Clark '98 Political Economy A Comparative Approach
Clark '98 Political Economy A Comparative Approach
Barry Clark
In order to keep this title in print and available to the academic community, this edition
was produced using digital reprint technology in a relatively short print run. This would
not have been attainable using traditional methods. Although the cover has been changed
from its original appearance, the text remains the same and all materials and methods
used still conform to the highest book-making standards.
Contents
Introduction ix
Neoclassical Economics 31
Modern Political Economy 33
Political economy was the original social science. Theorists such as Adam
Smith, John Stuart Mill, and Karl Marx developed broad visions of the
social system. Not until the latter half of the nineteenth century did politi-
cal economy splinter into economics, political science, sociology, social his-
tory, social psychology, and social philosophy. The motives for this
reorientation were mixed. By partitioning the study of human behavior and
society into narrower subdisciplines, social scientists hoped to emulate the
analytical power and precision of the natural sciences. However, ideologi-
cal motives also played a role in the disintegration of political economy.
The all-encompassing visions of Smith, Mill, and Marx revealed conflict
and tension in society. As political resistance to free-market liberalism
mounted in the mid-nineteenth century, social scientists attempted to estab-
lish a body of objective knowledge from which to formulate reasoned argu-
ments for particular social policies. By adhering to strict logic and factual
data, they hoped to resolve divisive political issues.
Proponents of each of the new social sciences recognized the importance
of defining their scope and method of analysis to establish boundaries sep-
arating the disciplines. As the most immediate heir to the legacy of politi-
cal economy, economics held the greatest potential for emulating natural
science because its scope was confined to behaviors most amenable to
X Introduction
modern political economy and, for each issue, examine the analyses and
policies offered by these perspectives. Finally, chapter sixteen examines the
roles of science and ideology in political economy.
The contending perspectives struggling for dominance in political econ-
omy represent dramatically different visions of the good society. Theoretical
debates over economic and political issues are ultimately based on these
visions, and citizens need to be aware of and consider the value commit-
ments underlying alternative policies before choosing among them.
This page intentionally left blank
PARTI
POLITICAL ECONOMY:
AN OVERVIEW
This page intentionally left blank
Chapter 1
Politics, Economics,
and Political Economy
Economics Politics
Primary Goal Prosperity Justice
Institutional Arena Market Government
Primary Actor Individual Community
P r i m a r y Goals
Economics is associated with efforts to achieve the highest possible
material standard of living from available resources. The primary eco-
nomic goal of prosperity has three dimensions: efficiency, growth, and sta-
bility. Politics, on the other hand, is linked with efforts to establish and
protect rights so citizens can receive and hold that to which they are enti-
tled. The primary political goal of justice, too, includes three dimensions:
individual freedom, equity in the distribution of benefits and burdens, and
social order.
However, distinguishing between economics and politics solely by
referring to their respective goals is ultimately unsatisfactory because
prosperity and justice are inextricably linked. A prosperous society is
more likely to be perceived as a just society because the range of indi-
vidual choice is broadened and order tends to prevail. Conversely, a just
society fosters prosperity by providing open opportunities, fair rewards,
and individual security to motivate production and accumulation of
wealth. Because prosperity and justice are often mutually reinforcing,
distinguishing between economic and political processes by referring to
their different goals is inconclusive. Both economics and politics are
concerned with promoting human well-being by maintaining prosperity
and justice.
Institutional Arenas
Politics often refers to activities associated with government, while
economics deals with activities occurring in the market. We use this dis-
tinction when we label campaigns, elections, and lawmaking as "political
activity," while referring to exchanges of commodities and money as
"economic activity." This method of distinguishing between politics and
economics is certainly common, but it also leads to ambiguity. Like eco-
nomic transactions, political activity often consists of mutually beneficial
Politics, Economics, and Political Economy 5
Primary Actors
From this perspective, economic activity is pursued by persons acting as
autonomous individuals, while political activity represents the efforts of an
entire community to collectively pursue goals. This distinction is observ-
able in the origins of the words "economics" and "politics." Economics
derives from the Greek words oikos, meaning household, and nomos,
meaning principle or law. As the principle of household management, eco-
nomics deals with efforts to attain private goals with available resources.
Economizing behavior can be directed toward any goal and practiced in
any institutional arena. Reflecting this approach, economics is sometimes
defined as the science of rational choice or the use of scarce means to
achieve specified ends.
Politics, on the other hand, derives from the Greek word polis, mean-
ing community or society. According to Aristotle, the public life of the
polis is the arena within which true freedom and human development
occur. Although economic activities are essential to human survival, they
fail to engage the uniquely human capacities for cooperation and collec-
tive decision-making based on reasoned argument, dialog, persuasion,
and compromise.
6 Political Economy
Efficiency
For the market. A perfectly competitive market will, with some excep-
tions, direct resources toward their most highly valued use, resulting in a
"Pareto optimal" or efficient economy in which no person can be made bet-
ter off without making someone else worse off. The market coordinates vast
numbers of transactions with minimal political supervision as prices provide
information and incentives to guide individuals and businesses in making
rational choices about employing resources and purchasing products.
Politics,Economics,andPolitical Economy 7
Growth
For the market. The market is a powerful mechanism for increasing
both the availability and productivity of economic resources. By placing
both negative and positive consequences of decisions directly on the indi-
vidual, the market provides strong incentives for prudent and industrious
behavior. When individuals know they will personally reap the rewards or
suffer the consequences of their actions, they are motivated to consider
their choices more carefully. As a result of the market's incentives, addi-
tional resources are made available, the quality of resources is upgraded,
and innovation and risk-taking are encouraged. The combination of tech-
nological development and expansion of resources provides an impetus
for economic growth.
The market also fosters psychological changes conducive to growth.
By minimizing the constraints of moral and cultural norms, the market
encourages individuals to create their own identities by transcending the
bounds of traditional roles and expectations. Self-reliant individuals may
experiment with diverse lifestyles and forms of expression. Formerly dor-
mant talents and desires are awakened. This process of self-discovery and
self-renewal becomes a significant source of the dynamism of market
societies. The productivity and innovation flowing from energized indi-
viduals contributes to rising standards of living that, in turn, broaden the
range of individual opportunities and renew the motivation essential to
economic expansion.
Against the market. The market's capacity for growth may be con-
strained by an inability to establish adequate social and economic infra-
structure. Growth requires transportation systems, education, and other
public goods that the market is ill-equipped to provide because of the dif-
ficulty in charging individuals for benefits received. Another constraining
factor is uncertainty due to lack of information. Investors may be reluctant
to finance ventures essential to growth when they are unable to accurately
assess the degree of risk involved. Growth may also be hindered by insuf-
ficient demand if wealth and income become so concentrated that spend-
ing on consumer goods lags.
The competitive individualism associated with markets may also func-
tion to obstruct growth. Competition for social status may entail excessive
consumption in order to display affluence. While high levels of consump-
tion contribute to immediate expansion of the economy, the correspond-
ing low level of saving may impede investment and therefore undermine
long-term growth. Competition may also foster frustration and envy that
interfere with productivity and growth. Finally, because competition cre-
ates insecurity, individuals may attempt to protect themselves by forming
organizations and interest groups to suppress the flexibility and dynamism
of the market.
Politics, Economics, and PoliticalEconomy 9
Stability
For the market. The market is extremely flexible in responding to chang-
ing patterns of consumer preferences, technology, and resource availability.
Through the price mechanism, these changes quickly elicit appropriate
reactions as businesses and consumers adjust their production and con-
sumption decisions, respectively. The market contributes to stability by
adjusting quickly before serious imbalances arise. Competitive pressures
reward prompt and effective responses to a changing business environ-
ment. Financial markets also contribute to stability. When the economy
slows, interest rates fall until borrowing and investing are again attractive.
Conversely, when the economy begins to overheat, rising interest rates
choke off borrowing and spending until stability is restored.
Against the market. "Boom and bust" cycles have persisted since the
market became the dominant institution for organizing economic activities.
In earlier years, these cycles were often confined to a particular market in
which a "speculative bubble" would develop as buyers anticipated ever-
rising prices. Eventually, the bubble would burst, bringing financial ruin to
some speculators. In modern times, however, the connectivity of markets
and the emergence of financial markets have created national and even
global cycles of instability.
This instability is partially explained by the role of expectations. A psy-
chological shift toward pessimism among investors may create a financial
crisis that spills over into the real economy, resulting in recession and
unemployment. Conversely, optimism leads to new investments and higher
spending that may trigger inflation.
Freedom
For the market. The market provides a wide range of freedoms.
Individuals have the right to make choices concerning employment, place
of residence, consumption patterns, and social relationships. Competing
alternatives constrain the power of any single person or firm to oppress and
manipulate others. The sense of freedom offered by the market may partly
explain the popularity of shopping. Consumers tend to enjoy the experi-
ence of being able to select from an array of alternatives—the power to
10 Political Economy
choose with whom they shall transact. The market also provides citizens
with opportunities to engage their resources, including entrepreneurial tal-
ent, in the most advantageous way. Finally, the market potentially protects
individuals from abuses of governmental authority by establishing decen-
tralized bases of power from which citizens can express opinions and orga-
nize opposition.
Against the market. While the market offers a considerable range of
choice, it also limits choice. The market provides only commodities that
can be sold at a profit and therefore fails to respond to demands for
goods such as national defense, a clean environment, or public trans-
portation. Since only a subset of human interests is expressible in the
market, the freedom of individuals to pursue their goals is correspond-
ingly narrowed.
Not only does the market limit the range of interests capable of fulfill-
ment, it also conditions individuals to tailor their interests to suit the capa-
bilities of the market. A social environment in which profitable commodities
are the major source of satisfaction causes humans to develop capacities
oriented toward consumption of commodities and diminishes their freedom
to establish self-directed goals.
Although individuals in a pure market are largely free of legal restric-
tions on exchange, the freedom of persons with few marketable assets will
be limited by their financial inability to pursue personal goals. Moreover,
the prospect of hunger and deprivation effectively coerce individuals to
seek employment. Once on the job, workers surrender much of their auton-
omy and self-direction to the authority of employers.
Even as consumers, citizens may not experience genuine freedom in the
market. In real-world markets, consumers have only limited information
and producers tend to be well-organized. Instead of being sovereigns of the
market, consumers may feel like the prey, surrounded by manipulative
advertising, inflated prices, shoddy merchandise, and deceitful sellers.
Historically, the link between markets and freedom has been based on
the assumption that the interests of different individuals are ultimately
harmonious. If no transactions are coerced, then all transactions must
benefit both buyer and seller and hence increase the overall well-being of
society. However, the record of real-world markets amply illustrates that
the freedom of one individual may restrict the freedom of another.
Markets allow practices such as monopolization of industries, pollution of
the environment, and discrimination, all of which narrow the choices
available to citizens.
Equity
For the market. With the forces of supply and demand establishing
resource prices, the market distributes rewards according to each person's
Politics, Economics, and Political Economy 11
Order
For the market. The market erodes traditional human relations based on
arbitrary privilege and hierarchy. By virtue of property rights and civil
rights, individuals engage only in transactions of their own choosing.
Freedom of choice and a sense of autonomy contribute to personal well-
being, and a satisfied citizenry usually implies an orderly society.
The market also fosters order by increasing specialization of labor, so that
formerly diverse and separate groups become mutually dependent. When
individuals benefit from market transactions, they have an interest in treat-
ing each other respectfully. Even nations may be less belligerent when their
economic well-being depends on the prosperity of their trading partners.
Finally, the market contributes to order by distributing society's benefits
and burdens without visible political authority. Each person's success or
failure appears to result from impersonal market forces, so there is no obvi-
ous target for resentment or envy. When individuals accept responsibility
for their own fate, they are less likely to disrupt society.
Against the market. The dynamism of the market undermines traditional
values and social structures. As individuals pursue their private interests,
cohesive communities and shared purposes are increasingly displaced by the
pursuit of satisfaction through consumption and ownership of commodities.
This individualism undermines the self-restraint and virtue essential to social
order. The market functions well only within a social context based on
respect for ethical norms and individual rights. When self-interested behav-
ior degenerates into unbridled selfishness, social bonds begin to unravel.
Another potential source of disorder in market societies arises from the
conflict of interest between owners of productive property and workers
dependent on employment for their livelihood. Owners generally seek max-
imum production from workers at minimum cost, while workers want
higher wages and more satisfying working conditions. This conflict may
extend beyond the workplace as class resentment and hostility manifest
themselves in crime and racial and ethnic unrest.
Freedom
For government. Government enables citizens to reach goals they would
be unable to attain through private action, and therefore contributes to free-
dom by broadening the range of feasible choices. For example, education,
Politics, Economics, and Political Economy 13
national defense, and security from crime may be better obtained through
government financing.
Freedom is more than the absence of external constraints; it also requires
a basic level of material well-being and a social environment conducive to
developing and practicing a broad range of human capacities. Government
may contribute to these conditions of freedom and also restrain powerful
individuals and groups from restricting the freedom of others.
By providing an alternative to the market as an arena in which goals can
be pursued, government not only increases the choices available to citizens
but allows for the development of a broader range of preferences and val-
ues. For example, citizens' commitment to racial equality or environmental
protection may be strengthened when they observe the authority of gov-
ernment being directed toward those goals. Government serves as a model
and teacher, enabling citizens to develop their capacities more fully.
Against government. Few public policies have unanimous support and,
therefore, government necessarily infringes on the freedom of some citi-
zens. Taxes, regulations, and laws are considered legitimate restrictions
when they are approved by the majority, do not violate individual rights,
and are aimed at promoting the public interest. However, since modern
societies often lack a clear consensus on the meaning of both individual
rights and the public interest, particular government actions may be per-
ceived as violations of freedom. More generally, democratic governments
may be coercive to the extent that they enable the will of the majority to be
imposed on the minority.
With its monopoly on the legitimate use of force through command over
the police and military, government has the potential to severely restrict
freedom. Some governments have either revised or abandoned the rule of
law to engage in arbitrary arrest, seizure of property, and surveillance.
Freedom can also be curtailed without resorting to visible oppression. If
factions of society hold undue influence over government, it ceases to
represent the public interest and becomes a tool with which powerful
groups oppress their fellow citizens.
Equity
For government. Equity requires that people be treated in accordance
with their rights. Whereas the market recognizes only property rights in
determining the distribution of income, a broader conception of equity
includes the recognition of human rights. Property rights entitle owners to
market-determined earnings of their resources, while government assigns
human rights to secure those individual interests deemed worthy of support,
even if they are not backed by individual purchasing power. While equity
based on property rights relies solely on the criterion of productivity, human
rights may recognize other criteria of equity such as need, dignity, or simply
14 Political Economy
Order
For government. Government promotes orderly human interaction by
defining and enforcing rights and obligations, thereby enabling individuals
to form stable expectations of human behavior. Without public knowledge
of the law, resolution of conflict would absorb substantial economic
resources. Government also fosters order by maintaining society's culture,
traditions, and boundaries. As a visible symbol and expression of society's
collective identity, a respected government becomes an object of psycho-
logical allegiance, facilitating the formation of both individual identity and
a sense of shared purpose and trust among citizens.
Government further contributes to order by promoting equality of
opportunity. When disparities of income, wealth, and power impede social
Politics, Economics, and Political Economy 15
Efficiency
For government. Government may improve efficiency by responding to
imperfections in the market. For example, lack of information can be reme-
died by government provision. Concentrations of private power that impede
competition can be addressed with antitrust lawsuits, regulation, or public
16 Political Economy
Growth
For government. Growth is contingent on the ability of society to pro-
duce more than it consumes and to direct this surplus into productive
investment. Government may be able to improve the market's ability to
produce a surplus. When custom and tradition keep resources out of pro-
ductive use, government has the power to pry these resources loose and
place them into active production. Furthermore, with its control over taxes,
spending, and interest rates, government can steer resources toward capital
accumulation. By financing education and research, government can con-
tribute to the long-run growth of the economy. Finally, government reduces
uncertainty for private investors by establishing well-defined property
rights, a smoothly functioning legal system, and stable market conditions.
Against government. Government taxation and borrowing absorb
money that might otherwise have flowed into productive private invest-
ment. Regulations may divert resources from their most efficient use and
contribute to stagnation. Subsidies and other forms of protective legislation
shield firms from competitive pressures to innovate and modernize.
Government redistribution of income may undermine incentives to engage
in productive activity. Not only is the positive incentive of higher income
diminished by taxes and regulations, but the disincentives posed by hunger
and deprivation are partially removed by welfare programs and social secu-
rity. Government efforts to achieve greater equality through income redis-
tribution tend to penalize success and reward failure, potentially
diminishing the market's dynamic potential for growth.
Stability
For government. The very presence of government authority increases
stability by minimizing conflict and providing security of property.
Appropriate government policies encourage "business confidence" that is
essential to stability. Even policies opposed by some businesses may be ben-
eficial to the economy. For example, antitrust policies, minimum-wage
laws, and progressive taxation can counterbalance the market's tendency to
foster concentrations of wealth and power that jeopardize stability. Finally,
when recession or inflation occurs, government can respond with appro-
priate fiscal or monetary policies.
Against government. Government efforts to redirect resources and alter
the distribution of income may, by reducing profitability and undermining
business confidence, contribute to instability. Government also has the
power to create a "political business cycle" as politicians seeking reelection
overstimulate the economy in hopes of creating a temporary boom to
please voters. Once the election is over, the stimulus is withdrawn and the
economy slips into recession. Even when government officials act with the
18 Political Economy
best of intentions, the tools of monetary and fiscal policy may increase
instability. By the time bureaucrats and politicians recognize a problem,
formulate a response, implement the policy, and wait for results, economic
conditions may have changed so that the policy is no longer appropriate.
More generally, by seeking to perpetuate prosperity, government may sup-
press the mechanisms, such as rising interest rates, that allow the market to
stabilize itself. When prosperity is artificially prolonged, the subsequent
recession may be more severe.
POLITICAL ECONOMY
Analysis of the market and government as political and economic insti-
tutions suggests that neither is solely capable of organizing society to secure
prosperity and justice. Both institutions are sufficiently flawed to require a
balancing of political and economic processes to sustain a healthy society.
In a positive sense, each institution serves to complement weaknesses of the
other. However, the market and government also generate powerful forces
reverberating against each other with potentially damaging consequences.
Since the market and government interact with each other, efforts to
analyze them separately will yield only partial, and therefore distorted,
understandings of the social system. Politics and economics are simply two
facets of the process by which society is organized to achieve both individ-
ual and community goals. To study this process, the interdisciplinary
approach provided by political economy is essential. Although political
economy was abandoned by most social scientists in the nineteenth cen-
tury, events of the twentieth century have accentuated its relevance. As a
result of the Great Depression and two world wars, issues such as growth,
distribution, and stability were transformed from economic into political
issues. The boundary between public life and private life was redrawn, with
politics encompassing an ever-larger realm of human activity. More
recently, deterioration of the natural environment and growing concerns
about the quality of life have led to renewed conflict and negotiation over
the appropriate boundary between public and private spheres. As the
domains of politics and economics vie for dominance, the interdisciplinary
approach of political economy offers great potential for analyzing and
responding to the problems confronting modern societies.
ADDITIONAL READING
Bell, Daniel, and Irving Kristol. The Crisis in Economic Theory. New York: Basic
Books, 1981.
Boulding, Kenneth. Towards a New Economics. Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar,
1992.
Politics, Economics,and PoliticalEconomy 19
He who knows only his own side of the case knows little of that.
John Stuart Mill
Neofascist
Theory
Romanticism
Edmund
& Corporatism
Burke
Nationalism
Neoconservatism
Neo-Austrian
Economics
New Classical
Economics
Classical Neoclassical The Classical Liberal Perspective
Political Economics
Economy
New Keynesian
Economics
Cambridge Neocorporatism
Economics
Post-Keynesian
Economics
Institutional
Economics
classical political economists were failing to carry out the mission of the
Enlightenment. Although the power of the state had been challenged and
restrained, the power of private property had actually increased due to the
elimination of most government restraints. In the spirit of the Enlightenment,
Radicals demanded that every aspect of society be subjected to criticism to
see whether it could withstand the test of reason. The rights of private prop-
erty were viewed as no more sacrosanct than the authority of church or state.
Central to the Radical call for a reconstruction of society was a strong
commitment to egalitarianism. Until all persons directly participated in the
formation of the institutions governing their lives and shared in the bene-
fits derived from those institutions, society would necessarily appear arbi-
trary and oppressive, and individuals would remain alienated. Radicals
condemned private property for breeding selfish interests that conflict with
the common good of society. In a private property system, individuals have
opposing interests and social cohesion disintegrates as the owners of prop-
erty oppress those with little or no property. Although each individual is
free to choose, oppression arises because inequality of property makes the
poor vulnerable to exploitation as the threat of starvation coerces them to
work for subsistence wages.
Radicals also condemned private property for alienating individuals
from any sense of community or control over their work. Relying on the
optimism of the Enlightenment, they concluded that people can join
together to collectively direct their social existence. Radicals envisioned a
classless society in which free individuals could live in harmony with each
other in their work, their communities, and their government. Such a soci-
ety would be egalitarian and communal, with citizens sharing a broad
range of common interests, including a commitment to maintain appropri-
ate conditions for the development and security of every person. Genuine
freedom requires access to sufficient resources for well-rounded human
development and hence can be secured only when the community as a
whole controls productive property.
Examples of early Radical thinkers include William Godwin (1756-1836)
in England, Thomas Paine (1737-1809) in America, and the Marquis de
Condorcet (1743-1794) in France. These writers were opposed not so
much to the principle of private property as to the excessive concentration
of ownership that restricted the opportunities and freedom of the majority
of the population. In the early 1800s, thinkers such as Robert Owen
(1771-1858) of England and Charles Fourier (1772-1837) and Henri de
Saint-Simon (1760-1825) of France popularized the idea of eliminating
private property. These " Utopian socialists" formulated detailed plans for
small communities based on shared ownership of property. Owen actually
put his ideas into practice, moving to the United States with a group of fol-
lowers to establish a community in Indiana called New Harmony.
Hundreds of other small experiments with communal living occurred
The History of Political Economy 27
during the nineteenth century in both Europe and North America. Growing
apprehension over the effects of industrialization and modernization
undoubtedly spurred this interest in alternative forms of society. The loss
of tradition, the squalor of large cities, and conditions in the early factories
persuaded many people that fundamental change was required to improve
the quality of human existence.
The influence of Radical thought was heightened immeasurably by Karl
Marx (1818-1883), a German philosopher and political economist who
constructed an impressive theoretical analysis of capitalism by weaving
together classical political economy, the ideas of the German philosopher
G. W. F. Hegel (1770-1831), and the communal vision of the Utopian
socialists. Building on the pessimistic theories of the classical political econ-
omists, Marx developed an elaborate theoretical argument that capitalism
would eventually crumble and be replaced by a society in which the means
of production were communally owned and operated. This new society,
Marx claimed, was incubating within capitalism and its birth would coin-
cide with the death of the parent. Thus, unlike the Utopian socialists who
sought to turn their backs on capitalist society, Marx portrayed capitalism
as the essential precondition for a new and better organization of society.
In capitalist factories, workers were acquiring the technical knowledge,
cooperative skills, and sense of solidarity that would enable them to revolt
and establish a communal society.
After Marx's death, his ideas inspired several distinct political traditions.
Several theorists, including Georgi Plekhanov (1857-1918) in Russia and
Karl Liebknecht (1871-1919) and Karl Kautsky (1854-1938) in Germany
upheld Marx's belief in the historical inevitability of communism.
However, when a proletarian revolution failed to appear by the early twen-
tieth century, Russian theorists V. I. Lenin (1870-1924) and Leon Trotsky
(1879-1940) introduced into Marxism the notion of a "vanguard party"
of intellectuals who would lead the workers in the struggle for socialism.
This strand of Marxism served as the theoretical basis for the Soviet Union.
In Western Europe and the United States, a different revision of Marx's
ideas was formulated by theorists such as Edward Bernstein (1850-1932) in
Germany, Sidney and Beatrice Webb (1859-1947 and 1858-1943) in
England, Jean Jaures (1859-1914) in France, and Eugene Debs (1855-1926)
and Norman Thomas (1884-1968) in the United States. Acknowledging the
rising standard of living enjoyed by workers in capitalist societies, these
"social democrats" rejected the Marxian concept of proletarian revolution.
Instead, they defended socialism as a more just and efficient economic system
whose obvious appeal to the working class would permit an evolutionary
transition from capitalism to socialism through the democratic political
process. The task of the revisionists was not to foment revolution, but to
establish a working-class political party and to educate all citizens about the
attractions of socialism.
28 Political l EEconomy
society was destroying the authority and emotional attachments that unite
individuals into communities. Self-interested human reason, he posited, will
always resent authority for placing limitations on the scope of individual
action. But without authority, all persons suffer as society degenerates into a
morass of conflicting desires and passions. Since human reason was not a
reliable guide for redesigning society, Burke proposed that the exercise of rea-
son should be confined to efforts by individuals to improve their private
lives. The grand schemes of intellectuals and Utopians would only disrupt the
traditional patterns of human interaction, engendering chaos.
Attempting to develop a defense of established traditions, Burke and
subsequent Conservatives looked back to the merits of medieval society. A
stable social order must be grounded in traditional institutions such as the
church and the patriarchal family. When efforts to reconstruct society
destroy traditional institutions, individuals are uprooted from their cus-
tomary roles in the community. Deprived of a cultural heritage, isolated
individuals lose meaning in their lives, become concerned solely with self-
gratification, and neglect their duties to others and to society as a whole.
From the Conservative perspective, the degeneration of the French
Revolution into violent anarchy was attributable to individualism and the
pursuit of self-interest. The Revolution foreshadowed an impending col-
lapse of civilization that could be averted only by strengthening traditional
values and institutions.
As the Enlightenment was sweeping Great Britain and France, a reaction
was brewing in Germany. Having been subjected to military conquest by
France and the threat of economic domination by British industry, many
Germans expressed disdain toward the cultures of their western neighbors.
Fearing the cosmopolitan values and lifestyles spawned by urban industrial
society, they were determined to avoid disintegration of their own culture.
This reaction to the Enlightenment has been labeled "romanticism."
Writers such as Johann Fichte (1762-1814), August von Schlegel
(1767-1845), Friedrich von Schelling (1775-1854), and Johann Herder
(1744-1803) expressed their opposition to the effects of modernization on
Germanic culture. Whereas the Enlightenment stressed the rationality of
humans, the importance of science, and the mechanical nature of reality,
the German romantics defended the unpredictability and irrationality of
humans, the importance of traditional culture in maintaining a cohesive
society, and a view of reality that includes spiritual and even mystical ele-
ments. Rather than adopting the analytical methods of modern science, the
romantics sought to develop their intuition and instincts, their passions and
feelings, their sensitivity to beauty, and their sense of harmony with nature.
They believed that personal fulfillment could be achieved only within the
context of a stable culture based on widely shared values. From their per-
spective, the Enlightenment view of humans as autonomous, rational, and
calculating, merely described the sordid conditions of English culture. The
30 Political Economy
disintegrate and a nation loses its vitality and power. Only government can
effectively oppose the cosmopolitan influences of the international market
economy. A strong government enables a nation to be self-determining, free
from constraints imposed by other nations and by the forces of the market.
Conservative nationalism is typically linked with cultural and politi-
cal chauvinism, which explains why racial and ethnic strife, imperialism,
and war often accompany nationalist sentiments. The desire for self-
determination frequently results in military conquest to expand national
borders or spheres of influence against real or imagined foreign threats.
Nationalists also find war and imperialism to be useful in diverting pub-
lic attention away from internal problems and toward the glory and
prestige of the nation. Some writers even touted war as a rare opportu-
nity for individuals to transcend the routine of everyday life and display
the noble human sentiments of courage, valor, strength, and patriotism.
An illustrious example of a nineteenth-century nationalist is the German
historian and philosopher Heinrich von Treitschke (1834-1896), whose
racist and militarist writings would later provide inspiration for Adolf
Hitler (1889-1945) and the Nazi movement.
NEOCLASSICAL ECONOMICS
The rise of Radicalism and Conservatism established alternatives to clas-
sical political economy. However, both perspectives met with considerable
opposition. Radicalism aroused fears of the confiscation of private property,
while many regarded Conservatism as a threat to democracy and modern-
ization. Despite the resistance to Radical and Conservative ideas, the influ-
ence of classical political economy waned during the nineteenth century for
several reasons. The classical predictions of widespread poverty and slow-
ing growth failed to materialize, raising doubts about the theories underly-
ing those forecasts. Also, Marx's use of classical political economy to attack
capitalism caused mainstream political economists to dissociate themselves
from Smith and Ricardo. Finally, the combination of an increasingly pow-
erful working class and social problems accompanying industrialization cre-
ated new demands for government intervention to improve education,
old-age security, public health, and occupational safety. In the face of these
pressures, the policy of laissez-faire became increasingly unpopular.
With the three dominant perspectives all seemingly flawed, an ideologi-
cal vacuum was developing. The time was ripe for a new approach to polit-
ical economy capable of defending both democracy and private property.
In 1871, three theorists, writing separately and unknown to one another,
simultaneously developed this new theory. Carl Menger (1840-1921) of
Austria, W. Stanley Jevons (1835-1882) of England, and Leon Walras
(1834-1910) of Switzerland changed the focus of political economy from
the classical concern with distribution and growth to a "neoclassical"
32 Political Economy
orientation that dealt solely with the behavior of individual consumers and
firms operating in competitive markets.
To emphasize their focus on individual choice, the neoclassical theorists
even changed the name of their field of study. Jevons referred to political
economy as "the old troublesome double-worded name of our science" and
urged his colleagues to replace it with the term "economics." His sugges-
tion gained wide acceptance, and by the beginning of the twentieth century,
neoclassical economics had attained dominant status among competing
perspectives in political economy. Neoclassical economists sought to con-
struct a theory that matched the scientific rigor of physics. To achieve this
goal, they applied mathematics as an analytical method to explain the
choices of individual consumers and producers. Under conditions of perfect
competition, individuals would engage in mutually beneficial exchanges
until they gained the most satisfaction possible from the resources at their
command—a situation labeled as efficient by the neoclassical economists.
Having demonstrated that free markets result in efficiency, the neoclassical
economists largely affirmed the classical prescription of laissez-faire while
avoiding the objectionable ideas of class conflict and economic stagnation.
Although early neoclassical economists shared many of the same values
and tools of analysis, disagreement among economists in Austria and
England gave rise to two separate traditions: Austrian economics and
Cambridge economics. Austrian economists were undoubtedly influenced
by the political climate in their country during the late nineteenth century.
As the Hapsburg empire crumbled, the working class grew increasingly
receptive to socialist ideas. In this environment, a group of academic econ-
omists in Vienna, including Carl Menger, Friedrich von Wieser
(1851-1926), and Eugen von Bohm-Bawerk (1851-1914) sought to
demonstrate the appeal of a free-market economy with virtually no gov-
ernment intervention.
In addition to defending the virtues of capitalism, Austrian economists
have been harsh critics of Marxism and socialism. Ludwig von Mises
(1881-1973) claimed that without the forces of supply and demand oper-
ating in a free market, prices could not accurately reflect consumer prefer-
ences or the relative scarcity of different resources. Socialist planners, he
argued, could not possibly gather enough information about resource avail-
ability and consumer preferences to permit calculation of appropriate prices
for all products and resources. As a result, shortages and surpluses for dif-
ferent commodities would inevitably plague a socialist economy and ineffi-
ciency would be rampant. Only capitalism provides incentive for gathering
the information required for efficient choices by allowing individuals to reap
the rewards of their own foresight, initiative, and innovation.
In contrast to Austrian economists, Stanley Jevons and subsequent econ-
omists at Cambridge University recognized a more positive role for gov-
ernment. Although committed to preserving the freedom of individual
The History of Political Economy 33
hierarchy stood on the right side of the chamber, while the proponents of
greater equality and individual freedom stood on the left. As a result, pro-
ponents of equality have since been called "leftists," while those who
defend hierarchy are called "rightists."
Rightists claim that hierarchical social relations are essential to a good
society. Individuals need distinctions of status to differentiate themselves
from others. A society lacking sufficient hierarchy will fail to provide
incentives for citizens to excel, resulting in a stifling mediocrity and drag-
ging the entire society into economic stagnation, boredom, and apathy.
Rightists also defend hierarchy as essential to organize the complex social
processes needed to maintain prosperity and order. Just as armies rely on
hierarchical chains of command to wage war, other institutions such as
corporations, schools, and families also must be hierarchically structured
to achieve their objectives.
Leftists, on the other hand, claim that human development flourishes
when individuals engage in cooperative, mutually respectful relations that
can thrive only when excessive differences in status, power, and wealth are
eliminated. According to leftists, a society without substantial equality will
distort the development of not only deprived persons, but also those whose
privileges undermine their motivation and sense of social responsibility.
This suppression of human development, together with the resentment and
conflict engendered by sharp class distinctions, will ultimately reduce the
efficiency of the economy.
The right/left dichotomy is often treated as synonymous with the con-
servative/liberal dichotomy. Although this usage of ideological labels may
have been appropriate for analyzing political debate in the late eighteenth
century, modern discourse has become more complex. In addition to the
dispute over hierarchy and equality, both rightists and leftists have devel-
oped internal splits over another question: should the private interests of
individuals take precedence over the interests of society? Individualists
defend the priority of individual interests, while communitarians defend
the priority of society's interests.
Individualists claim that a community has no interests other than the
aggregation of the individual interests within it. Therefore, the notion of a
public interest or common good is a myth; the good community is one that
allows individuals to freely pursue their private interests. Individualists are
not directly concerned about the well-being of the community because they
remain confident that any community securing individual freedom will be
made prosperous by the energies and talents of its citizens. For individual-
ists, freedom means the right to pursue one's interests with minimal con-
straint by society.
In contrast, communitarians view human development as a function of
the quality of the social environment and therefore expect the community
to provide a supportive and nurturing environment. By themselves,
The History of Political Economy 35
individuals are rather helpless in the face of social forces over which they
have no control, but the community as a whole can consciously engage in
actions to facilitate the development of individual interests and shape indi-
vidual character.
Individualists and communitarians have sought to discredit each other
through caricature. Communitarians are portrayed as supporting "anthill"
or "beehive" societies in which members simply serve their assigned role
with no room for individual creativity or expression. Individualists, on the
other hand, are accused of advocating an amoral society in which selfish,
isolated persons pursue their narrow interests, constrained only by laws
and the threat of punishment. Yet communitarians are vigorous defenders
of individual dignity, claiming that a nurturing community enables indi-
viduals to achieve their full potential. Conversely, individualists value
healthy communities but argue that communities are most peaceful and
prosperous when individuals are permitted to freely pursue their interests.
The debate between individualists and communitarians has occurred on
both the right and left sides of the political spectrum, resulting in four
major perspectives within political economy. The differences among these
four perspectives are illustrated in Figure 2.2.
In the top-right quadrant, the Classical Liberal perspective is associated
with both hierarchy and individualism. Although the earliest forms of lib-
eral thought were highly egalitarian, by the beginning of the nineteenth
century, many liberals concluded that the pursuit of individual freedom
Figure 2.2
Value Commitments of Perspectives in Political Economy
INDIVIDUAL
Modern Classical
Liberal Liberal
EQUALITY HIERARCHY
Radical Conservative
COMMUNITY
36 Political Economy
ADDITIONAL READING
Arblaster, Anthony. The Rise and Decline of Western Liberalism. New York: Bas
Blackwell, 1984.
Baradat, Leon P. Political Ideologies: Their Origins and Impact, 3rd ed. Englewo
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1988.
The History of Political Economy 37
Cole, Ken, John Cammeron, and Chris Edwards. Why Economists Disagree: The
Political Economy of Economics. New York: Longman, 1983.
Elliott, John E., and John Cownie, eds. Competing Philosophies in American
Political Economics. Pacific Palisades, CA: Goodyear, 1975.
Heilbroner, Robert. The Worldly Philosophers, 6th ed. New York: Simon 6c
Schuster, 1986.
Hoover, Kenneth. Ideology and Political Life. Monterey, CA: Brooks/Cole, 1987.
Polanyi, Karl. The Great Transformation: The Political and Economic Origins of
Our Time. Boston: Beacon Press, 1944.
Prychitko, David L., ed. Why Economists Disagree: An Introduction to the
Alternative Schools of Thought. Albany, NY: State University of New York
Press, 1998.
Schwarzmantel, John. The Age of Ideology. New York: New York University
Press, 1988.
Sowell, Thomas. A Conflict of Visions: Ideological Origins of Political Struggles.
New York: William Morrow, 1987.
Spechler, Martin C. Perspectives in Economic Thought. New York: McGraw-
Hill, 1990.
Voeglin, Eric. Prom Enlightenment to Revolution. Durham, NC: Duke University
Press, 1975.
Ward, Benjamin. The Ideal Worlds of Economics. New York: Basic Books, 1979.
Whynes, David K., ed. What Is Political Economy} New York: Basil Blackwell, 1984.
This page intentionally left blank
PART II
CONTENDING
PERSPECTIVES IN
POLITICAL ECONOMY
This page intentionally left blank
Chapter 3
John Locke(1632-1704)
John Locke, an English philosopher and physician, followed the
Hobbesian method by building his theories on assumptions about
The Classical Liberal Perspective 43
disorder in Great Britain had been largely resolved, and the task at hand
was to raise the material standard of living.
In his first major work, The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759), Smith
argued that humans are able, through social interaction, to overcome their
narrow self-interest and view situations from the perspective of an "impar-
tial spectator." The human capacity for sympathy would restrain aggres-
sive, selfish behavior and create a stable society. Yet Smith was deeply
concerned that the emerging market economy unleashed powerful and
potentially dangerous motives such as greed, envy, and selfishness. The
aggressive pursuit of self-interest threatened to erode the social bonds of
sympathy and concern for others. Given these pressures, Smith wondered
whether human virtue could withstand the temptations of wealth.
Motivated by these concerns, Smith turned his attention from moral phi-
losophy to political economy. After being introduced to the idea of laissez-
faire by a group of French political economists known as the Physiocrats,
he concluded that a market society could not only withstand the effects of
acquisitive selfishness, but could actually steer this "vice" into productive
and socially beneficial channels. Without meaning to do so, self-interested
individuals actually promote the good of society by engaging their talents
and resources in the most profitable use. By the time he published The
Wealth of Nations in 1776, Adam Smith had substituted the market for
individual conscience as the mechanism for reconciling self-interest with an
orderly and prosperous society.
Although Smith is often portrayed as the champion of capitalism, he was
not completely optimistic about the market. He found self-interest com-
patible with the public good only when competition prevailed, and he
warned that businessmen would constantly seek to suppress competition
and deceive the public to increase profits. Smith also expressed concern
about the well-being of workers in a market economy. While he recognized
the tremendous efficiency gained by dividing production into separate, rou-
tine tasks, he worried that the monotony and mindlessness of factory jobs
would render workers "as stupid as it is possible for a human being to
become." Finally, Smith set the tone for subsequent classical political econ-
omists with his fear that the dynamism and growth of a market society
would eventually come to an end as profitable investment opportunities
were exhausted.
Whatever qualms he may have expressed about capitalism, Adam
Smith's legacy has been his defense of free markets and nonintervention by
government. During the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, mercantilist
policies had involved government in taxing commerce, opening new mar-
kets in foreign lands, protecting companies from competition, and assuring
product quality. Smith believed this meddling interfered with the potential
benefits of the market and proposed that government be limited to three
The Classical Liberal Perspective 45
T h o m a s Malthus ( 1 7 6 6 - 1 8 3 4 )
Malthus, a professor of history and political economy at the East India
College in England, was most responsible for steering Classical Liberalism
away from its earlier predisposition toward the Enlightenment values of
optimism, egalitarianism, and faith in reason. In contrast to Enlightenment
thinkers, Malthus believed that human misery was caused by nature rather
than badly organized institutions. In his book An Essay on the Principle of
Population (1798), Malthus claimed that population grows at a faster rate
than do food supplies because of the limited availability of fertile land.
Population growth could be restrained either by "positive checks" such as
famines, plagues, and wars, or by "preventive checks" such as delayed
marriages and "moral restraint."
Malthus had little hope that humans would be capable of exercising the
restraint required to control population growth, so positive checks would
be the effective controls on overpopulation. Moreover, Malthus believed
that government should not attempt to interfere with the operation of these
positive checks. He proposed that raw sewage be permitted to flow in the
streets, that insect-infested swamps remain undrained, and that cures for
disease be suppressed, thereby allowing nature to carry out the grisly task
of limiting population growth.
In addition to rejecting efforts to help the poor, Malthus argued that the
privileges and wealth of the upper classes benefitted all of society. He rea-
soned that workers as a group received insufficient wages to permit them
to purchase the vast array of goods being produced by the new factories,
so the economy would be plagued by periodic "gluts" of unsold goods
unless some members of society could afford to spend large amounts on
consumption without adding to production. Idle consumption by the rich
was therefore essential to maintain high levels of employment.
Malthus represents a turning point in Classical Liberalism. The
Enlightenment attack on aristocratic privilege evolved into a defense of
capitalist inequality. Later in the nineteenth century, Malthus's ideas would
resurface as "social Darwinism." Relying on the evolutionary theory of
Charles Darwin, Herbert Spencer (1820-1903) in England and William
Graham Sumner (1840-1910) in America claimed that the human species
evolves according to the principle of "survival of the fittest." Any attempts
by government to aid the poor would cause deterioration of the human
gene pool by allowing unfit members of the human species to survive and
reproduce. This biological argument for hierarchy and inequality became a
powerful ideological force in Europe and the United States.
46 Political Economy
Priedrich A. Hayek ( 1 8 9 9 - 1 9 9 2 )
Although born in Austria, Hayek spent most of his adult life in England
and America, where he devoted himself to defending laissez-faire capital-
ism against the challenges posed by Conservatives, Modern Liberals, and
Radicals. In The Road to Serfdom (1944), Hayek rejected the notion of a
middle ground between capitalism and socialism; the concept of a "mixed
economy" is untenable. Government intervention disrupts the smooth
functioning of a free-market economy, thereby generating the need for
additional corrective intervention. This vicious circle by which govern-
ment-induced problems lead to a larger role for government will eventually
push society toward socialism. The only way to halt this process is to resist
the initial temptation to improve society through government action.
The movement of Classical Liberalism away from the Enlightenment's
optimism and confidence in human reason can be clearly discerned in Hayek's
writings. He defended the market not because he believed in the power of
individual reason, but rather because of his skepticism about the capacity of
the human mind to obtain knowledge. Since each person can have detailed
knowledge of only a small portion of society, humans lack sufficient knowl-
edge to plan or direct the entire economy. Hayek explicitly denounced what
he called "constructivist rationalism," which seeks to remake society in accor-
dance with more humane and enlightened values.
Hayek praised the market for upholding individual freedom and empha-
sized its ability to process and transmit vast amounts of information about
individual preferences, availability of resources, and technology. Prices
reflect the conditions underlying supply and demand, so individuals are
able to compensate for their personal lack of knowledge by simply com-
paring prices. Moreover, through their own particular experience, individ-
uals gain specialized knowledge of niches in the market and may take
advantage of any profitable opportunities they discover.
Hayek's distrust of human reason led him to oppose virtually all gov-
ernment activity on the grounds that politicians and bureaucrats cannot
know what is best for society. The task of politics should be merely to
establish a constitution and set of laws restraining individuals from harm-
ing others. Hayek warned that when government is permitted to expand its
activities Seyond the protection of property rights, it will inevitably become
the tool of special interests. Various groups will claim that their interests
should be met to promote the public good or to achieve social justice, but
these appeals are simply disguised attempts to secure government benefits.
The public good is simply the aggregation of the private interests of indi-
viduals, and justice is a "mirage" based on the false supposition that some
interests are more deserving of fulfillment than others.
Hayek rejected the notion that economics can provide a scientific basis
for predicting or attempting to control the future of the economy. Not only
The Classical Liberal Perspective 47
Robert Nozick ( 1 9 3 8 - )
A recent restatement of Classical Liberalism has been undertaken by
Harvard philosopher Robert Nozick in his book Anarchy, State, and
Utopia (1974). Nozick argues that the free market will create justice in the
distribution of rewards if the following three conditions are met: (1) prop-
erty must be acquired without theft, fraud, or coercion; (2) transfers of
property from one person to another must occur through free exchanges,
inheritance, gifts, or charity; and (3) any property holdings failing to meet
the first two requirements must be "rectified" through redistribution.
Nozick rejects the notion that justice requires any specific distribution
of rewards. On the contrary, if a particular "pattern" of distribution
were enforced, then government would have to confiscate and redistrib-
ute income earned in the market, thus violating individual liberty.
Nozick also dismisses any conception of justice linking reward with indi-
vidual merit. There are many possible criteria of merit including effort,
need, productivity, contribution, social status, or virtue, but society has
no way of objectively choosing from among these criteria. Therefore,
Nozick argues, any effort to assess individual merit and reward it would
be arbitrary.
Nozick instead proposes the following definition of justice: "from each
as they choose, to each as they are chosen." Each person's reward should
be determined by his or her choices of what to offer in the market and by
other people's choices to buy the person's goods or services. Personal
income may be justifiably low if an individual chooses not to offer much
or if what is offered is not desired by others.
For Nozick, inequality is the result of individual choice. So long as peo-
ple are free to choose, markets will tend to generate inequality, but this
inequality will be fair. In fact, attempts by government to interfere with
market distributions are the major cause of injustice. Nozick equates
taxation with slavery, claiming that it forces citizens to work for the
48 Political Economy
Neo-Austrian E c o n o m i c s
The conquest of Austria by the German army during World War II forced
many intellectuals in that country to emigrate. Ludwig von Mises
(1881-1973) and Friedrich A. Hayek were the principle carriers of Austrian
economics to England and the United States. Although never fully embraced
by mainstream economists, Mises and Hayek managed to gain the respect
of influential economists such as Lionel Robbins (1898-1984), Fritz
Machlup (1881-1973), Oskar Morgenstern (1902-1977), and Gottfried
Haberler. More recently, a neo-Austrian school of thought has developed in
the United States under the leadership of Israel Kirzner, Murray Rothbard
(1926-1995), and Roger Garrison. Neo-Austrian writings are featured in
the Austrian Economics Newsletter, the Journal of Libertarian Studies,
Social Philosophy & Policy, and Critical Review.
Although neo-Austrians are committed to free markets and personal lib-
erty, they reject the neoclassical assumption that individuals possess full
information. If full information prevailed, then planners could conceivably
replicate the market, and the defense of private property would be weakened.
50 Political Economy
New Classical E c o n o m i c s
When Keynesian policies faltered in the early 1970s, Classical Liberals
were quick to fill the theoretical void. New classical economics describes
the modern revival of laissez-faire ideas from the nineteenth century. Some
of its leading proponents are Thomas Sargent, Neal Wallace, Robert Lucas,
and Robert Barro. Writings by new classical economists can be found in the
Journal of Political Economy and the American Economic Review.
New classical economists focus on the role of expectations in affecting
individual behavior. Sargent and Wallace developed the theory of "rational
expectations" to demonstrate the fallacy of Keynesian efforts to lower the
rate of unemployment. If citizens have rational expectations, their behav-
ior will take into account any anticipated effects of government policy.
When government attempts to stimulate the economy, citizens anticipat-
ing greater inflation will raise their wage demands, thereby offsetting any
tendency for employers to hire more workers. In short, any deliberate
effort by government to increase economic activity will be frustrated by
the reactions of citizens seeking to defend their income against antici-
pated inflation. The new classical economists conclude that government
cannot lower the level of unemployment and therefore ought to abandon
such attempts.
Closely related to new classical economics are two other theoretical
approaches: monetarism and supply-side economics. The former, champi-
oned by Milton Friedman, seeks to revive the classical idea that the amount
of money in the economy affects prices but not the level of employment or
output. Monetarists conclude that active monetary policy by the Federal
Reserve System can have no positive impact on unemployment and there-
fore should be abandoned in favor of steady growth of the money supply
at a rate sufficient to accommodate increases in real output.
52 Political Economy
ADDITIONAL READING
Barry, Norman P. Hayek's Social and Economic Philosophy. London: Macmillan,
1979.
Boaz, David, ed. The Libertarian Reader. New York: The Free Press, 1997.
Boaz, David, and Edward H. Crane, eds. Market Liberalism: A Paradigm for the
21st Century. Washington, DC: Cato Institute, 1993.
Brittan, Samuel. A Restatement of Economic Liberalism, 2nd ed. London:
Macmillan, 1988.
Buchanan, James M. Post-socialist Political Economy. Lyme, NH: Edward Elgar,
1997.
Burke, T. Patrick. Ethical Principles for a Free Market. New York: Paragon House,
1993.
Conway, David. Classical Liberalism: The Unvanquished Ideal. New York: St.
Martin's, 1995.
Friedman, Milton. Capitalism and Freedom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1962.
Friedman, Milton, and Rose Friedman. Free to Choose: A Personal Statement. New
York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1980.
Hendrickson, Mark W., ed. The Morality of Capitalism. Irvington-on-Hudson, NY:
The Foundation for Economic Education, 1996.
Machan, Tibor. Capitalism and Individualism. New York: St. Martin's, 1990.
McKenzie, Richard, and Gordon Tullock. Modem Political Economy. New York:
McGraw-Hill, 1978.
Rand, Ayn. Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal. New York: Signet, 1967.
Roberts, Paul Craig. The Supply-Side Revolution. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1984.
Rockwell, Llewellyn H., Jr., ed. The Free Market Reader. Burlingame, CA: The
Ludwig von Mises Institute, 1988.
Rothbard, Murray. For a New Liberty. New York: Collier-Macmillan, 1978.
Rowley, Charles K. Liberty and the State. Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar, 1993.
Schotter, Andrew. Free Market Economics. New York: St. Martin's, 1985.
Shand, Alexander H. Free Market Morality: The Political Economy of the Austrian
School New York: Routledge, 1989.
Stigler, George J., ed. Chicago Studies in Political Economy. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1988.
Vaughn, Karen I. Austrian Economics in America. New York: Cambridge
University Press, 1994.
This page intentionally left blank
Chapter 4
ARCHITECTS OF RADICALISM
Jean Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778)
Unlike Hobbes's and Locke's portrayal of humans as self-interested crea-
tures who establish government only to protect their individual rights, the
56 Political Economy
debate would create shared values and a sense of solidarity. Rousseau also
believed that democracy and freedom required greater equality of property
holdings so that no citizen would be completely dependent on others for
survival. This equality would be maintained by a progressive income tax, a
tax on luxury goods, and government regulation of economic activity.
Although Rousseau was a vehement critic of repressive governments, his
legacy has provided support for totalitarianism. By portraying narrow self-
interest as immoral and damaging to society, Rousseau created the ratio-
nale for extending government control over all aspects of life to assure that
private interests do not interfere with the public good. While Rousseau
relied on small communities to harmonize private and public interests with-
out coercion, the potential for oppression increases as the size of the com-
munity grows. If the community is an entire nation, the opportunities for
meaningful political participation are limited, and any proclaimed general
will is likely to reflect the decisions of a small ruling party. Without politi-
cal participation, enforcement of the general will will be perceived as
oppressive by many citizens.
Karl Marx ( 1 8 1 8 - 1 8 8 3 )
Marx, a German political economist, spent most of his adult life in
London. After earning a doctorate in philosophy at the University of
Berlin, where he was heavily influenced by the ideas of G. W. F. Hegel,
Marx discovered socialism by reading the works of the Utopian socialists,
including Fourier and Saint-Simon. A friendship with Friedrich Engels
(1820-1895) established a lifelong working relationship resulting in many
coauthored works.
Marx believed that the material conditions of society, specifically the
production process, exerted a profound influence on all other dimensions
of human existence, including politics, religion, and ideas. Marx's critics
have labeled his approach "economic determinism," but he acknowledged
mutual interaction among the economy, other social institutions, and
human consciousness.
Marx mocked the Utopian socialists for their naive belief that small
groups of people could simply retreat from capitalist society to form com-
munities based on collective property. Without the benefits of modern tech-
nology, the division of labor, and large-scale production, these communities
would be doomed to poverty and failure. Marx was convinced that a suc-
cessful socialism could emerge only out of capitalist society, so he dedicated
himself to understanding the inner workings of the capitalist system and
the reasons for its ultimate demise.
According to Marx, the accumulation of capital is the driving force
shaping all other aspects of the social system. In Das Kapital (1867), he
analyzed the process by which capital seeks self-expansion through profits.
58 Political Economy
Edward B e r n s t e i n ( 1 8 5 0 - 1 9 3 2 )
Because of his political activism, Edward Bernstein was exiled from his
native Germany and lived in England from 1880 to 1901. Bernstein formed
a strong friendship with Friedrich Engels and became a major figure in
Marxist political circles. At the same time, however, Bernstein met Sidney
and Beatrice Webb (1859-1947 and 1858-1943), who had founded a
Radical group called the Fabian Society. Under the influence of the Fabians,
Bernstein concluded that orthodox Marxism had been rendered obsolete
by the evolving nature of capitalism. The middle class was growing rather
than disappearing, workers' standards of living were rising, ownership was
being dispersed through the public sale of corporate stock, and the increas-
ing market power of large corporations was putting an end to cut-throat
competition. Bernstein concluded that neither the collapse of capitalism
nor a proletarian revolution was inevitable. Instead, socialism could be
ushered in gradually and peacefully through the democratic political
process because workers outnumbered capitalists. To facilitate this process,
political leadership and educational programs were needed to demonstrate
to workers that their interests lay with socialism.
In Evolutionary Socialism (1899), Bernstein explicitly broke his allegiance
to Marxism. He objected to the Hegelian aspects of Marxism that portrayed
history as the inevitable movement toward a predetermined endpoint. In addi-
tion, Bernstein rejected Marx's claims to have developed a science of society.
Socialism, he claimed, would materialize not because "laws of motion" would
determine the course of history, but because socialism was a morally superior
and hence more appealing system for a large majority of the population.
In place of Hegel, Bernstein relied on the ethics of the German philoso-
pher Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) to argue that capitalism was immoral
because it encouraged people to regard one another as means to achieve
their own private ends. Socialism, by contrast, would enable people to
respect and be compassionate toward others without falling behind in a
competitive struggle for dominance. Bernstein's ideas were important in
establishing a Radical tradition known as "revisionism," which provided
the basis for social democratic political parties in Europe.
60 Political Economy
Thorstein Veblen ( 1 8 5 7 - 1 9 2 9 )
A distinctly American brand of Radicalism was founded by Thorstein
Veblen, a political economist whose caustic critique of corporate capitalism
and bourgeois lifestyles influenced American social theory significantly. In
his book The Theory of the Leisure Class (1899), Veblen contrasted
"dynamic" aspects of society such as science, the use of tools, and the
"instinct for workmanship," with "static" aspects such as superstition, rit-
ual, and habit. Veblen praised modern technology for undermining old tra-
ditions and myths, but argued that capitalist production, with its focus on
profits, tended to thwart the potential dynamism of technology.
Although capitalism was once a progressive force in vanquishing feudal
customs and authority, it spawned a new privileged class. This "leisure
class" had little direct involvement in production but lived in splendor on
income derived from the ownership of property. Veblen argued that the
leisure class interfered with the efficiency of capitalism by serving as role
models for the rest of society. The extravagant lifestyles of the rich set a
standard to which all other classes aspired. Unable to afford genuine lux-
ury, the middle and lower classes attempted to emulate the leisure class by
engaging in "conspicuous consumption." Since the motivation behind con-
spicuous consumption is to relieve the insecurity and sense of inferiority
created by the existence of a leisure class, Veblen concluded that abolishing
this class would conserve resources and make everyone happier.
Another problem created by the leisure class is erosion of the "instinct
for workmanship." While capitalism depends on the work ethic, Veblen
argued that the frivolous lifestyle of the leisure class creates frustration
and resentment throughout society. Seeking to emulate the leisure class,
people develop an aversion to work and seek shortcuts to success. Even
businesses are prone to this syndrome. Rather than encouraging innova-
tion and the production of high-quality products, corporations try to
manipulate the market and the consumer in pursuit of short-term profits.
Veblen coined the term "planned obsolescence" to describe the manufac-
ture of products that quickly deteriorate, forcing consumers to replace
them often.
Veblen believed that modern technology made large corporations and
concentrations of business power inevitable. Returning to an earlier era of
competitive capitalism was not a feasible option, so he proposed that con-
trol of corporations be delegated to engineers and scientists who, by virtue
of their training and temperament, focus on efficiency and quality. By rely-
ing on "technocrats" to restore dynamism to modern societies, Veblen
steered a path between capitalism and Marxian socialism. While convinced
of the waste and inefficiency of modern capitalism, he was also critical of
Marx and had no confidence in government expropriation of the means of
production. He anticipated that scientists and engineers would operate
The Radical Perspective 61
V. I. Lenin ( 1 8 7 0 - 1 9 2 4 )
Vladimir Ilyich Ulyanov, Russian theorist and activist who adopted the
name "Lenin," led the first successful socialist revolution in 1917. An
extremely forceful personality and skilled debater, Lenin almost single-
handedly refashioned Marxism to address the particular situation of Russia
in the early twentieth century. Because Marx had said very little about con-
ducting a revolution or about the nature of postrevolutionary society,
Lenin faced a formidable task.
Marx had envisioned socialism as arising from the misery and alien-
ation of workers in the most advanced capitalist countries. Moreover,
given Marx's predictions of centralized business power and a vanishing
middle class, the workers would constitute a vast majority of the popula-
tion so that a proletarian revolution would be spontaneous, widely sup-
ported, and democratic. In contrast, Lenin was faced with a backward
country ruled by an autocratic tsar and lacking a large industrial working
class. In What Is To Be Done? (1902), Lenin proposed that a "vanguard
party" of dedicated intellectuals take responsibility for initiating the revo-
lution and providing leadership for the masses. He also urged Radicals to
resist the temptation to join reform movements that would accomplish
only minor changes in the status quo; a genuine revolution was the only
solution to Russia's backwardness.
In Imperialism, The Highest Stage of Capitalism (1916), Lenin developed
another theoretical argument favoring the possibility of revolution in Russia.
He claimed that capitalism had evolved from its earlier competitive phase
into a monopoly phase that required corporations to move beyond national
boundaries in their quest for cheap resources and markets for their products.
Imperialism had three major consequences. First, it generated higher profits,
thereby permitting capitalists to pay higher wages to their workers in the
industrialized countries of Western Europe and North America. Lenin con-
cluded that workers in these countries had unwittingly become incorporated
into the exploiting class because they were benefitting from the profits
extracted from their fellow workers in the less-developed countries. As an
"aristocracy of labor," workers in the industrialized countries could no
62 Political Economy
Jiirgen Habermas ( 1 9 2 9 - )
Habermas is a German social theorist whose prolific writings during
the past thirty years have had a major impact on Radical thought. Like
many Radicals, Habermas was deeply disillusioned by Stalinism and the
authoritarian nature of the Soviet Union. Rather than dismissing Soviet
practices as an aberration from true Marxism, he has attempted to con-
struct a new Radicalism more explicitly sensitive to concerns about
individual freedom.
In Knowledge and Human Interests (1968), Habermas argues that
humans have three distinct types of interests: an interest in controlling
nature, an interest in improved communication with others, and an inter-
est in eliminating oppressive social structures. He indicts capitalism for
promoting the interest in control at the expense of the interests in commu-
nication and liberation. The profit motive constantly drives firms to
increase the technical efficiency of their production; this pressure spreads
throughout society as education, social interaction, family life, and recre-
ation become merely rational means to achieve the end of greater wealth.
Instead of earning money to live a more expressive and fulfilling life, peo-
ple learn to structure their lives to increase their earning potential.
The Radical Perspective 63
PRINCIPLES OF RADICALISM
The following definitions capture many of the essential features of the
Radical perspective.
Human Nature. Humans have certain biological needs and a capacity
for reason, but their social and natural environments significantly affect
their consciousness and behavior. The social context provided by language,
traditions, values, and modes of interaction is so essential to human devel-
opment that individuals cannot fully realize their talents and capacities
except in association with other persons.
Society. Society is more than just a collection of individuals. Society is a
living organism into which individuals enter at birth and leave at death.
Because society precedes the individual, it has interests apart from—and
potentially conflicting with—any particular individual's desires. A good
society encourages the fullest possible range of personal development and
social relations based on mutual respect.
Government. Government properly serves as the representative of the
collective interests of citizens. Government permits citizens to do for them-
selves collectively what they cannot accomplish as individuals.
Morality. Although Marxists have traditionally rejected the notion of a
Radical ethic, non-Marxist Radicals find a basis for morality in the human
need for social relationships based on mutual respect. An individual action
or a social system is immoral if it treats people as objects and demeans
their humanity.
64 Political Economy
RADICALISM TODAY
The brutality of Stalinism during the 1930s and 1940s was a major blow
to the credibility of Radical ideas. After World War II, the anticommunism
of the McCarthy era effectively suppressed Radical voices in America until
the 1960s. However, with the emergence of mass political movements for
civil rights, student power, women's liberation, environmental protection
and an end to the war in Vietnam, the Radical perspective enjoyed a renais-
sance. Three of the most important contemporary Radical schools of thought
are institutional economics, social economics, and post-Marxian theory.
Institutional Economics
Institutional economics arose out of Thorstein Veblen's scathing criti-
cism of both Marxism and neoclassical economics. Veblen found the neo-
classical portrayal of autonomous individuals rationally pursuing
maximum utility to be as implausible as the Hegelian dialectics underlying
Marxism. He proposed to analyze the economy as an evolving process
embedded in an institutional framework including the legal system,
political system, educational system, family life, work, customs, and ethics.
Because the entire array of institutions allocates society's resources and dis-
tributes income, to study the market in abstraction would be a pointless
and misleading exercise.
Veblen's approach was indebted to two major intellectual influences.
Pragmatism, a philosophical perspective developed by John Dewey
The Radical Perspective 65
have been reluctant to specify their visions of the proper balance between
market and government, but underlying their approach is an emphasis on the
Radical values of equality and community.
Among the prominent contemporary institutionalists are Daniel
Fusfeld, Marc Tool, Douglas Dowd, Ron Stanfield, and William Dugger.
Institutionalist writings are presented in the Journal of Economic Issues.
Social Economics
The roots of social economics lie in nineteenth-century continental
European economic thought. German and French political economists
exhibited much greater skepticism toward free markets than did their British
counterparts. They were particularly concerned about the effects of markets
on culture and the spiritual well-being of citizens. In 1931, Pope Pius XI
issued an encyclical criticizing markets for undermining the moral basis of
society. In 1941, the Catholic Economic Association (CEA) was founded in
the United States as part of an effort to engage Christian ethics and eco-
nomic theory. In 1970, the CEA changed its name to the Association for
Social Economics and opened membership to non-Catholics.
Social economics also has secular roots. In 1936, John Maurice Clark
(1884-1963), an ex-president of the American Economic Association,
published Preface to Social Economics, in which he urged the inclusion of
values and ethics in economic reasoning. Over the past half-century, social
economics has been closely linked with institutional economics as many of
the same theorists identify with both schools of thought. Prominent con-
temporary social economists include Amitai Etzioni, Warren Samuels, and
Stephen Worland. The major journals in which writings from this tradi-
tion can be found are the Review of Social Economy and the Forum for
Social Economics.
Like institutional economists, social economists have devoted much of
their effort to criticizing neoclassical economics and constructing alterna-
tive methods for analyzing economic activity. Social economics is touted as
offering a more integrated, holistic, evolutionary approach incorporating
social, cultural, and political factors into its understanding of economic
affairs. The ethical vision of social economists points toward greater equal-
ity, decentralization, and accountability of power, and the priority of
human development over profit.
Post-Marxian Theory
During the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, Marxism was
hardly visible in the United States due to rising standards of living and gov-
ernment repression of Radical organizations. Even when the Great
Depression triggered a resurgence of Radicalism, little of it was explicitly
The Radical Perspective 67
Marxist. By the 1950s, Marxian economics in the United States was con-
fined primarily to the works of two theorists—Paul Sweezy, the editor of
Monthly Review, and Paul Baran (1909-1964), a professor of economics
at Stanford University.
However, the 1960s witnessed a renewal of the Marxist tradition. Under
the umbrella of the Union for Radical Political Economics (URPE), Marx-
ism gained recognition as a legitimate field of scholarly research. However,
few Marxists in the United States or Europe aligned themselves with the
Soviet version of socialism as consisting of centralized planning, public own-
ership of all means of production, and an authoritarian government.
Western Marxists sought to develop new critiques of capitalism that would
eventually lead to decentralized, democratic, and participatory forms of
socialism. Within this "post-Marxian" tradition, a variety of approaches
have flourished. Some theorists, including Howard Sherman, Duncan Foley,
and David Laibman, have retained traditional Marxian concepts such as the
labor theory of value and the falling rate of profit. Writings from this per-
spective can be found in journals such as Marxism Today, Science &
Society, and the Review of Radical Political Economics.
A second post-Marxian approach rejects most of Marx's theoretical cat-
egories, claiming that changes in capitalism have rendered Marx's original
analysis obsolete. Marx himself is criticized for being insufficiently sensi-
tive to issues of individuality, race, gender, and pluralism. Indeed, theorists
from this perspective are so intent on preserving individual rights and
enlarging the scope of freedom and democracy that they might be labeled
"post-liberals" rather than post-Marxians. Among the most prominent the-
orists representing this approach are Herbert Gintis, David Gordon
(1944-1996), Samuel Bowles, Richard Edwards, and Thomas Weisskopf.
This perspective is represented in journals such as Politics & Society,
Socialist Review, Radical America, and New Left Review.
A third version of post-Marxism is called analytical Marxism. Theorists
such as John Roemer, Jon Elster, and Adam Przeworski have adopted the
techniques of neoclassical economics, including game theory and mathe-
matical modeling, to demonstrate Marxian concepts such as exploitation
and class conflict. Finally, other post-Marxian theorists, including Richard
Wolff, Stephen Resnick, and Jack Amariglio, have sought to revitalize
Marxian analysis by introducing concepts from contemporary philosophy
including poststructuralism and postmodernism. Their writings are pre-
sented in the journal Rethinking Marxism.
Post-Marxian visions of socialism do not preclude the possibility of con-
siderable private ownership of property and reliance on markets. To pre-
vent abuses of government power, post-Marxians emphasize the necessity
of participatory democracy; elected officials and bureaucrats should be
publicly accountable for their actions, and citizens should be actively
involved in the political process. Another bulwark against tyranny is
68 Political Economy
AN ASSESSMENT OF RADICALISM
Radicalism grew out of the industrialization process of Western Europe.
A new class appeared, lacking access to productive property and, therefore,
having no means of support except selling labor for wages. As capitalism
undermined the self-sufficiency of rural areas, farmers flocked to the cities,
only to find squalor, disease, horrendous working conditions, and subsis-
tence wages. These conditions contrasted so sharply with the bright future
anticipated by Enlightenment thinkers that attention turned toward private
wealth as the last bastion of privilege and unaccountable power. Some
workers and intellectuals began to demand the abolition of private owner-
ship of large-scale means of production.
Radical demands for greater equality have been partially realized
through the welfare state. By threatening to confiscate property, Radicals
forced the wealthy to make concessions. For example, the extension of civil
and human rights in democratic societies has given workers greater pro-
tection against the power of employers. Government support for labor
unions and a minimum wage partially insulates workers from competitive
market forces.
The perennial appeal of Radicalism is the vision of human liberation.
Radicalism shares the hope fundamental to nearly all religions—the com-
ing of a new age when people will live together in universal peace and pros-
perity. Marxism has been called a religion for those who have lost faith in
God. Radicalism also holds out a more secular appeal with its promise of
giving people control over their lives and destiny by restructuring social
institutions. For those who feel oppressed by slave owners, feudal lords, or
capitalist bosses, this opportunity for self-determination through coopera-
tion has been a powerful magnet.
With its emphasis on the social dimension of human existence,
Radicalism is attuned to Western religious and ethical beliefs that have tra-
ditionally condemned selfishness. Even if the pursuit of self-interest pro-
motes economic prosperity, theorists have perennially been concerned with
its potential for undermining individual virtue and distorting human rela-
tions. By appealing to the human capacities for cooperation and compas-
sion, Radicalism stakes out the moral highground in its confrontation with
liberal individualism.
Despite these strengths, the Radical perspective is currently in consider-
able disarray. Radicalism has been badly tarnished by the behavior of gov-
ernments purportedly following Marxist principles. The bleak and
The Radical Perspective 69
ADDITIONAL READING
Attewell, Paul. Radical Political Economy Since the Sixties. New Brunswick, NJ
Rutgers University Press, 1984.
Bowles, Samuel, and Richard Edwards, eds. Radical Political Economy. Brookfield,
VT: Edward Elgar, 1989.
Burkitt, Brian. Radical Political Economy. New York: New York University
Press, 1984.
Coughlin, Richard M., ed. Morality, Rationality, and Efficiency: New Perspectiv
on Socio-Economics, Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1991.
Dugger, William M., ed. Radical Institutionalism. Westport, CT: Greenwood,
1989.
Edwards, Richard C, Michael Reich, and Thomas E. Weisskopf. The Capitalist
System, 3rd ed. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1985.
Fold vary, Fred E., ed. Beyond Neo-classical Economics. Brookfield, VT: Edwar
Elgar, 1996.
Heilbroner, Robert. Marxism: For and Against. New York: W. W. Norton, 1980.
. The Nature and Logic of Capitalism. New York: W. W. Norton, 1985.
Lippit, Victor D., ed. Radical Political Economy: Explorations in Alternative
Economic Analysis. Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1996.
Mosely, Fred. Heterodox Economic Theories: True or False. Brookfield, VT:
Edward Elgar, 1995.
Roberts, Bruce, and Sue Finer, eds. Radical Economics. Boston: Kluwer, 1992.
Sawyer, Malcolm C. The Challenge of Radical Political Economy: An Introduction
to Alternatives to Neo-Classical Economics. Savage, MD: Barnes 6c Noble,
1989.
Sayer, Andrew R. Radical Political Economy: A Critique. Cambridge: Blackwell
1995.
Sherman, Howard J. Foundations of Radical Political Economy. Armonk, NY:
M. E. Sharpe, 1987.
Stanfield, J. Ron. Economics, Power and Culture: Essays in the Development of
Radical Institutionalism. New York: St. Martin's, 1995.
Wolff, Richard D., and Stephen A. Resnick. Economics: Marxian versus Neo-clas-
sical. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1987.
Chapter 5
The Conservative
Perspective
ARCHITECTS OF CONSERVATISM
E d m u n d Burke ( 1 7 2 9 - 1 7 9 7 )
Burke, a member of the British parliament and a distinguished orator,
was a reform-minded Whig who opposed royal authority and supported
the American quest for independence. He was not opposed to change in
The Conservative Perspective 73
T h o m a s Carlyle ( 1 7 9 5 - 1 8 8 1 )
Carlyle, a British social critic and historian, was a major figure in the
Conservative reaction to industrialization. He feared that commercial society
74 Political Economy
was destroying the emotional bonds and sense of duty that made civilization
possible. In particular, Carlyle scorned classical political economy, calling it
"the dismal science" and "pig philosophy" because it portrayed society as
an arena in which pleasure-seeking individuals struggle against each other
to get ahead.
Carlyle believed in the necessity of a hierarchical society governed by
charismatic leaders who could generate consensus among different groups.
Yet he was not simply a defender of the status quo. He blamed the British
aristocracy for neglecting its duty to govern wisely as it was swept up in the
capitalist pursuit of pleasure and profit. In On Heroes and Hero-Worship
(1841), he claimed that certain individuals are born leaders and should be
permitted to rise to positions of power. Unlike Burke, Carlyle admired
Robespierre and other leaders of the French Revolution for seizing the
opportunity to regenerate a stagnant society.
However, Carlyle was no democrat; he viewed rule by the masses as a
tragedy stemming from the aristocracy's failure to govern wisely.
Democracy spawns a clamor of competing interests, each lacking a vision
of the public good. His preferred model of society was revealed by his
admiration of Prussia and its military spirit. The ideal society would have
no political campaigns or elections. The wisest and most capable individu-
als would simply be promoted to positions of authority as is done in an
army. A hierarchical and authoritarian society promotes order, discipline,
cohesion, and a sense of purpose. Such societies become great nations and
citizens prosper both materially and spiritually.
In addition to his rejection of democracy, Carlyle condemned liberal
notions of freedom. If freedom means that individuals have no duties
restraining them, then the free pursuit of desires will lead to anarchy and
the destruction of society. Genuine freedom can be achieved only in the
context of a society based on shared values and common goals. Carlyle
feared that capitalism was undermining freedom and order by replacing the
traditional hierarchy based on virtue and wisdom with a new hierarchy
based on wealth. Traditional hierarchy had been a stabilizing force because
each class recognized its duties and functions; the aristocracy would gov-
ern wisely, while the rest of the population labored and lived in peace.
However, because capitalism promotes competition among self-interested
individuals, the resulting hierarchy of wealth does not carry with it any
sense of social obligation. Those who succeed feel no duty to wield their
power for the social good, and those who fail have little respect for or alle-
giance to society and its leaders.
To dampen the effects of capitalism, Carlyle proposed that political lead-
ers should take responsibility for the moral and spiritual regeneration of
society through a government-sponsored national church. In addition, gov-
ernment could provide public assistance programs, regulation of business,
and efforts to reform social relations within factories. While granting that
The Conservative Perspective 75
Vilfredo Pare to ( 1 8 4 8 - 1 9 2 3 )
An Italian economist and sociologist who spent most of his career at the
University of Lausanne in Switzerland, Pareto's fame derives primarily
from his book Manual of Political Economy (1906) in which he argued
that competitive markets and free trade result in an efficient allocation of
resources. His definition of efficiency, now referred to as "Pareto optimal-
ity," was a situation in which no reallocation can make one person better
off without making another person worse off.
Despite his arguments for the economic advantages of free markets,
Pareto's Conservatism, exhibited in The Mind and Society (1916), led him
to claim that all societies are naturally and inevitably controlled by elites.
He even developed a mathematical formula, known as "Pareto's law,"
showing the degree of inequality that is natural for any society. In addition
to defending a natural hierarchy, Pareto argued that power passes back and
forth between two fundamentally different elite groups. He used the label
"foxes" to describe cunning, flexible, risk-taking elites. Foxes are likely to
be innovative capitalists who thrive in a dynamic social environment. Lions,
on the other hand, are resistant to change and willing to use force to defend
the status quo. Lions are found in the aristocracy and in that portion of the
capitalist class that has made its fortune and now lives on property income.
When foxes control the government, society is dynamic and markets are
relatively free, but foxes will not exert the force necessary to maintain an
orderly society. In particular, the openness of a fox-controlled government
permits non-elites, such as workers and farmers, to gain greater political
power. In response to political instability, lions will overthrow the fox gov-
ernment in a "circulation of elites." Lions will use whatever force necessary
to restore order. They are likely to suppress free trade and to restrict
democracy, but these actions protect property and profits from the dangers
of egalitarian social reforms.
Pareto believed that both foxes and lions are essential to society. Foxes
sustain economic prosperity but fail to resist disorder, while lions defend
private property but are likely to cause the economy to stagnate under
their heavy-handed tactics. When Benito Mussolini and the Italian fascists
took power in 1921, they honored Pareto as an intellectual founder and,
76 Political Economy
Leo S t r a u s s ( 1 8 9 9 - 1 9 7 3 )
Leo Strauss, a political philosopher at the University of Chicago for
many years, devoted himself to resolving what he called "the crisis of
modernity"—the corrosive effects of the Enlightenment legacy of individu-
alism, ethical relativism, and faith in technology. In Natural Right and
History (1953), he contrasted two conceptions of natural right. In Greek
and early Christian society, natural right was based on a morality existing
independently of individual desires. Humans had a moral duty to seek the
good, and the purpose of politics was to cultivate virtue among citizens.
By contrast, early liberal theorists such as Hobbes and Locke used the
notion of natural right to refer to the rights of autonomous individuals to
pursue their self-interest without arbitrary restraint. This liberal version of
natural right unlinked the earlier connection between rights and corre-
sponding moral duties. Although Hobbes and Locke may have contributed
to the toppling of the aristocratic power structure, they opened a Pandora's
box of social disruptions. According to Strauss, when moral issues are rel-
egated to individual choice, society will lack standards of excellence, truth,
justice, and beauty. By making individual autonomy the primary social
value, liberalism transforms society into a mass of rootless individuals pur-
suing their private passions, undermines the moral framework essential to
nurturing civic virtue, and thereby condemns humans to alienation, anomie,
narcissism, decadence, and nihilism.
78 Political Economy
PRINCIPLES OF CONSERVATISM
The essential tenets of Conservatism are summarized in the following
definitions:
Human Nature. Humans are driven by strong passions that can be
directed toward either evil or good. The human capacity for reason is lim-
ited, with some persons having greater rational powers than others. The
manner in which instincts and desires are molded into a unique
personality is a function of the roles played and associations formed with
80 Political Economy
CONSERVATISM TODAY
Conservatism's inability to gain widespread popularity in the United
States has been attributed to the country's revolutionary origins, to the
absence of a feudal aristocracy, and to the emphasis on freedom of indi-
vidual choice. During the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries,
American Conservatism was found almost exclusively in the South, where
the plantation system and slavery were ideally suited for an ideology that
emphasized the importance of hierarchical community.
However, Conservatism was revitalized by the devastation wrought by
World War I and the Great Depression. These events served to undermine
the faith in reason and progress that had characterized Western societies
since the Enlightenment. As skeptics toward reason and science,
Conservatives often expressed their ideas in poetry and literature. T. S. Eliot
(1888-1965) and Ezra Pound (1885-1972) claimed that societies commit-
ted to individualism and technological progress were increasingly charac-
terized by mindless conformity, cultural degeneracy, and a loss of purpose.
They blamed both capitalism and democracy for degrading human spiritu-
ality and creativity. Capitalism's mass production breeds mediocrity, moral
decay, and insipid consumerism. Citizens of a "mass society" lose the capac-
ity for independent thought and seek only passive forms of entertainment
that make no demands on their intellectual or artistic capacities.
Conservatives have largely ignored neoclassical economic theory, claim-
ing that it reflects the worst aspects of modern society—the alienation of
the individual from social bonds and community values, the focus on mate-
rial gratification of sensual appetites, and the elevation of profitmaking and
efficiency as the guiding values for society. Economics, according to
Conservatives, serves to justify acquisitive and selfish behavior, thereby
undermining the cohesiveness and stability of society. The ethic of utility-
maximization legitimizes a materialistic lifestyle in which the consumption
of commodities is the primary source of pleasure.
However, in contrast to traditional economic theory, political economy
can accommodate a vision of society as a community bearing responsibil-
ity for the quality of life of its citizens. Conservative writers who find eco-
nomic matters too important to be left to liberal economists, are now
devoting considerable attention to political economy. Conservative politi-
cal economy currently appears in a variety of forms including neo-fascist
theory, corporatism, and neoconservatism.
Neo-fascist Theory
a strategy for restoring the ideals that had been vanquished by a century of
industrialization and modernization. As practiced in Germany and Italy
during the 1930s and 1940s, traditional fascism relied on a charismatic
leader to mobilize society, renew national and racial unity, and conduct vio-
lence and war against threats to the nation.
The roots of fascism lie in the romantic and nationalist beliefs that
Western civilization has been in a state of moral and cultural decline ever
since the Enlightenment unleashed the corrosive forces of individualism,
rationalism, atheism, and materialism. As traditional values, institutions,
and communities are destroyed, humans become alienated, culture degen-
erates, and society slowly crumbles.
Although World War II was fought to defeat fascism, considerable evi-
dence appears today of "neo-fascist" sentiments in both Europe and the
United States. During the 1980s, groups such as the Order, Aryan Nations,
White Aryan Resistance, and the Posse Comitatus proliferated. The eco-
nomic prosperity of the 1990s has undermined the growth of such organi-
zations, but numerous unofficial state militias have formed and young
"skinheads" give Nazi salutes and desecrate Jewish synagogues and ceme-
teries. Neo-fascism appeals to subordinate groups experiencing alienation
and a sense of powerlessness. It promises to restore both economic pros-
perity and national or racial pride.
Neo-fascism condemns liberals for making individual freedom the
supreme value, thereby denigrating the importance of community.
Liberalism breeds an abstract, universal mentality that mocks parochial,
local, or even national values as narrow and prejudiced and therefore
inappropriate for society as a whole. Only abstract values, such as free-
dom and tolerance, are acceptable to liberalism. However, these values
fail to reinforce people's emotional commitments to particular ethnic,
racial, or national communities. Liberalism wants to replace the
parochial community with "the brotherhood of man," but a global com-
munity remains merely an abstraction and cannot meet the emotional
needs of humans for a sense of belonging and attachment. If humans
attempt to identify with all mankind, they end up identifying with noth-
ing concrete and become alienated.
The linkage of liberal ideas with the quest for a global community
explains why neo-fascists regard communism and "one-world govern-
ment" as the logical culmination of liberalism and democracy. Communists
exploit the human need for community by promising a new society based
on equality and collective ownership of the means of production. But com-
munism suppresses the human need for private property and for member-
ship in a specific community based on race, ethnicity, or nationality. Only
neo-fascism can speak to these needs while simultaneously combating the
torpor and decadence generated by liberal democracy. Neo-fascism, there-
fore, represents a battle against both communism and capitalism. It relies
The Conservative Perspective 83
Corporatism
Corporatism proposes to reduce conflict and resentment in society by
establishing organizations for each particular occupation or industry. These
groups would provide individuals with communities in which to overcome
the isolation and alienation of modern society. The various organizations
would be integrated into a cooperative framework, with government serv-
ing as the ultimate authority and mediator. By consolidating individual
interests into large groups, corporatists intend to place decisionmaking in
the hands of group leaders who can resolve conflicts without resorting to
strikes or other forms of civil unrest.
Like fascism, corporatism has roots in romanticism and nationalism, but
it also grew out of the Roman Catholic church's vision of creating new
communities to replace those destroyed by industrialization and urbaniza-
tion. Early corporatist thinkers hoped that organizing capitalist society into
groups would reduce class conflict and social unrest. By the twentieth cen-
tury, corporatism was gaining increasing favor among capitalists as a solu-
tion to "cut-throat competition" in which all businesses were hurt. The
success of business-government cooperation during World War I per-
suaded many industrialists that corporatism was the wave of the future.
Indeed, corporatism was the basis for the National Industrial Recovery Act
(NIRA) of 1933, which was designed to combat the Great Depression by
giving labor the right to collectively bargain and by permitting corpora-
tions to cooperate with one another in establishing plans for production
and pricing.
Ironically, had the Supreme Court not declared the NIRA unconstitu-
tional in 1935, the United States would have embarked on a course bear-
ing similarities to the institutional framework of Nazi Germany. After the
NIRA was abolished, collective bargaining was reestablished through the
Wagner Act of 1935. Not until the late 1930s, when the United States
began preparing for war, did the Depression fade in response to the stimu-
lus of government spending. After World War II, corporatism was largely
discredited in the United States due to its similarity to fascism. However,
some business leaders continue to be attracted by the prospect of a coordi-
nated economy with no strikes and stable profits. During the economic tur-
moil of the 1970s, corporatist proposals were formulated by David
Rockefeller's Trilateral Commission, Henry Ford's Initiative Committee on
Economic Planning, and by the editors of Business Week magazine. Since
the Reagan years, corporatism has been largely dormant as business lead-
ers are generally satisfied with the performance of the economy.
a
Neoconservatism
A relatively new variant of Conservatism was formulated during the
1970s and 1980s by writers including Irving Kristol, Nathan Glazer,
Michael Novak, Peter Berger, Norman Podhoretz, Robert Nisbet,
Seymour Martin Lipset, and George Will. Neoconservative ideas can be
found in journals such as The Public Interest and Commentary. Many of
the neoconservatives were Radicals during their youth, but were pushed
toward Conservatism by their disgust with the student counterculture of
the 1960s, their dissatisfaction with the conciliatory nature of U.S. foreign
policy, and their disillusionment with the welfare state as a solution to
poverty and crime.
Neoconservatives present themselves as not much different from
Classical Liberals in their support for democracy, markets, and individual
liberty. However, while neoconservatives may appreciate the market's
vitality and efficiency, they also fear its potential for undermining tradi-
tional values and culture. The market stimulates and unleashes individual
desires for sensual gratification that conflict with the respect for authority,
the work ethic, and the sense of moral responsibility required for an
orderly society. Also, neoconservatives reject the ethical relativism of
Classical Liberalism, claiming that some values and lifestyles are better
than others. Finally, while neoconservatives oppose many current govern-
ment programs, they do defend a significant role for government in sus-
taining a social climate conducive to individual moral development and
social cohesion.
Neoconservatives claim that an "adversary culture" or "new class"
composed of professors, journalists, entertainers, social workers, health-
care professionals, and government bureaucrats has effectively captured
control of public opinion by virtue of its visibility and influence on the
media. These groups are assumed to be significantly more liberal than the
general population, and they use their power to build support for govern-
ment spending on social programs from which they directly benefit as
providers of health, education, and other human services.
The Conservative Perspective 85
AN ASSESSMENT OF CONSERVATISM
Conservatism has evolved over the past two centuries not so much
because of changes in its fundamental principles, but rather because of the
evolving nature of the problems confronting modern societies. Early
Conservatives blamed social disintegration and rootlessness on industrial-
ization and opposed both liberal democracy and laissez-faire capitalism. By
the end of the nineteenth century, however, a greater threat loomed on the
horizon as socialism became an influential political ideal soon to material-
ize in Russia. The prospect of socialism gaining a foothold in Western
nations caused Conservatives to suppress their concerns about capitalism.
After witnessing socialism in Russia and fascism in Germany and Italy,
most Conservatives conceded that capitalist democracy was the least evil of
all feasible systems. Since World War II, Conservatism has been wedded to
Classical Liberalism as the two formed a unified opposition to most forms
of government intervention.
However, Conservatives continue to believe that social order ultimately
rests on tradition and authority, and the market, with its emphasis on social
mobility and "getting ahead," undermines both. Conservatives are respect-
ful of government for its role as the visible representation of social unity,
while Classical Liberals often express contempt for government.
Conservatives also believe that social order requires some repression of
desires either by the individual's own commitment to virtue, by the social
conditioning provided by community values and institutions, or, ultimately,
by the threat of punishment from government. A capitalist market econ-
omy, on the other hand, fosters an ethic legitimizing the unbridled pursuit
of pleasure. Conservatives seek to maintain the integrity of national cul-
tures, while the market breeds cosmopolitan attitudes and lifestyles.
Finally, Conservatives uphold a morality based on objective values, but the
market makes the individual consumer the sole arbiter of values. This ten-
sion between the market and Conservative ideals explains why
Conservatives and Classical Liberals, despite their common interest in pro-
tecting private property and hierarchy, will never be entirely compatible.
With the dissolution of communism as a major threat to Western nations,
the alliance between Conservatives and Classical Liberals can be expected
to loosen, and the two perspectives will once again clash over their funda-
mentally different views of the market and government.
86 Political Economy
ADDITIONAL READING
Allison, Lincoln. Right Principles: A Conservative Philosophy of Politics. Oxfor
Basil Blackwell, 1984.
Buckley, William R, ed. Conservative Thought in the Twentieth Century. New
York: Bobbs-Merrill, 1970.
Drury, Shadia B. Leo Strauss and the American Right. New York: St. Martin's, 199
Holmes, Stephen. The Anatomy of Antiliberalism. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1993.
Kirk, Russell. The Conservative Mind: From Burke to Eliot. Washington, DC:
Henry Regnery, 1995.
Kristol, Irving. Neoconservatism: The Autobiography of an Ideal. New York: Th
Free Press, 1995.
Lakoff, George. Moral Politics: What Conservatives Know That Liberals Don't
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996.
Muller, Jerry Z., ed. Conservatism. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1997.
The Conservative Perspective 87
Nash, George. The Conservative Intellectual Movement in the U.S. since 1945.
New York: Basic Books, 1979.
Nisbet, Robert. Conservatism: Dream and Reality. Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 1986.
O'Sullivan, Noel. Conservatism. New York: St. Martin's, 1976.
Rossiter, Clinton. Conservatism in America, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1982.
Scruton, Roger. Conservative Texts: An Anthology. New York: St. Martin's, 1991.
Steinfels, Peter. The Neoconservatives: The Men Who Are Changing America's
Politics. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1979.
White, R. J., ed. The Conservative Tradition. New York: New York University
Press, 1957.
This page intentionally left blank
Chapter 6
used the term "natural" simply to defend their own particular vision of
the good society. Bentham sought instead to develop a scientific basis for
social theory. He based his theories on a system of ethics known as utili-
tarianism. In An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation
(1789), he claimed that pain and pleasure were the sole determinants of
human behavior and the sole criteria of right and wrong. For an individ-
ual or for society as a whole, the best course of action is that which max-
imizes pleasure and minimizes pain. Although Bentham acknowledged
the impossibility of measuring the pleasures of different persons and pre-
cisely calculating the social consequences of a particular policy, he sug-
gested that politicians should proceed as if such calculations could be
made. Only then would political decisions be based on an objective
assessment of their consequences.
To understand Bentham's motive for replacing natural law with utilitar-
ianism, we must focus on the changing political environment of late
eighteenth-century England. Classical Liberals had relied on the doctrines
of natural law and natural rights to support their arguments against the
arbitrary power of church and state. As that battle was being won, how-
ever, a new struggle between workers and owners of property began to
develop. With the grounds of political conflict shifting, the doctrine of nat-
ural rights became unacceptable to defenders of private property for two
reasons. First, Radicals such as Tom Paine had used the concept of natural
rights to defend workers' rights to participate in the political process.
Among property owners, the prospect of extending the vote to workers
raised fears of "mob rule" and a "tyranny of the majority" that might
eventually result in confiscation of property. Second, the doctrine of nat~
ural rights offered such firm protection for property that it precluded gov-
ernment reforms aimed at ameliorating the conflict between workers and
property owners. If property rights were absolutely inviolable, then gov-
ernment could not legitimately tax, regulate, or redistribute property. In
short, natural rights served to protect the status quo.
In contrast to the doctrine of natural rights, utilitarianism provided a
flexible and pragmatic basis for government intervention. Any reform
resulting in favorable consequences for society as a whole was considered
legitimate. Bentham claimed that rights were established by society's laws,
not by the laws of nature. With new laws, government could legitimately
create or eliminate certain property rights as long as the laws served the
public interest. Cutting all ties to natural law and natural rights enabled
Modern Liberalism to assure a wide latitude for government action.
On the controversial issue of whether government should engage in
redistribution of income and wealth, Bentham equivocated. On one hand,
utilitarianism provides a strong argument in favor of redistribution. The
law of diminishing marginal utility suggests that rich people get less plea-
sure from a dollar than do poor people, and therefore society's total utility
The Modern Liberal Perspective 91
can be increased by taking money from the rich and giving it to the poor.
Bentham stated that "the more nearly the actual proportion [of wealth]
approaches equality, the greater will be the total mass of happiness." On
the other hand, Bentham feared that redistribution would undermine the
security of property rights and reduce incentives, thereby contributing to
stagnation of the economy. He concluded that "when security and equality
are in opposition, there should be no hesitation: equality should give way."
Thus, while Bentham opened the door for extensive government activity, he
tended to support laissez-faire policies in economic affairs. His proposals
for reform were largely confined to the judiciary and penal systems, edu-
cation, and the electoral process.
only to prevent citizens from harming one another. Despite this dictum, Mill
did support three specific forms of intervention: public funding for educa-
tion, government encouragement of birth control, and an inheritance tax to
offset the tendency for property holdings to become concentrated.
Mill's efforts to synthesize the best of Classical Liberal, Conservative, and
Radical ideas set the tone for the subsequent development of Modern
Liberalism. Mill championed the cause of individual liberty and yet valued
the role of "superior minds" in providing guidance and leadership for the
rest of society. He supported universal suffrage, but only with the provision
that educated citizens would have multiple votes so that their impact on the
political process would be greater. In Principles of Political Economy (1848),
Mill emphasized the importance of secure property rights in fostering eco-
nomic prosperity, yet he also favored experiments with cooperatives in hopes
that they might eventually lead to a decentralized form of socialism.
Mill believed that both capitalism and democracy, while flawed, served
essential functions. Capitalism facilitated the accumulation of wealth that
would free humans from the drudgery of menial labor and permit them to
focus on the higher pleasures of intellectual and artistic expression. Full
democracy, by permitting all citizens to participate in society's collective
decisionmaking, would give citizens a sense of self-worth and dignity that
would, in turn, arouse their desire for more fulfilling lifestyles. Mill
acknowledged that social change would take time, but government could
hasten the process by providing public education and by promoting greater
social equality.
T h o m a s Hill Green ( 1 8 3 6 - 1 8 8 2 )
T. H. Green, an Oxford philosopher, sought to strike a balance between
the individualism of Classical Liberalism and the romantic notion of
organic community that had stimulated both Conservative and Radical
thought. Green was concerned that Classical Liberalism, with its emphasis
on protection of property rights and laissez-faire, would not appeal to
workers. The English Reform Bill of 1867 extended suffrage rights to a
broad spectrum of the working class, and if these new voters were to be
peacefully integrated into the political process, government action to
improve their living conditions would be necessary.
Green supported many of the tenets of Classical Liberalism, including
individual freedom, property rights, individual initiative, and self-reliance.
However, he redefined certain principles to challenge the commitment to
laissez-faire. Whereas Classical Liberals viewed humans as rationally pursu-
ing maximum pleasure, Green claimed that humans do not seek pleasure
directly, but rather strive to fulfill images of the kind of person they want to
be. In Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation (1879), he argued
that because these self-images are formed in a social environment, they reflect
The Modern Liberal Perspective 93
Alfred Marshall ( 1 8 4 2 - 1 9 2 4 )
An economics professor at Cambridge University in England, Alfred
Marshall developed much of the microeconomic theory that is taught in
undergraduate courses today. Although Stanley Jevons was the first to sug-
gest substituting the word "economics" for "political economy," the title
of Marshall's textbook, Principles of Economics (1890), confirmed that the
change in labels had been accomplished. By rejecting the term "political
economy," Marshall did not intend to exclude political or ethical consider-
ations from public debate. Prior to becoming an economist, he studied
94 Political Economy
ethics and was familiar with the writings of Hegel and Kant. Marshall was
deeply concerned about the plight of the poor and believed that economics
could provide guidance in public efforts to improve the quality of human
existence. He was motivated to adopt the term "economics" instead of
"political economy" by his desire to create a more scientific understanding
of society. Limiting the scope of analysis to "that part of individual and
social action which is most closely connected with the attainment and with
the use of the material requisites of well-being," Marshall anticipated a
narrower focus on measurable phenomena that could be expressed in
mathematical form. However, this definition meant that Marshall
acknowledged the existence of noneconomic dimensions of life and
noneconomic values that might also affect government policymaking.
For many of Marshall's successors at Cambridge, the distinction between
economics and political economy allowed economics to share the objectiv-
ity and rigor of the physical sciences, while political economy incorporated
ethical considerations and permitted consideration of both economic and
noneconomic goals. In sharp contrast, the Classical Liberalism of the
Austrian school portrayed economics as covering the allocation of scarce
resources to any goal, thereby making economics the "science of rational
choice" and denying the existence of noneconomic values.
Marshall was not a strong advocate of government intervention. In
fact, he was quite cautious about any proposals that would restrict eco-
nomic freedom or violate property rights, claiming that freedom and secu-
rity of property were essential to stimulate innovation, entrepreneurship,
and economic growth. As a first line of attack against the problems of
poverty and human suffering, Marshall hoped that individual citizens and
businesses would engage in "economic chivalry" through public service
and charitable contributions. However, he did recognize certain failings of
the market economy, including unequal power in labor-management rela-
tions, the presence of negative externalities such as pollution, and the
inability of the market to provide public goods such as universal educa-
tion. His receptiveness to some government intervention is exemplified by
his claim that "the human will, guided by careful thought, can so modify
circumstances as to [improve] the economic, as well as the moral, well-
being of the masses of people."
J o h n Maynard K e y n e s ( 1 8 8 3 - 1 9 4 6 )
As an economist from Cambridge University, John Maynard Keynes was
fully aware of the various flaws in the market uncovered by Marshall and
Pigou. However, his condemnation of laissez-faire capitalism went far
beyond previous criticisms. He blamed the "economic anarchy" of free
markets for causing high unemployment and excessive inequality in the dis-
tribution of income.
The Modern Liberal Perspective 95
John Rawls ( 1 9 2 1 - )
John Rawls is a Harvard philosopher whose book A Theory of Justice
(1971) touched off an intensive reexamination of the ethical foundations of
96 Political Economy
the experience of living in a fair society will minimize such protests as indi-
viduals develop a moral sensibility enabling them to value justice above
their own material gains.
Rawls is the first Modern Liberal to offer a criterion of distributive jus-
tice. If accepted, the Rawlsian principles would put an end to many of the
political struggles that have threatened to destroy the cohesiveness of mod-
ern societies. However, despite the widespread attention given to Rawls's
ideas, his theory of justice has not been widely embraced by Modern
Liberals because it potentially mandates massive redistribution of wealth.
goals. These two freedoms may conflict with each other when the negative
freedom of some persons poses an obstacle to the positive freedom of others.
Equality. "Equality of opportunity" and "equality under the law" are
two important components of social equality. However, both are jeopar-
dized by inequality of wealth and income, so greater "equality of result" is
essential to achieving social equality.
Justice. Justice is achieved when both human rights and property rights
are upheld. When these rights conflict, society, acting through government,
must find a balance that best serves the public interest.
Efficiency. Efficiency means maximizing the value of goods and services
produced. However, efficiency is only one criterion of a good society and
may be superseded by considerations of freedom, equality, or justice.
New K e y n e s i a n E c o n o m i c s
Despite the Keynesian revolution of the 1930s and 1940s, most U.S.
Keynesian economists, led by Paul Samuelson, affirmed the complementar-
ity of Keynesian macroeconomics and neoclassical microeconomics. The
former offered an understanding of the economy as a whole, while the lat-
ter was useful in explaining the behavior of individual consumers and
firms. Samuelson proposed a "neoclassical synthesis" in which both doc-
trines would coexist peacefully.
By the 1960s, the neoclassical synthesis had become so influential that
economists were formally installed at the highest levels of government
power. In addition to Samuelson, the leading economists of that period
included Robert Solow, Walter Heller (1915-1987), James Tobin, Gardner
Ackley, and Arthur Okun (1928-1980). Operating as members of or
The Modern Liberal Perspective 99
Neocorporatism
Although corporatism has a Conservative lineage, the Scandinavian coun-
tries and Austria practice a Modern Liberal version of corporatism empha-
sizing social equality and democratic participation. This "neocorporatism"
100 Political Economy
was proposed in the United States during the 1980s under the label of
industrial policy. Government would provide leadership in fostering coop-
eration among corporations, labor unions, and other powerful interest
groups. The logic behind neocorporatism is that the modern economy is so
dominated by interest groups that laissez-faire policies simply permit more
powerful groups to prey on unorganized entities such as small businesses,
farmers, non-unionized workers, and the poor. Breaking up the clusters of
power is deemed both politically infeasible and inefficient, so the only
alternative is government coordination of conflicting interests in an effort
to promote stability and prosperity.
In addition to mediating conflict, government would reduce uncertainty
by providing guidelines for economic development. Government would
also become more active in stimulating the economy through funding for
education, transportation, job training, and research and development.
Neocorporatists favor government aid to industries with significant poten-
tial for growth. Strategic trade policy, including subsidies and tariffs, might
be used to propel selected industries to international dominance.
Underlying these proposals is the belief that government must have a
coherent vision of the future and take steps to realize that vision if the econ-
omy is to be competitive in the global market.
Leading proponents of neocorporatism in the United States include
Lester Thurow, Robert Kuttner, and ex-Secretary of Labor Robert Reich.
Neocorporatism has failed to gain widespread acceptance because the pro-
posals for enlarging government's authority run counter to the political tides
of the late twentieth century. When the idea of industrial policy was first
presented in the 1980s, the Japanese and European economies were held up
as shining examples of what neocorporatism could achieve. Today, with
European unemployment exceeding ten percent and Japan in a lengthy
recession, critics of neocorporatism can turn the tables, using Europe and
Japan as arguments against government coordination of the economy.
Post-Keynesian Economics
The declining prestige of Keynesian economics in the 1970s was symp-
tomatic of the general disarray afflicting Modern Liberalism. Some
economists sought to rescue Keynesian ideas by arguing that American
economists such as Paul Samuelson had misinterpreted Keynes's ideas.
Early figures in post-Keynesian economics include Joan Robinson, a col-
league of Keynes at Cambridge University, and Michal Kalecki
(1899-1970), a Polish economist who independently arrived at many of the
same ideas as Keynes. Other important early contributors include Piero
Sraffa (1898-1983), Maurice Dobb (1900-1976), and Nicholas Kaldor
(1908-1986). In the United States, post-Keynesian economics was
advanced by Sidney Weintraub (1914-1983), Alfred Eichner (1937-1988),
The Modern Liberal Perspective 101
expense of other citizens. Economist Lester Thurow coined the term "zero-
sum society" to describe a no-growth economy in which one group's gain
is another group's loss. In a zero-sum society, redistributive policies are
likely to create resentment and anger, thereby eroding public support for
Modern Liberalism.
Second, Modern Liberalism's emphasis on universal values such as jus-
tice and human rights often conflicts with citizens' attachments to particu-
lar values and cultures. On issues ranging from welfare to criminal justice,
Modern Liberalism is widely perceived as defending abstract rights while
remaining insensitive to the wishes and interests of particular individuals or
groups. For this reason, critics blame Modern Liberalism for a decline of
moral standards and disintegration of traditional culture.
Finally, the flexibility of Modern Liberalism has created problems.
Because it encompasses values taken from conflicting ideologies, Modern
Liberalism lacks a clear and coherent vision of the public interest and there-
fore possesses no firm criteria by which to assess the performance of either
the market or government. The Modern Liberal commitment to individu-
alism means that individual preferences must be the ultimate source of
social values, yet Modern Liberalism is also committed to greater equality,
even if this goal requires manipulation of the market economy by govern-
ment. Once the beneficence of the market has been questioned, some crite-
rion of justice or the public interest is essential to give coherence to
government activities. Modern Liberal economists have relied on the con-
cept of economic efficiency as the criterion for government intervention;
government should improve the efficiency of the market by correcting cer-
tain failures, thereby promoting the well-being of society. However, devel-
opments in economic theory have demonstrated that efficiency is not
synonymous with maximum social welfare, leaving Modern Liberals with-
out clear guidelines for policymaking.
In attempting to resolve this dilemma, Modern Liberals face a choice.
They can simply accept the absence of a theory of justice, leaving both the
market and government without firm moral legitimacy, or they can formu-
late specific principles of justice to clearly define the public interest. To
choose the latter route, however, would commit Modern Liberals to gov-
ernment action aimed at bringing society into conformance with the prin-
ciples of justice. Most Modern Liberals remain too firmly committed to the
notions of ethical relativism, pluralism, diversity, and tolerance to support
any precise definition of justice that would legitimize such a powerful role
for government.
Despite these difficulties, Modern Liberalism is likely to remain a pow-
erful ideology. For those who find Conservatism, Classical Liberalism, and
Radicalism to be unacceptable, the synthetic and compromising nature of
Modern Liberalism will continue to hold appeal. Proponents of Modern
Liberalism offer no ultimate resolution of the conflicts between human
The Modern Liberal Perspective 103
rights and property rights, between freedom and equality, or between indi-
vidualism and community, claiming that these tensions between opposing
ideals are essential features of h u m a n existence.
ADDITIONAL READING
Anderson, Walter Truett, ed. Rethinking Liberalism. New York: Avon, 1983.
Arestis, Philip, and Thanes Skouras, eds. Post-Keynesian Economic Theory.
Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1985.
Eichner, Alfred, ed. A Guide to Post-Keynesian Economics. White Plains, NY:
M. E. Sharpe, 1979.
Gutman, Amy. Liberal Equality. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1980.
Kuttner, Robert. The End of Laissez-Faire: National Purpose and the Global
Economy After the Cold War. New York: Alfred Knopf, 1991.
MacLean, Douglas, and Claudia Mills, eds. Liberalism Reconsidered. Totowa, NJ:
Rowman & Allanheld, 1983.
Reich, Robert B. The Resurgent Liberal. New York: Times Books, 1989.
Rosenblum, Nancy L., ed. Liberalism and the Moral Life. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1989.
Rothenberg, Randall. The Neoliberals. New York: Simon 8c Schuster, 1984.
Shapiro, Ian. The Evolution of Rights in Liberal Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1986.
Spitz, David. The Real World of Liberalism. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1982.
This page intentionally left blank
PART III
CONTEMPORARY
ISSUES IN POLITICAL
ECONOMY
This page intentionally left blank
Chapter 7
Government and
the Market
During the first half of the twentieth century, the combination of two world
wars and the Great Depression served as a catalyst for expanding the role
of government. Public reaction was generally favorable up to the 1960s.
However, the political and economic upheavals of the past three decades
have fostered a pervasive cynicism and hostility toward government.
Politicians now frequently campaign for office as "outsiders" promising to
repair the damage caused by previous policies. Public apathy is reflected in
low voter turnouts and a relative lack of interest in political affairs.
In this chapter, we confront some of the basic questions about democ-
racy and capitalism: What is government's proper role in a market econ-
omy? What aspects of modern society prevent government from serving its
proper role and what changes in the economy and society might remedy
political shortcomings? Different answers to these questions come from
each of the four ideological perspectives.
least." The defense of a laissez-faire policy derives from the view that gov-
ernment represents a social contract among rational, self-interested persons
who would agree only to policies promoting their own interests. As a result,
government should be prohibited from engaging in any activities conferring
benefits upon some citizens at the expense of others. The proper role of gov-
ernment is reduced to that of a "referee" or "night-watchman," enforcing
laws protecting private property and the civil rights shared by all citizens.
Virtually all Classical Liberals accept government's role in establishing
and enforcing a system of laws to protect individual rights. Beyond that
function, consensus has been difficult to achieve. Adam Smith proposed
that government should print and regulate the money supply, provide cer-
tain "public goods" such as national defense, harbors, and roads, and levy
taxes to finance its functions. However, other Classical Liberals, particu-
larly those who are inclined toward libertarianism or even anarchism,
argue that these activities are both unnecessary and counterproductive.
Friedrich Hayek claimed that a government monopoly on the printing of
currency leads to excessive creation of money and a consequent devalua-
tion of its worth. He proposed a system in which several private firms
would be commissioned to issue different currencies. Competition to pro-
mote the use of each currency would provide a strong incentive for each
firm to limit printing because citizens would be attracted to a currency that
maintains its value over time.
Classical Liberals also challenge the argument that provision of public
goods establishes a rationale for government action. They argue that most
of the goods and services currently provided by government could be sup-
plied by private firms. In fact, government provision of goods and services
may explain why the private sector has not entered these markets. For
example, the availability of public education reduces demand for private
schools, expectations of social security benefits reduce private saving for
retirement, and the existence of welfare programs diminishes contributions
to private charities.
Even the authority of government to tax is controversial among
Classical Liberals. At the time of the American Revolution, representative
democracy was envisioned as the best method for keeping taxes low. If
elected representatives approved a tax, then citizens had implicitly con-
sented to be taxed. If large numbers of citizens opposed the tax, they could
vote for different representatives in the next election. However, the growth
of government power has led many Classical Liberals to describe taxation
as looting, plunder, or theft, in which citizens are deprived of their legiti-
mate earnings by the coercive power of government.
Classical Liberals challenge the very concept of "market failure," argu-
ing that many so-called failures actually result from government interven-
tion and would not occur if government were restricted to its proper role.
For example, the market power of large corporations is attributed to
Government and the Market 109
The A c t u a l Role of G o v e r n m e n t
From the Classical Liberal perspective, government in modern societies
neither promotes the public interest nor serves as benevolent guardian pro-
tecting the property and rights of all citizens. Just the opposite is true; gov-
ernment is a predatory oppressor, extorting money from citizens and
limiting their freedom. Moreover, government is the primary tool by which
powerful groups secure their privileges and oppress their fellow citizens. At
best, government is an inefficient bureaucracy, squandering resources while
providing services that, for the most part, are either unnecessary or could
have been produced in the private sector at lower cost.
The Classical Liberal analysis of government is called "public choice
theory." Pioneered during the 1960s by Anthony Downs, James Buchanan,
and Gordon Tullock, this body of ideas reflects the application of neoclas-
sical economic analysis to the political process. 3 The theory assumes that
the self-interested, maximizing behavior attributed to individuals in the
110 Political Economy
benefits that should be attainable only through market activity. Second, the
high tax rates required to meet the demands of rent-seekers discourage pro-
ductive activity and thus reduce the tax base from which government
derives its revenue. Third, tax avoidance and evasion become pervasive as
citizens try to protect themselves against the power of government to seize
their income for the benefit of special-interest groups. Fourth, the growing
perception that lobbying and political organizing are more rewarding than
market activity causes a diversion of resources away from production and
a resulting erosion of efficiency in the private sector. The combination of
more government spending and a declining tax base has created the mas-
sive deficits in the government's budget.6
To explain why interest groups proliferate in a democratic political sys-
tem not firmly constrained by a constitution, public choice theorists argue
that the benefits of any particular government program are often concen-
trated on a small segment of the population while the costs are dispersed
among all taxpayers. This imbalance gives interest groups a strong incen-
tive to organize and lobby in favor of particular programs, while taxpayers
are less motivated to resist since the cost to the individual citizen of any
single program is usually quite small.
Behavior of bureaucrats and politicians. The expansion of government's
role is also attributed to the self-interest of government employees.
Bureaucrats become "empire builders" since a larger agency offers greater
opportunities for career advancement, more funding, more recognition, and
more power. After a bureaucratic agency reaches a certain size, it can essen-
tially perpetuate itself by creating a large constituency of employees, clients,
and other beneficiaries who will resist any efforts to reduce funding.7
As for elected politicians, public choice theory portrays them as "political
entrepreneurs" who have entered politics anticipating high rewards in terms
of money and power. To explain why legislation benefitting only a narrow-
interest group is often approved, public choice theorists claim that politicians
have learned the art of "logrolling," forming coalitions in which they agree
to vote for the favored legislation of other politicians in return for the
promise of reciprocal support. As a result, many bills are passed that would
not otherwise gain a majority vote and government continues to expand.
Politicians are also portrayed as suffering from "rational myopia."
Because their primary goal is reelection, politicians focus only on the cur-
rent impact of public policy while ignoring long-term consequences. This
mindset contributes to budget deficits as politicians seeking reelection are
anxious to provide the immediate benefits associated with government
spending while shifting the costs onto future generations.
Behavior of voters. By interpreting political behavior as purely self-
interested, public choice theorists encounter difficulty in explaining why peo-
ple bother to vote. Voting requires time and effort, yet individuals realize that
their single votes will, in all likelihood, have no impact on the outcome of
112 Political Economy
any election. Therefore, the rational person, after comparing the costs and
benefits of a trip to the voting booth, would seemingly choose not to vote.
Similarly, citizens can be expected to remain "rationally ignorant" about pol-
itics.8 Becoming an informed citizen takes time and effort, and since this
knowledge is unlikely to benefit the individual in terms of influencing the
outcome of an election, voters seem to have no incentive to acquire sufficient
knowledge to vote wisely.
These arguments lead public choice theorists to worry about the out-
comes of democratic elections. The people willing to incur the costs of
becoming informed and voting are likely to be those who have a strong
interest in some particular issue or program, creating a bias in favor of gov-
ernment expansion. Other concerns about democracy include the claim
that voting is an imprecise method for registering individual preferences
since elections are infrequent, citizens are not permitted to vote separately
on each policy, and citizens have little discretion over the quantity or qual-
ity of public goods. Indeed, public choice theorists argue that government
will normally provide too many public goods since a majority of voters can
force the minority to share the burden of financing any particular public
good. In summary, public choice theorists fear that democracy breeds inter-
est groups seeking to manipulate government for private purposes. 9
The A c t u a l Role of G o v e r n m e n t
Radicals engage in an ongoing debate about the functions of govern-
ment in a capitalist society. This debate involves three distinct theories of
the state.
Government and the Market 115
"laws of motion" to describe the forces emanating from the economy that
largely determine the scope and content of government policy.
The impact of structural imperatives on public policy is transmitted
through two channels. First, because prosperity in a capitalist economy
hinges on healthy rates of capital accumulation, citizens tend to identify
their own interests with those of capitalists. For example, employees of a
steel mill may oppose regulations to limit air pollution because they fear
that reduced profitability for the mill may cost them their jobs. Second, the
threat of a "capital strike" poses a continual constraint on public policy.
Government actions that undermine profitability may discourage capital-
ists from investing in the domestic economy. To avoid the recession that
would surely follow a strike by capitalists, government must maintain
"business confidence" by creating conditions conducive to high profits and
continuing investment.
The content of government policy will change in response to evolving
economic conditions. In the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, the inter-
ventionist policies associated with mercantilism were appropriate for
reducing risk and expanding markets. Once the capitalist economy was
established, laissez-faire policies removed the remnants of feudal and mer-
cantilist strictures on production and exchange. By the late nineteenth cen-
tury, the transition to monopoly capitalism required that government
protect businesses against the perils of cut-throat competition. Government
codified and enforced business ethics, passed antitrust laws, and initiated
quality controls on various products. The Great Depression of the 1930s
mandated a vastly enlarged role for government in providing sufficient
liquidity and spending to maintain profitability and accumulation. These
goals were accomplished by establishing high levels of military spending,
by consciously pursuing expansionary monetary and fiscal policies, and by
equalizing income through progressive taxation, labor unions, and welfare
programs. These latter policies also function to maintain social order by
assuaging the anger of low-income families. Most recently, the develop-
ment of supply-side constraints on accumulation has led to tax cuts, dereg-
ulation, and privatization.
Class struggle theory. A third Radical theory of the state portrays politics
as an arena in which conflicting class interests vie with one another for dom-
inance. Government is a "contested instrument," potentially able to serve
either bourgeois or proletarian interests depending on the balance of class
power at any given time.14 Thus government in capitalist society will seek
to promote not only accumulation, but also legitimation of the system of
private ownership. 15 Accumulation is essential for economic prosperity, but
the viability of capitalism also requires that a broad spectrum of the popu-
lation perceive the system as legitimate. Government efforts to promote
legitimation may conflict with the narrow interests of capitalists in maxi-
mizing profits in the short run. For example, welfare programs, minimum-
Government and the Market 117
wage laws, and protection of the environment are likely to reduce profits for
some businesses, but without such policies, social unrest might threaten the
entire capitalist system.
P r o p o s a l s for P o l i t i c a l Reform
Radicals who adhere to either instrumentalist or structuralist theories of
government tend to be pessimistic about the prospects for political reform
within capitalism. Whether government is controlled by the ruling class or
by the structural imperatives of the economy, policies that directly advance
the interests of workers are unlikely except during periodic crises in capi-
talism when the very survival of the system is at stake.
However, the class struggle theory in which government is viewed as a
"contested instrument" raises the possibility that working-class efforts to
influence and even gain control of government may be effective. A well-
organized working class can achieve political victories aimed at challenging
capitalist control of the economy. Reform-minded Radicals concede that
the capitalist chss will strongly resist these challenges, but they are opti-
mistic that a combination of legal reforms, government policies, and per-
haps compensation for lost property rights may soften the opposition.
When opposing class interests are sufficiently balanced that government
can neither impose austerity measures to restore profitability nor grant
more favorable conditions to workers, the solution will likely be some form
of corporatism to break the political stalemate. While corporatism has
appeared in both Conservative and Modern Liberal versions, the overrid-
ing theme has been stronger government action to forge a consensus on the
distribution of society's benefits and burdens.
If, as happened in Germany and Italy in the 1920s, large numbers of
citizens conclude that foreigners, minorities, cultural change, and liberal
individualism are responsible for the nation's economic woes, then Conserv-
ative corporatism is likely to be the outcome. However, the more likely
event is that corporatism will appear in its Modern Liberal form as an effort
by government to promote cooperation, increased productivity, industrial
peace, and improved conditions for the working class. Yet Radicals warn
that Modern Liberal corporatism is still committed to preserving capitalism
and the privileges of private property and may therefore take on fascist
overtones. This "friendly fascism" will appear benign and committed to the
public interest, but the "iron fist in the velvet glove" will be used when
necessary to enforce austerity measures, silence political dissent, and restore
conditions for rapid capital accumulation. Only socialism can combine
genuine popular democracy with economic prosperity.16
Some Radicals propose to facilitate the transition from capitalism to
socialism by amending the Constitution. In addition to the protection of
civil rights, Radicals want the Constitution to define and protect economic
118 Political Economy
The A c t u a l Role of G o v e r n m e n t
Conservatives link the deterioration of government with the industrial-
ization and modernization accompanying the rise of capitalism. In a cap-
italist society, wealth and liberty replace virtue and order as primary
values. An oligarchy based on ownership of capital supersedes the tradi-
tional aristocracy. The polarization of classes causes conflict in the rela-
tions between rich and poor. Demagogues arise to exploit the resentment
of the poor and to persecute the rich. Moreover, the trend toward urban-
ization and geographic mobility undermines the stability of traditional
communities and the legitimacy of traditional authority. 22 As market
120 Political Economy
The A c t u a l Role of G o v e r n m e n t
The concentration of wealth and power in the industrialized nations
poses a challenge to the Modern Liberal view of government as a benevo-
lent administrator and impartial defender of the public interest. Increas-
ingly, government is subjected to the demands of large, well-organized
interest groups. In recognition of the changing political landscape,
political scientists such as Robert Dahl, David Easton, and David Truman
have revised the Modern Liberal theory of the state by introducing the
notion of interest-group pluralism. 33 While acknowledging that groups
have replaced individuals as the primary actors in politics, pluralists seek
to preserve the image of democratic government as representative of the
interests of society as a whole.
Pluralist theorists treat political power as separate from economic
power, arguing that political power is widely dispersed among a variety of
interest groups. Corporations, labor unions, environmentalists, senior citi-
zens, and other groups attempt to influence legislation, with the resulting
government policies reflecting the balance of these competing interests. The
most controversial aspect of pluralism is the claim that groups wield influ-
ence in direct proportion to the size of their membership. Critics argue that
pluralists overlook the effect of concentrated wealth in giving some groups
significantly greater impact on the political process.
While the doctrine of interest-group pluralism reflects the changing
nature of politics in industrialized countries, it has consequences reaching
far beyond the realm of academic theory. By encouraging competition
among interest groups, pluralism effectively legitimizes the transformation
of politics into a battle between conflicting interests with no common
ground on which to reach consensus. The worst fears of Conservatives and
Classical Liberals have been realized as politics has degenerated into a
Hobbesian "war of all against all." The result has been a rapid expansion
of government programs aimed at satisfying various interest groups, large
budget deficits, and a widespread loss of public confidence in government.
Unlike Conservatives and Classical Liberals, Modern Liberals have been
reluctant to rely on constitutional constraints to guide public policy. In the
early twentieth century, Modern Liberal jurists such as Oliver Wendell
Holmes, Jr. (1841-1935), Louis Brandeis (1856-1941), and Roscoe Pound
(1870-1964) initiated a loose interpretation of the Constitution to permit
an expanding role for government. Furthermore, Modern Liberals have
been largely unwilling to resolve political conflict by appealing to a well-
defined vision of the public interest or the good society. To do so would
126 Political Economy
NOTES
1. See Tyler Cowen, ed., The Theory of Market Failure: A Critical
Examination, Fairfax, VA: George Mason University Press, 1988.
2. Classical Liberal arguments for a constitution as the basis for viable democ-
racy are found in Friedrich A. Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty, Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1960; James M. Buchanan and Gordon Tullock,
Calculus of Consent: The Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy, A
Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1965; James M. Buchanan, Constitutional
Economics, Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 1991; Dwight R. Lee and Richard
McKenzie, Regulating Government: A Preface to Constitutional Economics,
Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, 1987; and Gerald W. Scully, Constitutional
Economics: The Framework for Economic Growth and Social Progress,
Washington, DC: The Heritage Foundation, 1991.
3. Major works in public choice theory include Anthony Downs, An Economic
Theory of Democracy, New York: Harper 8t Row, 1957; James M. Buchanan and
Robert D. Tollison, Theory of Public Choice: Political Applications of Economic
128 Political Economy
Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1972; Gordon Tullock, Private Wants,
Public Means, New York: Basic Books, 1970; Mancur Olson, The Logic of
Collective Action: Public Goals and the Theory of Groups, Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1965; and Charles K. Rowley, ed., Public Choice Theory,
Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar, 1993. For critiques of public choice theory, see Lars
Udehn, The Limits of Public Choice, New York: Routledge, 1996; Donald P. Green
and Ian Shapiro, Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory, New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1994; Kristen R. Monroe, ed., The Economic Approach to
Politics: A Critical Reassessment of the Theory of Rational Action, New York:
HarperCollins, 1991; and Jeffrey Friedman, ed., The Rational Choice Controversy,
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1996.
4. On the theory of rent-seeking, see David C. Colander, ed., Neoclassical
Political Economy: The Analysis of Rent-seeking and DUP Activities, Cambridge,
MA: Ballinger, 1984. See also Robert D. Tollison and Roger D. Congleton, eds.,
The Economic Analysis of Rent-Seeking, Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar, 1995;
Charles K. Rowley, Robert D. Tollison, and Gordon Tullock, The Political
Economy of Rent-Seeking, Boston: Martinus Nijhoff, 1988; and Gordon Tullock,
Rent Seeking, Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar, 1993.
5. See George J. Stigler, "The Theory of Economic Regulation," Bell Journal
of Economics & Management Science 2, no. 1 (Spring 1971): 3 - 2 1 . For addi-
tional analysis of the politics of regulation, see Barry Mitnick, The Political
Economy of Regulation, New York: Columbia University Press, 1980; James Q.
Wilson, ed., The Politics of Regulation, New York: Basic Books, 1980; and
Kenneth J. Meier, Regulation: Politics, Bureaucracy and Economics, New York:
St. Martin's Press, 1985.
6. The Classical Liberal explanation of budget deficits is elaborated in James M.
Buchanan and Richard M. Wagner, Democracy in Deficit: The Political Legacy of
Lord Keynes, New York: Academic Press, 1977; Phillip Cagan, ed., The Economy
in Deficit, Washington, DC: American Enterprise Institute, 1985; James M.
Buchanan, Charles K. Rowley, and Robert D. Tollison, eds., Deficits, New York:
Basil Blackwell, 1987; and Joseph White and Aaron Wildavsky, The Deficit and the
Public Interest, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press, 1989.
7. The functioning of bureaucracy is examined in Anthony Downs, Inside
Bureaucracy, Boston: Little, Brown, 1967; Aaron Wildavsky, The Politics of the
Budgetary Process, 4th ed., Boston: Little, Brown, 1984; William A. Niskanen,
Bureaucracy and Public Economics, Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar, 1994; William
C. Mitchell and Randy T. Simmons, Beyond Politics: Markets, Welfare and the
Failure of Bureaucracy, Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1994; and James P.
Pinkerton, What Comes Next: The End of Big Government—and the New
Paradigm Ahead, New York: Hyperion, 1995.
8. See Anthony Downs, An Economic Theory of Democracy, New York:
Harper and Row, 1957.
9. For Classical Liberal analyses of the problems associated with democracy, see
Samuel Brittan, The Economic Consequences of Democracy, London: Temple
Smith, 1977. See also Dan Usher, The Economic Prerequisite to Democracy, New
York: Columbia University Press, 1981.
10. Privatization is discussed in Richard Hula, ed., Market Based Public Policy,
New York: Macmillan, 1987; Edward H. Crane and David Boaz, An American
Government and the Market 129
Vision: Policies for the '90s, Washington, DC: Cato Institute, 1988; John D.
Donahue, The Privatization Decision: Public Ends, Private Means, New York:
Basic Books, 1989; Michael E. Beesley, Privatization, Regulation and Deregulation,
New York: Routledge, 1992; Dexter Whitfield, The Welfare State: Privatization,
Deregulation, Commercialization of Public Services, Boulder, CO: Westview Press,
1992; Fred E. Foldvary, Public Goods and Private Communities: The Market
Provision of Social Services, Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar, 1994; Stephen Edgell,
Sandin Walklate, and Gareth Williams, Debating the Future of the Public Sphere:
Transforming the Public and Private Domains in Free Market Societies, Brookfield,
VT: Avebury, 1995; Elizabeth I. Bailey and Janet Rothenberg Pack, eds., The
Political Economy of Privatization and Deregulation, Brookfield, VT: Edward
Elgar, 1995; and Philip Morgan, ed., Privatization and the Welfare State:
Implications for Consumers and the Workforce, Brookfield, VT: Dartmouth
Publishing Company, 1995.
11. See Richard A. Posner, The Economics of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1981; Richard A. Posner, Overcoming Law, Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1995; and Richard Epstein, Simple Rules for a Complex
World, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1995.
12. Instrumentalist interpretations of government are found in C. Wright Mills, The
Power Elite, New York: Oxford University Press, 1956; G. William Domhoff, State
Autonomy or Class Dominance, New York: Aldine de Gruyter, 1996; and G. William
Domhoff, The Power Elite and the State, New York: Aldine de Gruyter, 1990.
13. For a structuralist interpretation of government, see Nicos Poulantzas,
Political Power and Social Classes, London: New Left Books, 1975.
14. The Radical view of the state as a "contested instrument" is presented in Bob
Jessop, The Capitalist State, New York: New York University Press, 1982; Ralph
Miliband, The State in Capitalist Society, New York: Basic Books, 1969; and Ian
Gough, The Political Economy of the Welfare State, London: Macmillan, 1979.
15. See James O'Connor, The Fiscal Crisis of the State, New York: St. Martin's,
1973.
16. See Bertram Gross, Friendly Fascism: The Neiv Face of Power in America,
New York: M. Evans, 1980.
17. See Benjamin R. Barber, Strong Democracy, Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1984; Philip Green, Retrieving Democracy: In Search of Civic
Equality, Totowa, NJ: Rowman 6c Allanheld, 1985; Carol Could, Rethinking
Democracy: Freedom and Social Cooperation in Politics, Economics and Society,
New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988; Jane J. Mansbridge, Beyond
Adversarial Democracy, New York: Basic Books, 1980; and Peter Bachrach and
Aryeh Botwinick, Power and Empowerment: A Radical Theory of Participatory
Democracy, Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992; Paul Hirst, Associational
Democracy: New Forms of Economic and Social Governance, Cambridge, UK:
Polity, 1994; Chantal Mouffe, ed., Dimensions of Radical Democracy: Pluralism,
Citizenship, Community, London: Verso, 1992; C. Douglas Lummis, Radical
Democracy, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1996; and David Copp, Jean
Hampton, and John Roemer, eds., The Idea of Democracy, Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press, 1993.
18. Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, edited by J. P. Mayer and M.
Lerner, New York: Harper &c Row, 1966.
130 Political Economy
19. The origins of modern elite theory are found in Vilfredo Pareto, Sociological
Writings, edited by S. E. Finer, New York: Praeger, 1966; and Gaetano Mosca, The
Ruling Class, edited by A. Livingston, New York: McGraw-Hill, 1939.
20. See Jose Ortega y Gasset, The Revolt of the Masses [1932], Notre Dame, IN:
University of Notre Dame Press, 1985.
21. Joseph Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, New York:
Harper 6c Brothers, 1950.
22. See Robert A. Nisbet, The Twilight of Authority, New York: Oxford
University Press, 1975.
23. See Jacob Talmon, The Origins of Totalitarian Democracy, New York:
Praeger, 1960. See also Lionel Trilling, The Liberal Imagination, New York: Viking
Press, 1950.
24. Recent works on corporatism include Colin Crouch, ed., State and Economy
in Contemporary Capitalism, New York: St. Martin's 1979; Philippe Schmitter and
Gerhard Lehmbruch, eds., Trends Toward Corporatist Intermediation, Beverly
Hills, CA: Sage, 1979; James M. Simmie, Power, Property, and Corporatism,
London: Macmillan, 1982; Peter J. Williamson, Varieties of Corporatism, New
York: Cambridge University Press, 1986; Wyn Grant, ed., The Political Economy
of Corporatism, New York: St. Martin's, 1985; Louis Galambos and Joseph Pratt,
The Rise of the Corporate Commonwealth, New York: Basic Books, 1989; and
Martin J. Sklar, The Corporate Reconstruction of American Capitalism, New York:
Cambridge University Press, 1988.
25. See Michael Crozier, Samuel P. Huntington, and Joji Watanuki, eds., The
Crisis of Democracy, New York: New York University Press, 1975.
26. George Will, Statecraft As Soulcraft, New York: Simon 6c Schuster, 1983.
27. Robert A. Nisbet, Community and Power, New York: Oxford University
Press, 1962.
28. The classic article on market failure is F. M. Bator, "The Anatomy of Market
Failure," Quarterly Journal of Economics 72, no. 288 (1958): 351-79.
29. The concept of merit goods was introduced in Richard A. Musgrave, The
Theory of Public Finance, New York: McGraw-Hill, 1959.
30. This argument is developed in G. A. Akerlof and W. T. Dickens, "The
Economic Consequences of Cognitive Dissonance," American Economic Review
72, no. 3 (June 1982): 307-19.
31. For a Modern Liberal critique of the concept of government failure, see
Donald A. Wittman, The Myth of Democratic Failure: Why Political Institutions
are Efficient, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995.
32. See Harold G. Vatter and John F. Walker, The Inevitability of Government
Growth, New York: Columbia University Press, 1990. See also John F. Walker and
Harold G. Vatter, The Rise of Big Government in the United States, Armonk, NY:
M. E. Sharpe, 1997.
33. See Robert A. Dahl, Pluralist Democracy in the United States, Chicago: Rand
McNally, 1967; David Easton, The Political System, New York: Alfred A. Knopf,
1981; and David Truman, The Governing Process, New York: Alfred A. Knopf,
1951.
34. See Robert A. Dahl, Dilemmas of Pluralist Democracy, New Haven, CT:
Yale University Press, 1982. See also Theodore Lowi, The End of Liberalism: The
Second Republic of the U.S., 2nd ed., New York: W W. Norton, 1979.
Government and the Market 131
ADDITIONAL READING
Bowles, Samuel, and Herbert Gintis. Democracy and Capitalism. New York: Basic
Books, 1986.
Brittan, Samuel. The Role and Limits of Government. Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 1983.
Buchanan, James M. The Limits of Liberty: Between Anarchy and Leviathan.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1975.
Carnoy, Martin. The State and Political Theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1984.
Clarke, Simon. Keynesianism, Monetarism, and the Crisis of the State. Brookfield,
VT: Edward Elgar, 1988.
Cohen, Jeffrey E. Politics and Economic Policy in the United States. Boston:
Houghton Mifflin, 1997.
David, Wilfred L. Political Economy of Economic Policy. New York: Praeger,
1988.
Dolbeare, Kenneth. Democracy at Risk: The Politics of Economic Renewal.
Chatham, NJ: Chatham House, 1984.
132 Political Economy
Dugger, William M., and William T. Waller, Jr., eds., The Stratified State: Radical
Institutionalist Theories of Participation and Duality. Armonk, NY: M. E.
Sharpe, 1992.
Duncan, Graeme, ed. Democracy and the Capitalist State. New York: Cambridge
University Press, 1989.
Esping-Anderson, Gosta. Politics Against Markets. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1985.
Ferguson, Thomas, and Joel Rogers, eds. The Political Economy. Armonk, NY:
M. E. Sharpe, 1984.
Freeman, John R. Democracy and Markets: The Politics of Mixed Economies.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Glazer, Nathan. The Limits of Social Policy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1988.
Greenberg, Edward S. Capitalism and the American Political Ideal. Armonk, NY:
M. E. Sharpe, 1985.
Hibbs, Douglas A. The American Political Economy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1987.
Jordon, Bill. The State: Authority and Autonomy. New York: Basil Blackwell, 1985.
Kristol, Irving. On the Democratic Ideal in America. New York: Harper &c
Row, 1972.
Levinson, Marc. Beyond Free Markets: The Revival of Activist Economics.
Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, 1988.
Mills, Edwin S. The Burden of Government. Stanford: Hoover Institution Press, 1986.
Nell, Edward. Prosperity and Public Spending. New York: Unwin 6c Hyman, 1988.
Peretz, Paul, ed. The Politics of American Economic Policy Making. Armonk, NY:
M. E. Sharpe, 1987.
Stiglitz, Joseph. The Role of the State. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1989.
Stone, Alan, and E. J. Harpham, eds. The Political Economy of Public Policy.
Beverly Hills, CA: Sage, 1982.
Suleiman, Ezra N., and John Water bury, eds. The Political Economy of Public
Sector Reform and Privatization. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1990.
Chapter 8
Inflation and
Unemployment
During the 1920s, the U.S. economy experienced deflation and high inter-
est rates as the Fed kept a tight grip on the money supply. By 1929, these
conditions finally spoiled the optimism fueling speculation in the stock
market. The ensuing crash triggered an economic downturn that might
have been short-lived had Congress not passed the Smoot-Hawley Act of
1930, imposing high tariffs on imported goods. When other countries retal-
iated with similar tariffs, international trade collapsed and a full-blown
depression followed. From Friedman's perspective, these instances of gov-
ernment intervention, first the Fed's inept handling of the money supply
and later the Smoot-Hawley tariffs, prevented the natural equilibrating
forces o( the market from quickly restoring prosperity.2
The Austrian economists and Friedman gained little attention until the
Western economies encountered serious difficulties in the 1970s. The
inability of Keynesian policies to cope with simultaneous inflation and
recession opened the door for a resurgence of Classical Liberalism. Under
the labels of supply-side economics, monetarism, and new classical eco-
nomics, Classical Liberal political economy returned to center-stage nearly
as quickly as it had exited in the 1930s. These theories purport to demon-
strate that government causes both inflation and unemployment.
However, some disagreement remains over the connection between gov-
ernment and instability.
Supply-side economics, as popularized by Arthur Laffer, Jack Kemp,
and Jude Wanniski, blames inflation and unemployment on the rising costs
associated with government regulations, taxes, and the inefficiency of gov-
ernment programs. 3 Rising costs of production lead to reduced output and
employment as well as higher prices.
Monetarist economists, led by Milton Friedman, focus on the Federal
Reserve System as the cause of instability.4 By assuming that the economy
naturally operates at or near full employment and that the velocity of
money is fairly constant, monetarists conclude that any increase in the
money supply exceeding the real growth rate of the economy will cause
inflation. This "demand-pull" inflation results from "too many dollars
chasing too few goods."
New classical economists such as Robert Lucas, Thomas Sargent, Neil
Wallace, and Robert Barro propose a slightly different version of govern-
ment's role in destabilizing the economy.5 They argue that individuals
quickly learn from experience to anticipate the effects of government
action. These "rational expectations" enable individuals to effectively
block government efforts to stimulate the economy. For example, if the Fed
increases the money supply, workers may demand higher wages in antici-
pation of higher prices, and businesses, anticipating higher costs, will raise
prices to maintain their profits. New classical economists conclude that a
monetary stimulus causes only inflation, without any lasting impact on the
level of employment or output.
136 Political Economy
Stabilization Policies
The guiding principle behind Classical Liberal stabilization policies is the
belief in the inherent stability of a market economy free from the restraints
of government intervention. Once the barriers to profitability, saving, and
investment are removed by lowering taxes, reducing regulations, stabilizing
the money supply, and eliminating the budget deficit, the market economy
will naturally generate noninflationary growth. Classical Liberals also view
inflation as a more serious problem than unemployment since inflationary
pressures disrupt the market and are ultimately responsible for subsequent
recessions. They discount the severity of unemployment, arguing that offi-
cial statistics overstate the problem since many people considered unem-
ployed by the government actually work in the "underground economy."
Despite a consensus among Classical Liberals that the size of govern-
ment must be reduced to stabilize the economy, they disagree on the strate-
gies for accomplishing this goal. Some Classical Liberals want the Fed to
maintain a fixed rate of money growth equal to the two to three percent
long-run trend in real growth of the economy. They propose increased
independence of the Fed from political influence by Congress and the
President or even an amendment to the Constitution requiring a fixed rate
of monetary expansion. 8
Friedrich Hayek developed the idea of ending the Fed's monopoly on
money creation by allowing several privately-issued currencies to circulate.
Since the public would gravitate toward currencies that maintain their
value, competitive pressures would force each issuer to limit the amount of
money created.9 Another Classical Liberal strategy to restrain the growth
of money calls for a return to the gold standard. Money creation would be
limited by the size of a nation's official holdings of gold.
Classical Liberals also favor deregulation and privatization as methods
for reducing the scope of governmental activity. These policies would reduce
government spending, lower business costs, encourage more competition,
and improve efficiency. Classical Liberals argue that most of the activities
currently performed by government originated from the pressures of special-
interest groups, including the various bureaucracies that administer govern-
ment programs. A vast array of government programs can be eliminated or
transferred to the private sector without damaging the public interest.
138 Political Economy
Most Classical Liberals call for cuts in government spending to reduce the
size of government and stabilize the economy. The unprecedented expansion
of federal budget deficits during the 1980s and early 1990s heightened con-
cerns about government spending. Some Classical Liberals favor an amend-
ment to the Constitution requiring a balanced budget or establishing a ceiling
for government spending as a percentage of GDR Other Classical Liberals,
particularly supply-side economists, favor lower tax rates instead, arguing
that the incentive of higher after-tax earnings will lead to increased produc-
tive activity and therefore a broader tax base. With more to tax, government
revenues may actually increase despite lower tax rates. In short, supply-siders
claim that we can "grow our way out of the deficit."
However, not all Classical Liberals accept supply-side theories. While
relishing the idea that tax reductions serve to cut off the "lifeblood" of gov-
ernment, Milton Friedman argues that insufficient tax revenue has not
restrained government spending in the past. Friedman doubts that lower
tax rates can actually lead to increased tax revenue; instead, tax cuts may
simply result in larger deficits unless matched by similar or greater reduc-
tions in government spending.
Classical Liberals challenge the notion of a trade-off between inflation
and unemployment; they insist that only unanticipated inflation reduces
unemployment. As soon as people become accustomed to any particular
rate of inflation, the economy returns to the "natural rate" of unemploy-
ment, which can be lowered only by restoring competition to the market
through institutional reforms such as breaking up unions, deregulation,
and elimination of the welfare state.
When recessions occur, Classical Liberals oppose government efforts to
alleviate the hardship associated with unemployment and bankruptcy.
They believe that recessions restore discipline and efficiency to the econ-
omy. If government cushions the impact, the market's self-correcting mech-
anisms are thwarted. Conversely, if government resists the political
pressures to intervene, recessions will be short-lived and the economy will
resume stable growth.
The solution to the Depression was a vastly enlarged role for govern-
ment in the form of military spending, the welfare state, government regu-
lation, and collective bargaining for unions. By the 1970s, however, these
solutions for underconsumption had become obstacles to healthy rates of
capital accumulation. In this respect, Radicals concur with Classical
Liberals in viewing government intervention as a factor in economic stag-
nation. 13 Although welfare programs increase aggregate demand by plac-
ing money in the hands of people likely to spend it, welfare also results in
what Radicals call "decommodification of labor." Welfare establishes a
"social wage" received by workers even if they are unemployed, so labor is
no longer a commodity whose value is determined by supply and demand.
A capitalist economy cannot function well once labor has been decom-
modified; most jobs are so alienating that people will avoid work if gov-
ernment provides a social wage as an alternative.
Government involvement in the economy also leads to the "politiciza-
tion of accumulation." This phenomenon results from the success of work-
ers in using the democratic political process to secure rights such as
occupational health and safety, collective bargaining, nondiscrimination,
and protection against arbitrary layoffs. These rights diminish the prerog-
atives of capitalists and may pose barriers to profitability and accumula-
tion. While Radicals strongly support workers' rights, they claim that
capitalism will falter when the power of workers threatens to override the
power of capitalists.
Once the economy has been politicized, the allocation of resources no
longer appears natural and inevitable, and the distribution of income
becomes subject to bitter struggles between interest groups. Capitalism is
revealed as a system of power rather than a natural mechanism for accom-
modating individual preferences. As government and the economic system
lose legitimacy in the eyes of citizens, the political battle to gain control of
government undermines the accumulation process.14
The Keynesian solution to instability poses yet another problem for cap-
italism. The prosperity accomplished through Keynesian policies during the
1960s effectively suppressed the discipline of the market. Corporations
became more powerful and resistant to competitive forces. Organized labor
secured market power through collective bargaining and the threat of
strikes. The economy grew increasingly segmented, dividing into a "pri-
mary sector" consisting of large corporations and unionized workers, and
a "secondary sector" composed of small businesses and unorganized work-
ers. The firms and unions in the primary sector remain relatively insulated
from competitive pressures and therefore possess the power to raise prices
and wages. This phenomenon gives modern capitalism a built-in
inflationary tendency controllable only by maintaining slack in the econ-
omy through unemployment and slow growth.
Inflation and Unemployment 141
The increased power of labor unions forms the basis for another Radical
explanation of the business cycle—the "profit squeeze" theory.15 During
periods of expansion, unemployment declines and workers demand and
receive higher wages. As the expansion continues, rising wage costs squeeze
corporate profits, causing government to intentionally slow the economy as
a means of disciplining workers and restraining wage demands. This
Radical version of the "political business cycle" views government as using
monetary and fiscal policy to assist businesses in holding down labor costs
by periodically cooling the economy.16
Radicals view the federal budget deficit as a significant problem, but
they do not blame politicians or voters. The "fiscal crisis of the state" sim-
ply manifests deeper structural problems in contemporary capitalism.17 To
bolster corporate profits, government initiates vast spending programs
aimed at both stimulating demand and socializing many business costs. At
the same time, corporate taxes are kept low to reduce business costs even
further. The net effect of increased spending and insufficient taxes is a bud-
get deficit. Radicals attribute recent reductions in the size of the deficit to
cyclical prosperity. However, another recession will eventually trigger
renewed expansion of the deficit.
Radicals argue that the demise of Keynesianism was sealed by the glob-
alization of the economy. When national economies were relatively
autonomous, policies designed to stimulate growth through government
programs aimed at raising wages and aggregate demand were relatively
effective. However, in a global economy, these same policies create perverse
effects. Higher wages lead to higher business costs and reduced ability to
export. The combination of higher wages and government regulations
encourages "capital flight" as businesses relocate to countries with lower
cost structures. Finally, the earlier success of Keynesianism in assuring ade-
quate demand, stable profits, and economic growth undermines the pres-
sure on businesses to innovate. With only modest gains in productivity,
countries relying on Keynesian policies fall behind in international compe-
tition. Under these conditions, even the supporters of Keynesianism have
begun to search for different solutions.
Stabilization Policies
According to Radicals, the traditional policy of slowing the economy to
stop inflation is no longer viable.18 Personal, corporate, government, and
international debt is so immense that any significant downturn in the econ-
omy could trigger a chain-reaction of bankruptcies, leading to economic dis-
aster. Also, in a segmented or dual economy, the secondary sector serves as
a buffer for the primary sector. A recession that devastates small-business
owners, farmers, and unorganized workers may have little impact in
142 Political Economy
Stabilization Policies
Because Conservatives believe that economic problems such as inflation
and unemployment reflect the erosion of traditional values and institutions,
any viable solution must address issues seemingly unrelated to economics.
Conservatives believe that economic stability can be improved by policies
such as allowing prayer in public schools, banning pornography, and
restoring authority in the family, the workplace, and the school. Efforts to
directly confront economic problems, such as price controls or government
job creation, simply place more power in the hands of government and fur-
ther erode local communities.
a
availability of funds and low interest rates, and declining investment would
result in a multiplied drop in national income.
Implicit in Keynes's theory is the Modern Liberal belief that increasing
concentration of business power during the half century prior to the
Depression enabled corporations to divert a larger share of national income
to wealthy shareholders. Since wealthy families often save a considerable
portion of their income, this increasing inequality caused total spending to
lag behind production. Lacking sufficient demand for their products, cor-
porations reduced investment and laid off workers, contributing to further
declines in income and spending. The economy fell into an "underemploy-
ment equilibrium" with the prospect of permanent depression.
American Keynesians argued that business cycles could be managed by
the appropriate combination of monetary and fiscal policy to adjust aggre-
gate demand and restore investors' confidence. As a recession looms, gov-
ernment should increase its spending and/or reduce taxes. Conversely, the
beginning of an inflationary boom should be met with cuts in government
spending and/or tax increases. Government policymakers should be able to
"fine-tune" the economy and maintain stable growth indefinitely. The first
real test of Keynesian theory came with preparations for World War II. As
governments around the world initiated massive spending on weapons and
manpower, the Depression quickly faded. Within six months after the
bombing of Pearl Harbor, the unemployment rate in the United States fell
to virtually zero.
Keynesian policies attracted Modern Liberals because, in addition to
stabilizing the economy, they promoted greater equality. If inadequate
spending was the cause of recessions, then money should be placed in the
hands of those people most likely to spend it—the poor. By attacking the
Classical Liberal argument that growth and efficiency require significant
inequality so that wealthy people can save and provide funds for invest-
ment, Keynesianism provided Modern Liberalism with an economic theory
appealing to a broad spectrum of middle- and lower-class voters. Even
many wealthy voters finally agreed that Keynesian policies produced
growth and were therefore good for business.
Once World War II ended, Modern Liberals sought to maintain much
of the wartime planning apparatus that had steered the economy to
unprecedented levels of output. However, the political opposition of
Classical Liberals and Conservatives was sufficiently powerful to force the
dismantling of most wartime government agencies. Modern Liberals won
a minor victory with the passage of the 1946 Employment Act, which
established the President's Council of Economic Advisors and committed
the federal government to pursuing all practical methods to maintain high
levels of employment. In practice, the Employment Act had little impact
on government policy. Fortunately for the Modern Liberal agenda, the
Cold War with the Soviet Union quickly provided a new rationale for
148 Political Economy
Stabilization Policies
Modern Liberals acknowledge that supply-side factors now bear much
of the responsibility for inflation and unemployment, but they reject the
policy agenda of supply-side economics. Tax cuts and deregulation may
reduce business costs, but Modern Liberals doubt that the resulting
increases in profits will be directed toward new investment. Corporations
Inflation and Unemployment 149
links between academic and vocational studies, and tax breaks or subsidies
to corporations for retraining employees.
should increase savings, and global competition has resulted in greater effi-
ciency and productivity for U.S. businesses.34 The opening of trade and
investment opportunities around the world also holds promise for renewed
growth and prosperity. The Keynesian dream of conquering the business
cycle may yet become reality.
NOTES
1. See Friedrich A. Hayek, Unemployment and Monetary Policy: Government
as Generator of the "Business Cycle," Washington, DC: Cato Institute, 1979.
2. Milton Friedman and Anna J. Schwartz, A Monetary History of the United
States 1867-1960, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1963. For other
Classical Liberal interpretations of the Great Depression, see Lionel Robbins, The
Great Depression, London: Macmillan, 1934; Murray Rothbard, America's
Great Depression, Kansas City, KS: Sheed 6c Ward, 1975; and Thomas E. Hall
and J. David Ferguson, The Great Depression, Ann Arbor: University of
Michigan Press, 1998.
3. Key works in supply-side economics include Jack Kemp, An American
Renaissance: A Strategy for the 80s, New York: Harper &c Row, 1979; Victor A
Canto, Marc A. Miles, and Arthur B. Laffer, Foundations of Supply-side
Economics: Theory and Evidence, New York: Academic Press, 1983; Paul Craig
Roberts, The Supply-Side Revolution: An Insider's Account of Policymaking in
Washington, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1984; and Jude Wanniski,
The Way the World Works, New York: Basic Books, 1978.
4. See George Macesich, The Politics of Monetarism: Its Historical and
Institutional Development, Totowa, NJ: Rowman &c Allanheld, 1984; G. R. Steele
Monetarism and the Demise of Keynesian Economics, New York: St. Martin's
Press, 1989; and Thomas Mayer, Monetarism and Macroeconomic Policy,
Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar Publishers, 1990.
5. See G. K. Shaw, Rational Expectations: An Elementary Exposition, New
York: St. Martin's, 1984; and Jerome Stein, Monetarist, Keynesian and New
Classical Economics, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1982.
6. See Thomas D. Willett, ed., Political Business Cycles: The Political Economy
of Money, Inflation, and Unemployment, Durham, NC: Duke University Press,
1988; and Alberto Alesina and Nouriel Roubini, Political Cycles and the
Macroeconomy, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1998.
7. Mancur Olson, The Rise and Decline of Nations: Economic Growth,
Stagflation, and Social Rigidities, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1982.
8. See H. G. Brennen and James M. Buchanan, Monopoly in Money and
Inflation: The Case for a Constitution to Discipline Government, London: Institute
of Economic Affairs, 1981.
9. See Friedrich A. Hayek, Denationalization of Money, London: Institute of
Economic Affairs, 1976. For a more recent treatment of this subject, see
Lawrence H. White, Competition and Currency, New York: New York University
Press, 1989.
10. Radical interpretations of inflation and unemployment are presented in
James O'Connor, Accumulation Crisis, New York: Basil Blackwell, 1984; Michael
Inflation and Unemployment 153
Bernstein and David Adler, eds., Understanding American Economic Decline, New
York: Cambridge University Press, 1994; David Kotz, Terence McDonough, and
Michael Reich, eds., Social Structures of Accumulation: The Political Economy of
Growth and Crisis, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994; and Kenneth
Hoover and Raymond Plant, Conservative Capitalism in Britain and the United
States: A Critical Appraisal, New York: Routledge, 1989.
11. For a summary of the Radical view of the historical evolution of business
cycles, see Chapter 3 of Erik Olin Wright, Class, Crisis, and the State, London: New
Left Books, 1978.
12. The theory of underconsumption is fully elaborated in Paul Baran and Paul
Sweezy, Monopoly Capital: An Essay on the American Economic and Social Order,
New York: Monthly Review Press, 1966.
13. See Samuel Bowles, David M. Gordon, and Thomas E. Weisskopf, After the
Wasteland: A Democratic Economics for the Year 2000. New York: M. E. Sharpe,
1990.
14. Problems surrounding legitimacy are analyzed in William Connolly, ed.,
Legitimacy and the State, New York: New York University Press, 1984, and Jiirgen
Habermas, Legitimation Crisis, Boston: Beacon Press, 1975.
15. See Howard Sherman, Stagflation: A Radical Theory of Unemployment and
Inflation, New York: Harper &C Row, 1976.
16. See Michal Kalecki, "Political Aspects of Full Employment," Political
Quarterly 14, no. 4 (1943): 322-30. For a more recent account, see Raford Boddy
and James Crotty, "Class Conflict and Macro Policy: The Political Business Cycle,"
Review of Radical Political Economics 7, (Spring 1975): 1-19.
17. See James O'Connor, The Fiscal Crisis of the State, New York: St. Martin's,
1973. See also Robert L. Heilbroner and Peter Bernstein, The Debt and the Deficit:
False Alarms, Real Possibilities, New York: W. W. Norton, 1989.
18. Radical critiques of the economic policies of the 1980s are presented in Frank
Ackerman, Reaganomics: Rhetoric vs. Reality, Boston: South End Press, 1982;
Stephen Rousseas, The Political Economy of Reaganomics: A Critique, Armonk,
NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1982; Robert Lekachman, Greed Is Not Enough: Reaganomics,
New York: Pantheon, 1982; and Charles K. Wilbur and Kenneth P. Jameson,
Beyond Reaganomics, University of Notre Dame Press, 1990.
19. See Stephen A. Marglin and Juliet B. Schor, eds., The Golden Age of
Capitalism: Reinterpreting the Postwar Experience, Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1990.
20. See Robert Heilbroner, 21st Century Capitalism, New York: W W Norton,
1993.
21. Proposals for controls on capital mobility are presented in Barry Bluestone
and Bennett Harrison, The Deindustrialization of America, New York: Basic
Books, 1982. See also Bennett Harrison and Barry Bluestone, The Great U-Turn:
Corporate Restructuring and the Polarizing of America, New /ork: Basic Books,
1988. A Classical Liberal response to the Radical proposal for controls on capital
is presented in Richard B. McKenzie, Fugitive Industry: The Economics and Politics
of Deindustrialization, San Francisco: Pacific Institute, 1984.
22. See Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis, "Efficient Redistribution: New Rules
for Markets, States, and Communities," Politics & Society 24:4, December, 1996,
307-342.
154 Political Economy
ADDITIONAL READING
Adams, Gerald R, and Lawrence R. Klein, eds. Industrial Politics for Growth
and Competitiveness: An Economic Perspective. Lexington, MA: D. C.
Heath, 1983.
Arestis, Philip, and Mike Marshall, eds. The Political Economy of Full
Employment. Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar, 1995.
Clarke, Simon. Keynesianism, Monetarism and the Crisis of the State. Brookfield,
VT: Edward Elgar, 1988.
Epstein, Gerald A., and Herbert M. Gintis, eds. Macroeconomic Policy After The
Conservative Era. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1995.
Heilbroner, Robert L. Beyond Boom and Crash. New York: W. W. Norton, 1978.
Higgs, Robert. Crisis and Leviathan: Critical Issues in the Emergence of the Mixed
Economy. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.
Hillier, Brian. Macroeconomics: Models, Debates and Development. New York:
Basil Blackwell, 1986.
Hirsch, Fred, and John H. Goldthorpe, eds. The Political Economy of Inflation.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978.
Lindberg, Leon N., and Charles S. Maier, eds. The Politics of Inflation and
Economic Stagnation. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution, 1985.
Offe, Claus. Disorganized Capitalism. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1985.
Peterson, Wallace C. The Silent Depression. New York: W. W. Norton, 1994.
Rowthorn, Bob. Capitalism, Conflict and Inflation: Essays in Political Economy.
London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1980.
Shafer, Todd, and Jeff Faux. Reclaiming Prosperity: A Blueprint for Progressive
Economic Reform. Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1996.
Sherman, Howard J., and Gary R. Evans. Macroeconomics: Keynesian, Monetarist
and Marxist Views. New York: Harper &c Row, 1984.
Weidenbaum, Murray. Rendezvous with Reality: The American Economy After
Reagan. New York: Basic Books, 1988.
Weintraub, Sidney. Capitalism's Inflation and Unemployment Crisis: Beyond
Monetarism and Keynesianism. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley, 1978.
Wilson, Thomas. Inflation, Unemployment, and the Market. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1984.
This page intentionally left blank
Chapter 9
that they are unwilling to make sacrifices or plan for the future. In the ter-
minology of neoclassical economists, these people have a "short time-
horizon," making them unwilling to delay gratification and thus unable to
accumulate savings or invest in human capital. 4 Poverty may simply be the
result of choices by people who value leisure more than the material rewards
of work. In summary, Classical Liberals portray inequality as arising largely
from individual choice—both the choices of individuals to acquire and sup-
ply productive resources and the choices of individuals to demand the
resources possessed by others. In the words of philosopher Robert Nozick,
the market operates according to the distributive rule: "from each as he
chooses, to each as he is chosen."
A r g u m e n t s for I n e q u a l i t y
During the transition from feudalism to capitalism, Classical Liberals
stood in the forefront of efforts to demolish privilege and hierarchy. The
Enlightenment offered a vision of society in which distinctions of class,
race, creed, or nationality would not affect social mobility. Enlightenment
thinkers defended the basic natural equality of all persons and assumed
that the destruction of traditional customs and institutions would result in
much greater equality in income and wealth. However, this strong egali-
tarianism was most evident among French thinkers. English social theo-
rists, in contrast, expressed doubts about the natural equality of persons.
John Locke, for example, suggested that workers had less capacity for
rational thought. 6 The early Classical Liberals were unwilling to allow peo-
ple without property to vote. Thus, despite its roots in the egalitarian spirit
of the Enlightenment, Classical Liberalism began to justify inequality at an
early stage in its evolution.7 The Classical Liberal defense of inequality is
based on the following arguments:
Responses to Poverty
Early Classical Liberal theorists such as Thomas Malthus claimed that
poverty was the unfortunate consequence of the human propensity to over-
populate a world with limited fertile soil. Malthus urged that poverty be
ignored because any efforts to assist the poor would only encourage addi-
tional population growth and further misery. Although some Classical
Liberals favored private charity as a solution to poverty, they warned that
any assistance should be minimal so as to retain incentives to work.
Welfare not only rewards irresponsible behavior, it demoralizes all citizens
by breaking the link between effort and reward.
By the 1960s, however, the dramatic expansion of government's role in
the economy persuaded some Classical Liberals to adopt a more activist
stance toward poverty. Since they viewed government as a major cause of
poverty, they could no longer attribute poverty solely to the choices of poor
persons. These Classical Liberals acknowledged a public responsibility to
aid citizens damaged by misguided government policies. The most notable
proposal, often associated with Milton Friedman, is a negative income tax.
This policy would establish a break-even level of income; any person earn-
ing more would pay taxes, and any person earning less would receive
money from the government. With a negative income tax, each citizen
would be assured of receiving at least a specified minimum income.
Friedman claims that such a program redistributes income most efficiently.
All other welfare programs could be abolished, and the money could go
directly to needy recipients. Paperwork and bureaucracy would be reduced
since determining the level of a family's benefits would require only a tax
form. The negative income tax also would promote the dignity and self-
esteem of recipients by eliminating trips to the welfare office and giving
them control over their purchases. Finally, a negative income tax would
eliminate differences in levels of support among states, thereby ending the
phenomenon of the "welfare magnet" in which states or cities with more
generous welfare programs attract additional clients.
Although the Nixon administration seriously considered the negative
income tax, its popularity has declined in recent years. Most Classical
Liberals now favor economic growth as the optimal solution to poverty.
Using the slogan "a rising tide lifts all boats," they claim that policies to
increase the rate of investment and stimulate growth are the only reliable
methods to reduce poverty. Growth increases the incentives for productive
behavior by offering greater opportunities for individual advancement.
Classical Liberals prefer growth to welfare because they believe that wel-
fare programs actually create poverty by fostering dependency, causing the
Poverty and Inequality 163
jobs with smaller firms offering lower wages and less fulfilling work envi-
ronments. 13 While barriers such as racial and sexual discrimination rein-
force dual labor markets, Radicals argue that the fundamental cause of
labor market segmentation is the difference in "market power" between
large, monopolistic firms and small, competitive firms. Workers in the pri-
mary sector earn a higher rate of return on their human capital than do
workers in the secondary sector because large corporations can pay higher
wages while still maintaining a satisfactory rate of profit.
From the Radical perspective, dual labor markets benefit capitalists by
maintaining labor force stability. The skilled employees in the primary sec-
tor are offered attractive wages and working conditions to secure their alle-
giance and dedication. Less desirable employees can then be hired for
menial jobs at low wages. With little mobility between the two labor mar-
kets, workers in the primary sector receive wages in excess of the compet-
itive level, while workers in the secondary sector receive lower wages than
if the entire labor market were unified. Workers in the secondary sector are,
in effect, subsidizing the high wages of workers in the primary sector.
Dual labor markets also maintain divisions and disharmony among
workers, thereby undermining their bargaining power. By pitting lower-
paid workers against higher-paid workers, capitalists "divide and conquer"
the labor force. Radicals deny that low wages in the secondary sector are
caused by low levels of human capital and productivity among workers,
claiming instead that workers' behaviors and attitudes are largely condi-
tioned by their wage level and work experience. Those who have endured
low wages and unpleasant working conditions may develop a record of low
productivity, absenteeism, and frequent job turnover. In contrast, primary
sector workers tend to be highly dependable and committed to their firm
because they are paid well and enjoy job security and pleasant working
conditions. In summary, Radicals argue that attributing low wages to low
levels of human capital puts the cart before the horse; low wages and mea-
ger job prospects cause low levels of productivity among workers in the
secondary sector.
A r g u m e n t s for E q u a l i t y
Radicals embrace the Enlightenment claim that "all men are created
equal." For Radicals, this statement does not mean that individuals have
identical abilities, but rather that humans are, by virtue of being citizens,
entitled to participate in political and economic decisionmaking and to
enjoy a standard of living sufficient to fully develop their personal abili-
ties.14 Three arguments underlie this strong commitment to equality.
R e s p o n s e s to P o v e r t y
Because poverty and inequality are functionally necessary to capitalism,
Radicals doubt the viability of redistributive policies that stop short of a
Poverty and Inequality 167
major restructuring of the economy. In fact, they claim that many govern-
mental efforts aimed at helping the poor actually perpetuate inequality. The
social programs associated with the modern welfare state often function to
pacify low-income people and prevent social disorder. The major expan-
sions in the role of the welfare state occurred during periods when wide-
spread discontent threatened to overturn the existing power structure.
Capitalist welfare programs are not designed to reduce poverty and unem-
ployment, since depletion of the reserve army would increase the bargain-
ing power of workers. Radicals conclude that the primary purpose of
welfare programs is to maintain a pool of cheap labor and control over a
potentially rebellious lower class.15
In the past, Radicals were likely to favor a guaranteed minimum income
as a means of assuring that the basic needs of all citizens were met.16
However, the growing public disillusion with welfare has raised doubts
about the political viability of income transfers to able-bodied persons. The
notion of an entitlement or right to a decent standard of living has fostered
antagonism toward the poor resembling the resentment against wealthy
aristocrats in previous centuries. In an ironic twist, the poor are viewed by
many as the new privileged elite who have the luxury of living without
working. The Classical Liberal linkage between productive contribution
and reward is deeply embedded in modern ethics and is even mirrored in
Marx's insistence that reward correspond to labor. For these reasons,
Radicals tend to focus more on full employment and public provision of
basic necessities such as health care and transportation. Full employment
might be achieved either through government incentives to private employ-
ers or reliance on government as the employer of last resort. Also, appro-
priate fiscal and monetary policies might be used to push the economy
toward high levels of employment.
A recent Radical proposal for reducing inequality is called "asset-based
redistribution." Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis argue that giving all cit-
izens ownership rights to assets such as workplaces and residences would
result in increased productivity and efficiency as individuals assume the
rights and responsibilities of property ownership. Admittedly, some indi-
viduals would use their property more wisely than others, but Bowles and
Gintis believe that the resulting inequality would be substantially less than
in most existing societies where the bulk of assets are owned by a small
minority of the population. This proposal reflects a growing disenchant-
ment among Radicals with the traditional vision of socialism as consisting
of public ownership of property and central planning of production.
According to Bowles and Gintis, the socialist goal of a more egalitarian
society is achievable through a market economy in which an equitable pat-
tern of property ownership has been established and government provides
various regulations and insurance programs as buffers against the vagaries
of the market. 17
168 Political Economy
A r g u m e n t s for I n e q u a l i t y
The Conservative case for inequality includes the following arguments:
R e s p o n s e s to P o v e r t y
Conservative proposals for dealing with poverty include the follow-
ing policies:
1. Imperfect competition. Because the market never meets all the con-
ditions for perfect competition, the distribution of income will be unfair
even by the standards of neoclassical economic theory.27 To the extent that
monopolies and oligopolies exist, that information is lacking, that
resources are immobile, and that competing products are not homoge-
neous, the marginal productivity criterion for distribution will be violated.
In other words, those individuals and groups with market power, better
information, and more mobile resources will "exploit" less advantaged
groups. 28 Imperfect competition also means that the market will fail to
adjust instantaneously to changes in technology, resource availability, or
consumer preferences. While gradual adjustments occur, some individuals
will lose income and others will profit enormously from the temporary dis-
equilibrium. For example, the development of computer technology has
displaced thousands of bookkeepers while making Bill Gates the wealthiest
person in the world.
A r g u m e n t s for E q u a l i t y
Unlike Radicals, Modern Liberals are confident that substantially
greater equality can be achieved within the confines of capitalism. To jus-
tify redistribution, they have developed a wide variety of arguments in
favor of increased equality.
possess equal capacities for pleasure, then, according to the law of dimin-
ishing marginal utility, a rich person gets less satisfaction from a dollar than
does a poor person. Redistributing money from rich to poor increases total
satisfaction because the loss of utility by the rich would be less than the
gain in utility experienced by the poor. Bentham and Mill did not push for
redistribution, however, fearing that property owners would feel insecure
and stop investing.
4. Political stability. Keynes also argued that greater equality was essen-
tial to preserve popular support for capitalism and democracy. He believed
that both fascism and communism had been fueled by widespread anger
and resentment over excessive inequality, poverty, and unemployment.
wealth and income. Without justice and social solidarity, citizens are likely
to experience despair, insecurity, envy, and hostility. Too much inequality
challenges the legitimacy of property holdings because rewards no longer
appear to correspond to individual effort and ability. People with large
property holdings often appear to be richly rewarded for leading lives of
leisure. The aspirations of the poor decline as they perceive the market to
be merely a power struggle in which those who already own property
always win.
The most recent case for a link between equality and justice comes from
philosopher John Rawls, who claims that even a distribution of income in
accordance with personal ability would not be fair because ability is
affected by randomly distributed genetic endowments. According to Rawls,
justice requires that income and wealth be distributed in a manner that
maximizes the well-being of the poorest members of society. In other
words, rich people are entitled to their wealth only if it contributes to cap-
ital accumulation, job creation, and rising standards of living for the poor.
Greater equality should be pursued until any further redistribution would
so damage incentives and capital accumulation that the poor would actu-
ally be harmed.
Despite a strong commitment to greater equality, Modern Liberals, with
the exception of Rawls, have been reluctant to specify an optimal distribu-
tion. In fact, many Modern Liberals remain skeptical and cautious about
redistributive efforts. Bentham and Mill opposed significant redistribution,
fearing that property owners would feel threatened and would cease to
engage their assets in productive ventures. Modern Liberal economists have
also expressed concern that, beyond a certain level, equality is incompatible
with economic efficiency.30 Efforts to promote too much equality will
dampen the incentives for work and investment by both those from whom
money is taken and those to whom money is given. With lowered incen-
tives, the level of economic activity will decline due to inefficiency. This
"big tradeoff" between equality and efficiency has been the primary reason
for caution about any significant redistribution.
Responses to Poverty
Modern Liberalism currently stands at a historic watershed in its
approach to poverty. In the past, the market was condemned for permitting
and even exacerbating poverty, and government programs to redistribute
wealth and income were favored. The progressive income tax, the inheri-
tance tax, welfare programs, labor unions, agricultural price supports, rent
controls, minimum-wage laws, and social security were all intended to
reduce poverty and inequality. Modern Liberal economists acknowledged
that regulated prices caused inefficiency, but they argued that such policies
were more politically feasible than outright redistribution of income. For
Poverty and Inequality 177
example, the public would be more likely to favor milk price supports than
direct cash transfers to dairy farmers. However, by the 1960s, the results
of previous government efforts were so disappointing that Lyndon Johnson
launched a "War on Poverty" consisting of various welfare programs and
civil-rights laws. Unfortunately, the rising costs of the Vietnam war and the
onset of stagflation in the early 1970s effectively ended Modern Liberal
hopes for a quick solution to poverty.
In redesigning poverty programs, Modern Liberals have had to confront
two related constraints. First, concerns about budget deficits make any sig-
nificant expansion of funds to combat poverty unlikely. Second, the current
political climate is characterized by widespread resentment and insensitiv-
ity toward the poor.31 Recognizing the unpopularity of traditional welfare
programs, Modern Liberals now urge that public policy be reoriented from
dealing directly with the victims of poverty to challenging the market forces
and government policies causing poverty.32 The variety of Modern Liberal
proposals currently being considered include:
NOTES
1. For recent analyses of income and wealth distribution in the United States,
see Edward N. Wolff, Top Heavy: A Study of the Increasing Inequality of Wealth
in America, New York: Twentieth Century Fund Press, 1995; Anthony B. Atkinson,
Lee Rainwater, and Timothy M. Smeeding, Income Distribution in OECD
Countries, Paris: OECD, 1995; Jeffrey H. Bergstrand, et al., eds., The Changing
Distribution of Income in an Open U.S. Economy, New York: North-Holland,
1994; Denny Braun, The Rich Get Richer: The Rise of Income Inequality in the
United States and the World, Chicago: Nelson-Hall, 1991; and Sheldon Danziger
and Peter Gottschalk, Uneven Tides: Rising Inequality in America, New York:
Russell Sage, 1992.
2. See John Bates Clark, The Distribution of Wealth, New York: Macmillan,
1899. For an introduction to and critique of the marginal productivity theory of
distribution, see David Schweickart, Against Capitalism, New York: Cambridge
University Press, 1993.
3. Human capital theory is described in detail in Gary Becker, Human Capital,
2nd ed., New York: National Bureau of Economic Research, 1975. For a Radical
critique, see Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis, "The Problem with Human
Capital Theory, A Marxian Critique," American Economic Review 65, no. 2 (May
1975): 74-82.
4. The concept of a short time-horizon is utilized in Edward C. Banfield, The
Unheavenly City: The Nature and Future of Our Urban Crisis, Boston: Little,
Brown, 1968.
5. See Robert H. Frank and Philip J. Cook, The Winner-take-all Society,
New York: Free Press, 1995. The authors of this book do not condone the
growing inequality attributable to technology, and propose public policies to
address the problem.
6. For a detailed analysis of Locke's argument for differences in rationality
between the classes, see C. B. Macpherson, The Political Theory of Possessive
Individualism, Oxford: Clarendon, 1962.
7. The evolution of the concept of equality in Classical Liberal thought is pre-
sented in Amy Gutman, Liberal Equality, New York: Cambridge University Press,
1980. See also Ian Shapiro, The Evolution of Rights in Liberal Theory, New York:
Cambridge University Press, 1986.
8. For a Classical Liberal treatment of the issue of fairness and markets, see
Richard B. McKenzie, The Fairness of Markets, Lexington, MA: D. C. Heath,
1987. See also Gordon Tullock, Economics of Income Redistribution, Boston:
Kluwer-Nijhoff, 1983.
9. Hayek's critique of justice is developed in The Mirage of Social Justice,
Vol. 2, of Law, Legislation, and Liberty, London: Routledge St Kegan Paul, 1982.
Poverty and Inequality 179
10. Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia, New York: Basic Books, 1974.
11. See Charles Murray, Losing Ground: American Social Policy 1950-1980,
New York: Basic Books, 1984.
12. For a fuller account of the functionality of poverty, see Herbert Gans, "The
Positive Functions of Poverty," American Journal of Sociology 78, no. 2 (1972):
275-89. See also Charles Sackrey, The Political Economy of Urban Poverty, New
York: W. W. Norton, 1973.
13. Radical analysis of dual labor markets is presented in David M. Gordon,
Richard C. Edwards, and Michael Reich, Segmented Work, Divided Workers, New
York: Cambridge University Press, 1982; Richard C. Edwards, David M. Gordon,
and Michael Reich, eds., Labor Market Segmentation, Lexington, MA: D. C.
Heath, 1975; and David M. Gordon, Theories of Poverty and Unemployment:
Orthodox, Radical and Dual Labor Market Perspectives, Lexington, MA: D. C.
Heath, 1972.
14. See R. H. Tawney, Equality, London: George Allen and Unwin, 1931.
15. See Francis Fox Piven and Richard Cloward, Regulating the Poor, New
York: Pantheon, 1971.
16. Arguments for a guaranteed annual income are presented in Michael L.
Murray, ". . .And Economic Justice for All": Welfare Reform for the 21st Century,
Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1997.
17. Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis, "Efficient Redistribution: New Rules for
Markets, States, and Communities," Politics & Society, Vol. 24, No. 4, December,
1996.
18. Vilfredo Pareto, The Mind and Society: A Treatise of General Sociology,
New York: Dover, 1935.
19. See Arthur R. Jensen, "How Much Can We Boost IQ and Scholastic
Achievement?," Harvard Educational Review 39, no. 1 (Winter 1969): 1-123;
Richard Herrnstein, IQ and the Meritocracy, Boston: Little, Brown, 1973; and
Richard J. Herrnstein and Charles Murray, The Bell Curve: Intelligence and Class
Structure in American Life, New York: Free Press, 1994. Excellent surveys of the
debate over intelligence are presented in Daniel Seligman, A Question of Intelli-
gence: The IQ Debate in America, New York: Carol Publishing Group, 1992; and
Russell Jacoby and Naomi Glauberman, The Bell Curve Debate: History,
Documents, Opinions, New York: Times Books, 1995.
20. Kingsley Davis and Wilbert Moore, "Some Principles of Stratification,"
American Sociological Review 10 (April 1945): 242-49. For a fuller treatment of
the functional nature of hierarchy and inequality, see Talcott Parsons, The Social
System, Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1951.
21. See Kevin Phillips, The Politics of Rich and Poor: Wealth and the American
Electorate in the Reagan Aftermath, New York: Harper Collins, 1990.
22. These arguments are developed in Lawrence Mead, The New Politics of
Poverty, New York: Basic Books, 1992.
23. See Bertrand de Jouvenel, The Ethics of Redistribution (1951), Indianapoli
Liberty Press, 1990; and William A. Henry III, In Defense of Elitism, New York:
Doubleday, 1994.
24. The erosion of community in modern society is detailed in Robert A. Nisbet,
The Quest for Community: A Study in the Ethics of Order and Freedom, New
York: Oxford University Press, 1953.
180 Political Economy
ADDITIONAL READING
Atkinson, A. B. The Economics of Inequality. Oxford: Clarendon, 1983.
Baker, John. Arguing for Equality. New York: Verso, 1987.
Bonner, John. Economic Efficiency and Social Justice. Brookfield, VT: Edward
Elgar, 1995.
Brown, Henry Phelps. Egalitarianism and the Generation of Inequality. Oxford:
Clarendon, 1988.
Poverty and Inequality 181
Work occupies a central role in the lives of most people, and the nature of
work affects nearly all dimensions of human existence. Political economists
have long debated the question of how best to organize society's produc-
tive activities. How should labor be divided, industries organized, and
authority delegated? Is the market of government better suited to arrange
work that is efficient, yet satisfying for the people involved? In this chap-
ter, we shall investigate sharply contrasting interpretations of the role of
work in human life, the structure of authority in production, and the effect
of labor unions on the economy.
assure that workers would enter the factories, Classical Liberals sought to
abolish all forms of public welfare and increase the penalties for vagrancy
and theft.
Although Classical Liberals no longer believe that work is inherently
harmful, they do assume that most people would prefer not to work. The
incentive of monetary rewards is the primary enticement into the labor
force. Individuals choose to work because the anticipated utility of their
earnings exceeds the costs in terms of sacrificed leisure and the unpleas-
antness of work. Individuals decide when, where, and how much to work
by assessing the relative benefits and sacrifices associated with different
jobs and choosing the type of work offering the greatest net advantage. 2
Although a few talented individuals will be able to support themselves
through personally fulfilling work, Classical Liberals assume that most
people view work as a "disutility." A job is merely a means to earn money
so that leisure time can be enjoyed more fully. Unstimulating work may
actually be appealing to those seeking to support themselves with the least
possible use of mental and physical energies. If some people want fulfilling
work, Classical Liberals defend the market as the best guarantee that such
preferences can be met. For example, artists may devote themselves to their
crafts if they are willing to accept a lower standard of living. People who
value a more personalized work environment may seek employment in
small businesses, with awareness that they may sacrifice higher wages and
greater job security. The market allows people to balance their desire for
satisfying work against the value of higher wages.
Explanations of Hierarchy
Classical Liberals claim that existing institutional arrangements have
proven their worth by surviving in a competitive market. The history of
market-oriented societies consists of a continual elimination of inefficient
institutions as superior practices evolve over time. Applying this logic to
the structure of authority within the workplace, Classical Liberals conclude
that competition forces firms to adopt the most efficient organization of
work. If owners or managers adopt an inefficient structure of authority,
they will be penalized by the market as the firm experiences higher costs
and reduced profits.
Early in the twentieth century, management theorists such as Frederick
W. Taylor (1856-1915) and Frank Gilbreth (1868-1924) initiated "time-
and-motion studies" to reduce skilled jobs to simple, routine motions
quickly mastered by any worker. 3 Taylor's "scientific management" was
based on the Classical Liberal view of work as intrinsically unpleasant.
Workers are motivated solely by financial incentives. Taylor assumed that
workers derive little satisfaction from their jobs and therefore would not
object to routinization. Scientific management would actually relieve
Labor and Industry 185
workers from all responsibilities for planning and coordinating the pro-
duction process. Workers would simply engage in repetitive physical
motions. This more efficient division of labor also permitted management
to monitor work performance more effectively by establishing quantity,
quality, and time standards for each specific task.
In arguing that the market dictates an efficient organization of the firm,
Classical Liberals encounter an apparent contradiction. While defending
individual choice coordinated by the market as the best institutional arrange-
ment for achieving efficiency, Classical Liberals recognize the obvious effi-
ciency of large corporations in which thousands of people are "governed" by
hierarchical, centralized authority. The success of the modern corporation
seems to indicate that efficiency can be enhanced by suppressing individual
choice and market forces over a significant range of the production process.
To resolve this contradiction, Classical Liberal economists have formu-
lated "new institutional economics" and "property rights theory" to
demonstrate that corporate hierarchies and other seemingly nonmarket
institutions are efficient and arise from the rational choices of self-interested
individuals.4 Both of these theoretical approaches view society as a market
in which individuals engage in mutually beneficial exchanges. If the benefits
of an exchange are not immediately realized, both parties will seek to nego-
tiate a contract specifying future rights and obligations. Yet contracting is
often made difficult by the presence of "transaction costs." Economists
define a transaction cost as any cost not directly related to the production
of a commodity. Examples of transaction costs include the expense of gath-
ering information and specifying and enforcing contracts.
In the case of labor contracts, employers are often unwilling to fully
specify the obligations of both labor and management in a contract. Their
reluctance stems from imperfect information about the potential produc-
tivity of workers as well as a desire for flexibility in assigning tasks.
According to Classical Liberal economists, a hierarchical "governance
structure" within the firm solves these difficulties in labor contracting by
establishing a pyramid of command through which employers may assign
tasks and monitor work performance. Hierarchy permits corporations to
economize on transaction costs that would result from drawing up a fully
specified contract with each worker. The corporation will expand hierar-
chical control as long as the benefits gained by reducing transaction costs
and increasing output exceed the cost of additional supervision.
New institutional economics also offers an explanation for differences in
governance structures affecting white-collar and blue-collar workers.
Because employers assume manual labor is unpleasant and unfulfilling, they
conclude that workers will "shirk" their duties unless faced with the prospect
of detection and penalties. Therefore, rigid hierarchies and overt authority
prevail in industries such as mining and manufacturing. White-collar work-
ers, on the other hand, are more likely to resent close supervision, and they
186 Political Economy
perform tasks that are more difficult to monitor. Also, white-collar workers
often acquire skills on the job, so firing a worker and training a replacement
is costly. In such circumstances, direct supervision may be less efficient than
instilling in workers a sense of dedication to the job and loyalty to the firm.
This strategy is accomplished by establishing promotion ladders and pay
raises unrelated to productivity. Higher salaries can be economical if they
sufficiently reduce the need for supervision.
Classical liberals argue that a cooperative or egalitarian system whereby
workers monitor one another and share in the benefits of increased pro-
ductivity is infeasible. With so many people sharing the benefits, the
amount received by any single worker would be insufficient to provide an
incentive for monitoring co-workers. Only when the benefits of enhanced
efficiency accrue to a small number of owners and supervisory personnel
will incentive be adequate to elicit effective management of the firm.
According to Classical Liberals, hierarchy within the firm is entirely con-
sistent with workers' freedom. If hierarchy is efficient, and efficiency is
essential to the long-term viability of the firm, then even employees of
worker-owned firms would appoint or hire supervisory personnel and
encourage effective supervision by granting them the benefits accruing
from increased productivity. Thus, the structure of authority is independent
of who owns the firm. In the words of economist Paul Samuelson, "it
makes no difference whether capital hires labor or the other way around." 5
In a capitalist economy, workers may seek employment in a less hierar-
chical firm if they so desire. However, the large number of workers in
traditionally-structured jobs suggests that they value high wages more than
satisfying work. If people wanted more egalitarian work, they would seek
employment at lower wages with firms offering less structured environ-
ments. Employers should willingly dismantle hierarchy in exchange for
lower wages as long as reduced wage costs offset any loss of productivity.
If employers resist change, groups of workers could obtain loans to start
their own firms. If egalitarian work relations are truly more efficient, these
worker-owned firms would gradually drive capitalist firms out of business.
However, the virtual absence of large worker-controlled firms in capitalist
societies persuades Classical Liberals that hierarchy is the most efficient
form of work organization. 6
The Role of U n i o n s
Classical Liberals oppose labor unions, viewing them as groups seeking
to promote their own interests by suppressing competition in labor mar-
kets. To the extent that unions are successful in their goal of raising wages,
they cause the following problems:
1. Higher wages cause employers to substitute capital for labor, result-
ing in loss of jobs.
Labor and Industry 187
E x p l a n a t i o n s of Hierarchy
Radical explanations of hierarchy are based on Marx's distinction
between labor-power and labor. Labor-power is the ability to work; it is the
commodity sold by workers to capitalists in exchange for wages. In con-
trast, labor is the actual productive activity of workers. The purchase of
labor-power by capitalists does not guarantee that a specific amount of
labor will be performed, so capitalists confront the ongoing task of extract-
ing as much labor as possible from their employees. Workers, knowing that
capitalists reap most of the benefits of increased productivity, have little
incentive to exert themselves. Faced with this resistance, capitalists establish
hierarchical structures of control to increase the amount of labor performed.
Hierarchy also serves to reduce wage costs. Gradations of authority cre-
ate social distance and artificial barriers among workers occupying differ-
ent strata within the firm. By creating competition between workers for
promotions, capitalist employers fragment the workforce into antagonistic
groups, ensuring the maintenance of control over workers and suppressing
wage costs.
Although capitalists establish hierarchical control to secure high pro-
ductivity and low wages, Radicals argue that hierarchy actually reduces
efficiency. The inefficiency of hierarchy manifests itself in unmotivated
workers, extra layers of supervisory personnel, increased conflict within
the workplace, and an inability to utilize technology relying on a coopera-
tive and knowledgeable workforce. Understanding this argument requires
a brief excursion into the Radical interpretation of labor history and
changes in the organization of work. 13
According to Radicals, early capitalists introduced labor-saving tech-
nology to improve labor productivity and to reduce their reliance on
190 Political Economy
skilled artisans and craftworkers who, because they fully understood the
production process, could potentially leave and start their own competing
firms. Breaking down skilled work into numerous routine tasks enabled
capitalists to reduce the majority of jobs to physical motions requiring no
particular skill. As the increasingly limited tasks of workers narrowed
their understanding of the business, capitalists gained a monopoly over
knowledge of the production process and were able to exercise arbitrary
control over the organization and pace of work. As an added benefit for
capitalists, wages were held down by the virtually limitless supply of
unskilled labor.
However, this strategy of "deskilling" the labor force created a new set
of problems. The increasing homogeneity of workers led to an awareness
of their common interest in organizing to defend themselves. In response,
capitalists launched a new strategy of intentionally stratifying or seg-
menting the labor force. Hierarchical distinctions based on race, sex, level
of education, and credentials were utilized to "divide and conquer" the
labor force. For white-collar workers, hierarchical control was gradually
bureaucratized in order to minimize the arbitrary exercise of power so
offensive to professionals.
Radicals claim that technology and the internal structure of the firm
have been influenced more by capitalist concerns about maintaining con-
trol over the labor force than by concerns about efficiency. Capitalists are
only indirectly concerned about efficiency to the extent that it coincides
with profit maximization. While Classical Liberals argue that competitive
market forces make the capitalists' interest in maximizing profit synony-
mous with society's interest in efficiency, Radicals claim that profit-
maximization and efficiency will normally diverge. Although hierarchy
may be advantageous to the capitalist, it is inefficient and therefore con-
trary to the public interest.14
The debate between Radicals and Classical Liberals on the efficiency
of the capitalist firm has been difficult to resolve. First, empirical testing
of the efficiency of different forms of work organization is likely to be
inconclusive; no two firms are identical in every respect except for hier-
archical versus egalitarian structures of work. Second, efficiency ulti-
mately hinges on the motivation of workers. Classical Liberals, who
believe that most work is dissatisfying, anticipate that workers will
"shirk" unless placed within a hierarchical structure of command and
supervision. In contrast, Radicals believe that humans want and need to
perform meaningful work and that the implementation of more egalitar-
ian and participatory forms of work would unleash the repressed talents
and energies of workers who presently merely endure their jobs. These
conflicting beliefs cannot be scientifically proven or disproven because
human motivation results from historical, cultural, and economic factors
that vary over time and between societies.
Labor and Industry 191
The third difficulty in resolving this debate lies in disagreement over the
meaning of efficiency. Classical Liberals define efficiency in production as
cost-minimization and therefore feel confident that the same competitive
market forces driving firms to minimize costs will simultaneously enforce
efficiency. Radicals, by contrast, define efficiency as input-minimization; a
business is efficient if it produces a particular good with the fewest eco-
nomic resources. Competition may enforce cost-minimization relative to
other capitalist firms, but Radicals argue that capitalist firms actually use
more resources than would similar worker-controlled firms relying on
more egalitarian methods of production.
To demonstrate the inefficiency of capitalism, Radicals point out that
firms can potentially increase output without a corresponding increase in
cost by hiring additional supervisory personnel to extract greater amounts
of labor from workers. Although this achievement appears to be efficient
in terms of cost-minimization, the additional supervisors raise the amount
of labor being used to produce a particular product. Costs do not rise
because employees are working harder without an increase in pay. Radicals
conclude that hierarchy is inefficient because it fails to minimize the hours
of labor used to produce society's output.
Even if hierarchy failed to minimize costs, Radicals believe that capi-
talists would maintain authoritarian structures to secure profitability.
The Classical Liberal argument that competitive forces will subvert any
inefficient hierarchy rests on the assumption that at least one capitalist
will initiate the process by converting to an egalitarian organization of
work. However, the maverick capitalist would simply succeed in demon-
strating the superiority of worker control, thereby hastening the demise
of capitalism. Capitalists realize that even if worker control increases
productivity and profits, it will foster new forms of employee relations
and consciousness threatening to capitalist ownership. Radicals conclude
that capitalists will suppress egalitarian structures of work even if they
are more efficient.
Classical Liberal economists respond to the foregoing argument by
pointing out that if worker control were efficient, then groups of workers
would obtain loans either to start their own businesses or to buy out their
employers. Radicals, in turn, suggest two major obstacles to the establish-
ment of worker-owned firms. First, banks and other lending institutions
generally require significant collateral on large loans, effectively barring
groups of workers from obtaining the financing to start or buy out busi-
nesses. Second, the alienating nature of most jobs in capitalism has condi-
tioned workers to doubt their own entrepreneurial and organizational
abilities. In spite of these obstacles, Radicals remain confident that the
superiority of worker control will eventually prove itself, although the tran-
sition will require struggles for political power both within the firm and
throughout society.
192 Political Economy
The Role of U n i o n s
Radicals claim that unions have evolved from their original purpose of
challenging capitalist power to actually serving the interests of capitalists
by assuring predictable labor costs so long-term investment decisions can
be made. In return for union cooperation, capitalists grant substantial wage
increases, knowing that higher costs can be passed on to consumers
through higher prices. Radicals use the term "embourgeoisement" to
describe the process by which portions of the working class have managed
to secure for themselves a comfortable standard of living while ignoring the
plight of women, minorities, and nonunionized workers.
However, Radicals do not blame workers for the actions of labor
unions. As the U.S. labor movement developed in the late nineteenth cen-
tury, both moderate and Radical factions competed for dominance. Those
farsighted capitalists who recognized the inevitability of unionization took
measures to assure victory for the moderates. The American Federation of
Labor came to prominence partly because of support from capitalists who
viewed it as a lesser evil than the more militant Knights of Labor and
International Workers of the World. By backing the moderates, capitalists
undermined demands for greater control of the workplace and steered
workers toward "bread-and-butter" issues such as higher wages and better
working conditions.
Despite these criticisms, Radicals support labor unions as essential to
organizing the working class. As the industrialized sectors of the economy
deteriorate, Radicals predict that unions will become increasingly politi-
cized. Union demands will extend beyond wage increases to issues involv-
ing participation and control. As unionized workers suffer the effects of
industrial decline, they will become more interested in broadening their
membership by actively organizing minorities, women, government
employees, professional workers, and even members of the armed ser-
vices. Eventually, Radicals hope, unions will evolve from special-interest
groups to become representatives of the broad interests of the entire
working class.
E x p l a n a t i o n s of Hierarchy
Conservatives believe that hierarchical structures of authority are essen-
tial within businesses and throughout society. They offer the following
explanations for the emergence and persistence of hierarchy.17
The Role of U n i o n s
Conservatives are critical of labor unions for disrupting the natural hier-
archy of authority by usurping the prerogatives of owners and their
appointed managers. 18 However, Conservatives do not oppose the forma-
tion of occupational groupings. 19 Indeed, one of the recurring Conservative
critiques of modern society focuses on fragmentation and individualism.
Industrialization erodes community life, leaving anonymous individuals
with few social bonds. Labor unions, like other "intermediate institutions"
such as the family and the church, can integrate individuals into social net-
works, thereby fostering a sense of loyalty and belonging.
The unions envisioned by Conservatives would not function as special-
interest groups seeking maximum income and benefits for their members.
Instead, unions should join with neighborhood associations, businesses,
and government to promote a unified vision of society's goals and the
desire to cooperate and make sacrifices to achieve those goals. The labor
union should also function as a social group, providing a community in
which personal development is enhanced and members are socialized to
accept traditional values.
E x p l a n a t i o n s of Hierarchy
Modern Liberals note that F. W. Taylor's principles of "scientific man-
agement" were developed during a time when widespread poverty caused
many workers to view their jobs primarily as a means of providing food
and shelter for their families. However, as standards of living rose, work-
ers began to resist routinization and tight supervision, creating difficulties
for businesses relying on the techniques of scientific management. As a
result, a new "human relations" approach to management was popularized
during the 1920s by Elton Mayo (1880-1949) and extended during the
1940s by Kurt Lewin (1890-1947). 21 These theorists reflected the Modern
Liberal belief that people want to work if their jobs offer intrinsic satisfac-
tion. The key to eliciting high productivity from workers is to organize pro-
duction to satisfy the needs of workers for respect, autonomy, a sense of
belonging, and the opportunity to advance. Given a positive environment,
workers will cooperate with management in achieving the firm's goals.
When people view work as an opportunity for personal development,
wages become only one factor among many determining employee satis-
faction. The social needs of employees for companionship, for the respect
and approval of colleagues, and for self-direction can be met by reorganiz-
ing work to enlarge the range of tasks performed by each individual, to
reduce close supervision, and to encourage participation in decisionmak-
ing. Reliance on employee initiative is advantageous to the firm because it
eliminates layers of supervisory personnel and results in more satisfied and
productive employees.
Modern Liberals conclude that "enlightened management" can reduce
hierarchy and "humanize" the workplace without necessarily sacrificing
profitability. Workers become more productive when they feel trusted and
valued; building trust requires that managers relinquish tight control of the
production process. Paradoxically, by empowering workers, management
will actually become more effective. The "synergy" of ideas emanating
from teams of workers will increase the wealth of the firm. However,
humanization of work does have limits. Economist Kenneth Arrow claims
that under conditions of uncertainty and imperfect information, some hier-
archy is essential to economic efficiency.22 Even highly motivated workers
require clear lines of authority for processing information and communi-
cating decisions. Hierarchy gives workers knowledge of the location of
authority and responsibility.
Despite these limitations on worker control, many Modern Liberals
believe that greater equality and participation in the workplace are possi-
ble. The present need for hierarchical authority derives in part from
poverty and discrimination that have iert many workers inadequately pre-
pared for self-directed work. The "human relations" approach to manage-
ment is typically confined to large corporations whose employees are
highly educated and well paid. Smaller firms often must rely on employees
Labor and Industry 197
The Role of U n i o n s
with cheap sources of labor and reduces the bargaining power of unions.
Finally, in response to the Classical Liberal charge that unions cause infla-
tion, Modern Liberals argue that corporate efforts to raise profits are the
primary cause of "cost-push" inflation. Real wages in the United States have
been stagnant since the 1970s, so union demands for higher wages are typ-
ically an effort to catch up to rising costs of living initiated by corporate
price increases.
As international competition has become a growing concern in recent
years, some Modern Liberals have tempered their support for labor unions.
The Keynesian advocacy of high wages has been challenged by the increas-
ing mobility of resources and products throughout the global economy.
Competitive pressures from abroad force corporations to negotiate more
aggressively with unions, sometimes to the point of demanding concessions
of previous gains. Modern Liberals now expect unions to be prudent and
responsible in their wage demands and to cooperate with management in
the adoption of labor-saving technology.
Despite these concerns, Modern Liberals continue to defend unions as
essential to the economic security of workers. This security consists of more
than high wages; workers have rights to fringe benefits, safe working con-
ditions, and protection against arbitrary power. Because the market does
not recognize these human rights, they would remain unprotected without
labor unions and government regulation.
NOTES
1. Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations, London: Dent, 1910, vol. 2: 265.
2. For a rigorous presentation of the neoclassical view of work, see Ugo
Pagano, Work and Welfare in Economic Theory, New York: Basil Blackwell, 1985
3. Two major works on scientific management are Frederick W. Taylor, The
Principles of Scientific Management, 1911, New York: W. W. Norton, 1967; an
Frank Gilbreth, Motion Study, 1911, Easton, PA: Hive, 1972.
4. The pioneering work in "new institutional economics" is Ronald H. Coase,
"The Nature of the Firm," Economica, 4, (November 1937): 386-405. More recen
works include Armen Alchian and Harold Demsetz, "Production, Information
Costs, and Economic Organization," American Economic Review 62 (December
1972): 777-95; and Oliver E. Williamson, "The Economics of Organizations: The
Transaction Approach," American Journal of Sociology 87, no. 3 (1981): 548-77.
All three of these articles, along with other seminal works in the theory of the orga-
nization of the firm, are included in Louis Putterman, ed., The Economic Nature of
the Firm: A Reader, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1986. See also Richar
N. Langlois, ed., Economics as a Process: Essays in the New Institutional
Economics, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1986; and Oliver E.
Williamson, The Economic Institutions of Capitalism, New York: Free Press, 1985
Jack J. Vromen, Economic Evolution: An Enquiry Into The Foundations of New
Institutional Economics, New York: Routledge, 1995; and Oliver E. Williamson,
The Mechanisms of Governance, New York: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Labor and Industry 199
14. These claims are developed in Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis,
"Contested Exchange: New Microfoundations for the Political Economy of
Capitalism," Politics & Society 18, no. 2 (June 1990): 165-222; Samuel Bowles
and Herbert Gintis, "The Revenge of Homo Economicus: Contested Exchange and
the Revival of Political Economy," Journal of Economic Perspectives, 7:1 (Winter
1993): 83-102; and Samuel Bowles, Herbert Gintis, and Bo Gustafsson, eds.,
Markets and Democracy: Participation, Accountability and Efficiency, New York:
Cambridge University Press, 1993.
15. Sigmund Freud, Civilization and Its Discontents, translated by James
Strachey, New York: W. W. Norton, 1961.
16. See Daniel Bell, The Coming of Post-Industrial Society: A Venture in Social
Forecasting, New York: Basic Books, 1973.
17. The role of hierarchy in society was a central theme of sociologist Talcott
Parsons. For an accessible account of Parson's ideas, see Robert J. Holton and Bryan
S. Turner, Talcott Parsons on Economy and Society, New York: Routledge, 1989.
18. See Seymour Martin Lipset, ed., Unions in Transition, San Francisco:
Institute for Contemporary Studies Press, 1986.
19. See Emile Durkheim, The Division of Labor in Society, New York: Free
Press, 1933.
20. Abraham H. Maslow, Motivation and Personality, 3rd ed., New York:
Harper & Row, 1987.
21. Elton Mayo, The Human Problems of an Industrial Civilization, New York:
Macmillan, 1933; and Kurt Lewin, Resolving Social Conflicts, New York: Harper
& Row, 1948.
22. Kenneth J. Arrow, The Limits of Organization, New York: W. W. Norton,
1974.
23. On methods for increasing worker participation, see William G. Ouchi,
Theory Z: How American Business Can Meet the Japanese Challenge, New York:
Avon, 1982; and Donald L. Dewar, The Quality Circle Guide to Participation
Management, Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1980.
24. See John Kenneth Galbraith, The New Industrial State, Boston: Houghton
Mifflin, 1967.
25. See Richard B. Freeman and James L. Medoff, What Do Unions Do?, New
York: Basic Books, 1988.
ADDITIONAL READING
Aoki, Masahiko, Bo Gustafsson, and Oliver Williamson, eds. The Firm as a Nexus
of Treaties. New York: Russell Sage, 1990.
Burawoy, Michael. The Politics of Production. London: Verso, 1985.
Farkas, George, and Paula England, eds. Industries, Firms, and Jobs: Sociological
and Economic Approaches. New York: Plenum Press, 1988.
Gordon, David M., Richard Edwards and Michael Reich. Segmented Work,
Divided Workers: The Historical Transformation of Labor in the United
States. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1982.
Habermesh, Daniel S., and Albert Rees. The Economics of Work and Pay, 4th ed.
New York: Harper & Row, 1988.
Labor and Industry 201
Harrison, Bennett. Lean and Mean: Why Large Corporations Will Continue to
Dominate the Global Economy. New York, Guilford Publications, 1997.
Kalleberg, Arne L., and Ivar Berg. Work and Industry: Structures, Markets, and
Processes. New York: Plenum, 1987.
Kochan, Thomas A., Harry C. Katz, and Robert B. McKersie. The Transformation
of American Industrial Relations. New York: Basic Books, 1986.
Marshall, Ray. Unheard Voices: Labor and Economic Policy in a Competitive
World. New York: Basic Books, 1987.
Mishel, Lawrence and Paula B. Voos, eds. Unions and Economic Competitiveness.
Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1992.
Noble, David. America By Design: Science, Technology, and the Rise of Corporate
Capitalism. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1977.
Pahl, R. E., ed. On Work: Historical, Comparative and Theoretical Approaches.
New York: Basil Blackwell, 1988.
Piore, Michael J., and Charles F. Sabel. The Second Industrial Divide: Possibilities
for Prosperity. New York: Basic Books, 1984.
Pitelis, Christos, ed. Transaction Costs, Markets and Hierarchies. Cambridge, MA:
Blackwell, 1993.
Sabel, Charles F. Work and Politics: The Division of Labor in Industry. New York:
Cambridge University Press, 1982.
Turner, Lowell. Democracy at Work, Changing World Markets and the Future of
Labor Unions. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1991.
Witte, John F. Democracy, Authority, and Alienation in Work. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1980.
Zieger, Robert H. American Workers, American Unions, 2nd ed. Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins University Press, 1994.
This page intentionally left blank
Chapter 11
Minorities and
Discrimination
vigorously search for qualified minority candidates. Each of the four per-
spectives has a different view of affirmative action and a different interpre-
tation of the role of minority groups in society.
government would let the market operate freely, the talents and ingenuity of
minority persons would enable them to rise from poverty.3
While Glenn Loury places much of the responsibility for minority prob-
lems on the attitudes, values, and behavior found within minority families
and communities, he ultimately blames government welfare programs for
undermining the initiative of minorities and creating a sense of dependency
passed on from one generation to the next. Loury is particularly concerned
about the decline of the traditional nuclear family in the black community,
and he blames welfare programs that are more accessible for single moth-
ers than for families headed by males.4
To summarize, Classical Liberals largely deny the existence of discrimi-
nation, arguing that most of the pay differential between majority and
minority wages results from differences in productivity. These differences
may be due to genetic inheritance or cultural norms, but Classical Liberals
prefer to emphasize the role of individual attitudes and values. Those who
are unable or unwilling to make productive contributions in the market are
treated fairly when their rewards are correspondingly small. If discrimina-
tion does occur, government bears the blame because it perpetuates racism
by providing welfare programs that reward irresponsible behavior, posing
legal obstacles to the advancement of minority persons and facilitating
monopolistic concentrations of power that shield discriminators from the
disciplining force of competition.
Responses to Discrimination
Viewing competitive markets as the best defense against discrimination,
Classical Liberals want government to eliminate nearly all regulations on
business activity. Government aid to minority groups is also condemned
because majority citizens should not be coerced through taxation to assist
minority persons. Any person wishing to offer assistance may contribute to
private charities. Furthermore, with less assistance from government, minor-
ity persons will be motivated to acquire more skills and work more diligently.
For Classical Liberals, equal opportunity exists when no individual or
group is either advantaged or disadvantaged by government policies. Laws
and public policies should be "color-blind," affecting members of all
groups equally. Any reference to race, religion, gender, or ethnic back-
ground in the formation of public policy is discriminatory. In particular,
affirmative action is simply "reverse discrimination" against nonminority
members of society.5 Besides unfairly penalizing nonminorities, affirmative
action creates inefficiency by disrupting the market's allocation of persons
to jobs for which they are qualified. Whenever employment is based on cri-
teria other than productivity, efficiency will be lost.
Classical Liberals support publicly funded education to assure equal oppor-
tunity for all persons. Not only should government assure equal education for
Minorities and Discrimination 207
all children, but students should have equal access to borrowing money for
higher education. When markets are free and the avenues for acquiring human
capital are open to all, Classical Liberals assume that prejudice and bigotry
cannot persist. They point to increasing opportunities for minorities in profes-
sional and managerial positions as evidence that discrimination is fading.6
Eventually, equality of opportunity will create a society in which individuals
are rewarded solely on the basis of productive contribution of their resources.
was aided by the perception among influential members of the ruling class
that continued segregation would jeopardize profitability and social order.
On the other hand, racial and ethnic distinctions provide an easy method
to segregate the labor force and maintain hierarchy in the division of labor.
Although capitalism has accomplished significant integration of the global
population, the annexation of new sources of labor typically occurs under
extremely inequitable conditions. Minority groups often find themselves
ushered into the capitalist economy either as cheap labor or because they
possess natural resources attractive to capitalists. Therefore, despite capital-
ism's potential for integration, the accumulation process often subordinates,
exploits, and discriminates against newly assimilated groups. 8
Even within the industrialized nations, capitalists manipulate hostility
between racial and ethnic groups to undermine worker solidarity, thereby
weakening the power of the working class. This "divide and conquer"
strategy is exemplified by the practice of using black workers as "scabs"
during strikes to motivate whites to return to work. In addition, minorities
are easily relegated either to the most menial occupations or to the "reserve
army of the unemployed" because their lack of power impedes their ability
to exert political resistance.9
Racial hostility also legitimizes the inequality associated with capitalism.
Race and ethnicity create distinct and identifiable groups in society, legit-
imizing poverty as the natural fate of people with personal deficiencies. If
poor and unemployed persons are perceived as "outsiders" who are not
part of the community, their presence is more easily tolerated. The frustra-
tions of lower-class white workers are diffused by knowledge that they are
relatively successful compared to unemployed minority persons.
In blaming discrimination on capitalism, Radicals do not deny the exis-
tence of racism. Yet this hostility has been formed by perceptions of self-
interest created by the capitalist economy. For example, the belief that
minorities pose a threat to wages and job security fuels racism. However,
Radicals claim that antagonism toward minorities is misdirected. Economist
Michael Reich assembled statistics showing that cities in which black wages
lagged farthest behind white wages also tended to have the lowest wages for
unskilled white workers, the highest profit rates, and the least amount of
unionization.10 Reich found capitalist employers to be the primary benefi-
ciaries of discrimination, giving them an economic interest in its perpetua-
tion. White workers, on the other hand, benefit from increased solidarity
and bargaining power provided by greater racial equality and unionization.
Radicals attribute much of the persistence of discrimination to segmented
labor markets. During the late nineteenth century, as capitalism annexed and
assimilated new populations, profitability demanded the de-skilling and
homogenization of labor. Tasks formerly requiring substantial skill and
training were broken down into series of routine movements easily learned
by any worker. The resulting gains in efficiency provided a stimulus to
MinoritiesandDiscrimination 209
R e s p o n s e s to D i s c r i m i n a t i o n
Within the context of capitalism, Radicals propose two strategies for
combating discrimination and elevating the economic status of minorities.
First, they encourage the formation of interracial coalitions to pressure
employers and the government for programs to overcome the effects of dis-
crimination. Radicals argue that both majority and minority persons have
much to gain through cooperation. For example, the Congress of Industrial
Organizations (CIO) made a concerted effort during the 1930s to include
black workers in its unionization drives. As a result, the CIO achieved sig-
nificant bargaining power and dramatic success in raising wages and
improving working conditions for millions of workers. The Civil Rights
movement of the 1960s provides another example of an interracial coali-
tion yielding gains for both black and white citizens.
The second component of a Radical program to combat discrimination
consists of government policies to promote full employment and economic
growth. Without growth, the economy becomes a zero-sum game with the
gains of one group coming at the expense of another. Similarly, unemploy-
ment exacerbates the tensions between marginally employed workers and
those eager to take their jobs. With growth and full employment, the for-
mation of interracial coalitions should proceed more rapidly.
210 Political Economy
not logically imply any particular attitude toward minority groups. Some
Conservative theorists presume the innate inferiority of minority popula-
tions, and others do not.
Racism implies that race should be a relevant factor in determining a per-
son's political, economic, or social status. Racists typically buttress their
views by claiming that specific groups of people are genetically inferior and
represent a lower stage in the evolution of the human species. Because of
their diminished capacities, minority groups should be denied equal rights.13
Several prominent Conservative theorists have proposed that some minor-
ity groups are intellectually inferior to whites. William Shockley (the inven-
tor of the transistor and winner of a Nobel prize in 1955), Arthur Jensen,
Richard Herrnstein, and Charles Murray point to the fact that African-
American students in the United States perform less well on IQ tests than do
whites.14 While the differences in test scores are indisputable, Modern
Liberals and Radicals dismiss IQ tests as "culturally biased" measures of
those aptitudes nurtured by the white middle class. More generally, the crit-
ics challenge the very notion of innate or objectively measurable intelli-
gence.15 Since intelligence denotes the ability to manipulate symbols in a
manner judged to be correct by a specific culture, aptitudes associated with
intelligence in one culture may be insignificant in another culture. Therefore
no single test can objectively measure intelligence across cultures.
Those Conservatives who regard minority persons as innately inferior
offer several explanations for discrimination. They claim that discrimina-
tion selects the superior over the inferior and is therefore neither immoral
nor unjust. Also, discrimination and segregation discourage interracial
marriages, which would result in "deterioration" of the gene pool. Finally,
segregation protects the cultural achievements of the dominant society.
Nonracist Conservatives offer different explanations of discrimination.
Because many minority groups originated in parts of the world with less
exposure to capitalism, their cultures may not emphasize behaviors such as
initiative, punctuality, and delayed gratification that contribute to success in
a market economy. If cultural differences create barriers to social interaction,
employers may be reluctant to hire minorities because an individual's pro-
ductivity depends on the ability to function well within the dominant culture.
Conservatives also emphasize the importance of maintaining the integrity
of various cultural heritages within a pluralistic society. Race and ethnicity,
together with family, neighborhood, and nation, create meaning and identity
for individuals. In addition, shared values and customs forge strong social
bonds preserving traditional cultures and communities. Segregation may be
necessary to protect minority cultures as well as the dominant culture.
Conservative opposition to integration is ultimately based on rejection
of the Enlightenment ideal of a universal community, the "brotherhood of
mankind," in which equally free and rational individuals pursue their inter-
ests in peace and harmony. By treating all persons equally, the universal
212 Political Economy
R e s p o n s e s to D i s c r i m i n a t i o n
Conservatives are less concerned with alleviating discrimination than
with reestablishing segregation to minimize interaction between different
racial and ethnic groups. Those Conservatives who appeal to the innate
inferiority of minorities may favor the practice of eugenics, which
involves social control of human reproduction through sterilization of
"deficient" persons and selection of "superior" persons for breeding. For
example, government might require sterilization for individuals applying
for welfare assistance. The Nobel prize-winning physicist William
Shockley sought to promote selective breeding by establishing a sperm
bank for Nobel prize winners.
Most Conservatives would like to end all government efforts to promote
integration. Groups sharing sufficiently common cultural heritages will
Minorities and Discrimination 213
Responses to Discrimination
The Modern Liberal belief that discrimination is embedded in society's
institutions means that viable solutions must involve legal and structural
changes as well as changes in individual values. Modern Liberals were
instrumental in the Civil Rights movement during the 1960s, pushing for
legal reforms such as the Civil Rights Act, the Voting Rights Act, the Equal
Opportunity Act, and desegregation of schools.
However, equal schooling and equal opportunity cannot fully compen-
sate for the deprived family environments affecting many minority children
trapped in a "cycle of poverty." During the 1970s, Modern Liberals focused
on achieving greater "equality of result." Minority persons cannot take full
advantage of the opportunities opened by legal reforms unless their income
is sufficient to sustain normal human development. The most direct strategy
for improving the material well-being of minority groups is redistribution of
income and wealth. Although theoretical justification for such a policy has
been provided by Keynes and Rawls, most Modern Liberals oppose large-
scale redistribution as politically infeasible and damaging to incentives.
Instead, they opt for less ambitious financial assistance and government
intervention. Proposals include raising the minimum wage, providing
greater public assistance, and enforcing legal safeguards against discrimina-
tion. Some Modern Liberals also join with Radicals in supporting full
employment as a method for increasing minority opportunities.
As economic stagnation eroded support for direct government assistance
to minority groups in the early 1970s, Modern Liberals turned to affirma-
tive action to encourage employers to vigorously search for qualified
minority candidates. 20 Critics claim that affirmative action sets hiring quo-
tas, forcing employers to hire less-qualified job applicants, and that it con-
stitutes "reverse discrimination" against whites. However, Modern
Liberals defend affirmative action by arguing that whites, as a group, have
benefitted from past injustices inflicted on minority groups. Had discrimi-
nation not occurred, many whites would not have attained their present
216 Political Economy
NOTES
1. See Gary Becker, The Economics of Discrimination, 2nd ed., Chicago;
University of Chicago Press, 1971.
2. See Thomas Sowell, Markets and Minorities, New York: Basic Books,
1981. Other relevant works by Sowell include Ethnic America: A History, New
York: Basic Books, 1981; Race and Economics, New York: David McKay, 1975;
The Economics and Politics of Race, New York: William Morrow, 1983; Race
and Cultures: A World View, New York: Basic Books, 1994; and Migration and
Cultures: A World View, New York: Basic Books, 1996.
3. Walter Williams, The State Against Blacks, New York: McGraw-Hill, 1982.
4. Glenn C. Loury, "The Moral Quandary of the Black Community," Public
Interest 79 (Spring 1985): 9-22.
5. See Alan H. Goldman, Justice and Reverse Discrimination, Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1979; Frederick R. Lynch, Invisible Victims: White
Minorities and Discrimination 217
Males and The Crisis of Affirmative Action, New York: Greenwood Press, 1989;
and Richard Epstein, Forbidden Grounds: The Case Against Employment nt
Discrimination Laws, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1992.
6. See Dinesh D'Souza, The End of Racism, New York: The Free Press, 1995.
7. A Radical account of the effect of early capitalism on the lives of common
people is presented in E. P. Thompson, The Making of the English Working Class,
New York: Pantheon, 1963.
8. See Eric Williams, Capitalism and Slavery, New York: Putnam, 1966.
9. See William Tabb, The Political Economy of the Black Ghetto, New York:
W. W. Norton, 1970; Manning Marable, How Capitalism Underdeveloped Black
America, Boston: South End Press, 1983; and Lloyd Hogan, Principles of Black
Political Economy, Boston: Routledge St Kegan Paul, 1984.
10. Michael Reich, Racial Inequality: A Political Economic Analysis, Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press, 1981.
11. See David M. Gordon, Richard C. Edwards, and Michael Reich, Segmented
Work, Divided Workers: The Historical Transformation of Labor in the United
States, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1982.
12. The integrationist perspective is presented in Manning Marable, Beyond
Black and White, New York: Verso, 1995. The separatist perspective is presented
in John T. McCartney, Black Power Ideologies, Philadelphia: Temple University
Press, 1992.
13. See Carleton Putnam, Race and Reason, Washington, DC: Public Affairs Press,
1961. For a critical analysis of the history of racist ideas, see Thomas F. Gossett, Race:
The History of an Idea in America, New York: Schocken Books, 1963.
14. William Shockley, "Dysgenics, Geneticity, Raceology: A Challenge to the
Intellectual Responsibility of Educators," Phi Delta Kappan 53, no. 5 (January
1972): 297-307; Arthur R. Jensen, Genetics and Education, New York: Harper &
Row, 1972; and Richard Herrnstein, Educability and Group Differences, New
York: Harper & Row, 1973. More recently, the idea of hereditary IQ has been
defended in Richard J. Herrnstein and Charles Murray, The Bell Curve:
Intelligence and Class Structure in American Life, New York: Free Press, 1994.
Excellent summaries of these ideas and the debates surrounding them are found in
Steven Fraser, ed., The Bell Curve Wars: Race, Intelligence, and the Future of
America, New York: Basic Books, 1995; Russell Jacoby and Naomi Glauberman,
The Bell Curve Debate: History, Document, Opinions, New York: Times Books,
1995; and Joe L. Kinchloe, Shirley R. Steinberg, and Aaron D. Gresson III,
Measured Lies: The Bell Curve Examined, New York: St. Martin's Press, 1996.
The history of efforts to scientifically establish racial differences in intelligence is
detailed in Allan Chase, The Legacy of Malthus: The Social Costs of the New
Scientific Racism, New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1977; Pat Shipman, The Evolution
of Racism: Human Differences and the Use and Abuse of Science, New York:
Simon &c Schuster, 1994; and Edward J. Larson, Sex, Race and Science: Eugenics
in the Deep South, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1995. For a
response by Arthur Jensen to his critics, see Arthur Jensen, Straight Talk About
Mental Tests, New York: Free Press, 1981.
15. See Ashley Montague, ed., Race and IQ, New York: Oxford University
Press, 1975; N. J. Block and Gerald Dworkin, eds., The IQ Controversy, New
York: Pantheon, 1976; Carl Senna, ed., Race and IQ, New York: Third Press,
218 Political Economy
1973; James M. Lawler, IQ, Heritability, and Racism, New York: International
Publishers, 1978; and Elaine Mensh and Harry Mensh, The IQ Mythology: :
Race, Class, Gender, and Inequality, Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois University y
Press, 1991.
16. See Nathan Glazer, Affirmative Discrimination: Ethnic Inequality and Public
Policy, New York: Basic Books, 1975. See also Nathan Glazer and Daniel Patrick
Moynihan, Ethnicity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1975.
17. See Stuart Butler, Enterprise Zones: Greenlining the Inner Cities, New York:
Universe Books, 1981; and Deborah K. Belasich, Enterprise Zones: Policy
Perspectives of Economic Development, New York: Garland Publishers, 1993.
18. See Edmund S. Phelps, "The Statistical Theory of Racism and Sexism,"
American Economic Review 62, no. 4 (September 1972): 659-61.
19. See Kenneth J. Arrow, Some Models of Racial Discrimination in the Labor
Market, Santa Monica, CA: Rand Corporation, 1971. See also Ray Marshall, "The
Economics of Racial Discrimination: A Survey," Journal of Economic Literature
12, no. 3 (September 1974): 849-71.
20. For additional information on affirmative action, see Margaret C. Simms,
ed., Economics Perspectives on Affirmative Action, Washington, DC: Joint Center
for Political and Economic Studies, 1995; Nicolaus Mills, Debating Affirmative
Action, New York: Delta, 1994; and Francis J. Beckwith and Todd E. Jones, eds.,
Social Justice or Reverse Discrimination, Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books, 1997.
ADDITIONAL READING
Boston, Thomas D. Race, Class, and Conservatism. Boston: Unwin & Hyman,
1988.
Carnoy, Martin. Faded Dreams: The Politics and Economics of Race in America.
New York: Cambridge University Press, 1994.
Cherry, Robert. Discrimination. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, 1989.
Franklin, Raymond, and Solomon Resnick. The Political Economy of Racism. New
York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1973.
Gabriel, John. Racism, Culture, Markets. New York: Routledge, 1994.
Hacker, Andrew. Two Nations. New York: Ballantine Books, 1992.
Jennett, Christine, and Randal G. Steward. Three Worlds of Discrimination: Race,
Class, and Gender. South Melbourne, Australia: Macmillan, 1987.
Lauren, Paul Gordon. Power and Prejudice: The Politics and Diplomacy of Racial
Discrimination, 2nd ed. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1996.
Leiman, Melvin M. Political Economy of Racism. Boulder, CO: Pluto Press, 1993.
Marable, Manning. Beyond Black And White: Transforming African-American n
Politics. New York: Verso, 1995.
Oliver, Melvin L., and Thomas M. Shapiro. Black Wealth/White Wealth: A New
Perspective on Racial Inequality. New York: Routledge, 1995.
Reuter, Theodore, ed. The Politics of Race. Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1995.
Schiller, Bradley. The Economics of Poverty and Discrimination, 5 th ed. Englewood
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1989.
Van Dyke, Vernon. Human Rights, Ethnicity, and Discrimination. Westport, CT:
Greenwood, 1985.
Chapter 12
Traditionally, both political and economic theory have ignored the divi-
sion of humans into two sexes. This oversight reflects one of two
approaches to issues of gender. Either women and men are so equal in sta-
tus and role designation that theory need not distinguish between them, or
women's roles in the political and economic realm are so insignificant that
theory may safely ignore them. Neither of these approaches is appropriate
for modern industrial societies in which women are active participants in
public life yet remain relegated to jobs with lower status and income. Even
allowing for differences between men and women in educational back-
ground and number of hours worked, a gender wage gap of twenty-five to
thirty percent remains.
Gender discrimination poses additional issues besides those associated
with racial or ethnic discrimination. The anatomical differences between men
and women are undeniable. Some theorists go further to claim that women's
and men's behavior suggests different interests and values. The question
remains whether women are economically and politically disadvantaged by
these differences. Economists distinguish between "in-market" discrimina-
tion, which involves unequal treatment of equally productive persons, and
"pre-market" discrimination, which arises from social institutions including
schools, family structure, and traditional values. Pre-market discrimination
220 Political Economy
may render women less productive, in which case their lower wages do not
necessarily indicate in-market discrimination. Yet efforts to precisely assess
the extent of in-market discrimination are hampered by the porous bound-
aries separating public life and private life. When employers discriminate
against women, they often rely on prevailing stereotypes about women's
productivity. These same stereotypes affect child-rearing practices, educa-
tional programs, and training opportunities for women. Thus in-market dis-
crimination and pre-market discrimination may reinforce each other,
making separate statistical analysis of discrimination in the labor market
haphazard at best.
in that, they will establish segregated worksites where men and women
earn equal wages but work separately. In either case, wage discrimination
against women will end.
Classical Liberals rely on the following explanations for the differences
between male and female social roles and earnings:
For those women who do work outside the home, their child-bearing
and child-rearing commitments may cause them to choose jobs such as
retail sales or clerical work which permit intermittent employment and
require skills that do not depreciate rapidly over time. Such jobs typically
offer lower wages and few opportunities for advancement, leaving women
with less experience and seniority than their male counterparts. Statis-
tically, a significant portion of the gender wage gap is attributable to the
concentration of women in these occupations. However, Classical Liberals
argue that this occupational segregation and the resulting wage gap arise
from women's preferences. They are willing to work in low-paying jobs
because they value time to spend with their families.
Policy Proposals
Classical Liberals propose that discrimination against women can be
eliminated by establishing a free market. Virtually all government interven-
tion should be abolished, and public life should be made "gender-blind" by
removing all references to gender in laws and public policies. While the pro-
posed Equal Rights Amendment to the U.S. Constitution seems to promise
equal treatment for men and women, most Classical Liberals oppose it,
arguing that existing laws already protect the civil rights of women and that
the ERA would lead to increased government regulation of business and a
resulting loss of efficiency and freedom. This same argument has been
extended by some Classical Liberals to criticize the entire feminist move-
ment for seeking to use government to promote equality between the sexes
through quota systems and other forms of government intervention.6
Classical Liberals also oppose "comparable worth" laws, which would
establish fair wages for different occupations by evaluating jobs according
to such criteria as skills required, level of responsibility, and working con-
ditions. While Classical Liberals support "equal pay for equal work," they
claim that only the market can determine the value of a job. The Classical
Liberal case against comparable worth focuses on three arguments. 7 First,
the assessed worth of any job depends on which criteria are used in its eval-
uation, but no objective method exists for selecting the criteria. Given this
lack of objectivity, a bureaucratic evaluation of a job's worth would be no
fairer than the market's assessment. Second, to the extent that comparable
worth would raise wages in traditionally female occupations, it would
reduce the incentives for women to enter male-dominated professions and
therefore would perpetuate the current occupational segregation of women.
Third, since male workers would resist efforts to reduce their wages, the
effect of comparable worth would be to increase overall labor costs for
employers, reduce profitability, eliminate jobs, and slow economic growth.
Some Classical Liberal economists have proposed policies to extend the
logic of the market into the private realm of the family. In response to con-
cerns about overpopulation, Classical Liberals have suggested that the
most efficient way to limit population growth is to establish a market for
the right to bear children. Adults would be granted a voucher for the right
to produce one child, and then, depending on their preferences, they could
buy or sell vouchers to reach their desired family size. Unlike China's
efforts to control population growth by restricting the number of children
in a family, this policy would retain the freedom to choose one's family size.
The development of artificial insemination and fetal transplants has
already transformed child-bearing itself into a marketable service as some
women contract to bear children in exchange for money. In the absence of
legal obstacles, supply and demand will determine the appropriate price for
"renting the womb" of a surrogate mother. Extending this logic, economist
Richard Posner, who is also a federal judge, proposes that markets be
224 Political Economy
established for babies so that couples can buy and sell to achieve their
desired family size. This policy is consistent with economic efficiency,
which dictates that any commodity be allocated to those who are most
willing and able to pay for it.
1. Marxist feminism. Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels claimed that the
social roles available to both men and women are conditioned by society's
production process. The earliest communal societies were sometimes matri-
archal, but as soon as technological progress yielded production of a surplus
beyond what was immediately consumed, men instituted private property to
establish rights to the surplus. With the emergence of private property came
male dominance over women, motivated partly by men's desire to control
women's reproductive activities to assure transmission of property to legiti-
mate heirs. Women became essentially the property of men, sometimes to the
point of being bought and sold between different families and communities.
In the early years of capitalism, the sexual division of labor and the
nuclear family were strengthened because they contributed to the accumu-
lation of capital. By performing unpaid tasks such as childbearing and
housekeeping, women enabled employers to, in effect, hire two workers for
the price of one. Women also indirectly aided employers by providing a
The Political Economy of Gender 225
supportive home life so that their husbands were physically and emotion-
ally prepared to face another day in the factory. For men, home and fam-
ily became havens from the alienating experience of work. 8
However, as capitalism matured and the demand for labor increased,
market forces pulled women out of the home and into the workplace as a
source of cheap labor. Yet the entry of women into the labor force had an
unanticipated consequence: employers replaced a "family wage" with a
wage adequate to support only a single person. The nuclear family became
endangered as men could no longer earn enough to support their families,
and women became increasingly capable of financial independence. From
the Radical perspective, rising divorce rates, disintegration of families, and
the blurring of gender roles are not symptoms of moral decline, but instead
are consequences of capitalism. The accumulation process penetrates every
sphere of human existence, breaking down bonds and obligations between
people and replacing personal relations with a "cash nexus."
According to Marxists, the capitalist system is the enemy of both men
and women. As long as capitalism continues, all members of the working
class will lack control over their lives. Hostility between the sexes arises
as capitalists seek to fragment and divide the working class to assure a
steady supply of cheap labor. As long as men and women blame each
other for bad relationships and financial problems, their attention is
diverted from the real source of their frustration, which is the dominant
power of capital over people.
In the late 1960s, a resurgence of interest in both Marxism and feminism
led to "Marxist feminism," which holds that women's oppression is attrib-
utable to capitalism and that issues raised by feminists are best analyzed and
understood using the Marxist critique of capitalism. Among the most promi-
nent Marxist feminist theorists are Sheila Rowbotham and Michele Barrett.9
while upper-class parents are more likely to stress creativity and self-direction
for their children. As a result, the children of each class are socialized to fill
their respective future roles in the hierarchy of capitalist production.
Policy Proposals
Because the Radical perspective encompasses three distinct types of fem-
inism, Radicals offer a wide variety of proposals related to gender issues.
Marxist feminists believe that the oppression of women can be solved only
by ending capitalism and making the transition to a socialist society. Yet,
in addition to the socialization of the means of production envisioned by
Marx, they call for socialization of household production. Communal
households would be able to take advantage of economies of scale and
modern technology to accomplish such tasks as cleaning, shopping, food
preparation, and child care. All adults would be expected to share in these
responsibilities, and women would participate equally with men in the paid
labor force. Marxist feminists believe that only when women and men have
similar economic roles in society will male domination end. Women can be
most effective in bringing about social change by joining with men in a
working-class movement to end capitalism.
In contrast, radical feminists propose that the only viable strategy for the
liberation of women is to develop separate "women-centered" institutions
and communities that exclude patriarchal culture and male domination.
Because Radical feminists view the nuclear family as a key institution in
perpetuating patriarchy, some have suggested that the technology for pro-
ducing "test-tube babies" offers an unprecedented opportunity for women
to escape their biological dependence on men and to become autonomous,
self-directing persons. 13
Socialist feminists share much of the Marxist feminist skepticism con-
cerning the possibility of reform within a capitalist society. Not only is gov-
ernment an instrument in the hands of the ruling class, but legal reforms
cannot effectively end the institutionalized sexism shaping women's aspira-
tions. The liberation of women and men requires a broad-based socialist
movement to abolish both capitalism and patriarchy. While socialist femi-
nists reject the separatist strategy of radical feminists, they also insist that
feminist issues not be submerged in the struggle to end capitalism.
According to socialist feminists, capitalism is currently contributing to its
own demise. As women enter the labor market, they are disillusioned by the
alienating conditions of work and often face "double duty"—performing
household labor in addition to wage labor. The hours devoted to housework
are kept from declining by corporate marketing campaigns that create ever-
higher standards of housekeeping and parenting.14 Women's frustration
with the roles available to them in capitalist society will foster growing sup-
port for socialism. In the meantime, some socialist feminists advocate wages
228 Political Economy
The differing temperaments and abilities of men and women dictate well-
defined gender roles. Just as the human body requires different cells to
The Political Economy of Gender 229
function (such as bone, muscle, and skin), society needs differentiated gen-
der roles to remain healthy. The sociologist Talcott Parsons claimed that
women are best suited for "expressive" roles while men have greater apti-
tude for "instrumental" roles. Social harmony requires that women fill roles
as wives, mothers, and members of the "helping professions" while men
engage in physical or intellectual work manipulating the external world.
Conservatives insist that gender differences are naturally complemen-
tary. They view men as strong, aggressive, and inclined toward rational
analysis, while women are nurturing and emotionally expressive. Men need
women to raise children and provide a fulfilling home life, while women
need men as sources of authority and financial support. So long as men and
women accept one another's relative strengths and weaknesses, harmony
will prevail. Indeed, the different capacities of men and women constitute
the basis for sexual attraction and are therefore essential to reproducing the
human species.
In analyzing the breakdown of traditional gender roles and gender iden-
tities, Conservatives place much of the blame on the deterioration of the
nuclear family.17 The family, as the basic unit of society and the primary
site of socialization processes, prepares children for adulthood. Conserv-
atives reject the Classical Liberal notion that humans develop through
rational choice. The role models and socialization to which people are
exposed as children shape individual preferences and behavior. For both
children and adults, personal development requires involvement in a web
of hierarchical social relations. The authority of parents conditions the
child to later accept the authority of teachers, employers, and government.
In addition, children's observation of the relation between their parents
provides the basis for gender identity. When adult gender roles are vague
or ambiguous, Conservatives fear that children will become confused and
thwarted in the development of their own personalities.
Conservatives claim that blurring of gender roles and deterioration of
the nuclear family contribute to immorality and economic stagnation. They
blame this process on the following factors:
their purpose in life. George Gilder argues that men's economic productiv-
ity has been adversely affected by feminism because when women are
actively involved in the labor force, men no longer feel as compelled to
work. 19 Not only are women bringing their earnings into the household,
but their employment erodes men's attachment to work as a uniquely male
source of self-esteem. Moreover, having lost authority over their own fam-
ilies, men feel inadequate to assert themselves in the business world. To the
extent that feminism contributes to divorce, men are freed from most of
their domestic responsibilities, causing further deterioration of their identi-
ties as providers and hence diminishing their productivity in the workplace.
Finally, Conservative women such as Phyllis Schlafly and Anita Bryant
have claimed that the women's liberation movement consistently
degrades women who choose the role of housewife and mother. 20 Women
in traditional roles are made to feel inadequate in comparison with
women who pursue careers. The resulting confusion and loss of confi-
dence contributes to the blurring of gender roles as women feel compelled
to prove their worth outside the home. Conservatives claim to be the true
defenders of women's rights to keep the status and privileges attached to
their traditional roles.
Policy Proposals
Because they blame both government and the market for undermining
gender roles and threatening the family, Conservatives will not rely exclu-
sively on either institution to solve the problem. Their goal in reforming
government policies is to revitalize the market's potential for producing
wealth while protecting women and families from the corrosive impact of
market forces. Conservatives call on government to consciously promote
traditional values and gender roles. For example, they support a Family
Protection Act to reduce the pressures on women to work outside the home
by granting tax breaks to families with nonworking wives. This law would
also prohibit publicly funded lawyers from handling cases involving
divorce, abortion, or homosexuality.
Conservative policy proposals also include making divorce more diffi-
cult, prohibiting abortion, and making welfare less accessible for single
women. Public schools would be prohibited from using textbooks featuring
nontraditional roles for women. Some Conservatives, concerned that femi-
nism and narcissism have caused many young adults to shun the responsi-
bilities of parenthood, want government to pursue pronatal policies to
combat a "birth dearth." Such policies might include larger tax deductions
for families with children and public financial assistance with childrearing.
Conservatives have consistently opposed the Equal Rights Amendment,
claiming that it would further erode the differentiation between gender roles
and would abolish the legal requirement that men provide financial support
232 Political Economy
to their wives. The ERA, they claim, would actually result in men's libera-
tion from traditional responsibilities to their families.
Conservatives tend to be pessimistic about the future of gender roles and
the family. The economy's increasing inability to provide a "family wage"
for male workers contributes to the breakdown of the family, and, recip-
rocally, the breakdown of the family undermines the economy by produc-
ing self-centered, poorly socialized children who are ill-equipped to work
effectively and to handle the responsibilities of adult life. This circular path
of causation means that any effective Conservative strategy must simulta-
neously deal with misguided government policies, powerful economic
forces, and the influence of feminism.
By the end of the 1970s, many Modern Liberals became concerned that
their commitment to equal rights and equal treatment was imposing
unforeseen burdens on women. A third phase of Modern Liberal feminism
reintroduced notions of difference between the sexes. For example, social
psychologist Carol Gilligan claims that women view the social world as
one of relationships, commitments, and responsibilities, whereas men view
society as composed of separate individuals whose interaction is based on
rules and rights. 22 If, in their quest for occupational success, women adopt
the competitive individualism of men, they risk compromising their own
valuable qualities. Gilligan does not propose that women remain at home,
but suggests that institutional changes are necessary to accommodate the
different needs and interests of women in the workplace.
Similarly, Nancy Chodorow claims that differences in male and female
gender identity are determined at a very early stage of childhood develop-
ment. 23 Boys develop more "rigid ego boundaries" because they must dif-
ferentiate themselves from their mother. In the process, they form identities
as separate individuals in competition with others. Girls, on the other
hand, share the gender of their mother and, therefore, develop a more fluid
sense of self that emphasizes interpersonal connections and sympathy with
the needs of others. As a result, girls are prepared for the role of mother,
while boys, with their sense of separateness and independence, are pre-
pared to participate in the impersonal world of work and business.
Chodorow denies that gender differences are purely biological. If men
were to become more involved in the early stages of childrearing, tradi-
tional distinctions between the psychosocial development of boys and girls
might fade. In addition, if marriages provided greater emotional gratifica-
tion, women would not feel compelled to focus their energies primarily on
their children and would expect greater sharing of responsibilities between
husband and wife. However, for the foreseeable future, the differences
between adult gender roles are likely to be "reproduced" in children, and
feminists should recognize these differences when proposing public policies
related to gender issues.
While Modern Liberals acknowledge that competitive market forces
create pressures to integrate women into the labor force, they challenge
the Classical Liberal portrayal of the market as an adequate deterrent to
discrimination. Discrimination is resistant to market forces for the fol-
lowing reasons:
behavior. The employer who violates these norms by hiring women to per-
form "men's work" may be ostracized within the community or may feel
guilt for having exploited women for the sake of greater profit.
Discrimination can be disguised as protecting the dignity and virtue of
women, and this attitude may be sufficiently strong to withstand competi-
tive market forces.
Employers may also be reluctant to hire women due to concern about
the morale of male workers. Employers may worry that the presence of
women will distract men, disrupt their camaraderie, and create tensions
between co-workers. Male employees engaged in strenuous or risky jobs
are likely to feel particularly threatened by female co-workers whose pres-
ence undermines their enjoyment of work as a source of masculine pride.
Employers must be sensitive to these reactions since time and money have
been invested in training male workers. Hiring female workers will be
unappealing if it lowers male workers' productivity.
Policy Proposals
The initial orientation of Modern Liberal groups such as the National
Organization for Women was to make all laws gender-neutral, and they
were quite successful in accomplishing that goal. In the mid-1970s, how-
ever, Modern Liberals began to doubt the wisdom of perfectly gender-
neutral public policy. This reorientation evolved from the realization that if
236 Political Economy
women and men are treated equally in the job market, women may be
penalized due to their unique status as childbearers and, in many cases, pri-
mary homemakers. The pitfalls of a purely "equal rights" strategy were
highlighted in 1976 when the Supreme Court ruled that a proposed law
requiring employers to grant paid leaves of absence to pregnant women
was discriminatory because it treated women differently than men.
To move beyond formal equality under the law, affirmative action pro-
grams require employers to make concerted efforts to locate qualified
female and minority applicants for jobs. Another proposal for addressing
pay inequities is "comparable worth." While the wages attached to various
jobs are theoretically determined by supply and demand, Modern Liberals
claim that market-determined wages can be unfair due to discrimination
and gender stereotyping. In addition, women's family responsibilities force
them to crowd into occupations offering flexible hours, but this over-
crowding keeps wages for these occupations permanently depressed.
Therefore, if the financial burden of childrearing is to be shared equi-
tably by men and women, the market's determination of wages must be
overridden. Comparable worth provides an alternative to the market in
assessing the relative worth of different jobs. Each job would be evaluated
according to criteria such as level of responsibility, physical difficulty, and
amount of training required. By assigning points in each category, a
numerical rating would be established for each job, and pay would corre-
spond with that rating. The goal of comparable worth is to formulate an
objective measurement of the value of different jobs independently of the
market's valuation. 26
Those Modern Liberals who support comparable worth claim that it
would contribute to women's financial independence and enhance their self-
esteem and power. By paying women more than their market-determined
wages, society is acknowledging not only the unfairness of traditional wage
structures, but also the value of women's productive contributions in the
home. Modern Liberals claim that comparable worth can actually increase
efficiency because women's child-rearing activities create positive externali-
ties; the social benefits of good parenting exceed the private benefits to the
individual child or family. Adults who grew up in nurturing families are
more likely to work productively, vote intelligently, and contribute to the
good of society. When an activity produces positive externalities, the mar-
ket allocates insufficient resources to that activity, resulting in inefficiency.
To correct this market failure, government should compensate women for
their productive efforts in the home by setting their wages above the level
determined by supply and demand.
Other Modern Liberal proposals related to gender include marital prop-
erty reform to secure for married persons a legal right to half of any
property acquired during the marriage, even if only one spouse was in
the labor force. Such a law would recognize the productive contribution
The Political Economy of Gender 237 7
NOTES
1. See Jean Bethke Elshtain, Public Man, Private Woman: Women in Social and
Political Thought, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1981; and Susan
Moller Okin, Women in Western Political Thought, Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1979.
2. See Mari Jo Buhle and Paul Buhle, The Concise History of Woman Suffrage,
Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press, 1978; Judith Hole and Ellen Levine, Rebirth
of Feminism, New York: Quadrangle Books, 1971; Richard J. Evans, The
Feminists, Totowa, NJ: Rowman &c Littlefield, 1979; Sara M. Evans, Born for
Liberty: A History of Women in America, New York: Free Press, 1989; and Lois W.
Banner, Women in Modern America: A Brief History, 3rd ed., Fort Worth:
Harcourt Brace College Publishers, 1995.
3. Classical Liberal feminism is presented in Wendy McElroy, ed., Freedom,
Feminism, and the State, Washington, DC: Cato Institute, 1982; Ellen Frankel Paul,
Equity and Gender, Washington, DC: Cato Institute, 1988; and Joan Kennedy
Taylor, Women s Issues: Feminism, Classical Liberalism, and the Future, Stanford,
CA: Hoover Institution, 1993.
4. See Gary Becker, A Treatise on the Family, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1981. See also Gary Becker, The Economic Approach to Human
Behavior, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976.
5. See Richard B. McKenzie and Gordon Tullock, The Best of the New World of
Economics, 5th ed., Homewood, IL: Richard D. Irwin, 1989. See also Gary S. Becker
and Guity Nashat Becker, The Economics of Life, New York: McGraw-Hill, 1997.
6. The Classical Liberal case against feminism is presented in Michael Levin,
Feminism and Freedom, New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Books, 1987.
7. For a Classical Liberal critique of comparable worth, see Richard E. Burr,
Are Comparable Worth Systems Truly Comparable}, St. Louis: Center for the Study
of American Business, Washington University, 1986. See also Jennifer Roback, A
Matter of Choice: A Critique of Comparable Worth by A Skeptical Feminist, New
York: Priority Press, 1986.
8. See Eli Zaretsky, Capitalism, The Family and Personal Life, New York:
Harper 6c Row, 1976.
9. Sheila Rowbotham, Woman's Consciousness, Man's World, Baltimore:
Penguin, 1973, and Michele Barrett, Women's Oppression Today: The e
Marxist/Feminist Encounter, rev. ed., New York: Verso, 1988. See also Edith Hoshino
238 Political Economy
Altbach, ed., From Feminism to Liberation, Cambridge, MA: Schenkman, 1971, and
Evelyn Reed, Problems of Women's Liberation: A Marxist Approach, New York:
Pathfinder Press, 1971.
10. See Hilde Scott, Does Socialism Liberate Women}, Boston: Beacon Press,
1974.
11. Kate Millett, Sexual Politics, New York: Avon, 1971, and Mary Daly,
Gyn/Ecology: The Metaethics of Radical Feminism, Boston: Beacon Press, 1978.
A retrospective assessment of radical feminism is presented in Alice Echols,
Daring To Be Bad: Radical Feminism in America 1967-1975, Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1989. See also the collection of articles in Anne
Koedt, Ellen Levine, and Anita Rapone, eds., Radical Feminism, New York:
Quadrangle Books, 1973.
12. Juliet Mitchell, Woman's Estate, Baltimore, MD: Penguin, 1975; Zillah R.
Eisenstein, ed., Capitalist Patriarchy and the Case for Socialist Feminism, New
York: Monthly Review Press, 1979; and Nancy Hartsock, Money, Sex and Power:
Toward a Feminist Historical Materialism, New York: Longman, 1983. See also
Linda Jenness, ed., Feminism and Socialism, New York: Pathfinder Press, 1972;
Batya Weinbaum, The Curious Courtship of Women's Liberation and Socialism,
Boston: South End Press, 1978; and Lise Vogel, Woman Questions: Essays for A
Materialist Feminism, New York: Routledge, 1995.
13. See Shulamith Firestone, The Dialectic of Sex: The Case for Feminist Revo-
lution, New York: William Morrow, 1970.
14. See Arlie Hochschild, The Second Shift, New York: Viking, 1989; Juliet B.
Schor, The Overworked American: The Unexpected Decline of Leisure, New York:
Basic Books, 1991; and Lydia Morris, The Workings of the Household, Cambridge:
Polity, 1990.
15. George Gilder, Naked Nomads: Unmarried Men in America, New York:
Quadrangle Books, 1974. See also George Gilder, Men and Marriage, Gretna, LA:
Pelican, 1986.
16. See Eli Sagan, Freud, Women, and Morality, New York: Basic Books, 1988.
17. See Ronald Fletcher, The Abolitionists: The Family and Marriage under
Attack, New York: Routledge, 1988; Ronald Fletcher, The Shaking of the
Foundations: Family and Society, New York: Routledge, 1988; and Ferdinand
Mount, The Subversive Family: An Alternative History of Love and Marriage, e
London: Jonathan Cape, 1982. A historical account of the development of
Conservative opposition to feminism is presented in Michele A. Pujol, Feminism
and Anti-feminism in Early Economic Thought, Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar,
1992. For a critique of the Conservative perspective, see Pamela Johnston Conover
and Virginia Gray, Feminism and the New Right: Conflict Over the American
Family, New York: Praeger, 1983.
18. Conservative critiques of feminism can be found in Nicholas Davidson,
The Failure of Feminism, Buffalo, NY: Prometheus, 1988; Steven Goldberg, The
Inevitability of Patriarchy, New York: William Morrow, 1973; Midge Decter,
The New Chastity and Other Arguments against Women's Liberation, New
York: Coward, McGann and Geoghegan, 1972; Arianna Stassinopoulos, The
Female Woman, New York: Random House, 1973; and Elaine Storkey, What's
Right with Feminism, Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Erdman, 1985.
19. George Gilder, Wealth and Poverty, New York: Basic Books, 1981.
The Political Economy oj Gender 239
20. Phyllis Schlafly, The Power of the Positive Woman, New Rochelle, NY:
Arlington House, 1977.
21. Betty Friedan, The Feminine Mystique, New York: W. W. Norton, 1963. See
also Betty Friedan, The Second Stage, New York: Summit Books, 1981.
22. Carol Gilligan, In A Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women's
Development, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982.
23. Nancy Chodorow, The Reproduction of Mothering: Psychoanalysis and the
Sociology of Gender, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978.
24. See Barbara Bergman, "The Economics of Women's Liberation," Challenge
21, no. 5, (May/June 1973): 11-17.
25. See Isabel V. Sawhill, "The Economics of Discrimination Against Women:
Some New Findings," Journal of Human Resources 8, no. 3 (Summer 1973): 383-96.
26. See Elaine Johansen, Comparable Worth: The Myth and the Movement,
Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1984; Rita Mae Kelly and Jane Bayes, eds.,
Comparable Worth, Pay Equity, and Public Policy, Westport, CT: Greenwood,
1988; Steven L. Wilborn, A Comparable Worth Primer, Lexington, MA: Lexington
Books, 1986; Henry J. Aaron and Cameron M. Lougy, The Comparable Worth
Controversy, Washington, DC: Brookings Institution, 1986; Joan Acker, Doing
Comparable Worth, Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1989; Linda M. Blum,
Between Feminism and Labor: The Significance of the Comparable Worth h
Movement, Berkeley: University of California Press, 1991; Paula England,
Comparable Worth: Theories and Evidence, New York: Aldine de Gruyter, 1992;
and Sara M. Evans and Barbara J. Nelson, Wage Justice: Comparable Worth and
The Paradox of Technical Reform, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1989.
ADDITIONAL READING
Amott, Teresa. Caught in the Crisis: Women and the U.S. Economy Today. New
York: Monthly Review Press, 1993.
Bartlett, Robin L., ed. Introducing Race and Gender into Economics. New York:
Routledge, 1997.
Beneria, Lourdes, and Shelly Feldman, eds. Unequal Burden: Economic Crises,
Persistent Poverty, and Women's Work. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1992.
Birch, Bettina. The Endless Day: The Political Economy of Women and Work. New
York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1982.
Blau, Francine D., and Mariann A. Ferber. The Economics of Women, Men, and
Work, 2nd ed. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1992.
Burggraf, Shirley P. The Feminine Economy and Economic Man. Reading, MA:
Addison-Wesley, 1997.
Chavetz, Janet Saltzman. Gender Equity. Newbury Park, CA: Sage, 1990.
Clayton, Susan D., and Faye J. Crosby. Justice, Gender and Affirmative Action.
Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1992.
Donovan, Josephine. Feminist Theory: The Intellectual Tradition of American
Feminism. New York: Frederick Ungar, 1985.
Eisenstein, Zillah. The Color of Gender: Reimaging Democracy. Berkeley: University
of California Press, 1994.
Farganis, Sondra. Situating Feminism: From Thought to Action. Thousand Oaks,
CA: Sage, 1994.
240 Political Economy
Ferber, Marianne A., and Julie A. Nelson, eds. Beyond Economic Man: Feminist
Theory and Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993.
Ferguson, Kathy. Self, Society and Womankind. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press,
1980.
Folbre, Nancy. Who Pays for the Kids? Gender and the Structures of Constraint.
London: Routledge, 1994.
Fuchs, Victor. Women's Quest for Economic Equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1988.
Goldin, Claudia. Understanding the Gender Gap: An Economic History of
American Women. New York: Oxford University Press, 1990.
Gordon, Linda, ed. Women, the State and Welfare. Madison: University of Wisconsin
Press, 1990.
Humphries, Jane, ed. Gender and Economics. Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar, 1995.
Jacobson, Joyce P. The Economics of Gender. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 1994.
Jenson, Jane, Elizabeth Hagen, and Ceallaigh Reddy. Feminization of the Labor
Force: Paradoxes and Promises. New York: Oxford University Press, 1988.
Kelly, Rita Mae. The Gendered Economy. Newbury Park, CA: Sage Publications,
1991.
Martin, Susan Ehrlich. Doing Justice, Doing Gender. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage
Publications, 1996.
Mutari, Ellen, Heather Boushey, and William Fraher IV. Gender and Political
Economy: Incorporating Diversity into Theory and Policy. Armonk, NY:
M. E. Sharpe, 1997.
Nelson, Julie A. Feminism, Objectivity and Economics. New York: Routledge, 1996.
Okin, Susan Mollar. Justice, Gender, and the Family. New York: Basic Books, 1989.
Peattie, Lisa, and Martin Rein. Women*s Claims: A Study in Political Economy.
New York: Oxford University Press, 1983.
Peterson, Janice, and Doug Brown, eds. The Economic Status of Women under
Capitalism: Institutional Economics and Feminist Theory. Brookfield, VT:
Edward Elgar, 1994.
Phillips, Ann, ed. Feminism and Equality. New York: New York University Press,
1987.
Chapter 13
Culture encompasses the values, beliefs, customs, and habits that guide
human behavior. In the past, traditional divisions within social science
relegated the study of culture to sociology and anthropology, placing it
outside the proper scope of political economy. Furthermore, because
education functions, in part, to transmit culture over time, political econ-
omists also devoted little attention to education. With the exceptions of
school financing and the effect of education on individual earnings, econ-
omists were content to leave the study of society's educational process to
other disciplines.
The problem with this restricted vision is that if education and culture
play major roles in affecting human behavior, and if the economy and gov-
ernment are shaped by individual choices, then political economy is left
with incomplete understandings of the very institutions it claims to analyze.
Recognizing this deficiency, some political economists have recently sought
to include education and culture within their purview to illuminate the
effects of both institutions on the market and government. To examine
these issues, the viewpoints of each of the four ideological perspectives are
presented in this chapter.
242 Political Economy
E d u c a t i o n a l Policy
Despite their advocacy of public funding for education, Classical
Liberals fear that government's monopoly over education results in high
costs, low quality, and indifference toward students and parents. As long as
public education remains monopolistic, administrators and teachers know
that their salaries are not directly affected by the quality of education they
offer or by the number of students they instruct. Conversely, if a student
fails or drops out, the system does not penalize the school or teachers. As
a result, teachers and administrators have little incentive to provide high-
quality education. Public schools may become mere youth repositories
where unmotivated teachers stand guard over bored pupils.
Classical Liberals also claim that problems with public schools reveal a
serious flaw in democracy, which, because it is based on majority rule, may
be insensitive to local or minority interests. In formulating educational pol-
icy, democratic governments typically rely on bureaucracy to formulate a
standardized curriculum, but this centralized process limits the discretion
of local school officials, teachers, and parents. As a result, innovation is sti-
fled and local cultures and values may be suppressed.
In response to these concerns, Classical Liberals propose a method for
providing education to all children without direct government involve-
ment. Government can issue to parents a "voucher" redeemable for edu-
cation at any public or private school. 2 This proposal eliminates
government's monopoly over the provision of education while retaining
public financing. Schools compete with one another, and those schools
attracting more students receive additional government funding. The best
teachers will presumably move to successful schools because, by attracting
more students and redeeming more vouchers, these schools can offer higher
salaries. Conversely, students will shun schools offering inferior education,
and teachers' salaries at those schools will fall accordingly. To ensure main-
tenance of educational standards, vouchers should be redeemable only at
accredited schools.
By removing the financial barrier to attending private schools, the
voucher system permits families of all income levels to choose a school pro-
viding an education best suited to their children's needs. Vouchers eliminate
the penalty currently imposed on parents who choose private education for
their children and are forced to "pay twice"—once for taxes to fund pub-
lic schools and again for tuition at a private school. If public schools face
a large-scale exodus of students, administrators and teachers will presum-
ably reassess their methods and offer a more effective program. Those
244 Political Economy
function to transmit the class status of families from one generation to the
next. To support this argument, Bowles and Gintis offer statistical evidence
that despite a significant trend toward equalization in years of schooling
across social classes, there has been little change in income inequality dur-
ing the past half-century.
The key to the intergenerational transmission of status is the close cor-
respondence between the social relations of the classroom and the social
relations of adult worksites. Like workers, most students are trained to fol-
low rules, to accept authority, and to compete for external rewards such as
grades. However, not all students are trained to respond passively to
authority. The hierarchical division of labor also requires managerial and
creative talent. To meet this need, public schools typically offer different
forms of education to children depending on their class background and
expected adult status. This strategy is feasible because the residential seg-
regation of families according to income means that particular schools tend
to reflect the economic status of the neighborhood in which they are
located. Moreover, the financing of schools by the property tax assures that
affluent areas are able to offer superior education. Finally, schools may use
tracking to provide different educations for students with different demon-
strated abilities, but these abilities are often linked to family status.
Radicals claim that schools in more affluent neighborhoods tend to
stress creativity, independence, achievement, and leadership skills, while
schools in lower-income neighborhoods emphasize conformity and obedi-
ence. This dual educational system reflects parental expectations for their
children. White-collar parents have learned from their own work experi-
ence that leadership skills and innovative thinking are rewarded, whereas
blue-collar parents know that their jobs often require perseverance at rou-
tine tasks and submission to authority. Parents typically want schools to
instill in their children those personality traits that the parents have found
to be important in their own lives.
Besides its role in legitimizing and reproducing hierarchy, education is
functional to capitalism in several other ways. According to Radicals, a
major force behind public education has always been the demands of
employers that children be schooled in both the basic skills required for
productive labor and an ideology supportive of capitalism. Employers want
publicly financed education because the mobility of labor makes it unprof-
itable for individual firms to teach basic skills to workers who are then free
to move to other firms. With public education, taxpayers bear the expense
of much of the training of the labor force, thereby reducing business costs.
Radicals also emphasize the potentially disruptive and even revolution-
ary aspects of education. Schools may fail to reproduce the hierarchical
social relations of capitalism because capitalism itself is internally contra-
dictory. As a system of production, capitalism is characterized by hierarchy
and dominance as owners exercise power over workers for the purpose of
Education and Culture 247
E d u c a t i o n a l Policy
In proposing educational reforms, Radicals acknowledge that the func-
tional role of education in sustaining hierarchy and privilege assures that
most schools in a capitalist society are likely to remain repressive. Yet some
Radicals are sufficiently optimistic to formulate proposals for educational
reform within capitalist society. Education can be liberating if the author-
ity of teachers and curricular requirements are minimized to enable stu-
dents to pursue their own interests, to learn at their own pace, and to
integrate their formal knowledge with practical aspects of their lives.6 In
"free schools," there is little emphasis on grades, routine memorization, or
rule-following. Rather, students acquire a variety of skills, enabling them
to function effectively in many different social roles as they apply their
intelligence and creativity to learning, recreation, and work.
Radicals favor reliance on work-study programs to break down barriers
between knowing and doing. The physical and creative abilities of students
should be stimulated at the same time that intellectual capacities are
expanding. Education should also be a life-long process; adults should con-
tinue to learn and develop, with paid work being merely one outlet for their
productive energies.
Specific Radical proposals include Ivan Illich's idea of "deschooling soci-
ety."7 Illich believes that experts, including educators, scientists, bureau-
crats, and administrators, have gained such total control over social
institutions that most people no longer think or act independently.
Freedom has been suppressed by the very institutions that were designed to
create a rational and stable society. The only solution is to deschool soci-
ety by challenging and ultimately overturning the authority of experts and
the institutions they represent. Illich would have children work at least two
hours a day, with access to factories, offices, laboratories, and farms where
248 Political Economy
they could learn through experience. For Illich, even free schools are too
institutionalized because they continue to rely on teachers and classrooms
and therefore provide only the illusion of freedom. Genuine education can-
not be confined to a particular building with particular authority figures,
but rather must occur within the entire community as an ongoing process
for children and adults alike.
Not all Radicals share Illich's antiauthoritarian perspective.8 Some have
criticized free schools and "schools without walls" as being both naively
Utopian and counterproductive in the sense that they produce not libera-
tion, but maladjustment and confusion as students must inevitably face the
demands of adult work in a capitalist society. Indeed, the free-school move-
ment and other experiments with unstructured education peaked during
the 1970s and have been under considerable attack since then. Radicals
debate among themselves whether the collapse of free schools was due to
inherent internal problems or to the fact that students were simply ill-
prepared for life in capitalist society.
Surprisingly, some Radicals join with Classical Liberals in supporting
educational vouchers.9 In fact, the campaign for school choice has histori-
cal roots in the Black Power movement and alternative schools of the late
1960s. Radicals argue that if children from low-income families received
larger vouchers and financial support for transportation, their mobility
would challenge the monopoly of public schools, giving parents and local
communities greater control over the content of education. Moreover, if
parents and students chose to remain in local schools, the larger vouchers
could fund excellent schools in low-income neighborhoods and the preser-
vation of community values. From this perspective, educational vouchers
could redistribute opportunity and future earnings in favor of children
from low-income families and promote cultural diversity.
beings. Instead, driven by alienation and unmet needs, they opt for a life of
instant gratification through consumption and entertainment. Having
adopted this orientation toward life, they view traditional social structures
such as family and community as obstacles to the free pursuit of pleasure,
resulting in further disintegration of social bonds. In the absence of fulfill-
ing social relations, consumption is indeed the quickest and most direct
form of pleasure. Ironically, this distorted form of human existence con-
forms with the Classical Liberal portrayal of humans as autonomous,
pleasure-seeking creatures. Radicals, however, claim that such behavior is
not intrinsic to human nature, but is instead a response to the isolation and
alienation fostered by capitalism.
One of the hallmarks of capitalist culture is mass conformity, which
Radicals attribute to the need by alienated individuals to latch onto any
cultural expression seeming to offer solidarity with fellow citizens. At the
same time, fads and changing fashion prevail as individuals try to escape
the traditional hierarchy to establish a sense of autonomy and dignity.
Ultimately, though, the novelty and variety offered by capitalism may
prove dangerous to the system. Because profitability thrives on sales gen-
erated by continual changes in culture, people are conditioned to believe
that the past and present are never satisfactory; novelty becomes desired
purely for its own sake. In such a world, the very notion of a stable per-
sonal identity is undermined as continuity and tradition slip from memory.
On this point, Radicals agree with Conservatives; a focus on consumptive
pleasure makes satisfaction elusive. In the unceasing pursuit of pleasure,
individuals neglect social bonds and institutions essential to genuine fulfill-
ment. Moreover, pleasure-seeking individuals will resent the demands for
routinization and delayed gratification placed on them by bosses and other
authority figures. Capitalism therefore creates a culture that ultimately cre-
ates frustration with and even rejection of the system.13
Radicals affirm the worth of cultural expression that contributes to sub-
verting capitalist hierarchy and control. Conversely, cultural expressions
are condemned if they seem to reinforce and perpetuate the privileges of
dominant groups. Some Radicals have proposed that free speech should be
restricted to prevent language deemed offensive to subordinate groups such
as women and minorities.14 Several colleges and universities in the United
States have established sanctions against "hate speech," including possible
expulsion. Radicals have disrupted public lectures by speakers with whom
they disagree and have defaced art that is deemed oppressive. All of these
actions can be explained by the Radical belief in objective standards of
value that supersede individual preferences. Like Conservatives, some
Radicals feel morally obliged to defend the good and suppress the bad. In
practice, however, many Radicals, particularly in the United States, are so
wedded to the liberal principle of tolerance that they condemn cultural
repression of any sort.
Education and Culture 251
E d u c a t i o n a l Policy
The Conservative educational agenda focuses on three issues. First, true
knowledge and absolute values must be protected from the corrosive effects
of individualism, materialism, and the liberal notion that pleasure is the
sole criterion of value. Second, the unequal capacities of students for learn-
ing must be fully acknowledged in structuring the educational system.
Third, control over education must be placed securely in the hands of
252 Political Economy
proper authorities. We shall examine each of these principles and the spe-
cific policies flowing from them.
The drug culture pervading modern societies is, for Conservatives, the logi-
cal culmination of liberal utilitarianism in which pleasure is the sole criterion
of value. Conservatives regard many contemporary intellectuals, writers,
musicians, and artists as members of a "new class" or "adversary culture"
consciously seeking to subvert traditional society. Sociologist Daniel Bell
describes an inherent conflict between a capitalist economy and the culture
it spawns. The market demands workers who are self-disciplined, stable,
and able to delay gratification, while capitalist culture emphasizes hedonism
and rejection of authority.19
Conservatives are not simply cultural snobs who insist on the superior-
ity of classical music, art, and literature. They acknowledge the value of
popular culture if it emerges from traditional communities. For example,
folk music is treated as a genuine expression of rural culture. Quilting and
woodworking are legitimate art forms. Storytelling is crucial in transmit-
ting society's cultural heritage. Conservatives ultimately judge culture by its
contribution to maintaining social order; both high culture and popular
culture are valuable if they serve that task.
Educational Policy
Modern Liberals want education to be both compulsory and compen-
satory. Because formal education is only one component of children's
socialization, providing identical educational experiences to children from
vastly different family backgrounds will not secure genuine equality of
opportunity. The purpose of compensatory education is to provide instruc-
tion designed to overcome the disadvantages facing children from deprived
backgrounds. These disadvantages may include not only low academic
skills, poor health, and inadequate nutrition, but also lack of motivation
Education and Culture 257
due to the absence of role models or prospects for success. Modern Liberals
stress that education cannot bear the entire burden of ending poverty, and
therefore compensatory programs must be accompanied by a broader
attack on the causes of poverty.
With regard to curriculum, Modern Liberals emphasize the importance
of extracurricular activities such as student government and clubs. They
also propose that democratic ideals can be taught by democratizing the
classroom, giving students a greater voice in determining the structure and
content of their curriculum. Modern Liberals were instrumental in intro-
ducing the "open classroom," allowing students to pursue their strongest
interests and to advance at their own pace. 22
Modern Liberals are strongly committed to the public school system and
have been critical of proposals for either a voucher system or tuition tax
credits. 23 Both policies, they claim, would encourage increased racial seg-
regation of students, reduce governmental control over the quality of edu-
cation, and violate the Constitution's separation of church and state. If the
government offered to pay for education at any school selected by the fam-
ily, children of affluent families would flock to suburban and private
schools. In contrast, children of low-income families, unable to afford
transportation, would be forced to attend their neighborhood school, and
inner-city public schools would become the repositories for those unable to
afford an alternative. The best teachers would relocate to the more attrac-
tive suburban and private schools, and the goal of equal education for all
students would be sacrificed.
Modern Liberals also typically oppose merit pay for teachers, citing the
difficulty in measuring teacher productivity. The use of any particular cri-
terion of productivity, such as student scores on standardized tests, might
cause teachers to orient their efforts toward preparing students to perform
well on the tests while neglecting other areas of instruction. Merit pay is
also accused of having a divisive and demoralizing effect on teachers.
Many Modern Liberals have favored busing students to achieve racial bal-
ance throughout a school district.24 They argue that neighborhood schools
cannot possibly provide equal education for all students when neighbor-
hoods are segregated and funding for public schools is dependent on prop-
erty taxes. Also, integrated classrooms expose children to members of other
racial groups, diminishing the likelihood of racial conflict in the future.
Conservative and Classical Liberal critics of busing claim that children
cannot learn effectively in a hostile and foreign environment and that bus-
ing often contributes to increased residential segregation as some parents
choose to move rather than comply with the new regulations. They also
claim busing causes an exodus of students from public schools as parents
enroll their children in private schools. Another concern is the disruption
of neighborhood unity as children are relocated to distant schools. Modern
Liberals acknowledge these concerns and have recently softened their advo-
258 Political Economy
cacy of busing. Even if busing achieves the goal of providing equal educa-
tion for all children, it provides no ultimate solution to poverty and
inequality. Formal education is only one component of the socialization
process leading to acquisition of skills and personality traits essential to
future success. The family and the neighborhood often overshadow the
impact of the school on children's maturation.
Modern Liberals have recently begun to share with Conservatives the
desire to introduce moral education into the public school curriculum.
However, while Conservatives typically link moral education with religious
education, Modern Liberals simply want to provide students with a forum
in which they can clarify their own values through discussion of hypothet-
ical situations. This process of "values clarification" assumes that with
increased awareness developed through classroom discussions, children
will learn the Modern Liberal values of tolerance, sensitivity, honesty, and
respect for the rights of others.
In the face of growing concern about the United States' ability to com-
pete in global markets, Modern Liberals are shifting their focus from the
developmental and egalitarian roles of education to the economic role of
education in enhancing efficiency and growth. To assess the efficiency of
education, Modern Liberal economists rely on cost-benefit analysis to
compare the financial benefits of education with other forms of public
investment. They also compare the financial payback to dollars spent on
different departments within universities and on university education as
opposed to vocational education. Faced with intensifying competition from
abroad, government should reallocate public funding to those forms of
education yielding the largest gains in future productivity. However, some
Modern Liberals warn that by focusing on measurable changes in individ-
ual earnings and GDP, cost-benefit analysis of education can easily over-
look the intangible benefits of social equality, political stability, and
personal growth.
NOTES
1. The Classical Liberal perspective on the economic benefits of education is
presented in Fritz Machlup, Education and Economic Growth, Lincoln: University
of Nebraska Press, 1970; Richard B. McKenzie, The Political Economy of the
Educational Process, Boston: Martinus Nijhoff, 1979; and Martin O'Doe,noghue,
Economic Dimensions in Education, Chicago: Aldine-Atherton, 1971.
2. The original proposal for school choice appeared in Milton Friedman, "The
Role oi Government in Education," in Robert A. Solo, ed., Economics and the
Public Interest, New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1955. For additional
260 Political Economy
details on proposed educational voucher systems and school choice, see Myron
Lieberman, Privatization and Educational Choice, New York: St. Martin's, 1989;
David R. Henderson, The Case For School Choice, Stanford: Hoover Institution,
1993; and John E. Chubb and Terry M. Moe, Politics, Markets and America's
Schools, Washington, DC: The Brookings Institution, 1990.
3. See John Stuart Mill, On Liberty, New York: Liberal Arts Press, 1956.
4. Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis, Schooling in Capitalist America, New
York: Basic Books, 1976.
5. Radical interpretations and critiques of education are presented in Martin
Carnoy, Schooling in a Corporate Society, New York: McKay, 1972; Madan Sarup,
Marxism and Education, Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1978; and Kenneth A.
Strike, Liberal Justice and the Marxist Critique of Education, New York:
Routledge, 1989.
6. See Allen Graubard, Free the Children: Radical Reforms and the Free School
Movement, New York: Random House, 1972. See also Peter Marin, Vincent
Stanley, and Kathryn Marin, The Limits of Schooling, Englewood Cliffs, NJ:
Prentice-Hall, 1975.
7. Ivan Illich, Deschooling Society, New York: Harper 6c Row, 1971.
8. See Robin Barrow, Radical Education: A Critique of Freeschooling and
Deschooling, New York: John Wiley 6c Sons, 1978. See also Herbert Gintis, "Towards
a Political Economy of Education: A Radical Critique of Ivan Illich's Deschooling
Society," Harvard Educational Review 42, no. 1 (February 1972): 70-96.
9. See Herbert Gintis, "The Political Economy of School Choice," Teachers
College Record, 96, no. 3 (Spring 1995): 492-511; and Christopher Jencks,
Rethinking Social Policy: Race, Poverty and the Underclass, Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1992.
10. Important works on culture by members of the Frankfurt school include
Walter Benjamin, Illumination, New York: Harcourt Brace &; World, 1968;
Theodor W. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1983;
and Herbert Marcuse, The Aesthetic Dimension: Toward a Critique of Marxist
Aesthetics, Boston: Beacon Press, 1978. For a collection of writings from the
Frankfurt school, see Andrew Arato and Eixe Gebhardt, eds., The Essential
Frankfurt School Reader, New York: Continuum, 1982. For a review and assess-
ment of the Frankfurt school, see Ronald J. Schindler, The Frankfurt School
Critique of Capitalist Culture, Aldershot: Avebury Publishers, 1996.
11. Herbert Marcuse, One Dimensional Man, Boston: Beacon Press, 1964. See
also Robert Paul Wolff, Barrington Moore, Jr., and Herbert Marcuse, A Critique of
Pure Tolerance, Boston: Beacon Press, 1969.
12. For greater detail on the Radical analysis of culture, see Cary Nelson and
Lawrence Grossberg, eds., Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture, Urbana, IL:
University of Illinois Press, 1988. See also Louis Dupre, Marx's Social Critique of
Culture, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1983.
13. This argument is elaborated in Christopher Lasch, The Culture of
Narcissism: American Life in an Age of Diminishing Expectations, New York:
W. W. Norton, 1978.
14. See Catherine MacKinnon, Only Words, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1993, and Cass R. Sunstein, Democracy and the Problem of Free
Speech, New York: The Free Press, 1993.
Education and Culture 261
15. Allan Bloom, The Closing of the American Mind, New York: Simon &
Schuster, 1987.
16. See Arthur R. Jensen, Educability and Group Difference, New York: Harper
6c Row, 1973.
17. Jose Ortega y Gasset, The Revolt of the Masses [1932], Notre Dame, IN:
University of Notre Dame Press, 1985. For more recent analyses of the phenome-
non of mass society, see William Kornhauser, The Politics of Mass Society, Glencoe,
IL: Free Press, 1959; Salvador Giner, Mass Society, London: Martin Robertson,
1976; and Peter Davison, Rolf Meyersohn, and Edward Shils, eds., Culture and
Mass Culture, Teaneck, NJ: Somerset House, 1978.
18. Conservative critiques of contemporary U.S. culture are presented in William
J. Bennett, The De-valuing of America: The Fight for Our Culture and Our
Children, New York: Summit Books, 1992; Robert Hughes, The Culture of
Complaint: The Fraying of America, New York: Oxford University Press, 1993;
and Robert H. Bork, Slouching Towards Gomorrah: Modern Liberalism and
American Decline, New York: Regan Books, 1996.
19. See Daniel Bell, The Cultural Contradictions of Capitalism, rev. ed., New
York: Basic Books, 1996. Bell's thesis that capitalism tends to generate opposition
from intellectuals was also an important theme in Joseph Schumpeter, Capitalism,
Socialism, and Democracy, New York: Harper &c Row, 1950.
20. For an assessment of Dewey's impact on American education, see Reginald
D. Archambault, ed., Dewey on Education, New York: Random House, 1966.
21. Jean Piaget, The Essential Piaget, edited by H. E. Gruber and J. J. Voneche,
New York: Basic Books, 1977; Lawrence Kohlberg, Essays on Moral Development,
San Francisco: Harper &c Row, 1981; and Abraham H. Maslow, Motivation and
Personality, 3rd ed., New York: Harper & Row, 1987.
22. See Terrence E. Deal and Robert R. Nolan, eds., Alternative Schools:
Ideologies, Realities, Guidelines, Chicago: Nelson-Hall, 1978.
23. The Modern Liberal opposition to school choice is presented in Bruce Fuller
and Richard F. Elmore, Who Chooses? Who Loses?, New York: Teachers College
Press, 1995; Peter W. Cookson, Jr., School Choice: The Struggle for the Soul of
American Education, New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994; Jeffrey R. Henig,
Rethinking School Choice: Limits of the Market Metaphor, Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1994; and Kevin B. Smith and Kenneth J. Meier, The Case Against
School Choice: Politics, Markets, and Fools, Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1995.
24. On the issue of school busing, see Gary Orfield, Must We Bus?: Segregated
Schools and National Policy, Washington, DC: Brookings Institution, 1978;
Emmett H. Buell, Jr., School Desegregation and Defended Neighborhoods,
Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, 1982; and Edward J. Hayes, Busing and
Desegregation: The Real Truth, Springfield, IL: Charles C. Thomas, 1981.
ADDITIONAL READING
Aronowitz, Stanley, and Henry Giroux. Education Under Siege: The Conservative,
Liberal and Radical Debate over Schooling. South Hadley, MA: Bergin &c
Garvey, 1985.
Bernier, Norman R., and Jack E. Williams. Beyond Beliefs: Ideological Foundations
of American Education. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1973.
262 Political Economy
Carnoy, Martin, and Henry M. Levin. Schooling and Work in the Democratic State.
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1985.
DeYoung, Alan J. Economics and American Education. New York: Longman,
1989.
Edel, Abraham. Interpreting Education: Science, Ideology, and Value. New Bruns-
wick, NJ: Transaction Books, 1985.
Feinberg, Walter, and Jonas S. Soltis. School and Society. New York: Teachers
College Press, 1985.
Freire, Paulo. The Politics of Education. South Hadley, MA: Bergin & Garvey, 1985.
Giroux, Henry. Ideology, Culture, and the Process of Schooling. Philadelphia:
Temple University Press, 1981.
Gutman, Amy. Democratic Education. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,
1987.
Karabel, Jerome, and A. H. Halsey, eds. Power and Ideology in Education. New
York: Oxford University Press, 1977.
Katz, Michael B. Reconstructing American Education. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1987.
Persell, Caroline H. Education and Inequality. New York: Free Press, 1977.
Shaw, G. K., ed. Economics, Culture and Education. Brookfield, VT: Edward
Elgar, 1991.
Sowell, Thomas. Inside American Education. New York: Free Press, 1993.
Spring, Joel. American Education: An Introduction to Social and Political Aspects.
New York: Longman, 1982.
Webb, Rodman B. Schooling and Society, 2nd ed. New York: Macmillan, 1989.
Chapter 14
current trends are changed dramatically. This dire prediction has been
challenged by other researchers, and political economists continue to
debate the causes of and appropriate policies for coping with environ-
mental degradation.
and the corporation could "bribe" the citizen for the use of the lake as a
waste disposal site. Again, Coase argues, the optimal level of pollution
would result since the corporation would pay for the right to pollute until
the cost to the firm of additional pollution equals the additional benefit.
Thus, the assignment of private property rights over common resources
creates a market for the right to pollute, resulting in an efficient allocation
of resources without the need for environmental regulations.
Environmental Policy
Classical Liberals defend the ability of the market to protect the envi-
ronment. 3 If a particular resource is being depleted, its price will rise not
only in response to its current scarcity, but also to the anticipated higher
costs of extracting that resource in the future. This "scarcity pricing"
causes consumers and producers to search for cheaper alternatives and pro-
vides strong incentives to develop new technology for producing synthetic
266 Political Economy
costly to control would presumably bid highest for licenses, forcing other
firms to eliminate lower-cost forms of pollution. After licenses are auctioned
by government, firms could resell them, creating a market for the right to
pollute and enabling firms to adjust waste disposal in response to changing
patterns of technology, resource availability, or consumer demand.
Classical Liberals have generally been critical of the notion of market
failures, but they buttress their faith in the market by appealing to the con-
cept of "government failure."5 Bureaucrats, they claim, lack detailed infor-
mation with which to formulate efficient policies. Moreover, without
personal responsibility for the consequences of their policies, bureaucrats
lack incentive to formulate optimal policies. Bureaucrats favor uniform
pollution standards applicable to all industries because of the relative ease
of enforcement. However, economic efficiency is more likely to be attained
through different standards for different industries, a goal that can be
achieved by auctioning pollution licenses.
Government is also susceptible to manipulation by special-interest
groups. The firms most affected by environmental regulations have a
strong incentive to influence legislation. Certain industries may even be
successful in capturing control of a governmental agency by contributing
money, lobbying, and promising lucrative jobs to bureaucrats when they
leave government. Classical Liberals believe that government is unduly
influenced by the lobbying of environmental organizations such as the
Sierra Club and the Wilderness Society. Environmentalists, they claim, seek
to increase donations to their organizations by frightening the public with
exaggerated warnings of impending environmental disaster. When envi-
ronmental lists are successful in using government to coerce everyone to
comply with their values, they cripple the economy with restrictive regula-
tions and create a disadvantage in international competition.
Another Classical Liberal strategy for reducing environmental regula-
tions is based on the Fifth Amendment to the U.S. Constitution, which
states: "nor shall private property be taken for public use without just com-
pensation." This "takings clause" is interpreted to mean that any govern-
ment regulation reducing the value or profitability of property requires
payment to the owner for financial losses.6 Classical Liberals assume that
forcing government to pay for losses imposed by every regulation would
result in considerably less regulation. For example, zoning laws, laws to
protect endangered species, and laws to protect wetlands would become
prohibitively expensive for government. A related strategy for minimizing
regulation comes from Classical Liberals calling for "wise use" of the envi-
ronment. 7 They propose that every regulation should be examined to deter-
mine whether its benefits exceed its costs. For example, the government
would have to demonstrate that the dollar value of a protected species
exceeds the dollar value of the resources that could be removed from a nat-
ural area. Any regulation failing to meet this standard would be scrapped.
268 Political Economy
The term "deep ecology" was coined in 1972 by Swedish ecologist Arne
Naess, who views nature as a highly complex system of diverse yet inter-
dependent species and elements.10 Nature seeks equilibrium between all
subsystems, so any disruptive force in one area may have extensive and
unforeseen repercussions. Deep ecologists seek to grasp the functioning of
270 Political Economy
pretation is valid, the effort to completely dominate nature was not con-
doned by Marx and is another symptom of alienation in capitalist society.
E n v i r o n m e n t a l Policy
Marxists and deep ecologists agree on the necessity of transcending cap-
italism, but they offer quite different visions of socialism. Marxists empha-
size socialism's capacity for attainment of collective goals through
conscious planning of society's production. Unlike the market, a planned
economy can recognize noncommodity preferences such as the desire for a
clean environment and can translate such preferences into social policy.
With production guided by planning rather than profitability, resources can
be allocated to protect and restore the environment. By acting collectively,
citizens empower themselves to shape their society and their natural envi-
ronment in a manner most conducive to human development.
Collective planning could even extend across national borders. To pro-
tect countries from the pressures of global competition, international gov-
erning bodies might establish environmental standards to which all
countries must comply. Within each country, environmentalism might
require stringent controls on population growth, immigration, and con-
sumption. Even at the local level, the imperative of environmental integrity
may lead governments to narrowly circumscribe the freedom of individu-
als to use and dispose of resources.14
Deep ecologists, in contrast, reject a planned economy. They envision a
future society consisting of decentralized and largely self-sufficient com-
munities free from the coercive pressures of market and state. These com-
munities might consist of fewer than ten thousand people with communal
ownership of land and highly egalitarian and participatory social rela-
tions. The experience of living in close-knit communities should steer indi-
viduals away from material consumption, reducing pressures on the
natural environment. 15
Marxists point to the similarities between deep ecology and Conserv-
atism. Both are wary of technology and materialism, both appeal to objec-
tive values found in a spiritualized nature, and both envision a society
composed of relatively autonomous communities. Marxists are concerned
that small communities offer limited opportunities for personal develop-
ment, mobility, and creativity. Moreover, independent communities might
compete against one another, reviving the market conditions of capitalism.
Finally, Marxists criticize deep ecologists for diverting attention from the
class origins of environmental problems. According to Marxists, the ulti-
mate cause of pollution and exhaustion of resources is not the flawed
values of mankind but the division of society into owning and working
classes, with individual survival dependent on producing commodities for
sale in the market.
272 Political Economy
E n v i r o n m e n t a l Policy
In their optimistic moments, Conservatives retain a confidence that
nature, including the human species, is ultimately a self-equilibrating sys-
tem. As environmental degradation worsens, humans can be expected to
respond with new values upholding moral obligations to adopt ecologically
sound lifestyles. Signs of such a shift are apparent in growing public sup-
port for recycling and controls on pollution.
However, Conservatives are typically less optimistic and, when proposing
environmental policy, they often favor political rather than economic solu-
tions to pollution.19 Economic analysis focuses only on the preferences of
individuals and ignores society's interest in a healthy and sustainable natural
environment. Only the political process can promote such collective interests.
In advocating political action, Conservatives envision a different type of
politics from that of today's Western democracies.20 To remedy the short-
comings of democracy, political authority must be insulated from the pres-
sures of interest groups, and positions of leadership must be filled by
charismatic, wise, and virtuous persons. With political authority in the hands
of natural leaders, government can maintain a well-ordered society, reducing
alienation, the desire for consumption, and pressures on the environment.
In addition to reforming the political process, Conservatives would pro-
tect the environment by improving the socialization process shaping indi-
vidual desires. This strategy requires that schools, families, neighborhoods,
and churches be restored to their former roles as sources of authority and
meaning in the lives of individuals. A strong sense of identity and belong-
ing will dramatically reduce consumption and status-seeking. The pursuit
of wealth will become less important than the self-esteem and respect of
others gained through performing duties attached to one's social role. With
artificial desires for consumption suppressed, humans can reestablish a har-
monious relationship with nature.
E n v i r o n m e n t a l Policy
Modern Liberals view government intervention as essential to environ-
mental protection. Citizens and firms have little incentive to make private
sacrifices to control pollution because their individual actions have little
impact on the level of pollution. Government, on the other hand, can
gather information, assess damages, collect fees or taxes, and monitor the
enforcement of environmental laws more effectively and efficiently than
private citizens.
A. C. Pigou, who originally developed the theory of externalities, pro-
posed that government should respond to pollution with a tax on the pol-
luting firm equal to the value of environmental damage. The revenue from
the tax could be used to repair the damage or to subsidize citizens harmed
by pollution. However, this strategy assumes that government has perfect
information about the extent of pollution and its source. In the real world
of imperfect information, Modern Liberals advocate the establishment of
legal pollution standards to which industry must conform. They worry that
proposals to sell pollution licenses will give pollution the same ethical sta-
tus as hunting, fishing, driving a car, or getting married. To maintain a
strong social stigma against polluting, they want to keep it illegal beyond
specified levels.24 Modern Liberals also defend standards as essential to
maintaining equity; all regions or neighborhoods must meet the same stan-
dards, so pollution cannot be concentrated in a few sites.
Modern Liberals insist that environmental protection can be compat-
ible with economic growth and rising standards of living. This optimism
is based partially on the Keynesian view that additional spending—in
this case, on pollution control—serves to stimulate the economy by
creating greater demand for goods, more jobs, and higher incomes.
Unemployed workers might be hired to construct pollution-control
devices or repair environmental damage. Growth and environmental
protection are also compatible because countries pioneering in pollution
Pollution and the Environment 277
NOTES
1. Donella H. Meadows, Dennis L. Meadows, Jorgen Randers, and William W.
Behrens, The Limits to Growth, New York: University Books, 1972. For a rebuttal
to the pessimistic predictions of Meadows et al., see Edward Pestel, Beyond the
Limits to Growth, New York: University Books, 1989. The sequel to Limits to
Growth is Donella H. Meadows, Dennis L. Meadows, and Jorgen Randers, Beyond
the Limits: Confronting Global Collapse; Envisioning A Sustainable Future, Post
Mills, Vermont: Chelsea Green Publishing Company, 1992.
2. Ronald H. Coase, "The Problem of Social Cost," Journal of Law and
Economics 3 (October 1960): 1-44. For more accessible accounts, see William F.
Baxter, People or Penguins: The Case for Optimal Pollution, New York: Columbia
University Press, 1974, and Wilfred Beckerman, Pricing For Pollution, 2nd ed.,
London: Institute for Economic Affairs, 1990.
3. See Doug Bandow, ed., Protecting The Environment: A Free Market Strategy,
Washington: Heritage Foundation, 1986; David Glasner, Politics, Prices and
Petroleum: The Political Economy of Energy, Cambridge, MA: Ballinger, 1985;
Pollution and the Environment 279
ADDITIONAL READING
Ash worth, William. The Economy of Nature: Rethinking the Connections Between
Ecology and Economics. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1995.
Baumol, William J., and Wallace E. Oates. The Theory of Environmental Policy,
2nd ed. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988.
Pollution and the Environment 281
International Trade
and Development
include tariffs on goods imported from LDCs. The use of fiscal or mone-
tary policy to stimulate demand may inadvertently trigger inflation, result-
ing in higher prices for exports to LDCs. Finally, governments responding
to hunger and misery in LDCs may send aid in the form of capital or food.
According to Classical Liberals, this aid has the same effect on the global
economy as welfare programs have on domestic growth. Redistribution
from rich to poor undermines incentives and causes inefficiency by moving
resources away from their most productive use. Foreign aid effectively
slows the engines of the global economy and makes LDCs dependent on
industrialized nations.
D e v e l o p m e n t Policy
Classical Liberal policies on trade and development have been articu-
lated by neoclassical economists such as Jacob Viner (1892-1970), Harry
Johnson (1923-1977), Gottfried Haberler, and Sir Peter Bauer.2 From their
perspective, the same economic principles apply to both developed and
developing countries, so free trade and competitive markets are the optimal
strategies for raising standards of living anywhere in the world.
Development proceeds as the quantity and quality of economic resources
increase, and the market, with its strong incentives for providing produc-
tive resources, is the best mechanism to mobilize a nation for economic
growth. Policymakers should oppose social, cultural, and political forces
impeding the market's operation.
Classical Liberals are so confident of the benefits of free trade that they
urge countries to drop all trade barriers even if trading partners continue
to practice protection. Free trade permits a country to obtain cheaper
goods; the fact that other countries have restrictions on trade does not alter
the positive effects of lower-priced imports in restraining inflation, stimu-
lating innovation, and enabling citizens to enjoy higher standards of living.
Since all trade is voluntary, a country cannot possibly harm itself by
expanding its opportunities to buy from foreigners.
Classical Liberals acknowledge that the transformation from a tradi-
tional, agrarian society to a market economy is inevitably a wrenching
experience, but the trauma can be eased by free trade with the industrial-
ized nations. Foreign trade serves to strengthen the merchant and manu-
facturing classes within LDCs, breaking the grip of traditional elites on the
economy. Market forces also shift peasants out of subsistence farming and
into factories where, through enhanced productivity, their standard of liv-
ing can rise. Agricultural production should be performed by more effi-
cient, large-scale farmers. Finally, untapped natural resources will be
transformed into productive inputs once the incentive of profit and the
availability of capital make their extraction both attractive and feasible.
Classical Liberals are so certain of the ability of free markets to spur
International Trade and Development 287
profitmaking and individual initiative, would set the stage for a dynamic
and efficient system for lifting society out of poverty.
This version of the Radical theory of development is remarkably similar
to the Classical Liberal view and hence is also called "diffusion theory." The
relationship between the industrialized nations and the LDCs is claimed to
be mutually beneficial. Capitalism spreads outward from the industrialized
countries to the LDCs, eventually incorporating the latter into a global eco-
nomic system promoting the development of all countries. The industrial-
ized nations can export surplus goods and import cheap raw materials to
maintain profits, while the LDCs gain both markets for their raw materials
and the capital essential for modernization. Increased exposure to capital-
ism will eventually ensure worldwide industrial development.
Marx did observe that certain countries were more resistant than others
to capitalist penetration. In particular, he attributed the lack of industrial-
ization in Asia to the need for large-scale irrigation projects requiring
extensive political authority to mobilize resources. The power of the state
suppressed the entrepreneurial and commercial activity essential to the for-
mation of capitalism. Marx labeled such systems "oriental despotism" or
the "Asiatic mode of production."
The view that capitalism is ultimately beneficial to LDCs does not deny
that competitive international markets often wreak havoc on traditional
economies and social structures, but this disruption is necessary for the
transition to a modern capitalist society. Standards of living in the LDCs
will rise as industrial development and trade with other countries create
employment opportunities.
Dependency theory. In Marx's later writings, he argued that the con-
tinued accumulation of capital in the developed countries requires an
underdeveloped "periphery" of nations to serve as markets for excess
goods, sources of cheap resources, and profitable investment outlets.
Therefore, capitalism in one region requires the presence of a precapitalist
region, giving the developed countries a strong interest in keeping parts of
the world dependent and backward. Marx illustrated this point with the
British tactic of smashing handlooms and cutting off the thumbs of weavers
in India to assure that country's continued reliance on British textiles.
Historical roots of dependency theory are also found in the writings of
Lenin.7 Seeking to justify revolution, Lenin argued that Russia was being
damaged by its subordinate status among the European nations. He
claimed that western European firms had entered Russia in search of new
markets for their products and cheap labor. Whereas Marx originally pre-
dicted revolutions in the most industrialized capitalist nations, Lenin
argued that exploitation of foreign labor enabled capitalist firms to pay
higher wages in Europe and North America. These high wages served to
quell revolutionary discontent, turning North American and European
workers into an "aristocracy of labor" whose privileged position explained
290 Political Economy
These findings challenge both the Classical Liberal and Radical views that
capitalism results in a diffusion of development throughout the world.
D e v e l o p m e n t Policy
Radical policies for promoting economic development reflect the schism
between diffusion theory and dependency theory. Diffusion theory views
capitalism as a progressive force in global development, so the business class
in LDCs should be supported in its efforts to overthrow feudal oligarchies.
Insurgent movements by peasants and workers are not encouraged because
LDCs will not be ready for socialist revolution until capitalism has per-
formed its historical task of accumulating capital and preparing people for
industrial society. An illustration of policies emanating from diffusion
theory is presented by the former Soviet Union's initial reluctance to support
Fidel Castro's efforts to overthrow the Batista regime in Cuba. Soviet policy
also approved of multinational corporations for performing the necessary
task of injecting capital and technology into the LDCs.
In sharp contrast, dependency theorists encourage LDCs to minimize con-
tact with the mature capitalist countries to develop internal economic struc-
tures consistent with their specific needs. Dependency theorists favor national
autonomy or "collective self-reliance" among groups of LDCs to foster eco-
nomic development and national pride. This focus on psychological liberation
reflects a belief that LDCs have suffered from cultural as well as economic
imperialism. Exposure to Western lifestyles and consumption patterns has
alienated people in LDCs from their own cultures and has created a deep
sense of inferiority. Restoring national pride will release the productive ener-
gies of people who are presently crippled by a sense of powerlessness.
Other policy proposals from dependency theorists include a reorienta-
tion of agriculture away from production for export and toward meeting
the needs of local citizens, the use of labor-intensive or small-scale technol-
ogy to increase employment, public investment in infrastructure, and the
substitution of domestically manufactured goods for foreign imports.
During the 1980s, a coalition of Radicals and Modern Liberals pro-
posed a dramatic realignment of international relations called the New
International Economic Order (NIEO). 12 This strategy emerged from the
perception that domestic development policies are futile without major
revisions of the international political economy. The NIEO would entail
greater political control over multinational corporations, an enlarged role
for LDCs in international institutions such as the World Bank and the
International Monetary Fund, easier credit terms for LDCs, reduced trade
barriers for exports, increased foreign aid and technical assistance, and
taxes on the extraction of nonrenewable resources.
Radicals exhibit ambiguity in their position on free trade. They view it as
potentially damaging to LDCs, but they also condemn many protectionist
292 Political Economy
D e v e l o p m e n t Policy
Conservatives remained largely isolationist until the 1950s, opposing
nearly all commitments to and interventions in foreign countries. They con-
sidered foreign aid to developing countries as counterproductive because,
by increasing food supplies and promoting public health, it could lead to
explosive population growth, which might impede development. More
generally, foreign aid would cause a flood of rising expectations, resulting
in social disorder.
During the 1950s, however, Conservatives began to reassess their isola-
tionist policies in light of the growing threat of communist expansion.
Indeed, Conservatives became leading proponents of internationalism, call-
ing on the United States to assert its strength as leader of the "Free World."
According to Conservatives, global peace and security require that one
country gain "hegemony" with sufficient power to establish and enforce
the rules of international relations. 16 Without hegemony, the struggle
among nations for dominance leads to international tensions and conflict.
Despite this new "internationalist" orientation, Conservatives reject shared
international governance through representative organizations such as the
United Nations because LDCs outnumber the industrialized countries and
could therefore effectively wield power.
Conservatives want the United States to ally itself with those foreign gov-
ernments protecting private property and promoting trade with the West.17
These governments need not be democratic because the LDCs need strong
governmental authority to control ethnic and religious strife, to protect
International Trade and Development 295
domestic and foreign investment from excessive risk, and to actively resist
insurgent political movements. In determining which governments deserve
U.S. support, Conservatives distinguish between "authoritarian" and "totali-
tarian" regimes.18 Totalitarian governments pursue egalitarian or socialist
ends, but authoritarian governments promote favorable investment climates
and capitalist development while restricting free elections and democratic par-
ticipation. Conservatives oppose totalitarian regimes but tolerate the abuses
of civil liberties in authoritarian countries, hoping that economic development
will eventually create sufficient political stability to permit free elections.
The Conservative attitude toward foreign aid has changed along with
the transition from isolationism to internationalism during the 1950s. To
halt the spread of communism, Conservatives have supported military and
economic aid to vulnerable countries. However, as the threat of commu-
nism recedes, Conservatives are retreating to their former isolationism,
opposing virtually all government involvement with foreign countries.
Instead, they encourage churches, civic groups, and other private organiza-
tions to provide humanitarian aid to the citizens of LDCs.
Conservatives condemn free trade for subjecting countries to competi-
tive pressures over which they have little control. In the nineteenth century,
the German economist Friedrich List argued that less industrialized coun-
tries should place tariffs on goods from more advanced countries to give
"infant industries" time to mature and eventually become competitive in
international markets. Even when Conservatives acknowledge the potential
economic gains from free trade, they claim that the preservation of tradi-
tional culture, standards of living, and national security may require pro-
tectionist policies. Conservatives note that both the United States and
Germany practiced extensive protectionism during the late nineteenth and
early twentieth centuries while rapidly surpassing England, the country
most devoted to free trade at the time. 19
To summarize, Conservatives welcome trade when it contributes to the
vitality of both trading partners and does not undermine traditional cul-
ture, but they favor protectionist policies to prevent standards of living in
the industrialized countries from being undermined by competition with
low-wage manufacturers in the LDCs.
the LDCs to end hunger and misery that drive people to political eaxtremes.
During the 1950s and 1960s, economists such as Gunnar Myrdal
(1898-1987), Ragnar Nurkse (1907-1959), Raul Prebisch (1901-1985),
Paul Rosenstein-Rodan (1902-1985), William Arthur Lewis (1911-1991),
and Albert O. Hirschman constructed the new field of development eco-
nomics. These theorists sought to develop a synthesis of Classical Liberal
and Radical views. Like Classical Liberals, Modern Liberals accept the
need to mobilize resources and instill Western values of individual initiative
and achievement. However, Modern Liberals also validate the Radical view
that imperialism has been a major factor in blocking development, and
they propose that governments in both the industrialized countries and the
LDCs should pursue active policies to correct past injustices and hasten the
development process.
Modern Liberals attribute underdevelopment to the following causes:
D e v e l o p m e n t Policy
During the past half-century, Modern Liberals have formulated vari-
ous strategies for government to supplement the market in promoting
economic development. Although early European industrialization was
based on exports, economist Ragnar Nurkse claimed that export-led
growth was inappropriate for LDCs because of competition from more
advanced industries in the West. LDCs should instead pursue a policy of
import-substitution by promoting the domestic manufacture of formerly
imported goods. 21
To break the cycle of poverty, Paul Rosenstein-Rodan advocated a "big
push" with widespread investment by government and development of an
infrastructure of schools, highways, and communications systems.22 This
initiative is designed to take advantage of the positive and reinforcing
298 Political Economy
NOTES
1. See Anne O. Krueger, Economic Policies at Cross-Purposes: The United
States and Developing Countries, Washington, DC: Brookings Institution, 1993;
Ryan C. Amacher, Gottfried Haberler, and Thomas D. Willett, eds., Challenges to
a Liberal Economic Order, Washington, DC: American Enterprise Institute, 1979;
and Deepak Lai, Against Dirigisme: The Case for Unshackling Economic Markets,
San Francisco, ICS Press, 1994.
2. For a collection of essays representing the Classical Liberal perspective on eco-
nomic development, see David Wall, ed., Chicago Essays in Economic Development,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1972.
3. See Deepak Lai, The Poverty of Development Economics, Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1985; Peter T. Bauer, Dissent on Development, London:
Weidenfeld &c Nicolson, 1971; and Peter T. Bauer, Reality and Rhetoric: Studies in
the Economics of Development, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1984.
For a critique of Classical Liberal development theory, see John Toye, Dilemmas of
Development: Reflections on the Counter-revolution in Development Theory and
Policy, Oxford: Blackwell, 1987.
4. A Classical Liberal response to concern about plant closings and job loss due
to international competition is presented in Richard B. McKenzie, Fugitive
Industry: The Economics and Politics of Deindustrialization, Cambridge, MA:
Ballinger, 1984.
5. See Meivyn B. Krauss, How Nations Grow Rich: The Case for Free Trade,
New York: Oxford University Press, 1997; Anne O. Krueger, The Political
Economy of Protection, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996; and Charles
K. Rowley, Willem Thorbecke, and Richard E. Wagner, Trade Protection in the
United States, Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar, 1995.
6. Friedrich A. Hayek, The Road to Serfdom, London: Routledge &c Kegan
Paul, 1979.
302 Political Economy
ADDITIONAL READING
Spero, Joan E. The Politics of International Economic Relations, 4th ed. New York:
St. Martin's, 1990.
Strange, Susan. States and Markets: An Introduction to International Political
Economy, 2nd. ed. New York: Pinter Publishers, 1994.
Thurow, Lester. Head to Head: The Coming Battle Among Japan, Europe and
America. New York: William Morrow, 1992.
This page intentionally left blank
Chapter 16
Political economy does not treat of the whole of man's nature as modified by the
social state, nor the whole conduct of man in society. It is concerned with him solely
as a being who desires to possess wealth, and who is capable of judging of the com-
parative efficiency of means for obtaining that end.2
Having made this concession, Mill defended continued reliance on the con-
cept of homo economicus "not (because) any political economist was ever
so absurd as to suppose that mankind are really thus constituted; but
because this is the mode in which science must necessarily proceed." 3 This
statement is revealing, for it demonstrates that a commitment to the scien-
tific method has dictated the scope and content of political economy by
effectively precluding consideration of those dimensions of life unsuitable
for quantification and measurement.
If ideology is defined as reliance on values to interpret reality, then
despite its aspirations to scientific status, political economy has been ideo-
logical from the beginning. Early political economists were clearly engaged
in efforts to promote the interests of an emerging business class in its strug-
gle against government control and remnants of feudal authority. Most
modern economists might agree that every political economist prior to
310 Political Economy
1870, or perhaps even 1930, was an ideologue. Yet even modern econo-
mists cannot avoid ideology. Theorizing necessarily entails abstraction, and
science offers no certain guidelines as to which aspects of reality are most
relevant. Facts have significance in proportion to their usefulness in achiev-
ing human goals, and those goals are based on values. Therefore, the deci-
sion to focus on particular aspects of reality for the purpose of constructing
theories is a value judgment. Even in empirical research, values influence
which aspects of reality will be observed and what will be considered a
"fact." In the social sciences, researchers deal with issues about which all
humans have value-laden preconceptions, and these commitments cannot
be kept separate from scientific inquiry.
Criticism of the scientific method in political economy has a long his-
tory. Nineteenth-century French and German writers claimed that British
political economy was based on faulty assumptions and fallacious reason-
ing. In fact, the field of sociology was established, in large part, as a reac-
tion to political economy by French and German theorists such as Emile
Durkheim (1858-1917), Max Weber (1864-1920), and Ferdinand Tonnies
(1855-1936). Many, if not most, U.S. economists in the nineteenth century
favored the empiricist and historical method developed in Germany over
the rationalist and deductive reasoning of English economists. Even in
England, prominent economists such as Philip Wicksteed (1844-1927), F.
Y. Edgeworth (1845-1926), and John A. Hobson (1858-1940) argued that
economics was too abstract and narrowly defined to provide practical
guidance in public policymaking. The most renowned English economist of
the late nineteenth century, Alfred Marshall, was praised by A. C. Pigou for
realizing that:
ECONOMICS AS IDEOLOGY
Despite the concerted efforts of several generations of economists to cre-
ate a pure science of economics, values remain implicit in economic theory.
(Note: the terms "economics," "economist," and "economic theory" shall
hereafter refer to the neoclassical variants of these terms.) Examples of
these values include the following:
312 Political Economy
and sociocultural systems, and much of the precision and logic of econom-
ics would be lost. For example, economist Tibor Scitovsky demonstrated
that if preferences are dependent on the social environment, individuals in
situation A might prefer situation B, but if situation B were attained, the
different environment might cause the same individuals to prefer situation
A.8 Economists could no longer claim that markets generate a unique and
stable equilibrium reflecting individual preferences, resource availability,
and technology.
4. All preferences for private goods or services are equally valid but
deserve fulfillment only to the extent that they are backed by money. The
equal validity of preferences assumes that individuals are the best judges of
their own interests. This claim appeals to our sense of human dignity by
recognizing the capacity of individuals to direct their own lives. However,
it is ideological because it cannot be tested or even potentially falsified
using standard scientific methods. Any action can be interpreted as serving
a person's best interests because no method exists for assessing private
interests. Moreover, this assumption blinds economists to both the private
and social processes through which preferences arise. Individuals often
struggle with their own preferences, experiencing conflict between imme-
diate desires and prior commitments to other persons or moral principles.
In addition to their preferences, individuals have "metapreferences" guid-
ing them in choosing which of their desires to express and which to sup-
press. These metapreferences reflect the type of person the individual
aspires to become. Treating all preferences as equally valid is thus unscien-
tific because it fails to grasp essential aspects of preference formation. The
claim that preferences deserve fulfillment only to the extent that they are
backed by money is a corollary of economists' definition of rights as
including only property rights and those civil rights making no demands on
economic resources. This claim is unscientific because the definition of
rights is a value judgment.
or more parts of the economy, restoring competition to only one part may
decrease efficiency. For example, if a labor union faces a monopolistic
employer, then breaking up the labor union to improve competition may
reduce efficiency. This "theory of the second best" makes any policy rec-
ommendations concerning market structure more difficult to justify.9
When you dig deep down, economists are scared to death of being sociologists. The
one great thing we have going for us is the premise that individuals act rationally
in trying to satisfy their preferences.13
We do not possess much certain knowledge about the economic world and . . . our
best chance of gaining more is to try in all sorts of directions and by all sorts of
means. This will not be furthered by strident commitments of faith.14
CONCLUSION
Each of the four ideological perspectives examined in this book may be
faulted for neglecting one or more of the three governance structures.
Classical Liberalism, in its quest to shatter the organic unity of medieval
society, elevated the market at the expense of government and community.
This ideology proposed that the market would assure rational individual
behavior by making material self-interest consistent with the well-being of
society. Government would be reduced to the role of referee, protecting
property rights and enforcing contracts. What Classical Liberals fail to per-
ceive is that strong governments and vibrant communities are essential to
maintain smoothly operating markets. Without regulations and ethical
norms, self-interested behavior destroys markets. When government is
weak, mafias and militias arise as citizens attempt to secure through col-
lective action what they cannot obtain individually. When community is
weak, an amoral society breeds conflict, crime, and litigation, making busi-
ness activities increasingly costly and difficult.
Radicals and Conservatives emphasize the role of community, but in the
past, they viewed markets as divisive and disruptive to both community
and government. Since World War II, Conservatives have moved closer to
Science, Ideology, and Political Economy 323
NOTES
1. See Daniel Bell, The End of Ideology, Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1960; Chaim
Waxman, The End of Ideology Debate, New York: Funk & Wagnalls, 1968; and
Job L. Dittberner, The End of Ideology and American Social Thought, Ann Arbor,
MI: UMI Institute Press, 1979.
2. John Stuart Mill, Essays On Some Unsettled Questions of Political Economy
(1844), New York: Augustus M. Kelley, 1968, p. 137.
3. Ibid, p. 139.
4. A. C. Pigou, ed., Memorials of Alfred Marshall (1925), New York: Augustus
M. Kelley, 1966.
5. See Lionel Robbins, An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic
Science (1932), New York: New York University Press, 1984.
6. Anne O. Krueger, et al.y "Report of the Commission on Graduate Education
in Economics," journal of Economic Literature, 29:3 (1991), 1044-45. For addi-
tional assessment of graduate economic education in the United States, see Arjo
Klamer and David Colander, The Making of An Economist, Boulder, CO:
Westview Publishing, 1990.
7. Ronald H. Coase, The Firm, the Market, and the Law, Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1988, p. 185.
8. Tibor Scitovsky, "A Note on Welfare Propositions in Economics," Review of
Economic Studies, 9 (1941), 77-88.
9. Richard G. Lipsey and Kelvin Lancaster, "The General Theory of the Second
Best," Review of Economic Studies, 24:1 (October, 1956), pp. 11-32.
10. Milton Friedman, Essays in Positive Economics, Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1953.
11. Prominent works in experimental economics include Vernon L. Smith, ed.,
Experimental Economics, Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar, 1990, and Douglas D.
Davis, Experimental Economics, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993.
12. James Buchanan, "Economics and Its Scientific Neighbors," in Buchanan,
What Should Economists Do?, Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1979.
13. Charles Schultze, quoted in Robert Kuttner, Everything for Sale: The Virtues
and Limits of Markets, New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1997, p. 4 1 .
326 Political Economy
14. Frank Hahn, quoted in Warren J. Samuels, "The Case for Methodological
Pluralism," in Andrea Salanti and Ernesto Screpanti, eds., Pluralism in Economics,
Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar, 1997.
15. William Leach, Land of Desire: Merchants, Power, and the Rise of a New
American Culture, New York: Pantheon Books, 1993; Andrew B. Schmookler, The
Illusion of Choice: How the Market Economy Shapes Our Destiny, Ithaca, NY:
State University of New York Press, 1993; Andrew B. Schmookler, Fools Gold: The
Fate of Values in a World of Goods, New York: HarperCollins, 1993; and Barry
Schwartz, The Costs of Living: How Market Freedom Erodes the Best Things in
Life, New York: W W. Norton, 1994.
16. Michael Sandel, Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, New York: Cambridge
University Press, 1982. Other prominent works in communitarianism include
William A. Galston, Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal
State, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991; and Robert Bellah, et al.,
Habits of the Heart: Individualism and Commitment in American Life, Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1985. For comprehensive assessments of communi-
tarianism see Robert Booth Fowler, The Dance with Community: The e
Contemporary Debate in American Political Thought, Lawrence: University Press
of Kansas, 1991; Amitai Etzioni, The Spirit of Community: Rights, Responsibilities,
and the Communitarian Agenda, New York: Crown, 1991; Stephen Mulhall and
Adam Swift, Liberals and Communitarians, Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 1996;
Derek L. Phillips, Looking Backward: A Critical Appraisal of Communitarian
Thought, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993; and Cornelius Delaney,
ed., The Liberalism-Communitarianism Debate, Totowa, NJ: Rowman &
Littlefield, 1993.
17. See Sara M. Evans and Harry C. Boyte, Free Spaces: The Sources of
Democratic Change in America, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992, and
Robert Putnam, Making Democracy Work: Civic Traditions in Modern Italy,
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993.
ADDITIONAL READING
Audretsch, David B. The Market and the State. New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf,
1989.
Boswell, Jonathan. Community and the Economy: The Theory of Public Co-oper-
ation. New York: Routledge, 1990.
Bowles, Samuel, and Herbert Gintis. Democracy and Capitalism. New York: Basic
Books, 1986.
Daley, Herman E., and John B. Cobb, Jr. For the Common Good: Redirecting the
Economy Toward Community, the Environment, and A Sustainable Future.
Boston: Beacon Press, 1989.
Davidson, Greg, and Paul Davidson. Economics for A Civilized Society. Armonk,
NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1996.
Foldvary, Fred E., ed. Beyond Neoclassical Economics. Brookfield, VT: Edward
Elgar, 1996.
Friedland, Roger, and A. F. Robertson, eds. Beyond the Marketplace: Rethinking
Economy and Society. Hawthorne, NY: Aldine de Gruyter, 1990.
Haslett, D. W. Capitalism With Morality. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994.
Science, Ideology, and Political Economy 327
Aaron, Henry J., and Cameron M. Lougy. The Comparable Worth Controversy.
Washington, DC: Brookings Institution, 1986.
Acker, Joan. Doing Comparable Worth. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1989.
Ackerman, Frank. Reaganomics: Rhetoric vs. Reality. Boston: South End Press, 1982.
Adelman, Irma, and Cynthia Taft Morris. Economic Growth and Social Equity in
Developing Countries. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1973.
Adorno, Theodor W. Aesthetic Theory. Boston: Routledge &: Kegan Paul, 1983.
Agarwala, Prakash N. The New International Economic Order: An Overview.
New York: Pergamon, 1983.
Akerlof, G. A., and W. T. Dickens. "The Economic Consequences of Cognitive
Dissonance," American Economic Review 72, no. 3 (June 1982): 307-19.
Alchian, Armen, and Harold Demsetz. "Production, Information Costs, and Economic
Organization," American Economic Review 62 (December 1972): 777-95.
Alesina, Alberto, and Nouriel Roubini. Political Cycles and the Macroeconomy.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1998.
Altbach, Edith Hoshina, ed. From Feminism to Liberation. Cambridge, MA:
Schenkman, 1971.
Amacher, Ryan C , Gottfried Haberler, and Thomas D. Willett, eds. Challenges to
a Liberal Economic Order. Washington, DC: American Enterprise Institute,
1979.
Amin, Samir. Accumulation on a World Scale. New York: Monthly Review Press,
1974.
330 Bibliography y
Anderson, Terry L., and Donald R. Leal. Enviro-Capitalists: Doing Good While
Doing Well. Savage, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, 1997.
. Free Market Environmentalism. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1991.
Arato, Andrew, and Eike Gebhardt, eds. The Essential Frankfurt School Reader.
New York: Continuum, 1982.
Archambault, Reginald D., ed. Dewey on Education. New York: Random House,
1966.
Archer, Robin. Economic Democracy: The Politics of Feasible Socialism. New
York: Oxford University Press, 1995.
Arestis, Philip, and Victoria Chick. Recent Developments In Post-Keynesian
Economics. Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar, 1992.
Arestis, Philip, and Thanes Skouras, eds. Post-Keynesian Economic Theory.
Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1985.
Aronowitz, Stanley. False Promises: The Shaping of American Working-Class
Consciousness. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1973.
Arren, Judith, and Christopher Jencks. "Educational Vouchers: A Proposal for
Diversity and Choice," in George R. LaNoue, ed. Educational Vouchers:
Concepts and Controversies. New York: Teachers College Press, 1972.
Arrow, Kenneth J. The Limits of Organization. New York: W W. Norton, 1974.
. Some Models of Racial Discrimination in the Labor Market. Santa Monica,
CA: Rand Corporation, 1971.
Atkinson, Anthony B., Lee Rainwater, and Timothy M. Smeeding. Income Distrib-
ution in OECD Countries. Paris: OECD, 1995.
Bachrach, Peter, and Aryeh Botwinick. Power and Empowerment: A Radical Theory
of Participatory Democracy. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1992.
Baer, M. Delal, and Sidney Weintraub, eds. The NAFTA Debate. Boulder, CO:
Lynne Rienner, 1994.
Bailey, Elizabeth E., and Janet Rothenberg Pack, eds. The Political Economy of
Privatization and Deregulation. Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar, 1995.
Baily, Martin, Gary Burtless, and Robert Litan. Growth with Equity. Washington,
DC: Brookings Institution, 1993.
Bandow, Doug, ed. Protecting The Environment: A Free Market Strategy. Washing-
ton, DC: Heritage Foundation, 1986.
Banfield, Edward C. The Moral Basis of a Backward Society. Glencoe, IL: The Free
Press, 1958.
. The Unheavenly City: The Nature and Future of Our Urban Crisis. Boston:
Little, Brown, 1968.
Banner, Lois W. Women in Modern America: A Brief History, 3rd ed. Fort Worth:
Harcourt Brace College Publishers, 1995.
Baran, Paul. The Political Economy of Growth. New York: Monthly Review
Press, 1967.
Baran, Paul, and Paul Sweezy. Monopoly Capital: An Essay on the American
Economic and Social Order. New York: Monthly Review Press, 1966.
Barber, Benjamin R. Strong Democracy. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984.
Barbier, Edward, ed. Economics and Ecology: New Frontiers and Sustainable
Development. New York: Chapman & Hall, 1993.
Barrett, Michele. Women's Oppression Today: Problems in Marxist Feminist
Analysis. London: Verso, 1980.
Bibliography 331 1
Bramwell, Anna. The Fading of the Greens: The Decline of Environmental Politics
in the West. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994.
Brand, Donald R. Corporatism and the Rule of Law: A Study of the National
Recovery Administration. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1988.
Braun, Denny. The Rich Get Richer: The Rise of Income Inequality in the United
States and the World. Chicago: Nelson-Hall, 1991.
Braverman, Harry. Labor and Monopoly Capital: The Degradation of Work in the
Twentieth Century. New York: Monthly Review Press, 1974.
Brennen, H. G., and James M. Buchanan. Monopoly in Money and Inflation: The
Case of a Constitution to Discipline Government. London: Institute of
Economic Affairs, 1981.
Brewer, Anthony. Marxist Theories of Imperialism: A Critical Survey, 2nd ed. New
York: Routledge, 1992.
Brittan, Samuel. The Economic Consequences of Democracy. London: Temple
Smith, 1977.
Buchanan, James M. Constitutional Economics. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell, 1991.
. Freedom in Constitutional Contract: Perspectives of a Political Economics.
College Station, TX: Texas A&M University Press, 1977.
. What Should Economists Do? Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Press, 1979.
Buchanan, James M., Charles K. Rowley, and Robert D. Tollison, eds. Deficits.
New York: Basil Blackwell, 1987.
Buchanan, James M., and Robert D. Tollison. Theory of Public Choice: Political
Applications of Economics. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1972.
Buchanan, James M., Robert D. Tollison, and Gordon Tullock, eds. Toward a
Theory of the Rent-seeking Society. College Station, TX: Texas A&cM
University Press, 1980.
Buchanan, James M., and Gordon Tullock. Calculus of Consent: The Logical
Foundations of Constitutional Democracy. Ann Arbor: University of
Michigan Press, 1965.
Buchanan, James M., and Richard M. Wagner. Democracy in Deficit: The Political
Legacy of Lord Keynes. New York: Academic Press, 1977.
Buell, Emmett H., Jr. School Desegregation and Defended Neighborhoods.
Lexington, MA: Lexington Books, 1982.
Buhle, Mari Jo, and Paul Buhle. The Concise History of Woman Suffrage. Urbana,
IL: University of Illinois Press, 1978.
Burawoy, Michael. Manufacturing Consent: Changes in the Labor Process under
Monopoly Capitalism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979.
Burggraf, Shirley P. The Feminine Economy and Economic Man. Reading, MA:
Addison-Wesley, 1997.
Burr, Richard E. Are Comparable Worth Systems Truly Comparable? St. Louis:
Center for the Study of American Business, Washington University, 1986.
Butler, Stuart. Enterprise Zones: Greenlining the Inner Cities. New York: Universe
Books, 1981.
Butler, Stuart, and Anna Kondratas. Out of the Poverty Trap: A Conservative
Strategy for Welfare Reform. New York: Free Press, 1987.
Cagan, Phillip, ed. The Economy in Deficit. Washington, DC: American Enterprise
Institute, 1985.
Callenbach, Ernest. Ecotopia. Berkeley, CA: Banyan Tree Press, 1975.
334 Bibliography y
Campen, James T. Benefit, Cost, and Beyond: The Political Economy of Benefit-Cost
Analysis. Cambridge, MA: Ballinger, 1986.
Canto, Victor A., Marc A. Miles, and Arthur B. Laffer. Foundations of Supply-side
Economics: Theory and Evidence. New York: Academic Press, 1983.
Capra, Frit j of. The Turning Point. London: Flamingo, 1985.
Card, David, and Alan B. Krueger. Myth and Measurement: The New Economics
of the Minimum Wage. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1995.
Carnoy, Martin. Schooling in a Corporate Society. New York: McKay, 1972.
Carnoy, Martin, and Derek Shearer. Economic Democracy: The Challenge of the
I980's. White Plains, NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1980.
Castells, Manuel. The Economic Crisis and American Society. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1980.
Chase, Allan. The Legacy of Malthus: The Social Costs of the New Scientific
Racism. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1977.
Chodorow, Nancy. The Reproduction of Mothering: Psychoanalysis and the
Sociology of Gender. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978.
Chubb, John E., and Terry M. Moe. Politics, Markets and America's Schools.
Washington, DC: The Brookings Institution, 1990.
Clark, John Bates. The Distribution of Wealth. New York: Macmillan, 1899.
Cline, William R. Policy Alternatives for a New International Economic Order: An
Economic Analysis. New York: Praeger, 1979.
Coase, Ronald H. The Firm, the Market, and the Law. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1988.
. "The Nature of the Firm," Economica 4 (November 1937): 386-405.
. "The Problem of Social Cost," Journal of Law and Economics 3 (October
I960): 1-44.
Colander, David C , ed. Neoclassical Political Economy: The Analysis of Rent-seek-
ing and DUP Activities. Cambridge, MA: Ballinger, 1984.
Commoner, Barry. The Politics of Energy. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1979.
Connolly, William, ed. Legitimacy and the State. New York: New York University
Press, 1984.
Conover, Pamela Johnston, and Virginia Gray. Feminism and the New Right:
Conflict Over the American Family. New York: Praeger, 1983.
Cookson, Peter W, Jr. School Choice: The Struggle for the Soul of American
Education. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994.
Copp, David, Jean Hampton, and John Roemer, eds. The Idea of Democracy.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1993.
Could, Carol. Rethinking Democracy: Freedom and Social Cooperation in Politics,
Economics and Society. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1988.
Cowen, Tyler, ed. The Theory of Market Failure. Fairfax, VA: George Mason
University Press, 1988.
Crane, Edward H., and David Boaz. An American Vision: Policies for the '90's.
Washington, DC: Cato Institute, 1988.
Crouch, Colin, ed. State and Economy in Contemporary Capitalism. New York: St.
Martin's, 1979.
Crozier, Michael, Samuel P. Huntington, and Joji Watanuki, eds. The Crisis of
Democracy. New York: New York University Press, 1975.
Bibliography 335
Evans, Sara M., and Harry C. Boyte. Free Spaces: The Sources of Democratic
Change in America. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1992.
Firestone, Shulamith. The Dialectic of Sex: The Case for Feminist Revolution. New
York: William Morrow, 1970.
Fletcher, Ronald. The Abolitionists: The Family and Marriage Under Attack. New
York: Routledge, 1988.
. The Shaking of the Foundations: Family and Society. New York: Routledge,
1988.
Foldvary, Fred. Public Goods and Private Communities: The Market Provision of
Social Services. Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar, 1994.
Fowler, Robert Booth. The Dance with Community: The Contemporary Debate in
American Political Thought. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1991.
Frank, Andre Gunder. Capitalism and Underdevelopment in Latin America. New
York: Monthly Review Press, 1969.
. Crisis in the Third World. New York: Holmes 6c Meier, 1981.
Frank, Andre Gunder and Barry K. Gills, eds. The World System. New York:
Routledge, 1993.
Frank, Robert H. and Philip J. Cook. The Winner-take-all Society. New York: Free
Press, 1995.
Frankel, S. H. The Economic Impact on Underdeveloped Societies. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell, 1953.
Fraser, Steven, ed. The Bell Curve Wars: Race, Intelligence, and the Future of
America. New York: Basic Books, 1995.
Freeman, Richard B., and James L. Medoff. What Do Unions Do? New York: Basic
Books, 1988.
Freud, Sigmund. Civilization and Its Discontents, translated by James Strachey.
New York: W. W. Norton, 1961.
Friedan, Betty. The Feminine Mystique. New York: W. W. Norton 6c Co., 1963.
. The Second Stage. New York: Summit Books, 1981.
Friedman, Georges. Anatomy of Work. Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1961.
Friedman, Jeffrey, ed. The Rational Choice Controversy. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press, 1996.
Friedman, Milton. Essays in Positive Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1953.
. "The Role of Government in Education," in Robert A. Solo, ed. Economics
and the Public Interest. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press, 1955.
Friedman, Milton, and Anna J. Schwartz. A Monetary History of the United States
1867-1960. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1963.
Fuller, Bruce, and Richard F. Elmore. Who Chooses? Who Loses? New York:
Teachers College Press, 1995.
Galambos, Louis, and Joseph Pratt. The Rise of the Corporate Commonwealth.
New York: Basic Books, 1989.
Galbraith, John Kenneth. Economics and the Public Purpose. Boston: Houghton
Mifflin, 1973.
. The New Industrial State. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1967.
Galston, William A. Liberal Purposes: Goods, Virtues, and Diversity in the Liberal
State. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1991.
338 Bibliography y
Gray, H. Peter. Free Trade or Protection?: A Pragmatic Analysis. New York: St.
Martin's, 1985.
Gray, John. Beyond The New Right. New York: Routledge, 1993.
Green, Donald P., and Ian Shapiro. Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory. New
Haven: Yale University Press, 1994.
Green, Philip. Retrieving Democracy: In Search of Civic Equality. Totowa, NJ:
Rowman &c Allanheld, 1985.
Green berg, Edward. Workplace Democracy: The Political Effect of Participation.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1987.
Grinspun, Ricardo, and Maxwell A. Cameron, eds. The Political Economy of
North American Free Trade. New York: St. Martin's, 1993.
Gross, Bertram. Friendly Fascism: The New Face of Power in America. New York:
M. Evans, 1980.
Grundmann, Reiner. Marxism and Ecology. New York: Oxford University Press,
1991.
Gutman, Amy. Liberal Equality. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1980.
Habermas, Jurgen. Legitimation Crisis. Boston: Beacon Press, 1975.
Hall, Thomas E., and J. David Ferguson. The Great Depression. Ann Arbor:
University of Michigan Press, 1998.
Harris, Nigel. Competition and the Corporate Society. London: Methuon, 1972.
Harrison, Bennett, and Barry Bluestone. The Great U-Turn: Corporate Restructuring
and the Polarizing of America. New York: Basic Books, 1988.
Hartman, Heidi, ed. Comparable Worth. Washington, DC: National Academy
Press, 1985.
Hartsock, Nancy. Money, Sex and Power: Toward a Feminist Historical Materialism.
New York: Longman, 1983.
Hayek, Friedrich A. The Constitution of Liberty. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1960.
. Denationalization of Money. London: Institute of Economic Affairs, 1976.
. The Mirage of Social Justice. Vol. 2 of Law, Legislation, and Liberty.
London: Routledge 6c Kegan Paul, 1982.
. The Road to Serfdom. London: Routledge 6c Kegan Paul, 1979.
. Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics. New York: Simon &C
Schuster, 1967.
. Unemployment and Monetary Policy: Government as Generator of the
"Business Cycle." Washington, DC: Cato Institute, 1979.
Hayes, Edward J. Busing and Desegregation: The Real Truth. Springfield, IL:
Charles C. Thomas, 1981.
Heilbroner, Robert. 21st Century Capitalism. New York: W. W. Norton, 1993.
Heilbroner, Robert L. An Inquiry into the Human Prospect. New York: W. W.
Norton, 1980.
Heilbroner, Robert L., and Peter Bernstein. The Debt and the Deficit: False Alarms,
Real Possibilities. New York: W. W. Norton, 1989.
Henderson, David R. The Case For School Choice. Stanford: Hoover Institution,
1993.
Henig, Jeffrey R. Rethinking School Choice: Limits of the Market Metaphor.
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994.
Henry, William A., III. In Defense of Elitism. New York: Doubleday, 1994.
340 Bibliography y
Jevons, W. Stanley. The Theory of Political Economy, 2nd ed. London: University
Press, 1879.
Johansen, Elaine. Comparable Worth: The Myth and the Movement. Boulder, CO:
Westview Press, 1984.
Johnson, Chalmers, ed. The Industrial Policy Debate. San Francisco: Institute for
Contemporary Studies Press, 1984.
Jouvenel, Bertrand de. The Ethics of Redistribution (1951). Indianapolis: Liberty y
Press, 1990.
Kalecki, Michal. "Political Aspects of Full Employment," Political Quarterly 14,
no. 4 (1943): 322-30.
Kaus, Mickey. The End of Equality. New York: Basic Books, 1995.
Kelly, Rita Mae, and Jane Bayes, eds. Comparable Worth, Pay Equity, and Public
Policy. Westport, CT: Greenwood, 1988.
Kelman, Steven J. What Price Incentives?: Economists and the Environment.
Boston: Auburn House, 1981.
Kelso, Louis O., and Patricia Hetter Kelso. Democracy and Economic Power:
Extending the ESOP Revolution. Cambridge, MA: Ballinger, 1986.
Kemp, Jack. An American Renaissance: A Strategy for the 80s. New York: Harper
&C Row, 1979.
Keohane, Robert O. After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World
Political Economy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1984.
Keynes, John Maynard. The General Theory of Employment, Interest, and Money.
New York: Harcourt, Brace 6c World, 1964.
. "National Self-sufficiency," The Yale Review 22, no. 4 (June 1933):
769-75.
Kinchloe, Joe L., Shirley R. Steinberg, and Aaron D. Gresson III. Measured Lies:
The Bell Curve Examined. New York: St. Martin's Press, 1996.
Kirkpatrick, Jeane J. Dictatorships and Double Standards. New York: Simon 6c
Schuster, 1982.
. Legitimacy and Force. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Books, 1988.
Klamer, Arjo, and David Colander. The Making of An Economist. Boulder, CO:
Westview Publishing, 1990.
Koedt, Anne, Ellen Levine, and Anita Rapone, eds. Radical Feminism. New York:
Quadrangle Books, 1973.
Kohlberg, Lawrence. Essays on Moral Development. San Francisco: Harper 6c
Row, 1981.
Kolko, Gabriel. The Triumph of Conservatism: A Re-interpretation of American
History, 1900-1916. New York: Free Press, 1963.
Kornhauser, William. The Politics of Mass Society. Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1959.
Kotz, David, Terence McDonough, and Michael Reich, eds. Social Structures of
Accumulation: The Political Economy of Growth and Crisis. Cambridge,
UK: Cambridge University Press, 1994.
Krauss, Melvyn B. How Nations Grow Rich: The Case for Free Trade. New York:
Oxford University Press, 1997.
Krueger, Anne O. Economic Policies at Cross-Purposes: The United States and
Developing Countries. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution, 1993.
. The Political Economy of Trade Protection. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1996.
342 Bibliography y
Loury, Glenn C. "The Moral Quandary of the Black Community," Public Interest
79 (Spring 1985): 9-22.
Lovelock, James, Gaia. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979.
Lowi, Theodore. The End of Liberalism: The Second Republic of the U.S., 2nd ed.
New York: W. W. Norton, 1979.
Lustig, R. Jeffrey. Corporate Liberalism: The Origins of Modern American Political
Theory 1880-1920. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1982.
Macesich, George. The Politics of Monetarism: Its Historical and Institutional
Development. Totowa, NJ: Rowman Sc Allanheld, 1984.
Machlup, Fritz. Education and Economic Growth. Lincoln, NE: University of
Nebraska Press, 1970.
MacKinnon, Catherine. Only Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press,
1993.
Macpherson, C. B. The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism. Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1962.
Magaziner, Ira C , and Robert B. Reich. Minding America's Business: The Decline and
Rise of the American Economy. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1982.
Mahler, Vincent A. Dependency Approaches to International Political Economy.
New York: Columbia University Press, 1980.
Mandeiker, Daniel R. Environment and Equity: A Regulatory Challenge. New
York: McGraw-Hill, 1981.
Mansbridge, Jane J. Beyond Adversarial Democracy. New York: Basic Books, 1980.
Marable, Manning. Beyond Black and White. New York: Verso, 1995.
. How Capitalism Underdeveloped Black America. Boston: South End Press,
1983.
Marcuse, Herbert. The Aesthetic Dimension: Toward a Critique of Marxist
Aesthetics. Boston: Beacon Press, 1978.
. Eros and Civilization. Boston: Beacon Press, 1966.
. One Dimensional Man. Boston: Beacon Press, 1964.
Marglin, Stephen. "What Do Bosses Do: The Origins and Functions of Hierarchy
in Capitalist Production," Review of Radical Political Economics 6 (Spring
1974): 60-112.
Marglin, Stephen, and Julie Schor, eds. The Golden Age of Capitalism: Reinterpreting
the Postwar Experience. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990.
Marin, Peter, Vincent Stanley, and Kathryn Marin. The Limits of Schooling.
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1975.
Marshall, Ray. "The Economics oi Racial Discrimination: A Survey," Journal of
Economic Literature 12, no. 3 (September 1974): 849-71.
. Unheard Voices: Labor and Economic Policy in a Competitive World. New
York: Basic Books, 1987.
Marx, Karl. Capital, Vol. 3. New York: International Publishers, 1961.
Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels. The German Ideology. New York: International
Publishers, 1947.
Maslow, Abraham H. Motivation and Personality, 3rd ed. New York: Harper 6c
Row, 1987.
Mason, Ronald M. Participatory and Workplace Democracy: A Theoretical
Development in Critique of Liberalism. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois
University Press, 1982.
344 Bibliography
Phillips, Kevin. The Politics of Rich and Poor: Wealth and the American Electorate
in the Reagan Aftermath. New York: HarperCollins, 1990.
Piaget, Jean. The Essential Piaget, edited by H. E. Gruber and J. J. Voneche. New
York: Basic Books, 1977.
Pigou, A. C , ed. Memorials of Alfred Marshall (1925). New York: Augustus M.
Kelley, 1966.
Pinkerton, James P. What Comes Next: The End of Big Government—and The
New Paradigm Ahead. New York: Hyperion, 1995.
Piore, Michael J., ed. Inflation and Unemployment: Institutionalist and Structuralist
Views. White Plains, NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1979.
Pirages, Dennis C , ed. Building Sustainable Societies: A Blueprint for a Post-
Industrial World. Armonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1996.
, ed. The Sustainable Society. New York: Praeger, 1977.
Piven, Francis Fox, and Richard Cloward. Regulating the Poor. New York:
Pantheon, 1971.
Podhoretz, Norman. The Present Danger. New York: Simon 6c Schuster, 1980.
Polychroniou, Chronis. Marxist Perspectives on Imperialism. New York: Praeger,
1991.
Posner, Richard A. The Economics of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press, 1984.
. Overcoming Law. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1995.
Poulantzas, Nicos. Political Power and Social Classes. London: New Left Books,
1975.
Prestowitz, Clyde V, Jr. Trading Places. New York: Basic Books, 1988.
Pujol, Michele A. Feminism and Anti-feminism in Early Economic Thought.
Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar, 1992.
Putnam, Carleton. Race and Reason. Washington, DC: Public Affairs Press, 1961.
Putnam, Robert. Making Democracy Work: Civic Traditions in Modern Italy.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1993.
Putterman, Louis, ed. The Economic Nature of the Firm: A Reader. New York:
Cambridge University Press, 1986.
Reed, Evelyn. Problems of Women's Liberation: A Marxist Approach. New York:
Pathfinder Press, 1971.
Reich, Michael. Racial Inequality: A Political Economic Analysis. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1981.
Reich, Robert B. The Next American Frontier. New York: Times Books, 1983.
. The Resurgent Liberal. New York: Times Books, 1989.
. Tales of a New America. New York: Times Books, 1987.
. The Work of Nations: Preparing Ourselves for 21st Century Capitalism.
New York: Vintage Books, 1992.
Remick, Helen, ed. Comparable Worth and Wage Discrimination. Philadelphia:
Temple University Press, 1984.
Riggs, A. R., and Tom Vaik, eds. Beyond NAFTA: An Economic, Political and Soci-
ological Perspective. Vancouver: The Frazier Institute, 1993.
Roback, Jennifer. A Matter of Choice: A Critique of Comparable Worth by a
Skeptical Feminist. New York: Priority Press, 1986.
Robbins, Lionel. An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science
(1932). New York: New York University Press, 1984.
348 Bibliography
Sjostedt, Gunnar, and Bengt Sundelius, eds. Free Trade-Managed Trade?: Perspectives
on a Realistic International Trade Order. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1986.
Sklar, Holly. Trilateralism: The Trilateral Commission and Elite Planning for World
Management. Boston: South End Press, 1980.
Sklar, Martin J. The Corporate Reconstruction of American Capitalism. New York:
Cambridge University Press, 1988.
Smith, Adam. The Wealth of Nations. London: Dent, 1910.
Smith, Kevin B., and Kenneth J. Meier. The Case Against School Choice. Armonk,
NY: M. E. Sharpe, 1995.
Smith, Vernon L., ed. Experimental Economics. Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar, 1990.
Sobel, Lester A., ed. Quotas and Affirmative Action. New York: Facts on File, 1980.
Sowell, Thomas. The Economics and Politics of Race. New York: William Morrow,
1983.
. Ethnic America: A History. New York: Basic Books, 1981.
. Markets and Minorities. New York: Basic Books, 1981.
. Migrations and Cultures: A World View. New York: Basic Books, 1996.
. Race and Cultures: A World View. New York: Basic Books, 1994.
. Race and Economics. New York: David McKay, 1975.
Stabile, Donald. Prophets of Order: Class, Technocracy, and Socialism in America.
Boston: South End Press, 1985.
Stassinopoulos, Arianna. The Female Woman. New York: Random House, 1973.
Steele, G. R. Monetarism and the Demise of Keynesian Economics. New York: St.
Martin's Press, 1989.
Stein, Jerome. Monetarist, Keynesian and New Classical Economics. Oxford: Basil
Blackwell, 1982.
Stigler, George J. "The Theory of Economic Regulation," Bell Journal of Economics
& Management Science 2, no. 1 (Spring 1971): 3-21.
Storkey, Elaine. What's Right with Feminism. Grand Rapids, MI: William B.
Erdman's, 1985.
Strike, Kenneth A. Liberal Justice and the Marxist Critique of Education. New
York: Routledge, 1989.
Sunstein, Cass R. Democracy and the Problem of Free Speech. New York: The Free
Press, 1993.
Tabb, William. The Political Economy of the Black Ghetto. New York: W. W.
Norton, 1970.
Talmon, Jacob. The Origins of Totalitarian Democracy. New York: Praeger, 1960.
Tawney, R. H. Equality. London: George Allen and Unwin, 1931.
Taylor, Frederick W. The Principles of Scientific Management [1911]. New York:
W.W. Norton, 1967.
Taylor, Joan Kennedy. Women's Issues: Feminism, Classical Liberalism, and the
Future. Stanford, CA: Hoover Institution, 1993.
Tetreault, Mary Ann, and Charles Frederic Abel. Dependency Theory and the
Return of High Politics. Westport, CT: Greenwood, 1986.
Thompson, E. P. The Making of the English Working Class. New York: Pantheon,
1963.
Thurow, Lester. The Future Of Capitalism: How Today's Economic Forces Shape
Tomorrow's World. New York: W. Morrow 6c Co., 1996.
Bibliography 351
Weisberg, Barry. Beyond Repair: The Ecology of Capitalism. Boston: Beacon Press,
1971.
Weitzman, Martin L. The Share Economy: Conquering Stagflation. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1984.
White, Joseph, and Aaron Wildavsky. The Deficit and the Public Interest. Berkeley,
CA: University of California Press, 1989.
White, Lawrence H. Competition and Currency. New York: New York University
Press, 1989.
Whitfield, Dexter. The Welfare State: Privatization, Deregulation, Commercialization
of Public Services. Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1992.
Wilborn, Steven L. A Comparable Worth Primer. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books,
1986.
Wildavsky, Aaron. The Politics of the Budgetary Process, 4th ed. Boston: Little,
Brown, 1984.
Will, George. Statecraft As Soulcraft. New York: Simon 6c Schuster, 1983.
Willett, Thomas D., ed. Political Business Cycles: The Political Economy of Money,
Inflation, and Unemployment. Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1988.
Williams, Eric. Capitalism and Slavery. New York: Putnam, 1966.
Williams, Walter. The State Against Blacks. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1982.
Williamson, Oliver E., "The Economics of Organizations: The Transaction Approach,"
American Journal of Sociology 87, no. 3 (1981): 548-77.
. The Mechanisms of Governance. New York: Oxford University Press, 1996.
Williamson, Peter J. Varieties of Corporatism. New York: Cambridge University
Press, 1986.
Wilson, James Q., ed. The Politics of Regulation. New York: Basic Books, 1980.
Wilson, William Julius. The Declining Significance of Race: Blacks and Changing
American Institutions, 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980.
Wittman, Donald A. The Myth of Government Failure: Why Political Institutions
are Efficient. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995.
Wolff, Edward N. Top Heavy: A Study of the Increasing Inequality of Wealth in
America. New York: Twentieth Century Fund Press, 1995.
Wolff, Robert Paul, Barrington Moore, Jr., and Herbert Marcuse. A Critique of
Pure Tolerance. Boston: Beacon Press, 1969.
World Commission on Environment and Development. Our Common Future.
Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987.
Wright, Erik Olin. Class, Crisis, and the State. London: New Left Books, 1978.
Zaretsky, Eli. Capitalism, The Family and Personal Life. New York: Harper 8>C
Row, 1976.
Zucker, Seymour, and The Business Week Team. The Reindustrialization of f
America. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1982.
Index
Kaldor, Nicholas, 100, 174, 315 market failure, 33, 122, 296
Kalecki, Michal, 100 market power, 101, 144, 148, 149,
Kant, Immanuel, 59, 94 165, 175
Kautsky, Karl, 27 mark-up pricing, 101
Kemp, Jack, 135 Marshall, Alfred, 33, 93-94, 310
Keynes, John Maynard, 2 1 , 33, 36, Marx, Karl, 24, 27, 57-59, 115, 164,
94-95, 99, 146, 174, 197, 299, 166, 1 8 8 - 1 8 9 , 2 2 4 , 2 6 8 , 2 8 8 ,
315 289
Keynes, John Neville, 315 Marxist feminism, 224-225, 227
Kirzner, Israel, 49 Maslow, Abraham, 195, 255-256
Knights of Labor, 192 mass society, 81, 254
Kohlberg, Lawrence, 255 Mayo, Elton, 196
Kondratiev, Nikolai, 139 McKenzie, Richard, 51, 221
Kristol, Irving, 84, 171 means-tested benefits, 177
Krugman, Paul, 300 Menger, Carl, 31, 32
Kuttner, Robert, 100 mercantilism, 23, 116
Kuznets, Simon, 298 merit goods, 124
merit pay, 244, 257
Laffer, Arthur, 135 metapreferences, 313
Laibman, David, 67 Mill, James, 91
Lancaster, Kelvin, 314 Mill, John Stuart, 2 1 , 91-92, 95,
land reform, 298 173-174,176,258-259,309
law and economics, 4 1 , 113 Millett, Kate, 226
League of Women Voters, 232 minimum wage, 178
Lenin, V. I., 27, 61-62, 249, 289 Minsky, Hyman, 101
Lerner, Abba, 150, 174 Mises, Ludwig von, 32, 49, 134
Lewin, Kurt, 196 Mitchell, Juliet, 226
Lewis, William Arthur, 296 Mitchell, Wesley C , 65
libertarianism, 41 monetarism, 42, 52, 135, 136
Liebknecht, Karl, 27 Mont Pelerin Society, 72
Lindblom, Charles, 3 Montchretien, Antoyne de, 23
Lipset, Seymour Martin, 84 monument-building, 285
Lipsey, Richard, 314 Moore, Wilbert, 168
List, Friedrich, 295 Morgenstern, Oskar, 49
Locke, John, 42-43, 55, 77, 160 M c x a , Gaetano, 119
logical positivism, 310-311, 314 Mott, Lucretia, 220
logrolling, 111 multiculturalism, 216
Loury, Glenn, 205, 206 Murray, Charles, 168, 211
Lucas, Robert, 51, 135 Mussolini, Benito, 75
Myrdal, Gunnar, 296, 297
Machlup, Fritz, 49
Malcolm X, 210 Naess, Arne, 269
Malthus, Thomas, 25, 45, 162 National Bureau of Economic
Mann, Horace, 244 Research, 65
Marable, Manning, 210 National Industrial Recovery Act, 83
Marcuse, Herbert, 189, 249 National Organization for Women,
marginal productivity theory, 158, 232
161 national self-sufficiency, 299
Index 357