Emergent Time and Time Travel in Quantum Physics
Emergent Time and Time Travel in Quantum Physics
1 Institut für Physik, Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin, Zum Großen Windkanal 6, 12489 Berlin, Germany
2 Max-Planck-Institut für Gravitationsphysik (Albert-Einstein-Institut), Potsdam Science Park,
Am Mühlenberg 1, 14476 Potsdam, Germany; [email protected]
3 Ústav Teoretické Fyziky, Matematicko-Fyzikální Fakulta, Univerzita Karlova, V Holešovičkách 747/2,
180 00 Praha 8, Czech Republic; [email protected]
4 School of Mathematics and Statistics, Victoria University of Wellington, P.O. Box 600, Wellington 6140,
New Zealand; [email protected]
* Correspondence: [email protected]
† These authors contributed equally to this work.
Abstract: Entertaining the possibility of time travel will invariably challenge dearly held concepts of
arXiv:2312.05202v2 [gr-qc] 27 Feb 2024
fundamental physics. It becomes relatively easy to construct multiple logical contradictions using
differing starting points from various well-established fields of physics. Sometimes, the interpretation
is that only a full theory of quantum gravity will be able to settle these logical contradictions. Even
then, it remains unclear if the multitude of problems could be overcome. Yet as definitive as this
seems to the notion of time travel in physics, such a recourse to quantum gravity comes with its
own, long-standing challenge to most of these counter-arguments to time travel: These arguments
rely on time, while quantum gravity is (in)famously stuck with and dealing with the problem of time.
One attempt to answer this problem within the canonical framework resulted in the Page–Wootters
formalism, and its recent gauge-theoretic re-interpretation—as an emergent notion of time. Herein,
we will begin a programme to study toy models implementing the Hamiltonian constraint in quantum
theory, with an aim towards understanding what an emergent notion of time can tell us about the
(im)possibility of time travel.
Keywords: time travel; quantum gravity; minisuperspace; Page–Wootters formalism; emergent time;
relational dynamics
1. Introduction
As fascinating as the notion of time travel is, its long list of problematic issues—ranging
from the classical [1,2] & [3, p.212ff] to the quantum theoretical [4–7]—presents a very solid
case against it, and its absence is effectively a feature of the universe accessible to human
experience. Yet if one wants to look closely at these arguments, cracks and loopholes
start to appear—many of which shall be mentioned in the following. To an extent, it
Citation: Alonso-Serrano, A.; almost seems as if the best evidence against any notion of time travel is that of our daily
Schuster, S.; Visser, M. Emergent Time experienced notion of time and causality, our intuition. Still, the known universe is bigger
and Time Travel in Quantum Physics. than our day-to-day experience, and particularly the field of high energy physics is ripe
Preprints 2024, 10, 73. with examples experimentally, observationally, or theoretically open to inquiry—in which
https://doi.org/10.3390/universe10020073various concepts or preconceived notions of human-scale physics have to be let go. In no
field of theoretical physics is this more apparent than in the quest for quantum gravity. The
field of contenders is large, and still growing: String theory, loop quantum gravity, quantum
geometrodynamics, asymptotic safety, causal dynamical triangulation, causal set theory,
Copyright: © 2024 by the authors.
Hořava–Lifshitz gravity, . . . Each comes with its own set of new notions beyond what can
Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. be experienced directly by human senses. Yet, these proposals still have to address, in one
This article is an open access article way or another, an issue plaguing quantum gravity from its beginning: Time. This problem
distributed under the terms and of time, and its eventual resolution, then naturally will also impact what these theories have
conditions of the Creative Commons to say about (or against) time travel.
Attribution (CC BY) license (https:// The ‘problem of time’ in classical canonical gravity is settled by a careful, gauge-
creativecommons.org/licenses/by/ theoretic analysis [8] that distinguishes the different rôles played by the Hamiltonian, either
4.0/). in the constraint/gauge fixing or in the definition of observables, respectively. In quantum
2 of 20
gravity, however, the problem of time remains (at the very least) a topic of active discussion
and research [9–11]. The reason for this goes back even before a theory of quantum gravity
was the focus: While there are ways to give position and momentum a meaning in terms
of operators on (rigged) Hilbert spaces in quantum mechanics, this cannot be carried
over to time and energy. This was concerning to researchers in quantum mechanics early
on, as the time-energy uncertainty relations proved to be both reliable and instructive,
while not fitting into the standard paradigm of the Robertson–Schrödinger uncertainty
relations for (generic) Hermitian operators. Only the proof of Mandelstam and Tamm
in 1945 improved this uncertainty relation’s foundation, while begging the question of
why a different approach was needed [12]. Essentially, a series of impossibility results for
time operators canonically conjugate to a Hamiltonian was presented: Schrödinger used
an approach based on normalizability [13], similar to the argument for why plane waves
require a rigged Hilbert space. Pauli, in a footnote, used a simpler argument juxtaposing
discrete spectra and the continuous translation in energy such a time operator would
induce [14,15]. Finally (and in reply to what will be discussed shortly), Unruh and Wald
gave a general argument for semi-bounded Hamiltonians linked to unitarity [16]. Two at
first glance quite distinct approaches were developed in reply to these no-go results.
One approach was similar in spirit to the answer to early counterarguments to plane
waves, e.g., eigenstates of definite position and momentum. While with position and
momentum one relaxes the idea of being restricted to Hilbert space and instead works
in a rigged Hilbert space [17–19], here, when faced with the above-cited no-go results
concerning time operators, one relaxes the idea of Hermiticity. Instead, one introduces the
notion of a positive, operator-valued measure (POVM). It can represent not just perfect
measurements yielding a definite eigenstate, but also imprecise measurements [20]. Besides
allowing one to address the measurement problem in quantum field theory [21], phase
observables [22], or the already mentioned, imprecise measurement processes [20,23]—and
more important for the present context—this allows a notion of time measurement [24].
Since the no-go theorems relate to Hermitian operators, the more general POVMs are not
ruled out as time observables. As we will see, the context of time travel allows one to avoid
these no-go results by other means, too. Still, the bigger picture of gauge theory provides
the most pertinent background for extensions of the model to be described in this paper.
Another approach that developed independently from POVMs was to carefully dis-
tinguish between a clock and time. Paraphrasing Einstein [25], time is meaningful only
after specifying the clock measuring it. Early on, in developing canonical quantum gravity,
DeWitt [26] pointed out how different subsystem’s operators in a given Hamiltonian con-
straint could serve this purpose of an effective clock. Page and Wootters then took this idea
and made it more general and workable, by phrasing time evolution in terms of conditional
probabilities linking different subsystems [27,28].1 This Page–Wootters (PW) formalism
was soon challenged on various grounds by Unruh, Wald [16] and Kuchař [29], leading to
this approach lying dormant for some time.
Recent developments then made the latter approach re-emerge [30–35], and both
approaches converge [36,37]. This also allowed one to address and re-contextualize the
earlier criticisms of the PW formalism [37,38]. In essence, the clocks chosen within the
PW formalism become part of a gauge-theoretic picture of clocks; the ‘physical Hilbert
space’ being a ‘clock-neutral’ picture, and different clocks representing different ‘gauge
conditions’ [37]. These results form part of a larger research programme that aims to
ground the rulers and clocks at least implicitly employed in external symmetries with an
operational underpinning [39–44]. For our purposes below, the key takeaway is that the PW
1 With a bit of hindsight, already Schrödinger anticipated this in his footnote on page 245 of [13] [here, in our
translation and keeping the somewhat convoluted grammar of the original]: “An interesting application of
this is the following: if one knows of a system composed of several, coupled subsystems only the total energy,
then it is impossible to know more about the distribution of energy across the subsystems than the statistical,
time-independent data, which already follows from the knowledge of the total energy. Except for the case that
individual subsystems are in truth fully decoupled, energetically isolated from the others.”
3 of 20
formalism still works, if its defects and the criticisms of it are understood as related to issues
already familiar from electromagnetism: One has to choose whether a calculation should
be gauge-fixed or gauge-independent. Depending on the question at hand, one or the other
will be better suited to calculations or understanding. Our model below will be too simple
to fully showcase these developments, but given the criticisms the PW formalism faced, it
is important to keep the resolution in mind.
Within this special issue’s scope, many other pertinent links of time and time travel to
quantum physics could be made. A selected, non-exhaustive list would include: Deutsch
CTCs and (non/retro-)causal quantum processes [45–49], simulation of time (travel) in
analogues [50–52], semi-classical/quantum stability [4–7,53], et cetera. For the purposes of
this article, however, we would like to highlight only two further research avenues. One
is that of different notions of time. Yet another, non-exhaustive list would include at least
cosmological time, psychological time, parameter time, thermodynamic time, dynamical
versus kinematical time, . . . While this distinction is studied mostly in the context of ‘the
arrow of time’ [54], it is worth pointing out that many counterarguments to time travel
have to rely at least on some conflation of these concepts. To give just one example, if
thermodynamic arguments are brought forth, one needs to establish a more or less direct
relation between the thermodynamic notion implied by the second law2 and the notion
of time invoked in time travel. (This itself does not have to be the same notion as that of
general relativity (GR), where time travel can be identified with closed, time-like curves
(CTCs) or related concepts [56]. In theories other than GR, a different notion of time might
be relevant to describe time travel!)
The other important point to make is that despite all the counterarguments, time
travel is just one notion of many with questionable ‘physicality’ [57]. Even within the
context of GR, other notions of physicality vie for validity with the absence of time travel,
for example, various kinds of completeness (geodesic, hole free, . . . ) or the validity of
various kinds of energy conditions. These notions, however, are not all compatible with
each other [58–63]. One might find oneself in the uncomfortable situation that a dearly
held and important property (stability, completeness, fulfilled energy conditions, . . . ) will
require time travel to be permitted; and this just within GR. Other theories are unlikely
to be free from such problems, especially as many of the comforting no-go theorems are
specifically proven within the context of GR. It it therefore not surprising that in the context
of classical field theories of gravity alone, there exist many different ways to realize time
travel. This includes wormholes [3,64], warp drives [65], cosmologies [66–69], maximally
extended space-times (such as Kerr near the central ring singularity) [70], and various
more mathematical construction techniques [71–73]. The latter can also be employed
to distinguish between, for example, time travel (CTCs) and time machines (whatever
structure creates or causes CTCs) [59,60,73].
This finally brings us to the goal of this paper: We want to study what can be said
about the viability of time travel if time itself is only an emergent concept, as in the PW
formalism. Concretely, we will be studying an example of two non-interacting harmonic
oscillators similarly constrained to a fixed total energy of zero as in a Wheeler–DeWitt
(WDW) equation, i.e., it will mimic a minisuperspace model of time travel. This toy
model is by no means meant to exhibit an exhaustive description of whether and how
time travel can arise in the PW formalism. Nor should this model be taken literally as
a minisuperspace model, as no gravitational model is canonically quantized to arrive
at it; rather it demonstrates possible phenomenology. We will see that the results in
our toy model point to an extraordinarily bland version of Novikov’s self-consistency
conjecture [74–76].
2 One would also have to brush aside that standard thermodynamics has to artificially graft time onto its
formalism in the first place, leading to the very name ‘thermodynamics’ being rather unintuitive compared to
other occurrences of ‘dynamics’ in physical terminology [55].
4 of 20
1.1. Outline
Following the preceding introduction to and overview of the related research question
in section 1, we will provide an introduction into the methods employed: In section 2, we
briefly summarize the PW formalism. In section 3 we demonstrate POVM’s utility for
implementing time observables in the context of a single harmonic oscillator. The main
part of the paper is employing these concepts then, in section 4, to two harmonic oscillators
subjected to a WDW-like Hamiltonian constraint equation. We close by discussing our
results and pointing out future directions and open questions in section 5. Finally, the
appendices collect additional details and context: Appendix A reviews the mathematical
definition of a POVM, appendix B collects results concerning periodic time in the quantum
harmonic oscillator that supplement the discussion of section 3.1, while appendix C gives
additional details concerning the construction of the paper’s figures.
We will use natural units in which G = h̄ = c = 1.
H = HC ⊗ HR . (1)
where |Ψ⟩ is a state in the total Hilbert space H. In line with Schrödinger’s 1931 footnote,
this state |Ψ⟩ is required to be in a definite, fixed eigenstate of Ĥ with total energy E. More
generally, the PW formalism remains viable even for density matrices ρ̂, with the above
case regained by setting ρ̂ = |Ψ⟩ ⟨Ψ|.
Examples of such systems usually are constructed by symmetry-reducing the WDW
equation of quantum gravity, the quantized Hamiltonian constraint of GR:
Ĥ |Ψ⟩ = 0. (3)
In this expression, we gloss over many technicalities (such as operator ordering, domain
issues, topological concerns, configuration space considerations, . . . ) [19,26,77], as our
focus lies less on quantum gravity and more on the emergent notion of time that the PW
formalism provides. Still, we will occasionally take inspiration from quantum gravity. In
particular, one can consider our final model to be a crude example of a minisuperspace
model that has not been found through symmetry reduction. Already here, we therefore
want to point out that many questions the minisuperspace models of quantum black holes
or quantum cosmology try to answer, will not and cannot appear in our context. Most
5 of 20
This corresponds to the familiar idea of unitary time evolution of states in the Schrödinger
picture through a Hamiltonian, but—at this level of the discussion, anyway—is a defin-
ition. The Schrödinger or Heisenberg equations of motion would then be a result of this
approach [27,36].
The evolution of the subsystem ĤR is then evaluated in terms of relative probabilities
with respect to these clock states. To do this, let us first define the projector
P̂θ∗ := (|ψ(θ∗ )⟩ C C
⟨ψ(θ∗ )|) ⊗ 1R (5)
of a given state onto particular ‘clock time states’ |ψ(θ∗ )⟩ C in H C , leaving states in H R
unchanged. Then the evolution in H R by ĤR with respect to clock states is given by the
expression
tr ĤR P̂θ∗ ρ̂
E( ĤR |θ∗ ) = . (6)
tr P̂θ∗ ρ̂
This gives the conditional expectation value of the residual Hamiltonian ĤR when the clock
(state) ‘reads’ θ∗ . The technical requirements behind this interpretation are stationarity,
and commutativity of ĤR and ĤC , which we enforced by the block structure of Ĥ encoded
in equation (2). These assumptions are quite strong, especially once one wants to include
an interaction Hamiltonian coupling H C and H R on the right hand side of equation (2).
Given the recent clarification on this issue provided by [30,31,36,37], we want to return to
such generalizations at a later point, but stick to these more restrictive assumptions in the
present context.
Some general comments are appropriate at this point: First, fixing the initial, total
state |Ψ⟩ can, in general, greatly change the time evolution as described by equation (6).
Second, to reiterate: This is not the most sophisticated or modern implementation of the
PW formalism, see the previous paragraph. Third, without further specifying a particular
system comprised of the various Hamiltonians present in equation (2), we cannot even
begin our investigation. This holds true for the sort of time evolution people expect—one
without time travel—just as well as for the more unexpected time evolution—showcasing
a notion of time travel. The next step will be to lay the groundwork for our toy model,
specifying the state and the evolution.
Instead, we will try to find a way to implement the simplest possible version of
time travel. This is (Novikov) self-consistency. When the clock returns to a state, so
will the remainder system return to the same state it had when the clock last was in this
state. This situation can (at least in some systems and models) also yield existence results,
though usually at the expense of uniqueness [76,78–81]. So far, however, the PW formalism
as presented here does not allow for this. The evolution of the clock as prescribed by
equation (4) is ignorant of the domain from which to draw θ∗ .
In order to alleviate this problem, we will borrow concepts from the POVM approach
to time operators already mentioned in the introduction, and to be discussed in more detail
in the next section. In order to incorporate this in the PW formalism, we note that the key
ingredient for comparing the evolution of the clock with that of the remainder system is
encoded in the definition of the projector onto clock states, equation (5). The goal, thus, will
be to not only influence the clock evolution through a convenient choice of the global state
|Ψ⟩. Rather, we also will have to make a judicious choice of the clock states themselves,
and how to identify them in a meaningful way.
We want to construct a time operator for this. In order to do so, we look at the polar
decomposition of the ladder operator â, [85, Thm. VIII.32]:
â = Ŵ |c
a |. (9)
Here, |c
a| is easy to define as √
a| := n̂1/2 =
|c ↠â. (10)
The ‘operator’ Ŵ, however, is less simple than its occurrence in a ‘polar decomposition’
might suggest: It will not be unitary. More concretely [22]:
Ŵ Ŵ † = 1, (11)
but
Ŵ † Ŵ = 1 − |0⟩⟨0| ̸= 1. (12)
The phase or time states to be used are now constructed as eigenstates |θ ⟩ of Ŵ.
Ŵ |θ ⟩ = eiθ |θ ⟩ . (13)
While these eigenstates do exist, given the properties of Ŵ, they are now only an overcomplete
set of eigenstates.3 So different eigenstates |θ ⟩ and |θ ′ ⟩ will not be orthogonal, and express-
ing a general state |ψ⟩ in terms of these eigenstates will not be unique anymore. Each of
these states |θ ⟩ can be written as
Now is the time to define a concrete POVM. In this instance, let us define for all Borel
sets X of [0, 2π )
1
Z
B0 ( X ) := |θ ⟩⟨θ | dθ, (15)
2π X
1
Z
= ∑ 2π X
ei(n−m)θ |n⟩⟨m| dθ. (16)
n,m≥0
The index 0 is a first indication of what is to come: Different points on the unit circle S1
can be chosen as starting points. In the above definition, one starts on the positive real
axis, i.e., we choose our angle θ from [0, 2π ), as opposed to say from [θ∗ , θ∗ + 2π ) for some
θ∗ ∈ [0, 2π ).
Using
Z 2π
1
ei(n−m)θ dθ = δnm (17)
2π o
and
∞
∑ |n⟩⟨n| = 1 (18)
n =0
3 Such overcomplete states find ample application in, for example, the context of coherent states [23].
8 of 20
This means that the system Hamiltonian ĤR and the clock Hamiltonian ĤC are part of
a WDW-like equation. Naturally, this implies that it falls into the framework of the PW
formalism for a stationary Hamilton equation Ĥ |Ψ⟩ = E |Ψ⟩ with energy E = 0.
The previous two sections gave us the two most important ingredients in place: First,
the way to measure time evolution with respect to a clock system using the PW formalism’s
conditional probability (6). Second, the required clock states given by equation (13) with
respect to which we will measure evolution, and its representation in terms of the harmonic
oscillator eigenstates, equation (14). Now, we can make use of it by implementing the
Hamiltonian constraint (20) into this model. What remains to be done, though, is to specify
more explicitly the type of total state |Ψ⟩ ∈ H the ‘universe’ (as described by Ĥ) is in.
such as the precise nature of the inner product on the quantum gravitational wavefunctions,
as already discussed in [26, §9]. Two extremal options for inner products (with many in
between) are a quantum harmonic oscillator on the one side and a wave equation on the
other. We assume the inner product structure as the one familiar from and resulting in
standard quantum mechanics. Naturally, this leads to many directions into which to extend
our present model, and we will come back to these in our concluding section 5.
In conclusion and in conscious distinction to quantum cosmology, our toy model (20)
for time travel will be treated using a ladder operator approach of quantum mechanics.
This allows us to use the methods introduced in the previous two section, and hopefully
also provides easy extensions in diverse directions.
ωR 2n C + 1
= , where n C , n R ∈ N0 , (21)
ωC 2n R + 1
will this be possible. This commensurability condition will have far-reaching consequences
for our simple toy model in what is to come.4 In fact, these results will (for this toy model,
at least) be so far reaching, that the precise nature of the time operators employed or their
respective states used as initial state of the clock becomes immaterial. The interested reader
can find more details on a possible choice of time operators useful for the current purposes
in appendix B.
Quite generally, the wave function of the ‘universe’, |Ψ⟩, will have the following form:
Our calculation will proceed in three steps based on this general form.
1. The simplest possibility is a diagonal An,n′ . We will demonstrate that this leads, at
least according to the PW formalism, to the simplest time evolution possible. We will
demonstrate how this time evolution can be interpreted as a particularly boring case
of the Novikov self-consistency conjecture.
2. We derive a quite general statement about An,n′ when it is non-diagonal. Concretely,
introducing two sparse matrices ∆1 , ∆2 and a diagonal matrix D, it will take the form
3. A general identity for the conditional probabilities (6) in our toy model is derived.
4. Using the previous two steps, we will prove that the results of the first step carry over
to non-diagonal An,n′ , too.
In the first step, let us calculate the components of equation (6). This will tell us
straightforwardly what we want to know.
4 Deviating from the commensurability condition even a little would lead to non-normalizable wave functions.
In the context of quantum cosmology such wave functions can be encountered, such as the no-boundary
proposal [77, p.282]. For the sake of our (not necessarily gravitational) toy model, we believe that this would
add another layer of interpretational problems best left for a separate study.
10 of 20
With the currently assumed diagonal form for An,n′ , we can evaluate
1
(1C ⊗ ĤR ) |Ψ⟩ = ∑ An n + |n⟩C ⊗ |n⟩R , (26)
n 2
and, after a similar lead-up, likewise for the denominator of equation (6) that
tr P̂θ∗ ρ̂ = tr P̂0∗ ρ̂ . (31)
This equation gives additional insight about the coefficients An,n′ . In components, we can
write
∞
An,n′ = ∑ δn,s(2p+1)+ p ds δn′ ,s(2q+1)+q (36)
s =0
where D really is diagonal and ∆1 , ∆2 are sparse matrices connecting s with n and n′ ,
respectively.
The third step takes a look at the numerator of the conditional probability of the PW
formalism, equation (6). Note that equation (25) is fully general, and needed no diagonality
of An,n′ in its derivation. Its last two factors can now be evaluated with our general
ansatz (22):
1
(1C ⊗ ĤR ) |Ψ⟩ = ∑ An,n′ n′ + |n⟩ C ⊗ |n′ ⟩ R . (38)
n,n ′ 2
As in the first step, we can then use orthonormality of the Fock states |n′ ⟩ C , R and cyclicity
of the trace to show that
1
tr ĤR P̂θ∗ ρ̂ = ∑ C ⟨m|ψ(θ∗ )⟩ C Am,n′
∗ ′
An,n′ n + ⟨ψ(θ∗ )|n⟩C . (39)
m,n,n′
2 C
C
⟨m|ψ(θ∗ )⟩C = C ⟨m| e−i ĤC θ∗ |ψ(0∗ )⟩C , (40)
−i (m+ 12 )θ∗
=e C
⟨m|ψ(0∗ )⟩C . (41)
∑ Qm,n e+i(n−m)θ∗
tr ĤR P̂θ∗ ρ̂ = (42)
m,n
12 of 20
where " # !
Qm,n := ∑′ A∗m,n′ An,n′ (n′ + 1/2) C
⟨m|ψ(0∗ )⟩C C ⟨ψ(0∗ )|n⟩C (43)
n
This effectively demonstrates how the choice of the universe’s state |Ψ⟩ and the chosen
initial clock state |ψ(0∗ )⟩ C together fully determine the time evolution of our model. Equa-
tion (43) can equivalenty be expressed in ‘matrix form’ as
Note that this is again of the form (42), though with a simpler ‘Q’ for which D0 = 1. This
means any general statement that can be shown for Q will hold for the corresponding part
appearing in equation (45).
In our fourth and final step, we shall bring together our result (37) for An,n′ and
the result (44) for Qm,n to greatly constrain the conditional probabilities of equation (6).
Concretely, inserting the former into the latter gives:
In this expression, let us investigate the central, bracketed term, ∆1∗ D0 ∆1T :
∆1∗ D0 ∆1T = ∑ δn′ ,s(2q+1)+q [ D0 ]n′ δn′ ,s′ (2q+1)+q , (48)
ss′
n′
=: ( D3/2 )ss′ , (49)
another diagonal matrix. This in turn means that even more terms in the middle of
equation (47) reduce to yet another diagonal matrix D2 , defined as
whose middle part in brackets can, using the same approach as in equation (48), be shown
to be diagonal. Finally, it follows that Q itself is diagonal.
Essential for this result was the specific form of A, equation (37). Modifying the
underlying model will therefore likely change this result. For the PW formalism in our
context, though, the result is far-reaching: If we take equation (42), we see that for diagonal
Q, the term ei(n−m)θ∗ = 1, as n = m. The same observation holds for the denominator of
the PW conditional probabilities (6), equation (45). So, as in our first step when considering
diagonal An,n′ , even the general case produces trivial time evolution.
At first glance, this seems a very unremarkable result, and therefore of little use for any
interesting physics question. Ironically, this is not the case in our present situation, in which
we are discussing time travel: An evolution that is simply constant is certainly still trivially
a case of Novikov’s self-consistency conjecture. Given that nothing is happening, one
might even go so far as to say that it gives an odd entry to the intersection of the Novikov
13 of 20
self-consistency conjecture and the ‘boring physics conjecture’ [3]. It is simultaneously both
time travel and the absence of all evolution.
This result is also a marked departure from results in quantum cosmology [89,92]. The
reason for this disparity is the limited domain of the scale parameter in the models of the
form (20). Most importantly, limiting a harmonic oscillator to half of its configuration space
will prevent the application of ladder operators as we used them in the above analysis. This
again demonstrates how ‘simple’ changes to the model can quite radically change results.
Once the model systems for time travel are complex enough (and, thus, more complex
than our equation (20)), a natural question is: What happens to time travel in such
quantum reference frame transformations? And, linking to the previous point, does
this differ from the situation for merely periodic clocks?
• Lastly, the previous two points hint at the possibility of making time travel more a
local, emergent notion in a large system. This is, for one, the explicit way to study
time travel classically as CTCs in a space-time manifold, see, for example, [59,81]. For
another, this is similarly done in quantum physics, ranging from the rigorously and
explicitly local [46,97] to the more imprecise and only implicitly local [45,98]. Yet, so
far, these approaches all had to rely on an ad-hoc introduction of ‘background’ time.
There are other avenues along similar lines that warrant a closer look in the framework
of quantum gravity. In the canonical approach to it, for instance, different inner products
can be considered, so at least changing the mathematical framework drastically—begging
the question how much of the physical interpretation changes or has to change in tandem.
Other approaches to quantum gravity besides the canonical ones can also test emergent
notions of time in their respective frameworks. Besides a question of tractability, this was
part of the motivation to keep our toy model somewhat agnostic and conservative with
respect to a theory of quantum gravity.
Independent of which direction one would want to take, we believe that our first
result shows that emergent notions of time in quantum physics can lead to a multitude of
questions and interpretational conundra pertaining to time travel. The very introduction
of such an emergent time concepts undermines most traditional arguments against time
travel. The concepts evoked in these arguments simply have to rely on notions that are not
valid in more ab initio approaches.
Funding: A.A.-S. is funded by the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG, German Research
Foundation) — Project ID 516730869. This work was also partially supported by Spanish Project No.
MICINN PID2020-118159GB-C44. S.S. was financially supported by Czech Science Foundation grant
GACR 23-07457S. M.V. was directly supported by the Marsden Fund, via a grant administered by the
Royal Society of New Zealand.
Data Availability Statement: No new data were created or analyzed in this study. Data sharing is
not applicable to this article.
Acknowledgments: S.S. acknowledges support from the technical and administrative staff at the
Charles University. He thanks Emily Adlam, Antonis Antoniou, Julian Barbour, Martin Bojowald,
Leonardo Chataignier, Fabio Costa, Ricardo Faleiro, Klaus Fredenhagen, Philipp A. Höhn, Claus
Kiefer, Jorma Louko, Jessica Santiago, Alexander R. H. Smith, Reinhard Werner, Magdalena Zych, and
the participants of the 781st WE-Heraeus-Seminar ‘Time and Clocks’ in Bad Honnef, the Geometric
Foundations of Gravity 2023 conference in Tartu, the 13th RQI-North meeting in Chania, and the
Odborné soustředění ÚTF in Světlá pod Blaníkem for many valuable discussions and their interest.
Conflicts of Interest: The authors declare no conflict of interest. The funders had no rôle in the design
of the study; in the collection, analyses, or interpretation of data; in the writing of the manuscript; or
in the decision to publish the results.
Abbreviations
The following abbreviations are used in this paper:
This procedure fixes the set X in the original POVM B0 , and then uses it to construct
various Toeplitz operators. Different choices for f can be found in the literature (see, for
example, [83]), but we will focus on one of the simplest options:
f (θ ) = θ. (A4)
This will give us a time operator T̂0 , which we calculate with the above expressions to be
1
T̂0 = B̂0 [θ ] = ∑ i ( n − m)
|n⟩⟨m| + π1. (A5)
n ̸ = m ≥0
However, this operator is not unique. First of all, we could have chosen a different
starting point for our angles, changing the index 0 at that point. There is also a different,
but more physically motivated point of arriving at additional time operators. The time
operator T̂0 can be covariantly shifted to a new operator T̂θ∗ :
This covariant shift property is a general feature of such time operators from POVMs, see [24],
that is increasingly prominent and clear in their modern implementations [37,99]. Import-
antly, while all such T̂θ∗ fulfil canonical commutation relations with Ĥ (when the resulting
operator is well-defined), different time operators will not commute with each other:
These results deserve some commentary. The reason why these time operators are
still self-adjoint, despite the illustrious list of no-go theorems given in the introduction,
is two-fold [24]: One, they are hardly unique. Any change in starting point (phase) will
yield a different time operator. A covariant shift similarly yields new time operators. Two,
the domain of time is now periodic. The no-go theorems usually aim for R as domain for
time θ, or that the time would be unique in some sense. In the present context, it is more a
question of when one started the periodic clock, and what period the clock has. It is also
worth pointing out that our time operators subtly fail to satisfy the expected time-energy
uncertainty: It will not hold for all states in H, but only for a densely defined set [83,84].
This latter restriction is not an issue for our purposes, at least in the present article, and
the other reasons for evading the no-go theorems are what allows our application in the
context of time travel.
where Hn ( x ) is the n-th Hermite polynomial and the expansion coefficients are
s ! s !n !
1 2β χ20 1 − β2 χ0
cn = √ exp − Hn . (A9)
1 + β2 2(1 + β2 ) 1 + β2
p
2n n! 1 − β4
These coefficients cn simplify further for the ‘coherent case’, i.e., when β = 1, to
χn
1 2
cn = exp − χ0 √ 0 . (A10)
4 2n n!
Note that the index m in equation (A8) is meant to make more explicit that the sum runs
only over even n.
References
1. Roman, T.A. Inflating Lorentzian wormholes. Physical Review D 1993, 47, 1370–1379, [arXiv:gr-qc/9211012 [gr-qc]]. https:
//doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.47.1370.
17 of 20
2. Krasnikov, S. No time machines in classical general relativity. Classical and Quantum Gravity 2002, 19, 4109–4129, [arXiv:gr-
qc/0111054 [gr-qc]]. Erratum in Classical and Quantum Gravity 2014 31(7), 079503. https://doi.org/10.1088/0264-9381/31/7/079
503, https://doi.org/10.1088/0264-9381/19/15/316.
3. Visser, M. Lorentzian Wormholes: From Einstein to Hawking; AIP Series in Computational and Applied Mathematical Physics,
American Institute of Physics, 1996.
4. Hawking, S.W. Chronology protection conjecture. Physical Review D 1992, 46, 603–611. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.46.603.
5. Klinkhammer, G. Vacuum polarization of scalar and spinor fields near closed null geodesics. Physical Review D 1992, 46, 3388–3394.
https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.46.3388.
6. Visser, M. From wormhole to time machine: Remarks on Hawking’s chronology protection conjecture. Physical Review D 1993,
47, 554–565, [arXiv:hep-th/9202090 [hep-th]]. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.47.554.
7. Emparan, R.; Tomašević, M. Quantum backreaction on chronology horizons. Journal of High Energy Physics 2022, 02, 182,
[arXiv:2109.03611 [hep-th]]. https://doi.org/10.1007/JHEP02(2022)182.
8. Pons, J.M.; Sundermeyer, K.A.; Salisbury, D.C. Observables in classical canonical gravity: folklore demystified. Journal of Physics:
Conference Series 2010, 222, 012018, [arXiv:1001.2726 [gr-qc]]. https://doi.org/10.1088/1742-6596/222/1/012018.
9. Anderson, E. The Problem of Time; Vol. 190, Fundamental Theories of Physics, Springer, 2017. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-58
848-3.
10. Gioia, F.D.; Maniccia, G.; Montani, G.; Niedda, J. Non-Unitarity Problem in Quantum Gravity Corrections to Quantum Field
Theory with Born-Oppenheimer Approximation. Physical Review D 2021, 103, 103511, [arXiv:1912.09945 [gr-qc]]. https:
//doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.103.103511.
11. Kiefer, C.; Peter, P. Time in Quantum Cosmology. Universe 2022, 8, 36, [arXiv:2112.05788 [gr-qc]]. https://doi.org/10.3390/
universe8010036.
12. Mandelstam, L.I.; Tamm, I.Y. The uncertainty relation between energy and time in nonrelativistic quantum mechanics. Journal
of Physics 1945, IX, 249–254. English translation of Л. И. Мандельштам, И. Е. Тамм “Соотношение неопределённости
энергия-время внерелятивистской квантовой механике”, Изв. Дкад. Наук СССР (сер. физ.) 9, 122–128 (1945).
13. Schrödinger, E. Spezielle Relativitätstheorie und Quantenmechanik. Sitzungsberichte der Preußischen Akademie der Wissenschaften.
Physikalisch-mathematische Klasse 1931, pp. 238–247.
14. Pauli, W. Die allgemeinen Prinzipien der Wellenmechanik; Springer, 1990. Neu herausgegeben und mit historischen Anmerkungen
versehen von Norbert Straumann, https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-62187-9.
15. Pauli, W. General Principles of Quantum Mechanics; Springer, 1980. English translation of [14], https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-
61840-6.
16. Unruh, W.G.; Wald, R.M. Time and the interpretation of canonical quantum gravity. Physical Review D 1989, 40, 2598–2614.
https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.40.2598.
17. Böhm, A. Quantum Mechanics – Foundations and Applications, third ed.; Springer, 1993.
18. de la Madrid, R.; Böhm, A.; Gadella, M. Rigged Hilbert Space Treatment of Continuous Spectrum. Fortschritte der Physik 2002,
50, 185–216, [quant-ph/0109154]. https://doi.org/10.1002/1521-3978(200203)50:2<185::AID-PROP185>3.0.CO;2-S.
19. Thiemann, T. Modern Canonical Quantum General Relativity; Cambridge Monographs on Mathematical Physics, Cambridge
University Press, 2008.
20. Busch, P.; Lahti, P.; Pellonpää, J.P.; Ylinen, K. Quantum Measurement; Theoretical and Mathematical Physics, Springer, 2016.
21. Fewster, C.J.; Verch, R. Quantum Fields and Local Measurements. Communications in Mathematical Physics 2020, 378, 851–889,
[arXiv:1810.06512 [math-ph]]. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00220-020-03800-6.
22. Busch, P.; Grabowski, M.; Lahti, P.J. Who Is Afraid of POV Measures? Unified Approach to Quantum Phase Observables. Annals
of Physics 1995, 237, 1–11. https://doi.org/10.1006/aphy.1995.1001.
23. Auletta, G.; Fortunato, M.; Parisi, G. Quantum Mechanics; Cambridge University Press, 2009.
24. Busch, P.; Grabowski, M.; Lahti, P.J. Time observables in quantum theory. Physics Letters A 1994, 191, 357–361. https:
//doi.org/10.1016/0375-9601(94)90785-4.
25. Einstein, A. Zur Elektrodynamik bewegter Körper. Annalen der Physik 1905, 322, 891–921. https://doi.org/10.1002/andp.190532
21004.
26. DeWitt, B.S. Quantum Theory of Gravity. 1. The Canonical Theory. Physical Review 1967, 160, 1113–1148. https://doi.org/10.110
3/PhysRev.160.1113.
27. Page, D.N.; Wootters, W.K. Evolution without evolution: Dynamics described by stationary observables. Physical Review D 1983,
27, 2885–2892. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.27.2885.
28. Wootters, W.K. “Time” replaced by quantum correlations. International Journal of Theoretical Physics 1984, 23, 701–711. https:
//doi.org/10.1007/BF02214098.
29. Kuchař, K.V. Time and Interpretations of Quantum Gravity. International Journal of Modern Physics D 2011, 20, 3–86. Contribution
to: 4th Canadian Conference on General Relativity and Relativistic Astrophysics, https://doi.org/10.1142/S0218271811019347.
30. Giovannetti, V.; Lloyd, S.; Maccone, L. Quantum Time. Physical Review D 2015, 92, 045033, [arXiv:1504.04215 [quant-ph]].
https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.92.045033.
31. Marletto, C.; Vedral, V. Evolution without evolution, and without ambiguities. Physical Review D 2017, 95, 043510,
[arXiv:1610.04773 [quant-ph]]. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.95.043510.
18 of 20
32. Diaz, N.L.; Rossignoli, R. History state formalism for Dirac’s theory. Physical Review D 2019, 99, 045008, [arXiv:1806.01472
[quant-ph]]. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.99.045008.
33. Diaz, N.L.; Matera, J.M.; Rossignoli, R. History state formalism for scalar particles. Physical Review D 2019, 100, 125020,
[arXiv:1910.04004 [quant-ph]]. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.100.125020.
34. Diaz, N.L.; Matera, J.M.; Rossignoli, R. Spacetime quantum actions. Physical Review D 2021, 103, 065011, [arxiv:quant-
ph/2010.09136]. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.103.065011.
35. Gemsheim, S.; Rost, J.M. Emergence of Time from Quantum Interaction with the Environment. Physical Review Letters 2023,
131, 140202, [arXiv:2309.05159 [quant-ph]]. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevLett.131.140202.
36. Smith, A.R.H.; Ahmadi, M. Quantizing time: Interacting clocks and systems. Quantum 2019, 3, 160, [arXiv:1712.00081 [quant-ph]].
https://doi.org/10.22331/q-2019-07-08-160.
37. Höhn, P.A.; Smith, A.R.H.; Lock, M.P.E. The Trinity of Relational Quantum Dynamics. Physical Review D 2021, 104, 066001,
[arXiv:1912.00033 [quant-ph]]. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.104.066001.
38. Höhn, P.A.; Smith, A.R.H.; Lock, M.P.E. Equivalence of Approaches to Relational Quantum Dynamics in Relativistic Settings.
Frontiers in Physics 2021, 9, 181, [arXiv:2007.00580 [gr-qc]]. https://doi.org/10.3389/fphy.2021.587083.
39. Krumm, M.; Höhn, P.A.; Müller, M.P. Quantum reference frame transformations as symmetries and the paradox of the third
particle. Quantum 2021, 5, 530, [arXiv:2011.01951 [quant-ph]]. https://doi.org/10.22331/q-2021-08-27-530.
40. Goeller, C.; Höhn, P.A.; Kirklin, J. Diffeomorphism-invariant observables and dynamical frames in gravity: reconciling bulk
locality with general covariance 2022. [arXiv:2206.01193 [hep-th]].
41. Adlam, E. Watching the Clocks: Interpreting the Page–Wootters Formalism and the Internal Quantum Reference Frame
Programme. Foundations of Physics 2022, 52, 99, [arXiv:2203.06755 [physics.hist-ph]]. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-022-00620-7.
42. Höhn, P.A.; Russo, A.; Smith, A.R.H. Matter relative to quantum hypersurfaces 2023. [arXiv:2308.12912 [quant-ph]].
43. Hausmann, L.; Schmidhuber, A.; Castro-Ruiz, E. Measurement events relative to temporal quantum reference frames 2023.
[arXiv:2308.10967 [quant-ph]].
44. Höhn, P.A.; Kotecha, I.; Mele, F.M. Quantum Frame Relativity of Subsystems, Correlations and Thermodynamics 2023.
[arXiv:2308.09131 [quant-ph]].
45. Deutsch, D. Quantum mechanics near closed timelike lines. Physical Review A 1991, 44, 3197–3217. https://doi.org/10.1103/
PhysRevD.44.3197.
46. Bishop, L.G.; Costa, F.; Ralph, T.C. Time-travelling billiard-ball clocks: a quantum model. Physical Review A 2021, 103, 042223,
[arXiv:2007.12677 [quant-ph]]. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevA.103.042223.
47. Baumann, V.; Krumm, M.; Guérin, P.A.; Časlav Brukner. Noncausal Page–Wootters circuits. Physical Review Research 2022,
4, 013180, [arXiv:2105.02304 [quant-ph]]. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevResearch.4.013180.
48. Vilasini, V. Approaches to causality and multi-agent paradoxes in non-classical theories. PhD thesis, University of York, 2021,
[arXiv:2102.02393 [quant-ph]].
49. Adlam, E. Two roads to retrocausality. Synthese 2022, 200, 422, [arXiv:2201.12934 [physics.hist-ph]]. https://doi.org/10.1007/s1
1229-022-03919-0.
50. Jannes, G. Condensed matter lessons about the origin of time. Foundations of Physics 2015, 45, 279–294, [arXiv:0904.3627 [gr-qc]].
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-014-9864-3.
51. Barceló, C.; Sánchez, J.E.; García-Moreno, G.; Jannes, G. Chronology protection implementation in analogue gravity. European
Physical Journal C 2022, 82, 299, [2201.11072]. https://doi.org/10.1140/epjc/s10052-022-10275-3.
52. Sabín, C. Analogue Non-Causal Null Curves and Chronology Protection in a dc-SQUID Array. Universe 2022, 8, 452, [arXiv:quant-
ph/2207.14164]. https://doi.org/10.3390/universe8090452.
53. Visser, M. The reliability horizon for semi-classical quantum gravity: Metric fluctuations are often more important than
back-reaction. Physics Letters B 1997, 415, 8–14, [arXiv:gr-qc/9702041 [gr-qc]]. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0370-2693(97)01226-4.
54. Zeh, H.D. The Physical Basis of the Direction of Time, fifth ed.; The Frontiers Collection, Springer, 2007. https://doi.org/10.1007/97
8-3-540-68001-7.
55. Truesdell, C. Tragicomedy of Classical Thermodynamics; Springer, 1971.
56. Minguzzi, E.; Sánchez, M. The causal hierarchy of spacetimes. In Recent developments in pseudo-Riemannian geometry; Baum, H.;
Alekseevsky, D., Eds.; EMS Publishing House, 2006; p. 299–358, [arXiv:gr-qc/0609119 [gr-qc]].
57. Schuster, S. Frenemies with Physicality: Manufacturing Manifold Metrics, [arXiv:2305.08725 [gr-qc]]. Essay written for the
Gravity Research Foundation 2023 Awards for Essays on Gravitation.
58. Barceló, C.; Visser, M. Twilight for the energy conditions? International Journal of Modern Physics D 2002, 11, 1553–1560,
[arXiv:gr-qc/0205066 [gr-qc]]. https://doi.org/10.1142/S0218271802002888.
59. Earman, J.; Smeenk, C.; Wüthrich, C. Do the laws of physics forbid the operation of time machines? Synthese 2009, 169, 91–124.
https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-008-9338-2.
60. Manchak, J.B. On the Existence of “Time Machines” in General Relativity. Philosophy of Science 2009, 76, 1020–1026. https:
//doi.org/10.1086/605806.
61. Manchak, J.B. Some “No Hole” Spacetime Properties are Unstable. Foundations of Physics 2018, 48, 1539–1545. https://doi.org/10
.1007/s10701-018-0211-y.
19 of 20
62. Manchak, J.B. General Relativity as a Collection of Collections of Models. In Hajnal Andréka and István Németi on the Unity
of Science: From Computing to Relativity Theory Through Algebraic Logic; Madarász, J.; Székely, G., Eds.; Springer, 2021; Vol. 19,
Outstanding Contributions to Logic, chapter 19, pp. 409–425. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-64187-0_17.
63. Santiago, J.; Schuster, S.; Visser, M. Generic warp drives violate the null energy condition. Physical Review D 2022, 105, 064038,
[arXiv:2105.03079 [gr-qc]]. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.105.064038.
64. González-Díaz, P.F.; Alonso-Serrano, A. Observing other universe through ringholes and Klein-bottle holes. Physical Review D
2011, 84, 023008, [arXiv:1102.3784 [astro-ph.CO]]. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.84.023008.
65. Everett, A.E. Warp drive and causality. Physical Review D 1996, 53, 7365. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.53.7365.
66. Gödel, K. An Example of a New Type of Cosmological Solutions of Einstein’s Field Equations of Gravitation. Review of Modern
Physics 1949, 21, 447–450. https://doi.org/10.1103/RevModPhys.21.447.
67. Hawking, S.W.; Ellis, G.F.R. The large scale structure of space-time; Cambridge Monographs on Mathematical Physics, Cambridge
University Press, 1974. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511524646.
68. Griffiths, J.B.; Podolský, J. Exact Space-Times in Einstein’s General Relativity, first paperback ed.; Cambridge Monographs on
Mathematical Physics, Cambridge University Press, 2012.
69. Gray, F.; Santiago, J.; Schuster, S.; Visser, M. “Twisted” black holes are unphysical. Modern Physics Letters A 2017, 32, 1771001,
[1610.06135]. https://doi.org/10.1142/S0217732317710018.
70. Wald, R.M. General Relativity; The University of Chicago Press, 1984.
71. Penrose, R. Techniques of Differential Topology in General Relativity; Society for Industrial & Applied Mathematics, 1972.
72. Krasnikov, S. Hyperfast Interstellar Travel in General Relativity. Physical Review D 1998, 57, 4760–4766, [arXiv:gr-qc/9511068
[gr-qc]]. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.57.4760.
73. Manchak, J.B. No no-go: A remark on time machines. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 2011, 42, 74–76.
https://doi.org/10.1016/j.shpsb.2011.01.001.
74. Novikov, I.D. Time machine and selfconsistent evolution in problems with selfinteraction. Physical Review D 1992, 45, 1989–1994.
https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.45.1989.
75. Sklar, L. How Free are Initial Conditions? In Proceedings of the Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of
Science Association Vol. 1990, Volume Two: Symposia and Invited Papers. University of Chicago Press, 1990, pp. 551–564.
https://doi.org/10.1086/psaprocbienmeetp.1990.2.193097.
76. Friedman, J.; Morris, M.S.; Novikov, I.D.; Echeverria, F.; Klinkhammer, G.; Thorne, K.S.; Yurtsever, U. Cauchy problem in
spacetimes with closed timelike curves. Physical Review D 1990, 42, 1915–1930. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.42.1915.
77. Kiefer, C. Quantum Gravity, 3rd ed.; Vol. 136, International Series of Monographs on Physics, Oxford University Press, 2012.
78. Echeverria, F.; Klinkhammer, G.; Thorne, K.S. Billiard balls in wormhole space-times with closed timelike curves: Classical theory.
Physical Review D 1991, 44, 1077–1099. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.44.1077.
79. Fewster, C.J.; Higuchi, A.; Wells, C.G. Classical and Quantum Initial Value Problems for Models of Chronology Violation. Physical
Review D 1996, 54, 3806, [arXiv:gr-qc/9603045 [gr-qc]]. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.54.3806.
80. Bachelot, A. Global properties of the wave equation on non-globally hyperbolic manifolds. Journal de Mathématique Pures et
Appliquées 2002, 81, 35–65. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0021-7824(01)01229-6.
81. Dolanský, J.; Krtouš, P. Billiard in the space with a time machine. Physical Review D 2010, 82, 124056, [arXiv:1011.2881 [gr-qc]].
https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.82.124056.
82. Susskind, L.; Glogower, J. Quantum mechanical phase and time operator. Physics Physique Fizika 1964, 1, 49–61. https:
//doi.org/10.1103/PhysicsPhysiqueFizika.1.49.
83. Garrison, J.C.; Wong, J. Canonically Conjugate Pairs, Uncertainty Relations, and Phase Operators. Journal of Mathematical Physics
1970, 11, 2242–2249. https://doi.org/10.1063/1.1665388.
84. Galindo, A. Phase and Number. Letters in Mathematical Physics 1984, 8, 495–500. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00400979.
85. Reed, M.; Simon, B. Methods of Modern Mathematical Physics: I. Functional Analysis, revised and enlarged ed.; Academic Press, 1980.
86. Kiefer, C. Non-minimally coupled scalar fields and the initial value problem in quantum gravity. Physics Letters B 1989,
225, 227–232. https://doi.org/10.1016/0370-2693(89)90810-1.
87. Kiefer, C. Wave packets in quantum cosmology and the cosmological constant. Nuclear Physics B 1990, 341, 273–293. https:
//doi.org/10.1016/0550-3213(90)90271-E.
88. Page, D.N. Minisuperspaces with conformally and minimally coupled scalar fields. Journal of Mathematical Physics 1991,
32, 3427–3438. https://doi.org/10.1063/1.529457.
89. Brunetti, R.; Fredenhagen, K.; Hoge, M. Time in Quantum Physics: From an External Parameter to an Intrinsic Observable.
Foundation of Physics 2010, 40, 1368–1378, [arXiv:0909.1899 [math-ph]]. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-009-9400-z.
90. Hawking, S.W.; Ellis, G.F.R. Singularities in homogeneous world models. Physics Letters 1965, 17, 246–247. Typo in first author of
published version., https://doi.org/10.1016/0031-9163(65)90510-X.
91. O’Neill, B. Semi-Riemannian Geometry with Applications to Relativity; Pure and Applied Mathematics, Academic Press, 1983.
92. Conradi, H.D.; Zeh, H.D. Quantum cosmology as an initial value problem. Physics Letters A 1991, 154, 321–326. https:
//doi.org/10.1016/0375-9601(91)90026-5.
93. Zee, A. Quantum Field Theory in a Nutshell, second ed.; Princeton University Press, 2010.
20 of 20
94. Šafránek, D.; Deutsch, J.M.; Aguirre, A. Quantum coarse-grained entropy and thermodynamics. Physical Review A 2019,
99, 010101, [arXiv:1707.09722 [quant-ph]]. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevA.99.010101.
95. Šafránek, D.; Deutsch, J.M.; Aguirre, A. Quantum coarse-grained entropy and thermalization in closed systems. Physical Review
A 2019, 99, 012103, [arXiv:1803.00665 [quant-ph]]. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevA.99.012103.
96. Šafránek, D.; Aguirre, A.; Schindler, J.; Deutsch, J.M. A Brief Introduction to Observational Entropy. Foundations of Physics 2021,
51, 101, [arXiv:2008.04409 [quant-ph]]. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-021-00498-x.
97. Alonso-Serrano, A.; Tjoa, E.; Garay, L.J.; Martín-Martínez, E. The time traveler’s guide to the quantization of zero modes. Journal
of High Energy Physics 2021, 12, 170, [arXiv:2108.07274 [quant-ph]]. https://doi.org/10.1007/JHEP12(2021)170.
98. Lloyd, S.; Maccone, L.; Garcia-Patron, R.; Giovannetti, V.; Shikano, Y. Quantum mechanics of time travel through post-selected
teleportation. Physical Review D 2011, 84, 025007, [arXiv:1007.2615 [quant-ph]]. https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevD.84.025007.
99. Smith, A.R.S. Communicating without shared reference frames. Physical Review A 2019, 99, 052315, [arXiv:1812.08053 [quant-ph]].
https://doi.org/10.1103/PhysRevA.99.052315.