Rorty - Philosophy Without Principles (1985)
Rorty - Philosophy Without Principles (1985)
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/1343367?seq=1&cid=pdf-
reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to Critical Inquiry
Richard Rorty
459
what is meant are identical" and that one will look for an "account of
interpretation in general" only if one fails to recognize this identity (pp.
729, 723). Such failure leads to an attempt to connect meaning and
intention (as in Hirsch) or to disconnect them (as in Paul de Man). But
such attempts must fail, for they presuppose a break "between language
and speech acts" which does not exist (p. 733).
Knapp and Michaels defend this latter claim by saying that marks
which are shaped like a sentence of English do not count as language
unless the marks are backed up by an intention-unless they are inscribed
by somebody who meant something by them. If one grants this point,
Knapp and Michaels argue, one will not, with speech-act theorists such
as H. P. Grice, distinguish between what sentences mean and what a
given utterer means by them on a given occasion. Grice would say of a
pattern of marks created on a beach by random wave motion that it
means whatever the sentence it has been construed to token means, even
though nobody ever meant anything by it. Knapp and Michaels would
deny this (see p. 733, esp. n.13).4 For Grice's distinction opens up the
logical space they want to close: the space in which one asks the traditional
interpretive question "Granted that the sentence means such and such,
did its author use it to mean that on this particular occasion?"
Since I regard this as a useful question, I should like to keep the
space open and, thus, to side with Grice. So I would urge that anything-
a wave pattern, an arrangement of stars, the spots on a rock-can be
treated not only as language but as any given sentence of English if one
can find some way to map its features onto the semantic and syntactic
features of that sentence (and other actual and possible patterns or ar-
rangements or spots on the other sentences of English). "Linguistical-
ity" is, on this view, cheap. You can impute it to anything simply by
working out a translation scheme, just as you can impute goodness to
anything by imagining a desirable end to which it can be a means. The
question of whether the thing is really a sentence or whether we are
simply pretending it is, is just as bad as the question of whether goodness
is objective or subjective. Both questions should be eschewed by us prag-
matists, since both presuppose Hirsch's Husserlian distinction between
content and context, between essential and accidental properties (as op-
posed to the harmless distinction between normal or familiar properties
and abnormal or unfamiliar ones). So I think Knapp and Michaels should
not go out on a metaphysical limb by saying that the absence of an
'career option' of writing and teaching theory" (p. 800). In my view, this
career option consists in an opportunity to discuss philosophy books-
as well as novels, poems, critical essays, and so forth-with literature
students. Knapp and Michaels, however, construe it as the attempt to
supply foundations for literary interpretation. I would hope that the
latter rhetoric could be discarded while the career option remains. The
recent emergence of this option seems to me one of the healthier features
of American academic life. For, as Paul Alpers has remarked, courses in
"literary theory" have become "ports of entry" for a tradition of European
philosophical thought which had been neglected in America. There is
no particular reason why this tradition should be taught in literature
departments rather than in philosophy departments, but there is also no
particular reason why it should not be. It should certainly be taught
somewhere in our universities, and it seems to me greatly to the credit
of our literature departments that they have given it a home.