contemporary-non-positivism
contemporary-non-positivism
This Element defends and clarifies the thesis that the legality of
a system of rules depends on its moral features. Positivists who
deny this dependence struggle to explain: (1) the traditional
classification of moral norms as a form of a priori law; (2)
judicial reliance on moral norms in legal discovery; (3) persistent
theoretical disagreement about intra-systemic, law-determining Philosophy of Law
facts; (4) why radically arbitrary or immoral schemes of social
organization represent borderline cases of law; and (5) why law,
like other artifacts, can be evaluated in a kind-relative sense
(“as law”). Meanwhile, traditional versions of non-positivism
overstate the dependence going further than the desiderata
warrant. A moderate theory is formulated: law is an artifact
Contemporary Non-Positivism
Contemporary
whose existence depends on adequately performing an
essentially normative function. The theory’s justification lies in
its explanatory power: a comparison with other “value-driven”
Non-Positivism
artifacts, such as artworks, proves vital for understanding legal
language, reasoning, and practice.
CONTEMPORARY
NON-POSITIVISM
Emad H. Atiq
Cornell University
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Shaftesbury Road, Cambridge CB2 8EA, United Kingdom
One Liberty Plaza, 20th Floor, New York, NY 10006, USA
477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia
314–321, 3rd Floor, Plot 3, Splendor Forum, Jasola District Centre,
New Delhi – 110025, India
103 Penang Road, #05–06/07, Visioncrest Commercial, Singapore 238467
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781009539128
DOI: 10.1017/9781009288293
© Emad H. Atiq 2025
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions
of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take
place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press & Assessment.
When citing this work, please include a reference to the DOI 10.1017/9781009288293
First published 2025
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library
ISBN 978-1-009-53912-8 Hardback
ISBN 978-1-009-28830-9 Paperback
ISSN 2631-5815 (online)
ISSN 2631-5807 (print)
Cambridge University Press & Assessment has no responsibility for the persistence
or accuracy of URLs for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this
publication and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will
remain, accurate or appropriate.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism
DOI: 10.1017/9781009288293
First published online: February 2025
Emad H. Atiq
Cornell University
Author for correspondence: Emad H. Atiq, [email protected]
Abstract: This Element defends and clarifies the thesis that the legality
of a system of rules depends on its moral features. Positivists who deny
this dependence struggle to explain: (1) the traditional classification of
moral norms as a form of a priori law; (2) judicial reliance on moral
norms in legal discovery; (3) persistent theoretical disagreement about
intra-systemic, law-determining facts; (4) why radically arbitrary or
immoral schemes of social organization represent borderline cases of
law; and (5) why law, like other artifacts, can be evaluated in a kind-
relative sense (“as law”). Meanwhile, traditional versions of non-
positivism overstate the dependence going further than the desiderata
warrant. A moderate theory is formulated: law is an artifact whose
existence depends on adequately performing an essentially normative
function. The theory’s justification lies in its explanatory power:
a comparison with other “value-driven” artifacts, such as artworks,
proves vital for understanding legal language, reasoning, and practice.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contents
4 Outstanding Questions 68
References 73
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 1
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
2 Philosophy of Law
as a characterization of law in the juridical sense bears the same relation to its
subject matter as Newtonian physics does to the physical laws – of being
a powerful approximation, adequate for most practical purposes, but perhaps
less than fully accurate.
HLA Hart’s (1960) view, the most influential of all positivist accounts, is
helpfully illustrative of the assumptions and explanatory focus of positivists.
Hart was impressed by, among other things, the form or structure of legal systems.
Legal systems paradigmatically, and perhaps universally, exhibit a certain hier-
archical form. They consist of rules that prescribe or prohibit forms of conduct,
but there are also rules for determining, changing, and figuring out the rules of the
system. Hart was impressed, also, by the fact that participants in legal systems
seem to employ a “characteristic . . . normative terminology” of what people
ought to do or are permitted to do, and, moreover, that they seem to follow the
laws in a way that cannot be characterized as unreflective obedience (p. 56).
Rather, participants within legal systems – especially those who enjoy an “offi-
cial” status within the system – present the law as worth following. Such reflec-
tions led Hart to the view that legal systems are, essentially, a kind of social order
that (1) exhibits a hierarchical structure consisting of first-order rules as well as
higher-order rules – so-called “rules of recognition, change, and adjudication”;
and (2) includes fundamental rules that are followed by members of a community
based on certain normative assumptions that together comprise what Hart called
the “internal point of view” on the rules.
What makes Hart’s theory a positivistic account of law isn’t his emphasis on
the formal structure of legal systems or on the attitudes held by officials and
others in such systems (normative or otherwise); it’s a further claim of the form:
“. . . and that’s it.” Hart’s view is positivistic because any social order, no matter
how vicious, irrational, or bizarre (with some important caveats that we’ll get
to), counts as a legal system, so long as it manifests the relevant structure and
certain social facts regarding people’s attitudes towards the rules obtain.
Other positivists have emphasized other putatively necessary features of law,
such as the existence of power relations, especially, power relations between
a sovereign and subordinates, or the use of sanctions to elicit obedience (Austin
1832 [1995]). But all agree that social, and perhaps structural, facts alone can
account for law’s existence. More recently, positivists have tended to acknow-
ledge certain qualified connections between law and normativity – for example,
that law necessarily deals with matters of moral concern, makes moral claims,
and entails certain morally evaluable risks (Raz 1994; Shapiro 2011: p. 212;
Green & Adams 2019; cf. Hart 1958: p. 619). But no positivist worthy of the
name has ever conceded that a social order’s legality necessarily depends on its
merits, in a robustly normative sense of “merit” (Gardner 2001).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 3
While positivist accounts of law such as Hart’s have shed considerable light
on the nature of legal systems and legal objectivity, they are vulnerable to
challenge. For legal orders exhibit a broad range of features that aren’t so easily
explained if positivism is true, some of which it takes a degree of immersion in
legal history and practice to appreciate. Section 2 catalogs these features, which
concern: the role of moral and more broadly normative considerations in legal
reasoning, both historically (2.1) and in contemporary legal practice (2.2); the
nature and persistence of intra-systemic legal disagreement (2.3); the intuitive
distinction between bona fide legal systems and social orders established by
powerful organizations devoted to the criminal and the absurd (2.4); and the fact
that the law lends itself to both functional and kind-relative normative appraisal
(2.5). Overall, this section develops and consolidates the argument against
positivism drawing on recent scholarship not just in philosophy but in legal
history and social psychology as well. Section 3 explores the different forms of
non-positivism in the literature that have been motivated based on positivism’s
explanatory gaps, including natural law theory (Section 3.1), Dworkinian
interpretivism and the “one-system view” (Section 3.2), as well as dual charac-
ter and aggregative cluster accounts of the concept of law (Section 3.3). After
highlighting some problems for these more traditional views, I argue for
a moderate form of non-positivism that forges several surprising connections
across theories (Section 3.4). The main upshot is that we cannot make sense of
legal systems and their characteristic features without recourse to some genu-
inely normative criteria and without an account of the metaphysics of norma-
tivity. But, as I explain in Section 4, questions concerning the content of the
relevant norms and the nature of normativity remain unsettled in ways that
define an agenda for future work.
Let me note at the outset that the discussion is centered on ideas and argu-
ments, rather than persons and personalities, an approach I take to be essential
for moving the debate forward. This text does not aspire to be a comprehensive
summary or review of every contribution to legal philosophy made by its major
or prominent figures. There are plenty of excellent resources on the history of
jurisprudence that do just that. Instead, my goal is to foreground what I take to
be the most important issues, the most interesting arguments, and the most
compelling observations on which an original and attractive set of answers to
the traditional questions of jurisprudence can be based. That said, by the end of
the discussion, we will have covered more than enough ground to enable the
engaged reader to contribute intelligently to the full spectrum of philosophical
debates about the nature of law.
In preparation for the more substantive discussions to follow, the remainder
of this introductory section makes a few more observations about methodology.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
4 Philosophy of Law
Hopefully, the way I’ve described the project of legal philosophy sets it apart
from others with which it is often conflated, such as projects within lexical
semantics or practical ethics. As I see it, the central project of legal philosophy
is descriptive, explanatory, and synthetic: the goal is to catalog what legal rules
and practices are generally like and to develop a theory of law that explains the
systematic features while being consistent with our considered views on related
matters, such as the nature of rules, group agency, language, and morality. Since
not everyone shares this vision of legal philosophy, the remainder of this section
is devoted to correcting some common misconceptions about the subject,
several of which are surprisingly common even among philosophers. Those
who feel confident in their sense of the methodology should feel free to skip
ahead to Section 2 or, alternatively, return to Section 1 once they have seen the
methodology in action.
1
Raz’s (2002: p. 159) reflections on the possibility of law in a society of angels powerfully
illustrates this method.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 5
Our setup of the problem should help clarify why legal philosophy is not
exclusively or even primarily concerned with ordinary language or meaning.
Philosophers writing in this area certainly use the concept of law to help fix
a target of analysis (Raz 1979: p. 221). By the concept of law, I mean the broadly
shared application criteria or usage rules associated with a term in ordinary
language: “law” as employed in juridical contexts.2 We deploy our own under-
standing of this concept when we decide whether this or that actual or imaginary
social order constitutes a legal system. And more generally, much of philosophy
consists in scrutinizing the concepts we use and even revising our overall
conceptual framework to keep it in order, since we often don’t know which of
our concepts (including meta-concepts) need refining until their deficiencies
become salient to us through systematic reflection. So, philosophers can be said
to both use ordinary concepts and deploy a kind of conceptual expertise, one
that’s earned through careful reflection on a broad range of relatively basic and
important concepts.
But ultimately, ordinary terms and the shared concepts they express serve as
mere steppingstones, useful for the purpose of drawing attention to
a phenomenon that is interesting in its own right, and that may or may not be,
in the present context, the exclusive referent or meaning of the term “law.” The
phenomenon of interest is a kind or category of normative system that is
reflected in our general reasoning about social orders and their objective
features – a form of reasoning that philosophical thought experiments and
arguments more broadly are designed to elicit.3 By analogy, the term “water”
is ordinarily used to pick out different things in different contexts – often
(though by no means always) the potable stuff in rivers, lakes, and streams
with its standard percentages of isotopic isomers; but in other, more scientific
contexts, a specific substance with a particular constitution. Scientists are no
more beholden to ordinary usage, contexts, and meaning than philosophers of
law, and appreciating this fact does not require an extended detour through the
philosophy of vernacular kind terms (see, e.g., Putnam 1973; Kripke 1980). The
category reflected in philosophically informed reasoning about laws and legal
systems may not be semantically magnetic, in the sense of being a fitting
candidate for the shared meaning of a publicly available term. But it might
still be worth elucidating if it happens to be implicit in our considered
2
The points to follow do not turn on any particular theory of concepts, criterial or otherwise. The
observations hold just as well on inferentialist and use-theoretic accounts of the nature of
concepts. See, e.g., Dummett (1993), Brandom (1994).
3
For related points, see Marmor (2013) and Finnis (2007: p. 276): “There is no point in trying to
explain a common-sense concept which takes its meanings from its very varied contexts . . . My
purpose has not been to explain an unfocussed ‘ordinary concept’ but to develop a concept for use
in a theoretical explanation.”
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
6 Philosophy of Law
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 7
6
The precise relationship between the legality of a system of rules and the legality of specific rules
within a system is explored in subsequent sections.
7
On the essential properties of abstracta, see Fine (1994) and Zalta (2006). Roughly, the essential
properties of an abstract object are included in our conception of the object. To borrow one of
Zalta’s examples, being a detective is essential to being Sherlock Holmes, given that our concep-
tion of the fictional character plausibly “encodes” his being a detective. The fact that our
conception of an object encodes some property needn’t be transparent to reflection. Some
conceptual commitments are “discovered” because they are nonobviously entailed by other,
more transparent commitments. Many technical concepts that have worked their way into public
consciousness are used without complete mastery of their nature (see, e.g., Burge 1979). I think
this is true of legal concepts.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
8 Philosophy of Law
features of law that call out for explanation – that is, agreement about the
desiderata that constrain a philosophical account of legality. But the concern
is a perfectly legitimate one because philosophers often don’t share all the same
assumptions about law’s necessary or explanatorily relevant features. So, we
should stay alive to the possibility that positivists and non-positivists might be
categorizing social orders differently, and analyzing distinct categories as
a result, in ways that are on a par in terms of their ability to track objective
features of and distinctions within the social domain. But we cannot know
whether that’s true without engaging with the dialectic. Even if it turns out
that the philosophy of law has given us two coherent means of categorizing
social orders, the fact that exchange between these two camps persists and has
persisted for as long as it has suggests that there is enough overlap in their reasoning
about law for exchange to be productive – that is, for both positivist and non-
positivist philosophers to learn from each other about which regular features of law
invite explanation and how the explanatory puzzles might be resolved.
8
On the practical and ideological uses to which jurisprudence is sometimes put, see Atiq and
Mathews (2022).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 9
implicit in general usage. But pretending that their own use of the term
conforms to existing rules is an essential aspect of their persuasive strategy.
There are still more nuanced accounts of the role of pragmatic considerations
in the philosophy of law. Joseph Raz (1979), for example, argues explicitly that
philosophical analyses of categories like law may be driven in large part by the
need to explain certain settled features of law, but that there is room for practical
considerations, along with considerations of clarity and consistency with
a broader conceptual scheme, to refine our conception of law, and even to
modify it insofar as its precise contours are underdetermined. But none of
these views offer quite the same vision of legal philosophy as the one outlined
above. While I share Plunkett and Sundell’s view that philosophers don’t
necessarily use ordinary terms in ordinary ways (indeed, philosophical argu-
ments such as intuition pumps are often designed to put pressure on ordinary
concepts), I reject at least two claims that are either entailed or strongly implied
by their proposed interpretation: (1) that it doesn’t matter to participants in these
debates whether they are using a shared term to express a shared concept, and
(2) that the considerations that motivate participants are primarily pragmatic.9
The meta-linguistic negotiation account in its most unqualified form seems to
me flawed, since it flies in the face of serious reflection on the nature of
philosophical disagreement by participants in these debates and, also, since
metalinguistic negotiation seems to me to be both morally and rationally
objectionable in philosophical and legal exchange, even if it might be a more
acceptable communicative strategy in more playful contexts.
In any case, this text’s central task is emphatically not to lay out a practical
case for non-positivism (or a practical case for how we should use the term
“law” going forward). I shall defend non-positivism, simply, as an accurate
characterization of a kind, law, that regulates our considered judgments about
the general and necessary features of legal rules, a defense that should be
evaluated on those terms. Although non-positivists have sometimes relied on
pragmatic considerations to defend their account, I will not be summarizing
such arguments because, even if we assume their relevance, I am simply not
sure which way the pragmatic considerations cut. Whether judges and other
legal officials would behave better if they were to embrace a non-positivistic
9
See, e.g., Plunkett and Sundell’s (2013a: pp. 14–17) discussion of disagreements over the
spiciness of a meal or the criteria for being an athlete. On their interpretation of bedrock juridical
disagreements, jurists with different concepts of law “negotiate how words should be used” and
“pragmatically advocate” for their preferred concept (2013b: pp. 242, 264–267). In fact, the
application of their theory to disagreements in which participants explicitly contest the meta-
linguistic characterization is far from straightforward. See discussion in Rudolph (2023). For an
alternative account of legal disagreements that doesn’t necessarily involve ascribing different
concepts of law to judges (or philosophers) with superficially incompatible conceptions, see 3.4.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
10 Philosophy of Law
10
The historical literature on the subject is rich. For a survey and its significance for legal
philosophy, see Atiq (2023).
11
To pick just a few illustrative studies, see Helmholz (2015), Grey (1978), Corwin (1928), Pollock
(1902), and Vander Waerdt (1994).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 11
in their own cause (nemo iudex in causa sua), has been presented at various
times as a paradigmatic example of a priori law.12 A principle of reciprocity,
imposing reciprocal duties on sovereign and subject, enjoyed a similar status in
early English common law: of being law that applies ex proprio vigore.13 Legal
officials, including individuals tasked with law-discovery, believed that they
could rely on such principles to resolve disputes and obligate both subjects and
sovereign regardless of the existence of local statutes, legitimating customs,
agreements, or constitutions. The Romans called it “natural law,” but the prin-
ciples were given many other names at different times and in different systems,
including “moral law,” “unchangeable law,” and even the “the law of laws.”14
During the early modern period, especially, legal texts explicitly distinguished
these principles as a form of “natural,” universally applicable, and default law
from what they called “positive law,” or law posited by states and persons.
Three key features of this practice are worth emphasizing: (1) the fact that
jurists classified principles of rationality and morality as “law” (or “lex” or
“jus”), (2) that they deemed the legality of the principles a priori, and (3) the fact
that the principles of a priori legality were consequential within the system in
light of the broader practice of legal officials and other actors. To elaborate on
this third point, the principles of a priori law were employed by judges and
lawyers in thoroughly practical ways, including to resolve disputes, constrain
kings, queens, and legislatures, and fill gaps in other posited law, such as
statutory or precedential law. These contextual facts suggest that the relevant
judgments of law track the juridical sense of interest, and not the many other
senses of “law” that find expression in such phrases as “the laws of mathemat-
ics” or “the law of thermodynamics.” Later, we shall discuss a philosophical
position that the literature dubs “natural law theory” and its relationship to this
practice. But our present observations concern an entirely ordinary (i.e., non-
philosophical) regularity: a practice visible in both civil and common law
traditions, at least until the turn of the twentieth century.15
What is a legal positivist to make of this history?16 Neither the classification
of a principle like nemo iudex in causa sua as a form of law nor the explanations
12
See Yale (1974). For illustrative cases, see City of London v Wood (1702), 88 ER 1592 at 1602,
Thomas Bonham v College of Physicians (1610), 77 ER 646 at 652.
13
See discussion in Price (1997). As Price points out, “natural law or unwritten, fundamental law –
law that was beyond the reach of the customary or municipal law” – was the basis for the holding
in the famous case of Calvin v. Smith 1608, 77 ER 377 at 392, establishing birthright citizenship
in England for Scottish-born subjects after King James I became King of England (p. 96). The
case itself and the context in which it was decided are well worth examining for understanding
the salience and supremacy of the “law of reason” in early English common law.
14 15
See sources cited and discussion in Atiq (2023: p. 52). See sources cited Note 11.
16
Hart discusses the history of the principles of legality only in passing. See discussion in Waldron
(2008a).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
12 Philosophy of Law
jurists gave for why the principle counts as self-evident and universal law seem
consistent with positivism. Positivists maintain that a principle’s legality cannot
obtain independently of jurisdiction-specific social facts, such as facts about
local customs or rules of recognition. But that seems to have been explicitly
denied by ordinary legal officials, as part of their official story about the content
of their law. The a priori laws were not “derived” from more fundamental legal
rules. Their legal force was portrayed as independent of jurisdiction-specific
customs or conventions. And in several of these systems, jurists did not all agree
about the appropriateness of relying on the principles of “natural law.” And yet
a significant and visible number of jurists nevertheless did.17 Given this back-
ground, the positivist’s explanatory options appear limited (for a more detailed
analysis, see Atiq 2023).
One option would be to dismiss the historical claims as myths borne of
a premodern conception of the world. Past jurists were simply mistaken in
their assessment of either the content of the law or the reasons for legality. But
the mistake should seem puzzling if we assume positivism’s truth. Of course,
people have been mistaken about all sorts of things over the course of human
history. Far too often they have been mistaken about what justice requires. But it
is unclear why past jurists would have been so mistaken about the grounds of
legality, especially if we assume that positivists are right that the grounds are
purely social. For if we assume positivism, then there appears to be no connec-
tion between the grounds of law and jurists’ apparently mistaken beliefs about
it, which is odd because regular and systematic mistakes about a category in
ordinary use aren’t usually disconnected in this way from its nature. Bear in
mind that officials treated the legality of the principles of rationality and fairness
as a priori or self-evident; it wasn’t inferred based on complex arguments or
considerations. Accordingly, positivists need to explain why officials embedded
in these legal systems would be so mistaken about the concepts and categories
they used. Whereas some systematic mistakes about law may well be explain-
able in terms of positivist assumptions,18 the precise mistake that invites
17
See Atiq (2023: pp. 48–49) for examples of explicit contestation.
18
To illustrate, if we assume the truth of positivism, then perhaps it’s no surprise that people have
historically thought (falsely we may assume) that the gods or the spirits of the ancestors
determine law. According to positivism, social facts ground law, which can, in principle, include
facts involving the actions or desires of supernatural beings, especially beings with incredible
power (recall Austinian positivism’s emphasis on the power to coerce and command obedience).
On this picture, our historical counterparts weren’t confused about the a priori criteria of legality
(which would be puzzling); they were confused about the social facts – specifically, facts about
the kinds of beings that exist and their psychologies. One might be tempted to think that the
positivist can tell a similar story about people’s beliefs about moral principles. Since pre-modern
societies are more likely to believe that the gods demand compliance with moral principles, they
are more likely to treat these principles as law, even universal law given the gods’ universal
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 13
jurisdiction and authority. On this error theory, past jurists were implicitly applying social criteria
in treating moral principles as law, albeit on the basis of false assumptions about the social facts.
This effort to explain the phenomenon has the virtue of at least trying to forge a connection
between people’s mistakes about a category and its true nature. The problem, however, is that
this just-so story ignores the fact that past legal cultures knew how to distinguish the “laws of
god” from the “laws of reason,” and routinely did (Atiq 2022: p. 45). It ignores, also, the fact that
the legality of the principles of reason and justice was treated as self-evident, including within
cultures that didn’t think the gods were necessarily just or rational. By contrast, there were
regular attempts to explain the legality of the commands of the gods in more basic terms, like
their apparent authority over created beings. Thanks to Andrei Marmor for discussion on this
point.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
14 Philosophy of Law
19
Both Hart (1994: p. 240) and Raz (2004: p. 348) suggest, albeit in passing, that their explanatory
focus is on the features of a modern legal system. But they fail to engage with the question of
whether our modern conception of a legal system differs from or is continuous with the historical
conception. Moreover, they present themselves as disagreeing with their historical counterparts
on the nature of law. See Postema (2018) on why we should be skeptical of efforts to limit the
temporal scope of philosophical inquiry.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 15
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
16 Philosophy of Law
of legal content – that is, their specific function or role in judicial reasoning that
aims at law-discovery (1986a: pp. 20–35). The process of legal discovery does
not involve a mechanical or algorithmic application of moral values to situ-
ations, by reference, say, to a set of instructions consisting of clear conditions of
application and precise outcomes. In fact, as every competent lawyer knows, it’s
very difficult to predict, ex ante, the impact moral considerations have on
judicial determinations concerning the content of the law. Dworkin argued
based on such facts that the content and deliberative significance of moral
principles cannot be captured in terms of the kinds of rules that are grounded
in social practice and behavior, and so moral principles must be an independent
ground of law.
Second, Dworkin (1986a: p. 24) pointed out that even if socially grounded
rules or principles implicit in customs could, in theory, function as moral
principles do in their contribution to legal reasoning, judges don’t seem to
derive their moral conclusions from social facts or customary rules. Instead,
they simply intuit situations a certain way – as either just or unjust, reasonable or
unreasonable – and factor these intuitions into their legal decisions.
Furthermore, in cases like Henningsen and Riggs, it isn’t clear that there were
any socially accepted rules – say, a custom of disallowing murderers from
inheriting under a victim’s will – from which a judge could have derived the
necessary conclusions. As Dworkin puts it, instead of invoking “a particular
decision of some legislature or court,” judges in such cases have relied on a “a
sense of appropriateness developed in the profession.” This strand of the overall
argument questions whether a positivist account of the role of moral consider-
ations in legal practice is consistent with what judges, in fact, say and do.
In response to the first challenge, positivists have endeavored to show that
socially embraced rules and conventional norms can, in principle, function as
moral principles do in modern adjudication (Berman 2022). I shall grant for the
sake of argument that this response succeeds, that it is at least possible that
judges who appear to be reasoning about what is just or fair are, in fact, trying to
discern and apply some socially embraced rule (e.g., a rule whose content is
fixed by what most people believe to be fair, rather than what is, in fact, fair).
The present focus is on Dworkin’s second line of argument which seems to me
to be the stronger one – namely, that judges don’t behave as if they are deriving
their moral conclusions from socially embraced rules or conventions in the
relevant range of cases; instead, they seem to be relying on their own sense of
what justice and fairness require.
Positivists have offered several different responses to this second challenge.
Some maintain that Dworkin overstated the significance of moral reasoning in
adjudication, especially adjudication that involves law-discovery. When judges
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 17
rely on moral considerations to decide a case, they take on the role of quasi-
legislators, inventing new law rather than discovering pre-existing law (see, e.g.,
Marmor 2011: p. 66). Indeed, some forms of law-making by judges may be
expressly permitted by local legal conventions or rules of recognition. One glaring
problem with this account is that it doesn’t seem consistent with the official view of
participants within legal practice: judges for the most part don’t characterize what
they are doing as making up new law whenever they rely on moral principles,
a point I’ll come back to shortly.
Other positivists emphasize a distinction between law, or the grounds of law, and
the tools judges use to discern the law. The fact that judges rely on moral consider-
ations to reach legal conclusions is not a sufficient basis for inferring that the content
of the law must be determined by moral facts, for moral considerations could simply
be a convenient means of figuring out the nonmoral grounds of law given some
correlation between the two. To illustrate, suppose that in cases like Riggs, the law
of wills was determined, fully and without remainder, by the social facts concerning
the legislature’s overall secret preferences in relation to enforcement. It might still
make sense for a court to engage in moral reasoning to figure out the legislature’s
preference, on the assumption that legislatures are in general morally motivated. On
this interpretation, moral facts turn out to be evidence of what the law is, or of the
law-determining social facts concerning legislative intent, but aren’t, on their own,
an independent source of law. More generally, it is worth noting that judges rely on
all kinds of extra-legal rules and principles in adjudication as tools for figuring out
the law – principles of logic, grammar, statistics, and, indeed, morality – and so, one
cannot infer from adjudicative reliance alone that the relevant principles are law or
grounds of law (Raz 1994: ch. 9, Shapiro 2011: p. 272).
Finally, some positivists – self-described “inclusive positivists” – grant that
Dworkin successfully demonstrated that moral principles could have the status
of law and serve as grounds of law (Waluchow 1994; Coleman 2001; Kramer
2004). But they insist that when moral principles have this status, it is always in
virtue of contingent and jurisdiction-specific legal rules – specifically, more
fundamental rules of law within the system whose legality is grounded in social
facts alone. For instance, an enacted statue or constitution might direct judges to
rely on moral considerations to decide cases, or a socially embraced rule of
recognition might designate moral principles as a source of law.24 However,
inclusive positivists maintain that while “moral principles can enter . . . into any
particular society’s law (as criteria for legal validity or as legal norms)” they
“need not enter” (Kramer 2004: p. 245). The legality of a moral principle within
24
Marmor (2004b: pp. 9–11) helpfully distinguishes these different ways moral principles might
get into the law on the inclusive positivist picture.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
18 Philosophy of Law
25
This is one of several important claims that sets inclusive positivism apart from the form of non-
positivism that I ultimately defend in this volume. Nevertheless, there are similarities between
the two views along with important differences that I shall discuss in Section 3.
26
See, e.g., the dissent in State v Joyner, 625 A(2d) 791 (Conn. 1993) at 814, noting approvingly that
a commitment to natural law “pervaded eighteenth century legal thought throughout America,
including Connecticut.” See Postema (2018: p. 37) for the importance of trans-historical deference
within the common law.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 19
27
See discussion in Solum (2015).
28
For an opposing and unconventional take on the originalism debate, see Baude and Sachs (2019).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
20 Philosophy of Law
(Shapiro 2007). There are questions about how often such disagreements occur,
and how much theoretical disagreement is possible within a legal system (Leiter
2009, 2019; cf. Ewing 2017; Smith 2010).29 But everyone agrees that the phenom-
enon is sufficiently regular to demand an explanation.
The explanatory challenge for positivists is easily illustrated using Hart’s view.
Recall that according to Hart, the laws of a jurisdiction derive from higher-order
rules of recognition and adjudication that are embraced by legal officials. But
theoretical disagreements suggest a lack of consensus among officials about the
content of any such rules. Judges who embrace competing theories of constitu-
tional law, for instance, don’t agree on the law-determining facts, the jurisdic-
tion’s criteria of legal validity. So, if Hart’s view is correct, then judges in these
situations appear to be systematically mistaken, at least insofar as their claims
about the law-determining facts outstrip the agreed-upon content of any higher-
order rules. To illustrate, a rule of recognition in the United State won’t settle the
question of whether originalism or non-originalism offers the correct account of
the determinants of American constitutional law simply because there isn’t
anything resembling consensus on this issue among legal officials, whether
measured in terms of their beliefs or practical dispositions.30
In fact, the problem isn’t just that Hartian positivism entails that judges and
other legal officials must be mistaken about the law-determining facts within
their jurisdiction (so that positivism turns out not to be neutral on substantive
questions of legal content about which experts disagree). The problem is the
implication that officials who persist in theoretical disagreements must be
systematically and pervasively confused about the nature of law and legality.
For surely, these officials are aware of a remarkable lack of consensus concern-
ing the subject matter of their disagreement. And so, they must not realize that
social convergence on a rule of recognition determines the law. Insofar as
positivism entails an error theory about ordinary legal practice in the sense
that some opposing and mistaken philosophy of law pervades and regulates
legal practice, positivists owe us an explanation of why legal experts end up
29
The question of the limits of theoretical disagreement within a functioning legal system is
underdiscussed. Could a competent American jurist deny that acts of congress make American
law or the intra-systemic superiority of the US constitution? In fact, there are plenty of people
(both liberal and conservative) who think that the US constitution is not the supreme law of the
land in the United States. Nevertheless, the conceptual space for disagreement is probably more
constrained than non-positivists like to admit. See Watson (2023).
30
Some positivists maintain that there can be multiple, inconsistent rules of recognition, driven by
consensus within smaller groups of officials (Raz 1979: pp. 95–96; Gardner 2012: pp. 1–6). But
that doesn’t solve the puzzle about disagreement, since it’s unclear why these groups
take themselves to be right and opposing groups wrong about an alleged matter of fact: the
intra-systemic grounds of law.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 21
mistaken in these ways about the category – that is, they owe us a theory of
error.31
Of course, an error theory about theoretical disagreements turns out not to be
the only option if we’re willing to look past surface appearances – that is, the
claims of legal officials taken at face value. Perhaps their claims are simply
disingenuous or amount to a kind of pretense (Leiter 2009; Marmor 2010;
Plunkett & Sundell 2013). Watson (2023: p. 1), for instance, accuses Dworkin
of construing judicial speech too literally, and writes that:
31
It is generally agreed that philosophical error theories about ordinary practice bear a theoretical
burden of explaining, either in terms of the theory or ancillary commitments, why participants in
the practice end up systematically mistaken. For discussion, see Hirsch (2002: p. 116), Korman
(2009), and Kovacs (2019).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
22 Philosophy of Law
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 23
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
24 Philosophy of Law
have the right to rule, their claims have been manifestly normative – that might
makes right. By contrast, the situation we’ve described involves unapologetic-
ally nihilistic robbers and thieves who admit to serving no one but themselves.
Hart rightly questioned any account of the nature of law that would confer the
status of legality on this picture of pure coercion. His principal target was
Austin’s brand of positivism, according to which law just is the commands
issued by a “sovereign” who happens to be habitually obeyed because she
credibly threatens sanction. Austinian positivists would have no problem call-
ing the criminal organization’s system of rules a form of law, whereas many
positivists and non-positivists have felt, quite naturally I think, that although it
might resemble a legal system, it is too openly exploitative to count as one, to be
elevated, that is, to the status of law and legality.
Hart believed that what’s missing from the gunman situation is genuinely felt
obligation on the part of officials and the populace. Of course, there is a sense in
which the terrified citizens feel obliged to comply – namely, out of concern for
their own safety. But the existence of a legal system depends, Hart argued, on
officials and others taking what he called the “internal point of view,” embra-
cing the rules as, in some sense, worthy of obedience. In our hypothetical,
neither the tyrants running the show nor the citizenry speak in the characteristic
language of morality of what ought to be done, of what’s justified, obligatory, or
permissible when describing their rules. According to Hart, this is the reason
why the “gunman situation writ large” falls short of legality.
To avoid the Austinian implications, other positivists have proposed other
supplementary criteria as essential to law that aren’t satisfied in the gunman
situation. For instance, Raz (1994: ch. 9) maintains that law necessarily claims
authority over its subjects. On a standard construal of Raz’s authority thesis, the
claim of authority is supposed to be (a) a normative claim – a claim of genuine
or legitimate authority, not just raw power; and (b) endorsed by officials and
other key members of the legal system.32 Along similar lines, Shapiro (2011)
has argued that to ensure extensional adequacy, positivists should acknowledge
that law, necessarily, has a moral aim – roughly, that of promoting the general
good – whether or not it actually achieves that aim. As with Raz’s authority
thesis, Shapiro’s moral aim thesis is standardly interpreted in terms of represen-
tations and assumptions made by the officials of a legal system (Plunkett 2013).
So, perhaps what’s missing in the case of the radically criminal organization
32
For Raz, genuine or legitimate authorities issue directives that when followed by their subjects
enable those subjects to conform to what they have independent reason to do better than if the
subjects tried to figure out the directive-independent reasons for themselves. His concept of
authority is thus a manifestly normative notion.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 25
33
For further discussion of Fuller’s point, see 2.5.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
26 Philosophy of Law
research on laypeople’s intuitions about laws and legal systems (Flanagan &
Hannikainen 2020). Accordingly, a good account of the nature of law should be
able to explain why such cases seem hard (Atiq 2020a: p. 21). This fact can be
acknowledged without embracing any controversial non-positivist assumptions
about law’s essential goodness (e.g., that law is, necessarily, worthy of respect, or
that it essentially gives its subjects strong, even decisive, moral reasons for legal
compliance; cf. Finnis 2011; Murphy 2005). Even if positivists want to insist,
ultimately, that there can be radically selfish and tyrannical legal systems, or
morally mistaken systems of law composed of entirely arbitrary rules, they need
to explain, in terms of their theory and/or any ancillary commitments, why such
systems fall on the fuzzy edge of legality.34 And that’s not the same as explaining
why the social orders count as immoral, irrational, or, even, simply unfamiliar.
For things can be good or bad in ways that don’t tell against (or in favor of) kind-
membership. A weapon used in war might be highly immoral or unusual and yet
count as a paradigmatic example of an instrument of war. The explanatory
challenge involves saying why the moral badness or irrationality of law seems
connected in some way to questions of classification – that is, to whether a scheme
of social organization counts as a legal order. That is, perhaps, the least question-
begging way of characterizing the argument based on the various “gunman
situations.” For as we shall see in Section 3, non-positivists face an analogous
explanatory burden associated with evil or arbitrary law.
The options for revising positivism to explain the legal borderline seem
limited. Positivism is constrained, by design, in the kinds of facts it can appeal
to as potential grounds of law, or criteria of legality. The grounds and criteria
must be non-normative in nature. For instance, Hart’s claim that legal systems
are, essentially, hierarchical systems of rules is a claim about the formal, non-
normative features that law necessarily instantiates. One might hope that by
further specifying some such non-normative conditions on the existence of
a legal system, positivists might discover resources for distinguishing hard
from easy cases of legality. Indeed, law’s hierarchical structure was not the
only formal feature that Hart emphasized in his theory of law. In an intriguing
yet somewhat opaque passage, Hart (1958: p. 619) mentions that only rules of
more or less general application can constitute a legal system.35 He derives the
generality constraint from the very idea of a rule, which, according to Hart, has
34
Finnis (2011) makes a related though distinct point when he notes that a theory of law should
have the resources to explain why some instances of law are “central cases” and others
peripheral. What I’m emphasizing here (and have elsewhere) is an epistemic fact that invites
explanation: the fact that it is intuitively unclear how we should classify these various nonstand-
ard or unfamiliar cases (Atiq 2019: pp. 119–121; Atiq 2020a: fn. 53).
35
Notably, Hart’s discussion of generality appears in the context of his response to a point owing to
Fuller (1978), who famously argued that not just generality but various other features, like
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 27
the generality requirement baked into it. In fact, Hart’s claim that a rule, by its
very nature, cannot be overly specific in its content (turning, say, on some
person’s identity or some one-off situation) is eminently questionable. But we
can set the truth or falsity of his theory of rules aside. The point is simply to
illustrate how a non-normative feature, insofar as it is essential to law, might
constrain how arbitrary or absurd a legal system can possibly be.
This approach to the problem seems unlikely to succeed for several reasons.
First, the kinds of structural features of law that positivists have historically
emphasized fail to explain why the various gunman situations involve borderline
cases of law at best. Certainly, the essential generality of law does not, on its own,
rule out the emergence of what is manifestly a legal system out of explicitly selfish,
absurd, and moralizing tyranny.36 Second and more importantly, the more formal
or non-normative features we treat as essential to law, the more complicated our
positivist account of law becomes. And for any such non-normative feature that’s
alleged to be essential to law, positivists owe us an explanation of why it is essential
(consider Hart’s explanation of generality in terms of the nature of rules). And the
explanation cannot simply be that it helps positivists avoid the potential counter-
examples. Otherwise, the resulting strain of positivism will seem gerrymandered to
solve an extensional problem that positivists uniquely face. The borderline cases
we’ve discussed thus involve complicating the standard positivist story in ways
that positivists have yet to address.
My own view is that the classification of the various gunman scenarios should
not be a starting point for a theory of law (cf. Finnis 1980: pp. 9–11). Since it’s
not obvious what we should say about such cases – a fact we should all admit on
either intuitive grounds or on the basis of an inference from peer disagreement
(see Atiq 2019: pp. 119–121) – we may need to leave the problem posed by our
conflicting extensional intuitions unresolved, for now, and return to it after
we’ve examined our reasoning about laws and legal systems more broadly.
Our broader commitments in the philosophy of law might help us address the
problem. And that is precisely how I intend to proceed in the remainder of this
section and the next, by exploring what light we can shed on our uncertainty –
the fact that we don’t quite know what to say about the legal borderline – by
investigating other legal matters, such as the underdiscussed fact that law is
susceptible to kind-relative evaluation.
clarity, publicity, and nonretroactivity, are, in some sense, essential to law (cf. Waldron 2008b;
Raz 2019). We shall return to this Fullerian theme shortly.
36
Moreover, if the essential features of law are described in irreducibly normative terms, such as
nonarbitrariness, impartiality, or fairness, then the view begins to look a lot like non-positivism
(see 2.5). In fact, some positivists have suggested that even Raz’s authority thesis and Shapiro’s
moral aim thesis go a step too far in the direction of non-positivism (Plunkett 2013).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
28 Philosophy of Law
37
This section summarizes and builds on an argument in Atiq (forthcoming). As I explain at the
end of the section, the argument is strengthened by our extensional considerations in 2.4.
38
I rely here on Barney’s (2023) observations concerning the ubiquity of “qua-predication.”
39
For a critical view to which I’m broadly sympathetic, see, e.g., Scanlon (forthcoming).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 29
40
Natural lawyers argue that the moral merits of law are kind-relative merits. I’ll discuss their
arguments in detail in Section 3.1. This section is focused, exclusively, on a critique of positivism
based on a weak claim that even positivists by and large concede – namely, that the Rule of Law
defines a kind-relative standard for evaluating law.
41
This distinction between concrete and abstract artifacts, though not relevant to the argument of
this section, will matter later in Section 3.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
30 Philosophy of Law
42
As discussed in Section 1, I shall rely on an account of the essential properties of abstract objects
defended by Zalta (2006), among others.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 31
Our functionalist thesis about law thus needs to be a “modest and sober one.”
Fuller’s own view was that law’s essential function is to “subject conduct to
the guidance of rules” (38–57). But his view doesn’t quite explain why the
classic Rule-of-Law features define a kind-relative standard for evaluating laws.
One glaring problem with the proposal is that highly specific laws – say, rules
that impose one-off obligations on named individuals – can guide people’s
conduct perfectly well. In fact, an entire system of rules can be pervasively
specific, with different rules for each person, and yet succeed in guiding
conduct. Another problem is that not every feature, or set of features, that
causally contribute(s) to an artifact’s ability to perform its essential function
counts as a kind-relative virtue. This is because causal connections can be
contingent whereas kind-relative virtues appear to be modally general, perhaps
even necessary. So, even if the law’s instantiation of features like publicity
causally contribute to law’s ability to guide conduct in ordinary scenarios, that
doesn’t result in the kind of explanation we are after, one that’s true in a range of
43
For a recent development of an intentionalist/agentive model for explaining artifactual functions,
see, Evnine (2016). The intentionalist model does not explain function-talk in biology very well.
On an alternative nonagentive “etiological” model, kind-functions are identified with whatever
performance explains the emergence and proliferation of instances of the kind in environments
characterized by various selection pressures (see, e.g., Wright 1973). I am not aware of
a systematic application of a “pure” (i.e., entirely nonagentive) etiological account to explain
kind-relative virtues and our ordinary evaluative-talk, in particular. That said, the argument of
this section may be compatible with such an account, although the argument’s success would
then turn on the empirical question of what explains the persistence and proliferation of legal
systems, and whether a discovered etiological function can adequately explain the Rule of Law.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
32 Philosophy of Law
44
For a detailed discussion of various other problems with Fuller’s proposal and related positivist
accounts such as Marmor’s (2007), see Atiq (forthcoming: pp. 14–16). Cf. Raz (2019: pp. 4–5,
14). One response to the objection raised above involves supplementing Fuller’s account with an
ideal of rational guidance: law aims to guide its subjects through their powers of reason. But this
revision to the Fullerian view brings us much closer to the essentially normative view I am about
to defend, where law’s function is the realization of a limited normative ideal.
45
Simmonds (2008: ch. 1), drawing on Kant, argues that the Rule of Law embodies “an intrinsic-
ally valuable form of moral association,” because it creates certain spheres of freedom and
independence that wouldn’t be possible without it. For our purposes, we needn’t choose between
competing accounts of the nature of the ideal. Our present goal has been to motivate the thesis
that the realization of some distinctive normative ideal is law’s essential function and to draw out
the implications of this functional thesis.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 33
46
See, e.g., Thomasson’s (2003: p. 600, 2007: p. 59), Hilpinen (1993: p. 161), and discussion in
Atiq (forthcoming: pp. 10–12).
47
Shapiro maintains that “it is part of the nature of law to have a moral aim” but denies that “the
failure to attain this end undermines the law’s identity as law.” He points out (rightly) that “a
defective instance of a kind is not ipso facto an attenuated version of the kind.” Defective
instances can certainly be full-fledged members of a kind. However, Shapiro overlooks the fact
that radical defects can and do interfere with kind-membership. Ordinary examples of the
phenomenon are easily multiplied. I intend to produce a knife but due to incompetence and
lack of knowledge, my productive efforts result in a useless piece of scrap metal. What I produce
is not a knife because it falls so radically short of the function of knives. Why shouldn’t the same
be true of law qua functional kind? Notably, Shapiro doesn’t motivate his claims based on
a general theory of functional and goodness-fixing kinds, and a key point of this section is
precisely that our claims about the relationship between law’s nature, function, and existence
conditions are less ad hoc when located within a general and independently motivated theory.
48
As I argue elsewhere (Atiq forthcoming), Raz’s (1979, 2019) explanation of the Rule of Law is
questionable precisely because it portrays law as an oddly exceptional goodness-fixing kind.
However, Raz was acutely aware of the difficulties facing the traditional explanations offered by
positivists, especially in his later writings and unlike other writers on the Rule of Law.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
34 Philosophy of Law
exceptional, any such move will seem ad hoc. To reiterate, we’ve leveraged an
analogy with functional artifacts to explain a feature of law that needs explain-
ing. Following the argument where it leads – that is, accepting the consequences
of treating law as a functional artifact whose normative function explains its
kind-relative virtues – entails accepting a minimal role for normative facts in the
existence and grounding of legal systems.
Since this final argument is somewhat complex, it might be worth summariz-
ing its key premises:
***
Let us summarize the overall case against positivism. Positivists struggle to
explain several regular and striking features of legal systems and legal reason-
ing, including: (1) the traditional classification of moral principles as a form of
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 35
a priori law; (2) the role of such principles in legal discovery by contemporary
judges; (3) persistent theoretical (or higher-order) disagreement among jurists
about the law-determining facts within their legal system; (4) the fact that
radically arbitrary or immoral schemes of social organization represent, at
best, borderline cases of legal systems; and (5) the fact that law appears to be
a goodness-fixing kind whose kind-relative virtues plausibly derive from its
artifactual and functional nature. I haven’t claimed that positivist-friendly
explanations of the highlighted phenomena are impossible or inconceivable;
rather, I’ve argued that the theory’s explanatory power is questionable given
that the available explanations seem undermotivated and rely on ancillary
commitments that are less than fully satisfying. For instance, positivist explan-
ations involve uncharitable interpretation (legal officials are systematically
mistaken or confused), improbable assumptions (the category of law is histor-
ically discontinuous), and ad hoc rejections of general explanatory frameworks
(law is exceptional as a goodness-fixing kind). That said, a theory isn’t defeated
by explanatory gaps, baroqueness, or, even, a few counterintuitive implications.
The question is whether there are alternative, non-positivist theories that do
better at meeting our desiderata and without incurring new theoretical costs that
outweigh any gains. That is the question we now turn to.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
36 Philosophy of Law
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 37
morality into determinate and more precise requirements.52 Partly because law
gives specific content to, and is a means of complying with, general moral
imperatives, it has comparable normative force: it gives its subjects genuine
and often decisive reasons for compliance (cf. Murphy 2006; Finnis 2011).
Aquinas’ view has exerted a powerful influence on contemporary natural law
theorists, but it is widely acknowledged that his central claim was less than
precise. The claim that law “is an ordinance of reason” has been interpreted in at
least two ways, corresponding, roughly, to the “is” of identity and the “is” of
predication (Murphy 2005). The “strong natural law thesis,” which interprets
the claim as an identity statement, entirely excludes unjust or unreasonable rules
from the category of law (p. 19). This view is hard to maintain given how easy it
is to multiply examples of wicked, unjust, or otherwise unreasonable laws and
legal systems (cf. Finnis 1980). On an alternative and more popular interpret-
ation, the “weak natural law thesis,” Aquinas takes consistency with practical
reason to be a regular (or “generic”) feature of law,53 one that’s sufficiently
regular to define a constitutive standard for evaluating laws without ruling out
the possibility of unreasonable laws (Murphy 2006: p. 21). That is, when the law
departs from the true moral principles, law’s unreasonableness amounts to
a distinctly legal defect, a way of being defective as law. Recall our observation
in 2.4 that many ordinary kinds are associated with kind-relative or constitutive
standards for evaluating instances. The weak natural law thesis amounts to the
view that law isn’t just some ordinary goodness-fixing kind; its constitutive or
kind-relative virtues include such properties as being morally justified.
The weak natural law thesis plausibly entails some version of the strong. As
discussed previously, the existence and persistence of goodness-fixing kinds seems
subject to a threshold condition – instances must exhibit kind-specific virtues to
some, albeit underspecified, degree to count as members of the kind (2.5). Hence, if
the weak natural law thesis is true, then although mere unreasonableness or wicked-
ness may not preclude a social order from counting as a legal system, radical
unreasonableness and wickedness might. Proponents of the weak natural law thesis
often acknowledge as much.54 But this connection between the weak and strong
52
Summa Theologiae Part Ia IIae 96.
53
On this interpretation, Aquinas’ claim that law is an ordinance of reason amounts to a generic
claim like “tigers are striped.” An initial problem for this interpretation is that Aquinas is also
famous for the paradoxical-sounding thesis that an “unjust law is not law.” As we’ll discuss
shortly, there turns out to be a connection between the strong and the weak natural law theses.
54
Crowe (2019: p. 181) writes: “A poorly drafted, unjust or unreasonable standard will be legally
defective, while an incomprehensible or deeply repugnant standard may be no law at all.”
Similar endorsements of the claim that legality is inconsistent with radical injustice that reaches
“an intolerable level” can be found in Alexy (1999: p. 16), Radbruch (1973), and Soper (2007).
For a helpful discussion of the relationship between kind-relative defectiveness conditions and
existence conditions, see Murphy (2012: pp. 59–60).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
38 Philosophy of Law
theses is worth emphasizing because positivists sometimes struggle to see how the
weak thesis puts any pressure on their view. Both theses involve giving up, albeit to
varying degrees, a core positivist assumption – namely, that the existence of laws and
legal systems does not ultimately depend on moral facts and can be fully explained
without having to rely on a substantive theory of what morality demands.
In either form, natural law theory confronts two central challenges. One is
metaethical: the need to explain and motivate the existence of objective prin-
ciples of morality that float freely from the beliefs and preferences of agents.
I will return to this challenge in Section 4, as it deserves an extended discussion
since a commitment to some form of moral realism may turn out to be the main
theoretical cost of non-positivism.
The second challenge is meta-legal: it involves motivating the claim that law,
unlike other systems of socially dependent norms, bears the proposed connection
to what’s morally or rationally required. Of course, part of the case will be based
on considerations of explanatory power and an inference to the best explanation:
that is, some natural law hypothesis may be necessary for accommodating the
desiderata discussed in Section 2 (a point I shall return to in a moment). But more
specifically, if the weak natural law thesis is true, we should be able to explain
why being morally justified makes the law good as law, ideally in terms of an
independently motivated theory of goodness-fixing kinds. Natural law theorists
thus face a stronger version of the explanatory challenge discussed in 2.4. For the
idea that law’s kind-relative virtues include moral goodness is considerably more
controversial and, it seems fair to say, nonobvious than any corresponding claim
about the classic Rule-of-Law features, such as generality, nonretroactivity, and
publicity (cf. Marmor 2004a; Waldron 2008b).
Natural law theorists have responded to the meta-legal challenge in various
ways. On Finnis’ (2011: pp. 9–11, 2007) view, moral justification (or conform-
ity with the true principles of morality) defines a kind-relative standard for
evaluating law because paradigmatic instances of law – so-called “central
cases” – exhibit such justifiability. Finnis maintains that all philosophical
theorizing about kinds must start with uncontroversial instances, whose regular
features invite explanation, and that the central and paradigmatic cases of law
regularly promote the common good. Both claims are controversial. But even if
they were true, Finnis doesn’t explain why only some regular features of central
cases but not others define kind-relative standards of evaluation (on this point,
see Murphy 2012: pp. 50–51). It is a regular feature of paradigmatic law that it
consists of rules directed at imperfect, uncooperative human beings, and, so,
includes highly coercive and punitive measures. But that fact does not bear any
obvious connection to law’s constitutive virtues. It is not as though law is better
qua law if it is highly coercive/punitive, for we can imagine good law in
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 39
a society of angels (or even a society of better-than-average beings) that isn’t all
that punitive (cf. Raz 1999: p. 159).55 So, the question of why law’s moral
virtues make it good as law remains unanswered, even if we accept Finnis’ point
about the significance of central cases to philosophical theorizing about kinds.
An alternative and more popular approach to explaining why the moral merits
of law might be constitutive merits treats law as a functional kind. On this
approach, a kind’s constitutive virtues are characteristics that make instances
better at performing the kind’s essential function(s). Murphy (2005, 2006)
explores two types of functional explanations for the weak natural law thesis,
developing themes he finds in Moore (1992) and Alexy (2010a). The first
explains a kind’s essential function in terms of some “characteristic” perform-
ance by its instances. Whether a function is “characteristically” performed
depends on “not just statistical frequency” but frequency relative to “normal”
background conditions (2005: pp. 26–27). Elsewhere, I have expressed doubts
about any such account of function-attribution especially insofar as we want
functions to explain constitutive virtues (Atiq forthcoming: pp. 14–15). To take
an ordinary counterexample, a statistically dominant use of flathead screw-
drivers around the house is prying things open, and that’s true in normal
conditions since most screws are Philips-head. But prying things open is not
the constitutive function of flathead screwdrivers; nor does it define a kind-
relative standard for evaluating instances. What makes a good flat-head screw-
driver in the relevant sense of “good” is, plainly, effectiveness at turning
flathead screws. The corresponding claim about usefulness for prying things
open (that it makes the screwdriver good as a flathead screwdriver”) sounds
artificial. Put differently, not all “characteristic functions” in Muphy’s sense are
essential or virtue-defining functions.
In any case, based on his theory of function-attribution, Murphy (2005: p. 26)
argues that the characteristic function of law is “to lay down norms with which
agents will have sufficient [moral] reason to comply.” Murphy (2006: ch. 3,
2012) offers an additional argument in support of his claim about law’s essential
function. This alternative argument relies on the idea that the law consists,
essentially, of speech acts that involve various demands. We’re told that the
law’s specific demands – for example, “drive on the right!” – implicitly claim
(or presuppose) that subjects have decisive reasons to comply (cf. Alexy 1999).
Murphy maintains that such speech acts are defective as demands when their
content and presuppositions are false. Relatedly, law is defective as law (i.e., as
a system of norms making various demands on agents) when it fails to give
55
Raz relies on the “society of angels” scenario to show that coercion isn’t essential to law. My
point here is that coerciveness is also not one of law’s constitutive virtues, even though law is
characteristically coercive.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
40 Philosophy of Law
56
Similarly, Robert Alexy (2021: ch. 3) argues that law necessarily claims moral “correctness” and
the claim’s falsity renders law defective. Alexy considers the objection that law’s claim may be
“nothing more than an expression of an illusion or an error.” But his response is, to put it frankly,
obscure. As far as I can tell, there is no real discussion of the possibility that if I don’t intend
a sincere speech act, it’s content being false needn’t render it defective as a speech act. For further
discussion of the importance of sincerity in the productive intentions that bear on kind-relative
evaluation, see Atiq (forthcoming: 20–21).
57
If moral particularism is true, then there are no general, exceptionless principles that determine
the rightness or wrongness of actions in particular situations. See, e.g., Dancy (2004).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 41
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
42 Philosophy of Law
On the other hand, it’s less clear how natural law theory explains aspects of
legal reasoning highlighted by Dworkin and others. Consider the classification
of principles such as nemo iudex in causa sua as a source of law or, even, as
a priori law. The moral defects of law may be legal defects, or make the law
defective as law, but why should that entail the a priori legality of any moral or
rational principle? This seems to me to be a symptom of a larger problem: it isn’t
clear how the strong and weak natural law theses relate to the classification of
individual rules and principles under the concept of law. Natural law theorists
have traditionally focused on law as an institution, or on what makes an entire
system of rules a legal order, while being relatively less concerned with
articulating general “criteria of legal validity” for specific rules or principles
within legal systems. But we employ the concept of law to refer to both systems
of rules and specific rules of law, such as those derived from statutes or court
decisions. Presumably, there is some connection between these two ways of
using the category.
One possibility is that natural law theory can simply absorb what Hart (or any
other positivist) says about the social criteria of legality (e.g., derivability from
the customary rule of recognition), albeit subject to a moral constraint on the
existence of a legal order.58 But then the theory risks inheriting the problems
Hart faces in relation, say, to theoretical disagreement (more on this in
a moment). Alternatively, the theory might by supplemented with an independ-
ent account of adjudication that sheds light on the nature of legal reasoning
(Finnis 2011; Crowe 2019). For instance, Crowe (2019: p. 196) argues that
a judge’s role in interpreting law is to “interpret legal materials in such a way as
to render them non-defective as law.” As a consequence, judges must be
sensitive to law’s purpose and function. If, ex hypothesi, all law constitutively
aims at justice or the common good, and if judges are entitled to consider law’s
purpose in figuring out what the law is, we have the beginnings of an explan-
ation for why moral principles might be regarded as a form of law: the content of
such principles constrains the content of individual legal rules at least as
formulated by judges.
Still, the proposal as sketched leaves several questions unanswered. Why
assume that a judge’s professional responsibility is to “improve” the law by
making legal pronouncements which render the law “non-defective”? Why not
embrace what seems to be the more standard view – that a judge’s sole
responsibility is to take a clear-eyed view on what the law is, no matter how
defective it might be “as law” or in any other sense? Crowe’s conception of the
judge’s role is controversial to say the least. Moreover, even if we assume that
58
For discussion on this point, see Murphy (2005).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 43
judges are entitled to take the overarching moral purpose of law into account in
discovering specific laws, it isn’t obvious why that would entitle jurists to
declare moral principles a priori law even in the absence of formal promulgation
(cf. Aquinas, Summa Theologiae).
Perhaps relatedly, it’s not obvious whether natural law theory sheds
enough light on a central feature of legal reasoning in complex legal systems –
persistent theoretical disagreement – to constitute a sufficient advance on legal
positivism. For even if law either essentially is or aspires to be an “ordinance of
reason” (compatible, that is, with the requirements of reason and morality), it’s
unclear why jurists persistently disagree about the grounds of legality in full
awareness of a lack of intra-systemic consensus on the question. Consider, for
instance, a natural law theory that follows Hart in its specification of the social
criteria of legality (derivability from the customary rule of recognition) while
adding a moral threshold condition (which applies irrespective of the social
facts). On the one hand, the “Hartian” natural lawyer can invoke explanatory
resources that weren’t available to Hart: some disagreements about the grounds
of law persist because of persistent moral disagreement within the legal com-
munity about what justice, in fact, requires. On the other hand, the explanation
seems incomplete since participants in theoretical legal disagreements often
explicitly disavow moral motivations. Many constitutional originalists in the
United States, for instance, maintain that their account of the grounds of
constitutional law is motivated not by a sense that originalism entails morally
good outcomes; rather, they claim to be motivated by a correct understanding of
what law is and the judge’s professional responsibility.59 More generally, it
seems that persons who agree on moral matters can, and often do, disagree
about the grounds of law persistently and without conceptual confusion. So,
there is more to the phenomenon that needs explaining. And since explaining
theoretical disagreement plays such a central role in Ronald Dworkin’s theory
of law, perhaps that is where we should look next for insights into law’s nature.
59
See, e.g., Baude and Sachs (2019).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
44 Philosophy of Law
nonmoral, social facts: roughly, facts concerning the actions of various institutions
(e.g., a legislature or law-making body) and the desires and beliefs of agents
operating within those institutions. The relevant social facts might include facts
concerning the socially embraced rules of recognition, change, and the like.
However, Dworkin maintained that any derivation of law, or legal rights and duties,
from such social facts involves “interpretation” of institutional practice and, relying
on his general theory of interpretation, defended a non-positivist metaphysics of law.
On Dworkin’s view, whether one is interpreting a poem or a painting or indeed,
the social practices that result in law, interpretation necessarily involves treating an
object of interpretation (e.g., a set of sentences) as an instance of a normatively
significant kind (e.g., a sonnet with aesthetic properties). Instances of normatively
significant kinds can be ranked as better or worse based on kind-relative normative
criteria. Moreover, the process of interpreting an object as an instance involves
attributing meaning, purpose, and content to it “in order to make of it the best
possible example of the form or genre to which it is taken to belong” (Dworkin 1986:
p. 52). Interpretation is always constrained, to some extent, by the non-normative
features of the object of interpretation. In the case of a sonnet, an interpretation must
be responsive to the text, some range of meanings to which the terms and expressions
are susceptible, and the intentions of the author – features Dworkin discussed under
the rubric of a “dimension of fit.” But a good interpretation imputes content that
elevates the object of interpretation by representing it as a good instance of the
relevant kind, and even if, for example, the imputed content cannot be located fully
in the intentions of the agent(s) who produced the object. In the case of a sonnet, an
interpretation that renders the sonnet more lovely but at the cost of fidelity to the
intentions of its author might be superior to an interpretation constrained entirely by
authorial intentions. Hence, evaluative considerations define a “dimension of justi-
fication” that, Dworkin argued, is an essential element of ideal interpretation.
In the case of legally relevant social practices, the normatively significant
kind to which these practices allegedly belong (when imbued with legal con-
tent) is “a general justification for the exercise of state coercion” (1986a:
p. 190). That is, the social facts interpreted as resulting in legal duties, rights,
and responsibilities (including propositions of the form <the law requires
that . . .>) imply an explanation of why the state is justified in coercively
enforcing its rules against its subjects. Naturally, this justification will be
more or less plausible depending on the goodness or justice of legal rules and
requirements. Moral principles, therefore, operate as a constraint on legal
interpretation.60 Dworkin maintained that morality constrains the interpretation
60
On the relevant set of principles, including the master principle of integrity, see Dworkin (1986a:
pp. 90–93).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 45
of any action or aspect of institutional practice that produces law – including, for
example, a prior precedent or judicial ruling. That is, any interpretation of what
the law requires in any context must be evaluated for how well it contributes to
the overall justification for the state’s coercive authority.
Note that there is a way of construing Dworkin’s claims in exclusively
epistemic terms. What he offers is a heuristic for adjudication, an account of
how judges should go about “discovering” law in light of social practice facts
that doesn’t necessarily track the law’s metaphysics. However, any such con-
strual would underestimate the radical nature of Dworkin’s thesis. On the
intended metaphysical construal, there is nothing more to legal facts – facts
concerning, say, the legality of a rule – than facts concerning the best interpret-
ation of social practice. The fact that the law obliges drivers to drive on the right
is in some sense reducible to the fact that the best interpretation of what we do
around here is that we expect and coercively enforce driving on the right. And
the latter fact concerning the best interpretation is grounded in both non-
normatively characterized social facts (the choices and intentions of institu-
tional actors) and moral facts (our institutional practice is portrayed in a morally
good light). Hence, legal facts are partly grounded in moral facts.
Like the natural law theorist, Dworkin conceives of legally relevant social
practices as having a normative role: namely, as contributing to a case for
justified state coercion. But his reasons are radically different. Dworkin is
motivated by a certain conception of interpretation within legal practice and
its metaphysical implications – that is, its implications concerning the nature of
legal facts.61 These reasons are the source of the view’s distinct advantages but
also some of its unique vulnerabilities.
Let’s start with the advantages. The view straightforwardly explains why
judges reach for moral principles when interpreting prior precedent and institu-
tional practice. Judges engaged in interpretation are keen to cast the law in its
morally best light, even if that means going beyond the manifest intentions and
actions of agents. It was no accident, for example, that even though there was no
prior judicial opinion or statute that would have prevented a murderer from
inheriting under a victim’s will in Riggs v Palmer, the court nevertheless held
that principles of justice “constrain” what the law requires. It’s less clear how
Dworkin’s view explains the historical treatment of moral principles as a priori
law, but we can develop a plausible story for at least some such principles: moral
principles, insofar as they operate as conceptual constraints on what the law
could be, are akin to “laws of law.” If, for example, law cannot permit largescale
61
Dworkin differs also in his metaethics – in particular, his account of the nature of moral facts.
See, e.g., Dworkin (2011). But we can ignore this difference for now. On Dworkin’s metaethical
quietism, see McGrath (2014).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
46 Philosophy of Law
62
Perhaps all we need to know to be competent with the concept of law is certain uncontroversial
extensional truths involving it along with the fact that the concept’s application involves
interpreting a legally relevant set of social practices. However, we needn’t take a view, here,
on what determines concept possession and concept mastery.
63
It is no accident that Dworkin (1986: pp. 87–88) names his hypothetical judge who interprets the
law correctly “Hercules.” The task of making moral sense of social practice, including the entire
legal history of a given jurisdiction, is, indeed, herculean.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 47
norms, given that not every moral duty is legislated, enforced, or relied on by
lawyers. Since Dworkin wasn’t very precise on how considerations of fit and
justification are balanced, the theory’s extensional implications – its implica-
tions about the content of the law within jurisdictions – are hard to evaluate.64
One relatively clear implication seems counterintuitive: the legal facts – that is,
the content of the law within a jurisdiction – may be entirely inconsistent with
subjects’ beliefs about the law, since subjects who are morally mistaken may be
radically cut off from the “morally best” interpretation of social practice (Raz
1985: p. 309; Marmor 2011: pp. 90–92).65
Recently, theorists who share Dworkin’s emphasis on legal reasoning, though
not necessarily his controversial account of interpretation, have argued that
ordinary legal practice supports the view that legal norms are identical to
a subset of moral norms (Greenberg 2014; Hershovitz 2023; Ryu 2024).66 To
illustrate based on Greenberg’s (2014) development of the “one-system view,”
legal interpretation involves “moral reasoning about what is [morally] required
as a consequence of . . . relevant lawmaking actions,” rather than reasoning
about what would make an entire system of coercion “the best it can be” given
the constraints of fit and justification (pp. 1303–1304). On this picture, legal
requirements are supposed to be identical (or reducible) to those moral require-
ments (concerning, say, rights and responsibilities) that result from the actions
of specific institutions. Nevertheless, what we morally should do given institu-
tional choices and actions can be inferior to what we morally should do in an
ideal institutional context, so there remains on this view a meaningful distinc-
tion between moral and legal norms (whether it is a sufficient distinction is
debatable, however, as we’ll discuss). Other defenders of the “one-system
view” have explained the legally relevant subset of moral norms differently,
64
On this point, see Finnis (1987).
65
It’s worth noting that Dworkin’s view entails two kinds of radical legal error: (1) an entire
community could fail to appreciate the legality of a norm; or (2) an entire community could
wrongly take some norm to be law. I think the second upshot, emphasized by Marmor (2011,
ch. 2), is more implausible than the first. See discussion in Atiq (2020a: pp. 23–24). Raz’s (1985)
critique of these implications of Dworkin’s view is part of a more general critique based on the
thesis that law necessarily aspires to be authoritative – that is, it purports to give subjects
knowable peremptory reasons for action. Raz argues that free-standing moral principles are
incapable of being directives, and insofar as their application involves moral reasoning, they
cannot give subjects peremptory, content-independent reasons for action. But the claim that all
laws must take the form of knowable and authoritative directives is highly suspect, as is the claim
that legal imperatives cannot invite moral reflection from those who are subject to them. I suspect
Raz mistakes generic truths about legal norms for necessary truths. For discussion on the
peremptory status of legal directives and moral reasoning, see Kramer (2004: p. 23).
66
Dworkin (2011: p. 403) seems to have favored a related thesis in his later work. On the continuity
between Dworkin’s interpretivism and the one-system view, see Nye (2021).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
48 Philosophy of Law
while sharing the core assumption that legal and moral norms form a single,
unified body of norms.67
On what basis might one conclude that ordinary legal practice favors the
“one-system” thesis? In several papers, Greenberg (2004, 2008) offers an
intriguing argument. He argues that while social facts concerning, for example,
the choices and intentions of legislatures play a role in determining the law,
a core assumption of adjudicative practice (one he endorses) is that the law-
determining social facts stand in a special relationship to facts concerning what
the law is. Greenberg calls this relation “rational grounding.” Roughly, the idea
is that the legal facts (concerning what the law requires) must be intelligible
given the law-determining social facts. “Intelligible” sounds like a normative
notion. To say that the law is intelligible given the social facts in a jurisdiction
sounds a lot like saying that there is something to be said in favor of the law
given the social facts. But Greenberg expressly disavows the normative inter-
pretation (pp. 190–191). He maintains that intelligibility means something like
a priori accessibility: any rational agent who knows the law-determining social
facts within the system should be able to derive, through a priori reflection –
from the armchair, as it were – facts about legal rules, permissions, prohibitions,
and so on.68 But if positivism were true, then the legal facts wouldn’t be
derivable a priori from the social facts. The argument for this claim is subtle
but turns primarily on the fact that the social facts – concerning people’s
behavior, customs, and so on – are always compatible with a range of competing
rules or principles.69 Legal positivism would have to be (surprisingly) some
kind of a priori conceptual truth, Greenberg argues, for there to be anything like
an a priori connection between legal content and the social facts. And quite apart
from his critique of positivism, Greenberg suggests that the rational intelligibil-
ity of law favors the one-system of view. For many moral facts are derivable
a priori from social facts – that is, what we morally ought to do, given the
67
Hershovitz (2015, 2023: p. 192) seems to be moved by the thought that legal rules and
obligations couldn’t be “normative” in any sense besides the sense in which moral rules
and obligations are normative. He suggests that of the moral obligations that qualify as
legal obligations, some essentially depend on institutional choices, while others are simply
moral obligations that are enforceable in court (Hershovitz 2015: pp. 1202–1203, 2023:
pp. 84–91, 182–183).
68
There might be other precisifications of Greenberg’s somewhat elusive concept of “rational
grounding.” I think my interpretation renders the argument interesting and worthy of engage-
ment. For an alternative take, see Chilovi and Pavlakos (2022).
69
The reasons are related to Wittgenstein’s puzzles about rule following (see Kripke 1982). To get
a sense of the reasons, consider the history of your practice involving the rule for addition. Your
behavior in adding up numbers is consistent with a rule of quaddition, which operates like
addition but only for numbers up to some arbitrarily large number that you’ve never “added”
before. For a similar point about social practice being compatible with many different legal rules,
see Greenberg (2004: p. 182).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 49
70
To be fair, Greenberg acknowledges this possibility and explicitly invokes normative or value
facts in the argument, rather than moral facts. But his ultimate view of the nature of legal facts,
the moral impact theory, is cashed out in specifically moral terms.
71
In a similar vein, Hershovitz (2023: p. 192) maintains that when legal actors make claims about
legal rights and obligations in court, they make claims about who morally owes what to whom.
Unfortunately, he offers scant evidence in support of this claim about ordinary legal practice. As
far as I can tell, Hershovitz seems impressed mainly by the use of deontic and normative
terminology in law and our practical goals in litigation. But we often speak in deontic terms –
that is, in the language of obligation and right – without intending anything moral. Chess players
might instruct a novice in terms of moves that ought to be made. That doesn’t show that chess
players intend a moral claim. In fact, Hershovitz acknowledges that ordinary legal actors
routinely distinguish legal from moral obligation but insists that ordinary legal actors must be
confused or speaking loosely (pp. 10–13, 109–111; cf. Hershovitz 2014: pp. 1191–1192).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
50 Philosophy of Law
to enforce the Fugitive Slave Act during the antebellum period in the United
States, even though they weren’t morally obliged (cf. Finnis 1980). Likewise,
moral and legal obligations seem to come apart in various mundane and morally
neutral cases. Dindjer (2020: p. 193) offers a nice illustration:
Plausibly one very often has pro tanto obligations to comply with
[traffic] rules. But it is difficult to imagine that, for every driver under
all possible circumstances, this will be true – difficult to believe, for
example, that, on an obviously deserted country road with no danger
present, an experienced driver invariably violates a [moral] obligation in
driving before the traffic lights have turned to green, or not indicating
before a turn.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 51
72
Describing the debate between “intentionalists” and “anti-intentionalists” in literary interpret-
ation, Kubala (2019: pp. 509–510) notes that “for the anti-intentionalist” there can be “a plurality
of acceptable interpretations.” The idea that there is one value-maximizing “super” interpretation
seems to be a minority position in literary theory.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
52 Philosophy of Law
views we shall explore next take the nature of the ordinary concept and the rules
governing its application as their primary focus.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 53
73
See Plunkett and Philips (2023), who argue that the results might be driven not by dual meanings
but contextual factors.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
54 Philosophy of Law
Another option would be to characterize the relationship between the moral and
the social criteria of legality in terms of “aggregative clustering” (Atiq 2020a).
Aggregative cluster concepts are concepts whose application involves an imprecise
“aggregation” of distinct properties exhibited by members: an object falls under
such a concept just in case it exemplifies to a sufficient (albeit imprecise) degree the
associated properties (see Kovacs 2018; cf. Hedden & Nebel 2024). For instance,
the concept RED applies to colors based on some combination of hue, chroma, and
brightness, but the principle of combination is not precise enough to yield clear
verdicts for every shade of color. More generally, aggregative cluster concepts are
associated with clear and indeterminate instances. For instance, the concept BIGGER
THAN applies to pairs of objects based on properties of volume, length, and mass.
The ingredient properties can converge and result in easy comparisons, but they can
also diverge in ways that lead to indeterminacy.74 Nevertheless, concepts of redness
and being bigger track objective similarities across members.
I have suggested in prior work that the concept of law may integrate in
similarly imprecise yet principled ways the moral and social properties of
rules.75 Borrowing from Hart, suppose that the relevant social property is just
the property of being a rule that’s derivable from the rule of recognition embraced
by a community from the internal point of view (i.e., with the requisite normative
assumptions). The moral property might be the property of being a good or just
rule. The key idea is to see these properties, when instantiated together, as
determining a more complex and somewhat indeterminate property – perhaps
the normative property of being sufficiently well-supported by a select class of
reasons for following rules. One possibility is that legal actors weigh broadly
“social” reasons for following rules as well as moral reasons in deciding whether
a rule is sufficiently well-supported to count as law.76 Rational agents regularly
74
A rigorous statement of how the ingredient criteria of such “multi-dimensional concepts” are
aggregated to yield overall judgments is beyond the scope of this volume. For problems and
potential solutions, see Hedden and Nebel (forthcoming).
75
One reviewer inquired why the “dual character” and “cluster concept” theories should be
discussed together. The latter might seem related to Dworkin’s interpretivism, especially in
light of the question I pressed earlier against the interpretivist of why the legality of a rule should
depend on the “best” interpretation of the social and moral facts as opposed to a “sufficiently
good” interpretation. The cluster concept theory may be understood as a version of interpreti-
vism with a fuzzy threshold of sufficiency. However, the main motivations for the theory – e.g.,
explaining inconsistent juridical intuitions about law, including intuitions that interpretivists
dismiss as erroneous – differ from the motivations for Dworkin’s interpretivism and are closer to
the motivations for the dual character theory. See discussion in Atiq (2020a: pp. 19–21). To
borrow an observation of Simon Blackburn’s, often what matters in philosophy is not where we
end up (our conclusions) but where we begin (e.g., what we set out to explain).
76
Valenti (2024) argues that a distinctive reason to respect socially constructed norms is that doing
so respects people’s agency as reflected in their considered commitments. Valenti describes these
reasons as “moral” in nature, but that’s beside the point. The key idea for our purposes is that the
cluster theory relies on different species of genuine reasons – e.g., Valenti’s social reasons as well
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 55
weigh different kinds of reasons for action – including reasons that flow from our
subjective attachments, such as special concern for a loved one or community
conventions or one’s life projects, as well as impartial, other-regarding moral
considerations – in deciding whether a course of action is justified relative to the
totality of their values. So, it’s not implausible to think that legal actors might be
doing something similar in the legal domain.
I confess to no longer being certain of the view’s viability as described in
prior work for reasons that will become clear shortly. I restate it here mainly to
illustrate how the aggregative-cluster model might be applied to the concept of
law, a point of some relevance to the discussion to follow, and to draw out
its non-positivist implications. Both dual-character and aggregative-cluster
accounts purport to identify, albeit at a very high level of generality, the rules
for applying the legal concept correctly – that is, in ways that entail true claims
of legality. On the dual character theory, a rule or body of rules must meet moral
conditions to count as law in at least one ordinary sense of “law.” Likewise, on
the aggregative cluster model, whether the concept of law applies to some rule
turns on its moral features. The relationship between such conceptual theses and
a metaphysical thesis concerning the nature of legality – that is, the category
that philosophers of law are interested in – is not straightforward.77 One reason
concerns our methodological observation from Section 1: the philosophy of law
is not necessarily interested in all of the ways the ordinary concept of law might
be employed; rather, the goal is to understand a sense of legality that is
consistent with certain distinctions between social orders that become apparent
upon reflection, and that can shed explanatory light on some very general
phenomena associated with legal systems. So, the question remains whether
the concept of law as characterized by the accounts we’ve discussed above can
help us address our specific theoretical needs. As I’ll explain shortly, there is
some reason to think so. But for now, note that if a conceptual thesis of the sort
discussed in this section turns out to be true, then it is extremely tempting to
think that some facts of law in the ordinary sense of “law” are explained by facts
of morality, at least in the same way that facts of bachelorhood are explained
by facts concerning gender and marital status. The onus is on the positivist
to explain why this implication, which seems prima facie inconsistent with
positivism, would be philosophically irrelevant even if true.
as, say, impartial or welfarist reasons. The aggregative cluster concept of law thus tracks
a complex normative property of rules being sufficiently well-supported by a subset of normative
reasons, where the relevant subset defines a genuine, if partly indeterminate, normative ideal.
77
See generally Smithson (2020), who distinguishes concept-grounding from kind- or property-
grounding.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
56 Philosophy of Law
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 57
moral obligations – make the law defective as law. But no such claim follows
from the limited conclusions we reached at the end of Section 2.
The Normative Artifact Thesis does entail a form of non-positivism, how-
ever. Recall that there are excellent reasons for embracing the threshold condi-
tion on the existence and persistence of functional artifacts: genuine instances
must effectively perform, to some degree, the artifact’s constitutive function (or
functions). And so, whether a social order counts as a legal system plausibly
depends on its ability to minimally satisfy a normative ideal the realization of
which is, ex hypothesi, law’s essential function. Put differently, the existence of
law is grounded in, and partly explained by, the existence of rules of social
organization that are to some extent, and in a restricted sense, good.
On its own, the Normative Artifact Thesis is not a complete theory of law for the
same reason that the strong and weak natural law theses aren’t. A comprehensive
theory of law should have something to say not just about the nature of law
construed as a kind of social order, but also about the general criteria of legality
that jurists use to discover specific laws. After all, we employ the concept of law to
refer to systems of rules as well as specific rules of law, and presumably there is
some connection across these different uses of the category. And so, it’s not enough
to know that the existence of a legal order depends on both social and normative
conditions; we want to know how the social and normative features of rules relate
to determine a rule’s legality within a bona fide legal system.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
58 Philosophy of Law
subject to a normative condition. Legal rules are rules that are validated by
a jurisdiction’s socially embraced rule of recognition, though the existence of
a legal order, and, relatedly, the effectiveness of its rule of recognition at generating
law, depends to some minimal degree on the order’s normative merits.
However, we cannot rely exclusively on a Hartian view of the criteria of legality,
even supplemented by a normative threshold condition, for the reasons Dworkin
gave. No such criteria satisfactorily explain, whether in vindicating or debunking
terms, such features of legal reasoning as the treatment of moral principles as
a source of law. Moreover, throughout legal history, jurists have felt free to invoke
principles of impartiality, reciprocity, and the like as law and on seemingly a priori
grounds, when their entitlement to do so rarely seems secure on the basis of the
jurisdiction’s rule of recognition alone. Indeed, such practices have persisted in
jurisdictions with persistent disagreement about the grounds of law, and disagree-
ment, specifically, about whether the moral content of a principle, on its own,
suffices for its legality. So, the Hartian view couldn’t be complete.
Fortunately, the considerations that justify the Normative Artifact Thesis also
suggest a principled and explanatorily powerful supplementation of Hart’s account
of the criteria. Once we’ve acknowledged law’s essentially normative function,
together with the fact that this function arises in the standard way for artifactual kinds
(i.e., through the psychology of creators and sustainers), we’ve indirectly strength-
ened the case for something like a dual character account of the concept of law, at
least in its application to individual rules within a legal system. Recall that the dual
character account maintains that there are distinct but related criteria of application
for the legal concept. And dual character accounts were originally motivated based
on artifactual concepts, especially artifacts with ostensibly normative functions,
such as artworks, including plays, paintings, symphonies, and novels (Lio et al.
2020). Plausibly, the function of artworks is to be valuable in some restricted sense,
given the intentions of those involved in their production (the conceivers, creators,
and sustainers). And relatedly, there appear to be both social and normative senses of
“art,” at least when the concept is used to pick out specific instances. We sometimes
recognize objects as art simply for being housed in a museum or in virtue of being
judged as art by a community of artists, thus applying purely social criteria of
classification tied to art’s production and recognition. But it is also entirely common
to employ normative criteria based on what is plausibly art’s evaluative function.
One can coherently and without conceptual confusion refrain from calling some-
thing art, despite its social recognition as such, that isn’t appropriately moving,
interesting, or otherwise aesthetically valuable.78 Moreover, there is evidence in the
78
When employed this way, the concept ART is an essentially normative concept. To call something
art is to endorse it based on a broad set of aesthetic values and virtues. For an illuminating
discussion of the way both “practice-internal” and “practice-external” reasons, values, and
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 59
One possibility is that the relationship between the social and normative criteria is
captured by the model of an aggregative cluster concept. The criterion of legality
is, always, some weighted combination of two factors: (1) how close a rule is,
given its content, to being derivable from (or entailed by) the socially embraced
rule of recognition, and (2) how it contributes to the law’s realization of its
normative aspirations. We needn’t assume, as Dworkin did, that there must be
some single “best” way of balancing considerations of “fit” and “justification.”
norms inform our aesthetic judgments, see Kubala (2021). On “art concept pluralism” and the
distinction between “conventional art” and “aesthetic art,” see, e.g., Mag Uidhir and Magnus
(2011: pp. 90–92). For a related distinction in legal theory, between internal and external
statements of law, see Toh (2011).
79
See Clark and Rehding’s (2006) discussion of the traditional view of music as “a fact of external
nature” – as sound-structures discovered by the musician – in contrast to the view of “music as
the interior moral power of human nature.” As in the legal case, one needn’t endorse such
contested claims within the practice of art to appreciate the flexibility of the operative concepts.
The relevant fact to be explained is simply that the historical record is full of references to so-
called natural artworks and nature’s artistic prowess. Such claims plausibly involve the applica-
tion of art-concepts based exclusively on the values or ideals that art is meant to realize rather
than social or agential criteria. For a theory of musical artifacts based on the model of discovery,
selection, and indication by the artist (rather than literal creation), see Levinson (1980). For
a defense of the assumption that all art is the product of a successful “art-intention,” see Mag
Uidhir (2013).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
60 Philosophy of Law
Any such strong assumption would have to be motivated. But the weaker
assumption that, in general, the social and normative properties of rules together
inform legal classification has an explanatory payoff. Recall that positivist
explanations of the legality of moral principles weren’t altogether unreasonable.
The social conditions concerning, for example, what’s customary within legal
systems may not have fit the legality of moral principles perfectly given disagree-
ment among jurists. But there has always been some degree of recognition,
among significant groups of jurists, of the a priori legality of moral principles.
The moral features of such principles may have compensated for their imperfect
fit with more broadly shared customs and tradition. I say “may” and have hedged
my claims here in an effort to remain neutral on the intra-systemic question of
legal substance: whether judges were right to classify the relevant principles (or,
on the opposite extreme, socially embraced yet utterly wicked principles) as law.
The goal is to charitably explain judicial behavior as neither bizarre nor dishonest,
not to establish that some claim made by this or that judge is correct (or incorrect).
The correctness of the relevant claims is dialectically contested and not a pre-
theoretical datum. Accordingly, our explanation should be neither plainly vindi-
cating nor debunking; it should be rationalizing.
Still, it’s unclear how much progress has been made towards rationalizing
legal behavior. If the normative criteria of legality are very general and limited
(as we’ve assumed they must be if they derive from law’s essential function),
then the criteria presumably validate many different principles that are socially
embraced to varying degrees. They wouldn’t necessarily pick out, say, the
principle the court in Riggs relied on, which invalidated a claim to inheritance
on grounds of injustice to the decedent. For a contrary principle, enforcing the
claim in the absence of express statutory prohibition, might have been equally
consistent with the formal Rule of Law and the limited normative ideal it
captures. Indeed, the dissenting justice emphasized as much – that enforcing
the will as written would be in a sense fair, especially given that the criminal law
would punish the injustice at issue.80
We can solve this problem by leveraging yet another general and entirely
familiar feature of artifactual kinds. Once we acquire concepts of such kinds
(the concept of a knife, say), we easily grasp more fine-grained or precisfied
concepts (carving knife, paring knife, utility knife, army knife, and so on).
These more fine-grained concepts involve further specification of the social/
agential and functional properties that define the general category.81 So, it’s
80
22 NE 188, 191-2 (NY 1889).
81
What follows is best understood as a hypothesis about how to model conceptual combination in
the case of complex artifact-concepts, a hypothesis supported by its usefulness in explaining
categorization and reasoning.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 61
plausible that the more specific normative criteria jurists have sometimes relied
on in deeming, on seemingly a priori grounds, specific moral principles as law
derive not from the concept of law as such (although some limited normative
principles may well derive from the general concept), but from more fine-
grained concepts of American law, Roman law, and other kinds of law. Far
from being ad hoc, the assumption is a natural one to make given the broader
theory of artifacts we’re relying on. Concepts of American law or Roman law
don’t just involve more specific social properties (being a legal order embraced
by Americans) than the general concept but also more specific normative
properties (for instance, as the US constitution indicates, the property of being
a system of rules that is not just good in terms of Rule-of-Law fairness but
conducive to “the general welfare, and . . . the blessings of liberty to ourselves
and our Posterity”).82 Concepts of normative or value-driven artifacts exhibit
precisely this structure. The criteria for being a classical, romantic, or impres-
sionist art song, involve further specification of the non-normative as well as
normative criteria for being an art song. Whereas an art song must instantiate to
some extent some very general aesthetic ideal, romantic art songs plausibly
exhibit a specific form of aesthetic goodness – a distinctively romantic aes-
thetic. Likewise, the criteria for being an expressionist painting or an abstract
painting or a renaissance painting, and so on, are plausibly specifications of the
more general non-normative and normative criteria for being a painting. Notice,
also, that it’s more plausible to ascribe relatively specific moralistic intentions to
Americans involved in the creation and sustaining of American law than it
would be to attribute such intentions to every community that has ever created
or sustained a legal order. The normative intentions that are shared across legal
systems must be very general and indeterminate; but they can be more specific
in the case of individual legal systems.
The resulting explanation of the role of moral principles in legal reasoning
might seem superficially similar to the explanation offered by “inclusive posi-
tivists” (see Section 2.2). But there are important differences, and the compari-
son will prove helpful for further clarifying the present view and its ability to
better explain judicial practice. Inclusive positivists allow that moral principles
could enjoy the status of legality within a legal system, but they insist that what
makes such principles law are contingent social facts within the system –
specifically, facts that ground the system’s more fundamental or higher-order
82
Obviously, that’s not to say that there are as many fine-grained concepts of law as there are
individual states or jurisdictions. As I discuss later, we should only posit more fine-grained
concepts when necessary to explain the conceptual practices of distinct legal-linguistic commu-
nities, and specifically based on the kinds of legal claims that participants find primitively
compelling.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
62 Philosophy of Law
83
See discussion in 2.2.
84
Positivists disagree about how much convergence is required to ground a higher-order rule of
law, but they agree that convergence is based on the actual observable behavior of relevant
officials. See Hart (1994: pp. 95, 102), Raz (1979: pp. 95–96), Leiter (1995), and Kramer (2018:
p. 84).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 63
circumstances (for example, with full information about the facts relevant to its
application). This entails that the concept AMERICAN LAW might be shared despite
plenty of actual disagreement over whether some candidate moral principle (e.g., the
Riggs principle of not letting persons profit from their own wrongdoing) qualifies as
law. Naturally, judges don’t have access to facts concerning what their linguistic
community would find primitively compelling in circumstances of full information
(about social, moral, linguistic, and other facts). A judge’s assumption that her
understanding of the concept will attract convergence in ideal circumstances (and
so qualify as “shared”) may be based on nothing more than a hunch, intuitive
seeming, or leap of faith. But that’s not a unique feature of the legal case; it is
a general phenomenon: our intuitions about sharing a concept with others (1) are
often “epistemically primitive,” (2) withstand conflicting conceptual starting points
or basic intuitions within the community, and (3) tend not to be based on a systematic
survey of past usage and present dispositions to apply associated terminology in
actual and counterfactual scenarios (see, e.g., Schroeter 2012: pp. 191–192).85
Of course, how we come to have the basic conceptual dispositions that we do
and why our intuitions about concept-sharing are often reliable turn on complex
issues in the philosophy of language.86 My strategy in this section has been to
locate the basic dispositions we find among jurists within our broader concep-
tual practices involving normative artifacts. But we needn’t resolve, here, the
nature of concepts, concept possession, or concept mastery to recognize the
basic point that the rules that govern our concepts, and that may or may not be
shared by others, are very different from rules of law, and relatedly, that our
present explanation of judicial practice diverges substantially from the inclusive
positivist’s explanation, and in ways that make it better as an explanation.
Among other things, rules of law are embraced with a greater degree of self-
consciousness (recall the importance of Hart’s “internal point of view”) and by
a select few in the linguistic community designated as “officials.”87 Moreover,
as positivists often remind us, not all rules that jurists rely on in adjudication
count as legal rules just for being relied on. Our conceptual dispositions in
relation to normative artifacts together with general norms of communication –
in particular, the fact that our basic conceptual commitments needn’t be based
85
Schroeter (2012) suggests that the reliability of these primitive appearances of “samesaying”
might be based on a willingness to adjust one’s own conception based on the fully informed
understandings and intuitions of others. Since we don’t take ourselves to be using arbitrary
stipulative categories, our private representational practices are rarely decisive.
86
The literature on concept individuation, possession, and mastery is complex. I point the
interested reader to the work of Lewis (1975), Burge (1979), Peacocke (1992), Brandom
(1994), Horwich (2005), Davis (2005), and Schroeter (2012). Rabin (2018) provides a helpful
overview of some important themes.
87
See, e.g., Leiter (2021), who describes the rule of recognition as a rule that officials “treat as
obligatory” given their actual practice.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
64 Philosophy of Law
88
Notice that this account leaves room for the Riggs majority and the dissent to be engaged in
a good faith disagreement about a shared subject matter, AMERICAN LAW, despite their inconsistent
conceptions of that subject in nonideal circumstances. Moreover, by leaving open the possibility
of a good faith disagreement between jurists, our account avoids having to (a) speculate about
their “true” motivations or (b) paraphrase their claims. Contrast, for instance, an interpretation of
bedrock juridical disagreements as a “meta-linguistic negotiation”; see Plunkett and Sundell
(2013b) and the discussion in 1.3.
89
Recall from our earlier discussion in 2.2 that inclusive positivists maintain that there are no moral
or essentially normative principles whose legality can be secured on conceptual grounds alone
and independently of jurisdiction-specific social facts. On the present view, at least some thin
normative ideals are legal ideals in all jurisdictions, whose legality is derived from the general
concept of law as a value-driven artifact. The ideal of the Rule of Law constrains the very
existence of a legal system. Inclusive positivists have traditionally denied that the normative
characteristics of a legal system bear on its existence. Finally, the moderate strain of non-
positivism I’ve defended in this section consists of more than just an account of the criteria of
legal validity, and my overall argument for the view differs substantially from the case
Waluchow (1994), Coleman (2001), Kramer (2004), and others have made for inclusive
positivism.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 65
Dworkin was thus correct in thinking that all it takes to be a competent user of
the concept of law – to possess the concept as opposed to mastering it – is to
know the core of the institutional practices to be interpreted. However, compe-
tent use of the concept does not require applying some precise aggregation
principle that would decide hard cases – that is, cases involving rules whose
social and moral properties diverge radically in their legal implications.
Nevertheless, jurists may end up endorsing competing claims about the
grounds of (American, English, Roman . . .) law that are more precise (or fine-
grained) than is conceptually warranted for a range of understandable reasons.
Indeterminacy in the concept(s) of law needn’t be obvious.90 And so long as
a candidate precisification of the concept is compatible with the core of legal
practice, it might seem plausible as an account of the concept’s criteria of
application, especially if enough others in the relevant linguistic community
endorse the precisification. It is, thus, possible that participants in theoretical
legal disagreements have competing beliefs about the precise criteria of appli-
cation that ideal reasoners in the jurisdiction – those who reason correctly about
social, moral, linguistic, and perhaps even philosophical matters – will converge
on. This final step in the argument is admittedly speculative, but no more so,
I submit, than any other explanation of persistent theoretical disagreement in the
literature, a phenomenon that may well amount to one of the more challenging
puzzles in legal philosophy. Nevertheless, I hope I’ve demonstrated that the
view we’ve developed has several resources for explaining it.
***
We’ve covered a lot of ground in this final section and so a summary might be
helpful. My primary goal throughout has been to clearly state a pared-down non-
positivist hypothesis about law and ask – both positivists and non-positivists – why
it couldn’t be true. If the view suffers from some obvious flaw, presumably it will
come to light when its core commitments are summarized, and so here they are.
90
Indeterminacy certainly doesn’t follow from the mere fact that officials in a legal system don’t
agree on a precise rule of recognition. Indeed, while it’s quite obvious that socially embraced
higher-order rules of interpretation and adjudication in, say, the American legal system won’t
settle the originalism/nonoriginalism debate (since there is no actual consensus among legal
officials), it is far less obvious whether the concept AMERICAN LAW is similarly indeterminate with
respect to the debate. For reasons I’ve noted, whether and in what ways the concept is
indeterminate turns on more complex considerations than just the actual behavior and commit-
ments of legal officials. It might turn, for instance, on their dispositions to employ legal language
in idealized circumstances of full (social, moral, linguistic . . .) information. Since we don’t have
direct access to such dispositions, the best we can do is formulate a hypothesis about the shared
concept that is then tested for explanatory and theoretical adequacy. Indeed, I’ve argued for
conceptual indeterminacy based primarily on considerations of explanatory power and fit with
a broader conceptual scheme and not the mere fact of actual disagreement.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
66 Philosophy of Law
91
However, we shouldn’t expect a non-normative specification of the ideal to fully capture its
normativity. When a legal system realizes the ideal, the fact that it does is an essentially
normative fact. Admittedly, I’m relying here on my own meta-normative commitments –
specifically, skepticism about reductive accounts of normativity. On the relevance of meta-
normative theory generally, see Section 4.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 67
a rule falls under the concept, users of legal language rely on both social criteria,
such as the rule’s similarity to one derivable from a socially embraced rule of
recognition, as well as normative criteria, such as the rule’s contribution to law’s
normative aspirations. Both properties count in favor of the rule’s legality, but
the contribution each property makes (and what, in aggregate, counts as legal
sufficiency) is indeterminate. Conceptual competence follows from an under-
standing of easy and prototypical cases of law, where the social and normative
properties of rules more or less point in the same direction. Hard cases involving
divergence inspire understandable disagreement, even understandable errors
within a community based on the assumption that the concept of law affords
greater precision. Finally, the general concept of law lends itself to further
specification, with system-specific concepts of AMERICAN LAW or ROMAN LAW,
defined in terms of more fine-grained social and normative criteria of applica-
tion. Moral properties of rules may have greater legal significance in some such
jurisdictions on conceptual grounds alone, and not because a fundamental law
within the system, such as a legal rule of recognition, confers the status of
legality on moral principles.
The resulting view amounts to a moderate strain of legal non-positivism, one
that locates law within a broader conceptual framework involving artifactual,
functional, and goodness-fixing kinds. Its core commitments have been motiv-
ated based on clearly defined desiderata and general features of the broader
explanatory scheme on which it relies. The theory explains why law is suscep-
tible to kind-relative evaluation and why certain characteristics of law are
widely recognized as law’s constitutive virtues, without departing from general
theories of functional and goodness-fixing kinds. It explains, with considerable
neutrality on questions of legal substance and without undermotivated lack of
charity towards legal actors, the contested classification of moral principles as
a form of a priori law, juridical reliance on moral principles in adjudication, and
persistent theoretical disagreement about the grounds of law. The explanation
leverages general truths about our conceptual practices involving artifacts with
normative functions. The overall view has these virtues without insisting on
a counterintuitive correspondence between legal and moral facts, or on a robust
obligation to follow the law wherever there is law, or on law’s moral defects
being essentially legal defects. I don’t mean to suggest that that the view I’ve
sketched has no theoretical costs in comparison to, say, Hartian positivism. In
fact, I’ll address shortly what seems to me to be the most salient cost (shared
with other forms of non-positivism): namely, that the account makes liberal use
of normative concepts as well as an ontology of normative properties and facts.
Additionally, the account is clearly more baroque than Hart’s view, but a view
that is complex in principled ways doesn’t have to be “frilly.” That is, it needn’t
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
68 Philosophy of Law
4 Outstanding Questions
We have considered objections to specific versions of non-positivism as they
have come up. But questions remain that arise regardless of the form a non-
positivist view takes, including the relatively moderate position I outlined at the
end of the previous section. In what follows, I offer a brief discussion of two
important challenges confronting the non-positivist research program. The
discussion is brief because addressing these challenges comprehensively
would take us too far afield and the present goal is limited to identifying lines
of further inquiry.
92
Consider persistent disagreements about the content of the good and the right. Maybe such
disagreements undercut the plausibility of the claim (endorsed by positivists and non-positivists
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 69
alike) that some normative assumptions about law – its reasonableness or authority, say – are
widely shared among officials involved in the production and sustaining of legal orders.
93
Indeed, some versions of non-positivism, such as the dual character theory, seem to me to be
agnostic on whether laws in fact exhibit the moral properties our concepts ascribe to them.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
70 Philosophy of Law
94
For a general discussion of why an error theory about a domain of discourse needn’t undercut the
usefulness or practical point of the discourse, see Burgess (1998).
95
Traditionally, quasi-realists like Blackburn and Gibbard have endeavored to vindicate objectivist
claims in metaethics based on minimalist accounts of the concept of truth and related idioms of
objectivity. See discussion in Salinger (2023). For an alternative approach to the objectivity of
our moral commitments that is, in principle, compatible with quasi-realism, see Atiq (2021:
pp. 14052–14056). For an application of expressivist accounts of normative judgment (but not
quasi-realism) to legal theory, see Toh (2011).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Contemporary Non-Positivism 71
96
In Section 1.3, I identified several authors who make a practical case for positivism. On
“reformist” projects generally and the possibility of “conceptual ethics,” see McPherson and
Plunkett (2024).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
72 Philosophy of Law
systems is richly complex, and that through the study of law in full generality,
we come to have a better grasp on the nature of value-driven artifacts, functions,
group agency, morality, kind-relative evaluation, and interpretation. What
would thus be effective as a critique of our descriptive (rather than practical)
methodology is a demonstration that despite our efforts to be systemic, we
ended up overlooking general features of laws and legal systems that invite
explanation. And the right response to such a critique would be an even more
systematic philosophy of law.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
References
Alexy, R. (2010a). The argument from injustice: A reply to legal positivism
(1st paperback ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.
Alexy, R. (2010b). The dual nature of law. Ratio Juris, 23(2): 167–182.
Alexy, R. (2021). Law’s ideal dimension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Almeida, G. (2023). A dual character theory of law. Journal of Legal
Philosophy, 49: 1–24. https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.4065049.
Atiq, E. H. (2019). Legal obligation & its limits. Law and Philosophy, 38(2):
109–147.
Atiq, E. H. (2020a). There are no easy counterexamples to legal anti-positivism.
Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 17(1): 1–26. https://doi.org/
10.26556/jesp.v17i1.701.
Atiq, E. H. (2020b). Review of natural law and the nature of law. Notre Dame
Philosophical Reviews. https://ndpr.nd.edu/reviews/natural-law-and-the-
nature-of-law/.
Atiq, E. H. (2021). Acquaintance, knowledge, and value. Synthese, 199(5–6):
14035–14062. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03409-9.
Atiq, E. H. (2023). Legal positivism and the moral origins of legal systems.
Canadian Journal of Law & Jurisprudence, 36(1): 37–64. https://doi.org/
10.1017/cjlj.2022.17.
Atiq, E. H. (forthcoming, 2025). Law, the rule of law, and goodness-fixing kinds.
In K. Brownlee, D. Enoch, & A. Marmor (eds.), Engaging Raz: Themes in
normative philosophy. Oxford University Press. https://philpapers.org/rec/
ATILTR.
Atiq, E. H., & Mathews, J. (2022). The uncertain foundations of public law
theory. Cornell Journal of Law & Public Policy, 31: 389–450.
Austin, J. (1832) [1995]. The province of jurisprudence determined,
W. E. Rumble (ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi
.org/10.1017/CBO9780511521546.
Banner, S. (2021). The decline of natural law: How American lawyers once used
natural law and why they stopped (1st ed.). New York: Oxford University
Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780197556498.001.0001.
Barney, R. (2023). Platonic qua-predication. Analytic Philosophy, 65(4):
453–472.
Baude, W., & Sachs, S. (2019). Grounding originalism. Northwestern University
Law Review, 113: 1455–1492.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
74 References
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
References 75
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
76 References
Green, L., & Adams, T. (2019). Legal positivism. In E. N. Zalta (ed.), The
Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/
win2019/entries/legal-positivism/.
Greenberg, M. (2004). How facts make law. Legal Theory, 10(3): 157–198.
https://doi.org/10.1017/S1352325204040212.
Greenberg, M. (2008). Hartian positivism and normative facts: How facts make
law II. In S. Hershovitz (ed.), Exploring law’s empire: The jurisprudence of
Ronald Dworkin, 265–290.
Greenberg, M. (2014). The moral impact theory of law. Yale Law Journal, 123:
1288.
Grey, T. C. (1978). Origins of the unwritten constitution: Fundamental law in
American revolutionary thought. Stanford Law Review, 30(5): 843.
Hamburger, P. A. (1993). Natural rights, natural law, and American
constitutions. Yale Law Journal, 102(4): 907.
Hannikainen, I. R., Tobia, K. P., De Almeida, G. D. F. C. F., et al. (2021). Are
there cross-cultural legal principles? Modal reasoning uncovers procedural
constraints on law. Cognitive Science, 45(8), e13024.
Hart, H. L. A. (1958). Positivism and the separation of law and morals. Harvard
Law Review, 71(4): 593. https://doi.org/10.2307/1338225.
Hart, H. L. A. (1994). The concept of law (2nd ed.). UK: Oxford University
Press.
Hedden, B., & Nebel, J. M. (2024). Multidimensional Concepts and Disparate
Scale Types. Philosophical Review, 133(3): 265–308 .
Helmholz, R. H. (2015). Natural law in court: A history of legal theory in
practice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Hershovitz, S. (2014). The end of jurisprudence. Yale Law Journal, 1234:
882–1345.
Hershovitz, S. (2023). Law is a moral practice. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press.
Hilpinen, R. (1993). Authors and artifacts. Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society, 93: 155–178.
Hirsch, E. (2002). Against revisionary ontology. Philosophical Topics, 30(1):
103–127. https://doi.org/10.5840/philtopics20023013.
Horgan, T., & Timmons, M. (1991). New wave moral realism meets moral twin
earth. Journal of Philosophical Research, 16: 447–465. https://doi.org/
10.5840/jpr_1991_19.
Horwich, P. (2005). Reflections on meaning (1st ed.). Oxford: Oxford
University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/019925124X.001.0001.
Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics: A defence of conceptual
analysis. UK: Oxford University Press.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
References 77
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
78 References
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
References 79
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
80 References
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
References 81
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
82 References
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Acknowledgments
I am grateful to audiences at Columbia University, Cambridge University,
Oxford University, Yale University, and the Philadelphia Normative
Philosophy Conference for their questions and comments on presentations
based on the second and third sections. I received especially helpful feedback
from Rachel Schutz, Bill Watson, Andrei Marmor, Crescente Molina, Amin
Afrouzi, Matthew Kramer, David Enoch, Xi Zhang, Samantha Godwin, Shelly
Kagan, Brian Leiter, Angelo Ryu, and two anonymous reviewers. The editors of
the Cambridge Elements Series in the Philosophy of Law – Kenneth Ehrenberg,
George Pavlakos, and Gerald Postema – are owed a special thanks for their
invitation to contribute to the series. This volume has helped me synthesize my
work in legal philosophy over the last five years. The views I defend in
Sections 2.4 and 3.3 build on observations in Atiq (2019, 2020a), Section 2.1
offers an abridged version of the argument in Atiq (2023), and Section 2.5
summarizes and further develops an argument in Atiq (forthcoming).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Philosophy of Law
Series Editors
George Pavlakos
University of Glasgow
George Pavlakos is Professor of Law and Philosophy at the School of Law, University of
Glasgow. He has held visiting posts at the universities of Kiel and Luzern, the European
University Institute, the UCLA Law School, the Cornell Law School and the Beihang Law
School in Beijing. He is the author of Our Knowledge of the Law (2007) and more recently has
co-edited Agency, Negligence and Responsibility (2021) and Reasons and Intentions in Law
and Practical Agency (2015).
Gerald J. Postema
University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill
Gerald J. Postema is Professor Emeritus of Philosophy at the University of North Carolina at
Chapel Hill. Among his publications count Utility, Publicity, and Law: Bentham’s Moral and
Legal Philosophy (2019); On the Law of Nature, Reason, and the Common Law: Selected
Jurisprudential Writings of Sir Matthew Hale (2017); Legal Philosophy in the Twentieth
Century: The Common Law World (2011), Bentham and the Common Law Tradition, 2nd
edition (2019).
Kenneth M. Ehrenberg
University of Surrey
Kenneth M. Ehrenberg is Professor of Jurisprudence and Philosophy at the University of
Surrey School of Law and Co-Director of the Surrey Centre for Law and Philosophy. He is the
author of The Functions of Law (2016) and numerous articles on the nature of law,
jurisprudential methodology, the relation of law to morality, practical authority, and the
epistemology of evidence law.
Associate Editor
Sally Zhu
University of Sheffield
Sally Zhu is a Lecturer in Property Law at University of Sheffield. Her research is on property
and private law aspects of platform and digital economies.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293
Philosophy of Law
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 189.222.133.103, on 03 Mar 2025 at 09:59:13, subject to the Cambridge Core terms
of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009288293