02 Dhammajoti English
02 Dhammajoti English
htm
Supported by:
Save Tibet Foundation
K.L. Dhammajoti
Hong Kong University
1
In my presentation, I shall discuss the gradual ascendance of doctrinal importance of
the concept of adhimukti (following the sūtra-s and the śāstra-s, I shall use this term
interchangeably with adhimokṣa) from Early Buddhism, through the Abhidharma
doctrines, to Yogācāra, examining in particular the contribution of such a concept to
the development of the vijñaptimātratā doctrine of the Yogācāra. In this way, I hope
to bring out the Buddhist understanding of subjectivity in cognitive experience from
the Abhidharma and the Early Yogācāra perspectives.
It has been a fundamental Buddhist teaching since Early Buddhism that the way we
experience the external world is significantly determined by our inner mental states —
our rāga, dveṣa, moha, etc. Such a teaching may be seen as one pertaining to the
psychology of experience. But going a step further, the Sarvāstivāda, committed
realists as they are, have now pinpointed an ontologically existent force — adhimokṣa
— that actually conditions the appearance of the world to us in every moment.
Moreover, they acknowledge that on the basis of a meditative practice in which the
efficacy of adhimokṣa predominates, the external world can convincingly be perceived
to exist in a drastically determined form “physically”, and not just psychologically.
Such a doctrine is undoubtedly one of subjectivity in cognitive experience.
According to this exposition, then, the reality — namely, the experiential world of the
unenlightened ordinary people — is the cognitive domain of adhimukti. This pertains
1
to both external material things as well as inner sensations (pleasure, displeasure,
etc.). This is quite in line with what we have seen before in the texts of Early
Buddhism and Abhidharma: adhimukti decisively conditions the way we perceive the
world, and also our experience of existence! Such a level of reality perceived through
adhimukti is further described as a perception resulting from conceptualization
conditioned by successively perpetuated ideations in the world. This may be said to be
the early Yogācāras’ doctrine of subjectivity in cognition: Existence as experienced
by the ordinary people is necessarily and decisively conditioned by the type of
resolute receptivity or affirmative mentality represented by adhimukti. For the
completely unenlightened, what is perceived is what they have actually already
resolutely decided to perceive!
In the later Yogācāra development, we may note that one of the major proofs for
doctrine of vijñaptimātratā precisely relies on the adhimukti-based meditative
experience of the aśubhā. The *Mahāyāna-saṃgraha, in arguing for this
vijñaptimātratā thesis, asserts that a bodhisattva endowed with four knowledges can
awaken into the fact that no external object (artha) exists at all. Of the four, two are
particularly relevant in this connection:
A major point in the above argument is that a being’s experience of his existence is
dependent on the particular gati of rebirth. Such a notion is also shared by the
Śrāvakayāna. Indeed, on the basis of the Anuruddha-sutta, the
Abhidhamma/Abhidharma and the Vastu-saṃgrahaṇī, we may say that there is an
essential parity between, on the one hand, the doctrines in those earlier sources that
adhimokṣa-based meditative praxis conditions rebirth, and on the other, the gati-
dependence proof of vijñaptimātratā as well as the buddha-visualization experiences
in the *Pratyutpannabuddha-saṃmukhāvasthita-samādhi-sūtra, etc. The
fundamentally important difference is that the latter has now doctrinally come to teach
that such rebirth and buddha- or god-encounter experiences are cittamātra or
vijñaptimātra. But in both cases, it is the adhimukti-based praxis that stands out as
what effectuates the distinctive experiences. This is, in a gist, the early Yogācāra
doctrine of subjectivity in sentient experiences: subjectivity not only in terms of
cognitive experiences in the present human existence, but also of the conditioning of
rebirth states and the totality of experiences pertaining thereto in the samsaric context.
2
However, as the Viniścaya-saṃgrahaṇī — again invoking the adhimukti meditative
experience — explains: in spite of all external phenomena having no ontological
status outside conceptualization, the totality of phenomenality does not vanish upon a
single individual acquiring the non-conceptualizing wisdom.
A vastu may be either arisen from an unshared conceptualization as its cause or from a
shared conceptualization as its cause. In the former case, for one free from
conceptualization, it also ceases accordingly. In the latter, even if one is without
conceptualization, it will not cease completely, being sustained by others’
conceptualization ... But although it is not ceased, the one possessing purity penetrates into
it with proper and pure vision. Just as, numerous meditators (yogācāra), exercising
adhimukti in diverse manners (sna tshogs su mos par byed pa) by means of their equipoised
knowledge, perceive differently with regard to one and the same thing; likewise is the case
here. (Similar position in the *Mahāyāna-saṃgraha.)
In summary: the later Yogācāras’ doctrine, totally denying the ontological status of
external phenomena as it does, ipso facto denies any objectivity in our cognitive
experiences. In substantiating this view, they have importantly relied on the earlier
Buddhist teachings related to adhimukti. What I further hope to have brought out
above is that, significantly, even the teachings in the early discourses, the Abhidharma
tradition, as well as the early Yogācāras — all not idealistic in the vein of the
vijñaptimātratā doctrine — likewise hold the position of subjectivity in cognitive
experience. For them, one might say that the world we experience is in a significant
sense the world of adhimukti.