
$102 that he would have been willing to accept in a year for giv-
ing up the $100 now, a gain of $48. In fact, because moneylend-
ing is a trade, like any other trade, both parties must gain or they
would refuse to participate.
A moneylender may be defined as someone who loans out
his own money or the money of others. In the latter case his
function is that of intermediary between the lender and bor-
rower. In either case, the moneylender is as honest as any other
The Moneylender 123
INA
for the rich, because the greater the supply of a good in any given
market, the lower the price. The question of whether or not it is
fair to prohibit exorbitant rates of interest is not now under dis-
cussion, only the effects of such a law. And these effects are,
quite clearly, calamitous for the poor.
18
One ofthe great evils of charity, and one ofthe most cogent rea-
sons for refusing to contribute to it, is that it interferes with the
129
130 Defending the Undefendable
1G. William Domhoff, The Higher Circles (New York: Random House,
1970.)
2Frances F. Piven and Richard A. Cloward, Regulating the Poor (New
York: Random House, 1971).
The Noncontributor to Charity 133
and Adam still has more than Richard. If Adam wishes to act
morally, according to the brother’s keeper moral view, he will
have to share again with Richard. The sharing can end only
when Richard no longer has less than Adam.
The doctrine of absolute income equality, a necessary conse-
quence of the brother’s keeper philosophy, will admit of no pros-
perity for anyone over and above the meager pittance the most
helpless individual is able to amass. Thus the brother’s keeper
philosophy is in direct and irreconcilable opposition to the nat-
ural ambition to improve one’s lot. Believers in it are torn by
ultimately conflicting views and the result, naturally enough, is
hypocrisy. How else can one describe people who claim to be
practitioners of the brother’s keeper philosophy, and yet have
well-stocked pantries, a television, a stereo set, a car, jewelry, and
real estate, while in many parts of the world people face starva-
tion? They dogmatically affirm their commitment to equality,
yet deny that their lush wealth is in any way contradictory to this
commitment.
One explanation offered is that a certain amount of wealth
and well-being is necessary for them to maintain their jobs,
which allows them to earn the money to contribute to the less
fortunate. Clearly, it is true that the brother’s keeper must main-
tain his own ability to “keep” his brothers. His demise due to
starvation is not called for by the brother’s keeper philosophy.
The wealthy brother’s keeper thus explains himself as being
in a position similar to the slave owned by the “rational” slave
owner. For the slave must be at least minimally healthy and
comfortable, even contented, if he or she is to produce for the
owner. The wealthy brother’s keeper has, in effect, enslaved him-
self for the benefit of the downtrodden whom he aids. He has
amassed the amount which he needs in order to best serve his fel-
low man. His wealth and standard of living are just what a
rational profit-maximizing slave owner would allow his slave to
enjoy. Everything in his possession is enjoyed only to the extent,
and for the sole purpose of, increasing and/or maintaining his
economic ability to help those who are less fortunate than he is,
according to this argument.
The Noncontributor to Charity 135
THE CURMUDGEON
139
140 Defending the Undefendable
land or the land may have been given in the form of a gift at one
time or another. The land then passed into the control of the
curmudgeon through an unbroken chain of voluntary events, all
consistent with the principle of homesteading; in other words,
his land title would be legitimate.
Any attempt to wrest it from him without his consent thus
violates the principle of homesteading, and hence is immoral. It
is an act of aggression against an innocent party. (The question
will be raised regarding land which has been stolen. In fact, most
of the earth’s surface meets this criteria. In such cases, if there is
evidence that (1) the land has been stolen, and (2) another indi-
vidual can be found who is the rightful owner or heir, this per-
son’s right of ownership must be respected. In all other cases, the
actual owner must be considered the rightful owner. De facto
ownership is sufficient when the owner is the original home-
steader or when no other legitimate claimant can be found.)
Many recognize this when the curmudgeon resists the
demands on his property by private business. It is clear that one
private interest does not have the right to intrude upon another
private interest. However, when it is the state, as represented by
eminent domain laws, the case seems different. For the state, it
is assumed, represents all the people, and the curmudgeon pur-
portedly is blocking progress. Yet in many cases—if not all—
governmental laws of eminent domain are used to further pri-
vate interests. Many urban relocation programs, for example, are
at the behest of private universities and hospitals. Much of the
condemnation of private property by eminent domain laws is
accomplished for the special interests of lobbies and other pres-
sure groups. The condemnation of the land on which Lincoln
Center for the Performing Arts in New York City was built is a
case in point. This tract of land was condemned to make way for
“high culture.” People were forced to sell their land at prices the
government was willing to pay. Whose culture this center serves
is clear to anyone who reads the list of subscribers to Lincoln
Center. It is a Who’s Who of the ruling class.
In considering the second set of arguments for private prop-
erty rights, the practical arguments, there is one based on the
142 Defending the Undefendable
P 'S L
O B EAL
H OB T TA
S D RE V Y
GA ND
CI CA
JIM'S
BARBER
SHOP
DORB'S
Y
WARNST
KOLD CUTS
MILK
by transferring money and property from the poor to the rich can
only be done on the basis of the past behavior of the stewards in
question. But there is no guarantee that the future will resemble
the past, that those who were successful entrepreneurs in the
T
cushion for needle bearing tenants with a penchant for voodoo,
pin-
147
148 Defending the Undefendable
MODHES
УТЛАЗЯ
155
156 Defending the Undefendable
pay slightly lower prices for goods of slightly higher quality, but
these gains would be more than counteracted by the increased
carfare, and time lost in transit. We know this because these
options are always open to ghetto inhabitants. Since local people
patronize neighborhood stores presently, they must feel they do
better closer to home.
The ghetto dwellers could not even make deals with one
another by which some would do the shopping for the rest. This
would implicitly convert some of them to ghetto merchants, and
the same choice would be open to these new ghetto merchants
as were available to the old ones. There is no reason to suppose
that they would be oblivious to the financial incentives which
would sweep the old ones out of the ghetto. The only reasonable
way for ghetto dwellers to handle this unruly situation would be
to form a “shopping collective,” with members helping one
another in the arduous task of shopping. But to do this would be
to revert to a way of life in which food gathering becomes a very
time-consuming activity. Instead of developing skills as produc-
ers and pulling themselves out of poverty, ghetto dwellers would
be reduced to working on collectivist schemes made necessary
by the disappearance of the ghetto merchants. The proof that
this is an inefficient alternative is that it is not presently used, in
the face of competition from the ghetto merchant.
If this came to pass, the “progressive forces” of city planning
would undoubtedly come forth with an alternative solution of
letting the government take over by nationalizing the (ghetto)
merchant business. The logic here defies analysis. For since it is
clear that government intervention would create the chaos (by
prohibiting price differentials in the ghetto) in the first place,
how can the solution lie in still more government intervention?
The first problem with the suggested solution is that it is
immoral. It involves forcing everyone to pay for a nationalized
food industry whether or not they wish to. It also curtails the
freedom of citizens by prohibiting them from entering this
industry.
The second problem is pragmatic. Based on the evidence
available, such a solution would be unworkable. Up to the
162 Defending the Undefendable
THE SPECULATOR
165
166 Defending the Undefendable
1Adam Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of
Nations (New York: Random House, 1973), p. 243, paraphrased.
The Speculator 167
represent and the harm they do are more theoretical than real .
The speculator who guesses wrong will suffer severe financial
losses . Buying high and selling low may misdirect the economy,
but it surely creates havoc with the speculator’s pocketbook. A
speculator cannot be expected to have a perfect record of predic-
tion, but if the speculator guesses wrong more often than right,
he will tend to lose his stock of capital . Thus he will not remain
in a position where he can increase the severity of famines by his
errors. The same activity which harms the public automatically
harms the speculator, and so prevents him from continuing such
168 Defending the Undefendable
THE IMPORTER
169
170 Defending the Undefendable
THE MIDDLEMAN
179
180 Defending the Undefendable
No. 10
9
8
7
6
5
4
3
2
1
T
SAM'S DISCOUN
SECRET :
NATE
ELIMI
EMAN
the MIDDL !
TEREO
OFFICE NSOLE COLOF
0999 TV
$219
WHV
OLEGA
ESALE
Sapply
er
o rt
sp
Fa
an
rm
Tr
er
Mi
dd
er
le
k
me
or
n
W
Diagram 1
Tra
nsp
ort
er
Farmer Middlemen
er
rk
Wo
Diagram 2
THE PROFITEER
185
186 Defending the Undefendable
If, on the other hand, the entrepreneur thinks that the price
of the final good is likely to be greater than the combined costs
of all the factors, he will engage in the opposite behavior. He will
produce the frisbees and/or invest in companies which under-
take such production.
The third type of hidden opportunity which the en-
trepreneur can seize upon does not involve any price discrep-
ancies, either inter- or intratemporal. This type of opportunity
involves goods that have not yet been produced, and therefore
have no prices at all. Consider in this regard the frisbee before it
was produced or invented. There was no guarantee, at that time,
that the public would accept it. In cases of this kind, the entre-
preneur feels, thinks, or divines that there is something, the lack
of which may not even be apparent to anyone else, that con-
sumers would greatly value if they could but be told of its exis-
tence and convinced of its beneficial attributes. In this case the
entrepreneur plays nursemaid to the idea, through the processes
of invention, financing, advertising, and all other steps necessary
to bring an idea to public acceptance.
After having considered some of the types of activities profit
making entrepreneurs are likely to engage in, the results of profit
seeking can be assessed.
One result is immediately apparent—the collection and dis-
semination of knowledge. The knowledge of hitherto unpro-
duced products is an obvious and dramatic example, but as we
have seen, the knowledge engendered by profit seeking behavior
is by no means limited to such exotic occurrences. On a daily
basis, the profit seeker is constantly bringing to the market
knowledge about price differentials, both inter- and intratempo-
ral.
This knowledge is of great benefit to all concerned. Without
it, people in New Jersey would be eating strawberries which they
would much rather sell, if they could find someone willing to
pay more than 25¢ per jar. That is, the New Jerseyans only eat
the berries because of their lack of knowledge of people who
value them more than they themselves. In addition, without
this knowledge, there would be people in New York not eating
The Profiteer 189
strawberries because they assume that the only way to get them
is to pay 45¢ a jar, when in truth, they could be had for less .
Ofcourse, the profit seeker does not bring this knowledge to
bear as a teacher might. He is not one who goes about the coun-
tryside explicitly imparting information . As a matter of fact, after
his work is done, none of the people in New Jersey and New
York may even be aware of the relative prices of strawberries in
those markets . What the profit seeker does is make sure that the
effects of knowledge of prices in the different areas are felt. The
profit seeker does not directly spread the knowledge himself; he
merely spreads the strawberries which , in the absence of knowl-
edge oftheir prices, would not have been so allocated .
It is perfectly true then, that the profit maker takes advan-
tage of the ignorance of other people. If the relevant knowledge
were present, the entrepreneur could hardly earn profits by ship-
ping strawberries from New Jersey to New York. Although true,
however, it is hardly reprehensible . Anyone whose function it is
to sell a commodity must sell it to those who lack it. The fact that
the lack is determined by ignorance does not make the lack—or
the need any less real. The profit seeker “takes advantage ” of
the lack of knowledge of his customers in the same way that the
farmer “takes advantage ” of the hunger of his customer— by
providing that which his customer lacks.
The profits of the entrepreneur, therefore, are not made at
the expense of anyone else. It is not true that there must be losses
elsewhere in the economy equal to the gains ofthe entrepreneur,
because it is not true that the entrepreneur fails to create any-
thing. The entrepreneur does create . He creates the possibility of
cooperation between disparate, and in many cases widely sepa-
rated, groups . He is a broker or intermediary in opportunities, as
it were. It is his function to see to it that mutually beneficial
opportunities are not bypassed . Why this type of effort should be
singled out and denigrated as “not honest work” is beyond the
scope of reason.
BANG
"
Ah! I suspected as much. He's a masochist!"
THE STRIPMINER
People who work in such mines for long periods of time com-
monly contract “black lung disease, ” the dreaded miner’s mal-
ady caused by breathing in coal particles. Deep mining is haz-
ardous to workers in other ways. Mine entrapments, for example,
in which hundreds of miners are trapped far below the surface of
the earth, occur with deadly regularity. The immediate cause
may be a cave-in, escaping gas, an explosion, or water seepage,
but the ultimate cause is the deep- mining method itself.
In strip mining, as the name implies, the earth is stripped,
layer by layer, until the coal stream is unearthed . Although espe-
cially well suited for coal beds that lie close to the surface, strip
mining has also proven feasible at moderate depths . Strip min-
ing is free of the danger of cave- ins, and other forms of entrap-
ment, and of black lung disease . It is also a much cheaper
method than deep mining. In spite of these advantages , strip
mining has been roundly condemned by practically all sources
of “informed, ” “liberal, ” and “progressive” opinion .
The supposed explanation for this otherwise inexplicable
state of affairs centers around two criticisms of strip mining: it is
199
200 Defending the Undefendable
STRIP
NG
MiNi
G
STRIP MININ RTS
PERVE
is
RE
NATU !
RAL
UN NATU
hula hoop industry, that was allowed to violate the law in this
manner. Now there is no necessary connection between the hula
hoop industry and pollution . But if excess plastic clutter were
allowed, there soon would be a connection between this industry
and pollution, at least in the mind ofthe public. And so it is with
the coal mining industry, and with strip mining in particular.
There is nothing about the strip mining method of coal mining
202 Defending the Undefendable
THE LITTERER
205
206 Defending the Undefendable
the law. The government can function this way because it is out-
side the market. It does not obtain its revenues from the market
THE WASTEMAKERS
ists, we are (that is, the free- market system is ) presently wasting
the resources we have. In the view of still others , built- in obso-
lescence is a tragic, totally unnecessary component of this waste .
213
214 Defending the Undefendable
poor quality (as they agreed to do) and he made products which
were only slightly better, he would gain customers and increase
his profits. Given the profit motive (which was the incentive for
the cartel) the members are not likely to honor the agreement.
Second, there will be great temptations for businessmen out-
side the cartel agreement to enter the industry. By turning out
products even slightly better than those turned out by the cartel
manufacturers, they will attract customers and profits.
Paradoxically, the forces tending to break up the cartel would
become stronger as the cartel became more successful. For the
stronger the cartel, the greater the decrease in the quality of the
product. The lower the quality, the easier it would become to
attract competitors’ customers. Even a slight increase in quality
would accomplish this.
Advertising also hastens the process of breaking up cartels
which try to restrict quality. In fact, advertising tends to prevent
their formation in the first place. Advertising builds up brand
names with attached good will. The brand name stands for a cer-
tain level of quality. If a firm allows the quality of its product to
deteriorate, it loses the good will it has spent millions attaining.
Independent rating agencies like Consumers Union also
tend to prevent cartels from forming, and to break them up if
they do occur. By keeping strict tabs on the quality of merchan-
dise, such rating agencies keep the public apprised of even slight
deteriorations of quality.
Finally, even if all members maintain the agreement, and no
outsiders step in, the restriction on quality is still more likely to
fail than to succeed. For it is impossible for all manufacturers to
restrict quality to exactly the same degree. The ones who restrict
quality least will inevitably gain better reputations, more cus-
tomers, and increased profits. The market will continue to be a
testing ground, weeding out companies which produce inferior
goods. Failing the test means bankruptcy; passing the test means
survival.
It seems clear then, that in a free market, cartels cannot be
maintained. But they can be maintained, and built-in obsoles-
cence with them, if the government steps in. For example, when
216 Defending the Undefendable
manufacturers to get back into (or enter for the first time) the
low quality tire field, as profits there began to rise . In this way
the market would tend to bring about consumer satisfaction .
The lowly paper plate can serve to further illustrate the point
that built- in obsolescence is not wasteful when low quality prod-
ucts are cheaper to make than high quality products . Who would
218 Defending the Undefendable
offer such cars. They would offer them at a higher price, if con-
sumers wanted these with all the present frills and comforts. If
the consumers preferred, the manufacturers would offer them at
the same price as lower quality cars, but without the extras.
Furthermore, in a free market, “using up” resources does
not pose a serious threat. As scarcities develop, powerful forces
automatically come into play to correct them. For example, if
wood were to fall into short supply, its price would be forced up.
As a consequence, consumers would buy fewer products made
of wood. Producers would tend to substitute other materials for
wood wherever possible. Cabinets, furniture, boats, etc., would
be made of other, less expensive materials. New, possibly syn-
thetic, materials would be developed. Greater care would be
taken to recycle the suddenly more valuable “used” wood. Old
newsprint, for example, would be chemically treated and reused
with greater efforts. The increased price of wood would provide
incentives for entrepreneurs to plant more seedlings and take
care of forests more intensively. In short, given a dearth of one
or even several resources, a free economy automatically adjusts.
As long as its adjustment mechanism, the price system, is not
interfered with, other cheaper and more plentiful resources will
be substituted, and those in short supply will be better pre-
served.
But what would happen, it may be asked, if not just one or
several, but all resources were in short supply? What would hap-
pen if we depleted all our resources at the same time? This is the
stuff from which science fiction is made, so we will have to
indulge in a bit of science fiction ourselves to deal with it. But
we will stop short of assuming that everything magically van-
ishes from the face of the earth. In that eventuality, we would
have nothing helpful to suggest.
In order to make sense of the view, we will not assume that
all resources suddenly disappear, or that the earth suddenly
shrinks and shrivels away, but that economic resources get used
up and turn into ashes, waste, and dust. For example, we will
assume not that coal disappears entirely, but that it gets used up
and replaced by ashes, dust, pollutants, and chemical derivatives
220 Defending the Undefendable
“If not for the minimum wage law and other progressive
legislation, the employers, the fat- capitalist-pig exploiting
employers, to be precise, would lower wages to whatever
level they wanted . At best, we would be pushed back to
the days of the sweatshop; at worst, to the days of the
industrial revolution and before, when mankind waged
an often losing battle with starvation.”
assumes a villain where none exists . What does the law actually
accomplish and what are its consequences ?
The minimum wage law is, on the face of it, not an employ-
ment law but an unemployment law. It does not force an
employer to hire an employee at the minimum wage level, or at
any other level . It compels the employer not to hire the employee
at certain wage levels, namely, those below the minimum set by
law. It coerces the worker, no matter how anxious he may be to
accept a job at a wage level below the minimum, not to accept
the job. It obligates the worker who is faced with a choice
223
224 Defending the Undefendable
"You must stop this insane diet, J.T.-so what ifthe union
does callyou a '
FAT CAPITLISTIC PIG'!"
a $100.00 per hour minimum wage law went into effect. How
many of us have such great productivity that an employer would
be willing to pay $100.00 for an hour of our services? Only those
thought to be worth that much money would retain their jobs.
The rest would be unemployed. The example is extreme, of
course, but the principle which would operate if such a law were
passed does operate now. When wages are raised by law, the
workers with low productivity are discharged.
Who is hurt by the minimum wage law? The unskilled,
whose productivity level is below the wage level legislated. The
unemployment rate of black male teenagers is usually (under-)
estimated at 50 percent, three times the unemployment level of
the 1933 depression. And this percentage does not even begin to
take into account the great numbers who have given up search-
ing for a job in the face of this unemployment rate.
The lost income that this represents is only the tip of the ice-
berg. More important is the on-the-job-training these young
men could be receiving. Were they working at $1.00 per hour (or
even less) instead of being unemployed at $2.00 per hour, they
would be learning skills that would enable them to raise their
productivity and wage rates above $2.00 in the future. Instead
they are condemned to street corners, idleness, learning only
those skills which will earn them jail sentences at some early
future time.
One of the greatest hurdles facing a black teenager is look-
ing for his first job. Every employer demands work experience,
but how can the young black get it if no one will hire him? This
is not because of some “employer conspiracy” to denigrate
minority teenagers. It is because of the minimum wage law. If an
employer is forced to pay for an experienced-level worker, is it
any wonder that he demands this kind of labor?
A paradox is that many black teenagers are worth more than
the minimum wage but are unemployed because of it. In order to
be employed with a $2.00 an hour minimum wage law, it is not
enough just to be worth $2.00. You have to be thought to be worth
$2.00 per hour by an employer who stands to lose money if he
guesses wrong and may go broke if he guesses wrong too often.
230 Defending the Undefendable
THE SCAB
233
234 Defending the Undefendable
people who habitually buy from him. He would own the cus-
tomer’s patronage and he would, therefore, have a right to object
if “his” customer patronized another merchant.
The sword cuts both ways. Let us take the case of “my tai-
lor.” If we were to take this phrase literally, we would have to say
that the tailor may not shut down his shop, relocate, or declare
himself bankrupt, without the permission of the customers. He
is “their” tailor.
In both these cases, of course, it is clear that the possessive
pronoun is not meant to imply literal possession. Clearly, neither
buyer or seller has the right to insist upon the permanence of a
business relationship, unless of course, a long-term contract has
been agreed upon by both parties. Then, and only then, would
the merchant and the customer have the right to object if either
party ended the relationship without the consent of the other.
Now let us consider “my job.” What is the worker implying
when he objects to the scab taking “his” job away? The worker
is arguing as though he owned the job. He is, in other words,
assuming that service, after a certain period of time, obligates
the employer to the employee as strictly as if they had agreed to
a contract. But in fact, the employer has never obligated himself
contractually.
One wonders how the workers would react if the principle
upon which their anti-scab feeling is based were adopted by the
employer. How would they feel if employers assumed the right
to forbid long-term workers from leaving their employment?
What if he accused another employer who dared to hire “his”
worker of being a scab! Yet the situation is entirely symmetrical.
Clearly, there is something wrong with an argument which
asserts that once people voluntarily agree to trade, they are there-
after compelled to continue to trade. By what shift in logic is a
voluntary relationship converted into a strictly involuntary rela-
tionship? Hiring an individual does not imply slave-holding
rights over that person, nor does having worked for an employer
give one the right to a job. It should be evident that the worker
never “owns” the job, that it is not “his” job. The scab, therefore,
The Scab 235
237
238 Defending the Undefendable
243
244 Defending the Undefendable
253
254 Defending the Undefendable
skilled, 174
organized , 231
landlords, 147–54 obligations, positive, 249-50
law, 94-95 obsolescence, planned, 213-20
legal tender laws, 105 opportunities , 186-89
leisure, 30 outlaws, 75-96
lenders, 121-27
libeler, 47-50
libertarianism , xiii–xiv, xvi Packard, Vance, 213
licensure, 77-79 paper
lifespan , 34-35 money, 106
litterers , 205-11 products, 217–19
256 Defending the Undefendable
wages , 224-32
MS
TR
IP
MN
E
LE
MU
SE
TE
RE
ISBN 978-1-933550-17-6
90000 >