HALL Queering Philosophy 2022
HALL Queering Philosophy 2022
Queering Philosophy
Kim Q. Hall
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form or by any elec-
tronic or mechanical means, including information storage and retrieval systems, without
written permission from the publisher, except by a reviewer who may quote passages
in a review.
The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of American
National Standard for Information Sciences—Permanence of Paper for Printed Library
Materials, ANSI/NISO Z39.48-1992.
Contents
Acknowledgments vii
Bibliography 137
Index 149
v
Acknowledgments
In addition to all the other affective ups and downs that ordinarily attend
writing—anxiety, stress, doubt, frustration, joy, curiosity—the long process
of working on this book has felt like carving a space for existence in the
discipline of philosophy. This might seem like a strange way to open the
acknowledgments section for this book. After all, I am definitely a phi-
losopher with all the requisite degrees and therefore part of the profession of
philosophy. And yet, like many queer philosophers (those of us whose work
can be said to queer philosophy in some way), my place in philosophy is
always in question, a fact most clearly reflected in the frequency with which
I still encounter questions or assertions expressing doubt about whether my
research and teaching counts as real philosophy. If anything, this book is an
effort to explore the queer significance of being in question, philosophically
and otherwise, in ways that also call into question the disciplining boundaries
and function of philosophy.
As such, it seems only fitting to acknowledge those who have helped me
to stay with and in the trouble of a discipline that, too often, closes as many
doors as it opens. Here, I want to acknowledge some of the folks inside and
outside philosophy’s disciplinary walls who have helped me, in various ways,
to understand that philosophy can be otherwise. Whether I’ve met them or
not, some are listed here because of my admiration of their work. Some have
been mentors at various times in my career. Some I know as collaborators and
colleagues, and some are friends and/or family. And some, happily for me,
are all the above. In one way or another and against the odds, all have helped
me to feel mighty real at some point in my queer philosophical career. In the
vein of Sara Ahmed’s feminist killjoy survival kit (2017), they have been part
of my always in-process queer philosophical toolbox.
For their early encouragement and support, I thank Donna Turney, Florence
Martin, and Jeffner Allen. Reading Simone de Beauvoir, Angela Davis, Audre
Lorde, and Gloria Anzaldúa, along with many other feminist scholars, ignited
a philosophical passion and curiosity in me that, thankfully, has never been
vii
viii Acknowledgments
I think many adults (and I among them) are trying, in our own work, to
keep faith with vividly remembered promises made to ourselves in child-
hood; promises to make invisible possibilities and desires visible; to make
the tacit things explicit; to smuggle queer representation in where it must
be smuggled and with the relative freedom of adulthood, to challenge
queer-eradicating impulses frontally where they are to be so challenged.
—Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick, “Queer and Now”
Could it be that not knowing for sure what should and should not be
acknowledged as philosophy has itself a certain philosophical value? And
is this a value we might name and discuss without it thereby becoming a
new criterion by which the philosophical is rigorously demarcated from
the nonphilosophical?
—Judith Butler, “Can the ‘Other’ of Philosophy Speak?”
1
2 Introduction
philosophy, as well as call into question the temporal frame in which queer
might appear as now out-of-date. A silo approach depends on a linear, or to
use Elizabeth Freeman’s (2010) helpful concept—chronormative—temporal-
ity in which the past is always superseded by an always better present that
anticipates an even better future. A silo approach to assessing the relevance
of a theory relies, even if unintentionally, on a sense of rigid distinctions
between fields. For example, within a silo approach, distinctions between
queer, feminist, critical race, decolonial, transnational, and crip theories are
drawn in such a way that it is possible to select one as less or more relevant
than the others.3 But, if we take intersectionality seriously as a framework for
thinking through the complexities of how one is situated within contingent,
entangled networks of oppression and privilege, it becomes clear not only
that truly transformative theory and politics requires thinking both within
and between these theoretical frameworks, but also that the complexities and
differences within queer studies and communities should caution us against
a too-quick dismissal of queer theory overall. While it’s true, as David
Eng, Jack Halberstam, and José Muñoz indicate, that “queer studies in the
past has rarely addressed such broad social concerns” (e.g., global capital-
ism, racialization, and imperialism) and that its centering of privileged, US
queer subjects contributes to this epistemic ignorance, this is not true for
all contributions to queer scholarship, past and present (2005, 5). In part,
this means that transformative work in queer studies seeks to refigure the
dominant narrative about the queer archive. This approach doesn’t deny the
ongoing importance of figures such as Michel Foucault, Judith Butler, and
Eve Sedgwick but, instead, seeks to both question and augment the standard
archive through critiquing and decentering its whiteness and reclaiming the
work of queers of color such as Audre Lorde, Gloria Anzaldúa, and James
Baldwin, to name just a few. The transformative possibility of queer futures is
intimately related to the conceptualization of queer pasts. Rather than move in
a linear fashion from the past toward a (presumed better) future, the temporal
framing of queer studies moves sideways (Stockton 2009).
Whatever else it has been, queer theory has been about time. In Time
Binds: Queer Temporalities, Queer Histories, Elizabeth Freeman proclaims
that queer was never meant to be hip or in fashion. Instead, its resistance to
normalization places queerness at odds with the present. That which is queer,
Freeman argues, is behind “the times,” out of step:
At one point in my life as a scholar of queer culture and theory, I thought the
point of queer was to be always ahead of actually existing possibilities. On this
model, it seemed that truly queer queers would dissolve forms, disintegrate
identities, level taxonomies, scorn the social, and even repudiate politics alto-
gether (and indeed, there is one wing of queer theory that does privilege this
4 Introduction
kind of negating work). But this version of “queering” the social text strikes
me as . . . about having the problem solved ahead of time, about feeling more
evolved than one’s context. Now I think the point may be to trail behind actually
existing social possibilities: to be interested in the tail end of things, willing to
be bathed in the fading light of whatever has been declared useless. (2010, xiii)
As the standard origin story of queer theory goes, queer theory emerged as
an academic field in the late 1980s and early 1990s in the US. While queer
theory has a reputation of being abstract, highly theoretical, and (especially in
some philosophical quarters) difficult to read, it’s important to remember that
the emergence of the field owes a debt to AIDS, LGBTQ, and feminist activ-
ism. The context of anti-LGBTQ violence and the fight for survival motivated
the field’s beginnings.
The authors of what came to be described as queer theory’s foundational
works (e.g., Michel Foucault, Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick, Judith Butler, and
Gloria Anzaldúa) did not identify their work as contributing to something
called queer theory. Indeed, as David Halperin points out, “no such theory
existed” when their foundational works were published (2003, 340). The term
“queer theory,” Halperin explains, was introduced by Theresa de Lauretis as a
panel title for a conference and “as a joke” (339). Then, as now, some objected
to the term “queer” because of its history and ongoing use as anti-LGBTQ
hate speech (340). De Lauretis used the term because it was being reclaimed
in the world, even if it had not yet been embraced within academia (339).
Queering theory, making it queer and critiquing its heteronormative assump-
tions, was the impetus behind titling the panel queer theory (340).
Queer theory’s genealogical approach to sexuality and gender informs
its critique of identity, a critique that seeks to reconceive rather than reject
identity. Queer critique of identity has important implications. In particular,
it challenges the use of identity as a unifying ground for activism. As Butler
explains, the positing of identity as a shared ground for activism inevitably
leads to a failure to reach one’s desired political goals (1990b, 6–8). It’s not
only that identity-based organizing excludes the obvious—those who aren’t
members of one’s identity group; it’s that identity-based organizing can also
exclude the very people one assumes to be part of one’s group (3–4, 14–15).
In trying to establish the necessary and sufficient conditions for group mem-
bership, one falsely universalizes the experiences and perspectives of one
segment of the group and, thus, alienates the rest. In troubling gender, Butler
proposed what would later be understood as a queering of feminism. By ques-
tioning rather than assuming “woman” as the subject of feminism, queering
feminism forges a politics in which such common grounds are, importantly,
in the making, collectively and contingently conceived and created in the
work of organizing. As a method, queering draws attention to the systems of
power that normalize and naturalize identity’s definitional limits. Rather than
reinforce structures of oppression, queer theory seeks to make visible and
Introduction 7
While the version of queer theory’s origins offered above has long counted as
the official origin story of the field, there is much that this account ignores.
More than mere oversight, the gaps in the official account falsely universalize
whiteness and US centeredness and, thus, dull the critical edge of queerness,
threatening to homo-and trans-normalize it.5 While Foucault, Butler, and
Sedgwick (long understood as queer theory’s holy trinity) are tremendously
important, they aren’t the only formative figures. For example, Cherríe
Moraga’s and Gloria Anzaldúa’s co-edited This Bridge Called My Back:
Writings by Radical Women of Color (1981), Audre Lorde’s Sister Outsider
(1984), and Gloria Anzaldúa’s Borderlands/La Frontera: The New Mestiza
(1987) pre-date Butler’s Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of
Identity (1990b) and Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick’s Epistemology of the Closet
(1990). The challenges to one-dimensional6 analyses presented in those texts
were just as important for Butler’s questioning of the subject of feminism as
Foucault, Beauvoir, and Wittig. Butler acknowledges this context in the fol-
lowing passage from Gender Trouble:
If one “is” a woman, that is surely not all one is; the term fails to be exhaustive,
not because a pregendered “person” transcends the specific paraphernalia of its
gender, but because gender is not always constituted coherently or consistently
in different historical contexts, and because gender intersects with racial, class,
ethnic, sexual, and regional modalities of discursively constituted identities.
As a result, it becomes impossible to separate out “gender” from the political
and cultural intersections in which it is invariably produced and maintained.
(1990b, 3)
time, I didn’t realize how rare it was for Simone de Beauvoir and Angela
Davis, despite their philosophy degrees, to be taught in an undergraduate
philosophy class.
It is interesting that many of the philosophers who have influenced queer
theorists have had a vexed relationship with the field. For example, Foucault
once said in an interview, “When I write, I couldn’t tell you if I’m doing
history or philosophy. I’ve often been asked what it meant to me to write
what I wrote, what I spoke about, what I was trying to say, why one thing
and not another, if I was a philosopher or a historian or a sociologist, and so
on. I had a hard time answering” (2013, 44–45). Ladelle McWhorter notes
Foucault’s expressed “aversion” to academic philosophy (2016, 23). Like
queerness itself, many of the philosophers who have influenced queer theory
have understood their work as liminal, situated between fields and question-
ing disciplinary boundaries. While credentialed in philosophy, their work
raises questions about the values and assumptions that shape how philosophy
distinguishes itself as a discipline. Poised in the spaces between fields, their
work suggests that queering philosophy rejects the normalizing imperative
that defines philosophy as the application and explication of particular meth-
ods and texts. To queer philosophy is to engage in an experiment in what
philosophy might be, a practice of radical love of wisdom.
Queering philosophy (at least the sense of it I defend in this book) con-
sists of more than adding content about LGBTQ lives and experiences to
existing philosophical theories or peppering one’s philosophical work with
LGBTQ-themed thought experiments while neglecting to substantively
engage LGBTQ scholarship. Instead, queering philosophy is a critical prac-
tice that thinks on and against institutionalized philosophy in such a way that
it points to the possibility of doing philosophy otherwise. When one does phi-
losophy otherwise, one’s work is often characterized as “not real philosophy”
by those who are more normatively situated within the field’s continental or
analytic mainstream. That which is queer is often deemed outside the realm
of “the real.” In the face of the dismissal of their work as not real philosophy,
some queer philosophers might be tempted to refuse the label of philosopher
for themselves, leaving the field to the mainstream. However, queering phi-
losophy does not reject philosophy; it rethinks, reconceives, and transforms
it. A queer perspective on philosophy conceives of a field that can be some-
thing other than it has been or is.
In this section, I propose and briefly describe three methodologies that
are part of a practice of queering philosophy: (1) critical remembering or
Introduction 13
1. Critical Remembering/Counter-Memory/Counter-Knowing
Disciplines are defined by their archives and the disciplined path by which
one is supposed to access, utilize, and ultimately reproduce the field. Staying
in line with this normalized path is what disciplinary training aims to produce
(see Ahmed 2006). The archive of a particular domain, constituted by autho-
rized texts and concepts, is itself founded on the exclusion of those texts,
concepts, questions, and figures that are disauthorized and delegitimated, or
as Foucault puts it the “disqualified,” “insufficiently elaborated,” “naïve,”
“hierarchically inferior,” “subjugated knowledges” (2003, 7). Exclusions
from the official archive are connected to exclusions of groups of people, cul-
tures, and perspectives from the field because the creation and maintenance
of the archive itself is rooted in a dominant group’s consensus about what is
worth knowing, preserving, and citing. Within academic philosophy in North
America, the differences between continental and analytic philosophy have
been, in part, differences about which post-Kantian archives philosophers
deem worthy of preservation and ongoing attention. As Bertrand Russell
(2004, 116–117) and Max Horkheimer (2002, 255) pointed out, philosophy is
unique among all other humanities in that differences in position, methodol-
ogy, and archive often result in being labeled nonphilosophy.
But much more than a question about which books can be found on one’s
bookshelf, an archive is about memory: remembering that which one deems
worthy of remembering (see Ferguson 2012 and 2019). Archives orient one
within a field in political and value-laden ways. One’s relationship to, as well
as one’s efforts to create and preserve, an archive is part of an ethical practice
of remembering on whose shoulders one stands, those who have made one’s
thinking and existence in a field possible (see Ahmed 2017). Feminist, queer,
and crip archives also enable survival and the creative imagining necessary
for persistence in the work of field transformation. In Living a Feminist
Life, Sara Ahmed writes, “Citation is feminist memory. Citation is how we
acknowledge our debt to those who came before; those who helped us find
our way when the way was obscured because we deviated from the paths
we were told to follow” (2017, 15–16). Ahmed recounts her disciplinary
training—she was expected to engage the work of white male figures and to
14 Introduction
disability, race, gender, class, nation, and age. Thinking alongside brings
into question strict or pure boundaries between fields and categories. Hence,
counter-memory as a practice of queering philosophy strives to remember
without monumentalizing and, thus, to reorient oneself in the hopes of doing
philosophy otherwise.
2. Smuggling
Smuggling is the act of bringing in that which is forbidden by the powers that
be because it is useful for and cherished by those who desire it nonetheless.
Sedgwick identifies smuggling as a method of queer theory in an epigraph
that opens this introduction. Queering philosophy is a practice of smuggling
in what one needs (texts, concepts, figures, etc.) to call attention to and resist
queer-eradicating practices in the field and to gather the tools one needs to
survive. Queer-eradicating practices in philosophy can take many forms,
one of which is the failure of institutionalized philosophy to take up or sub-
stantively respond to philosophically relevant contributions in queer studies
(see Winnubst 2010). Those of us who have been engaged in the practice of
queering philosophy share the experience of reading beyond the discipline of
philosophy, not simply because of interest but because so many mainstream
philosophy texts either ignore or pathologize queer and trans lives. While
questions and issues of importance to queer and trans people may be dis-
cussed in mainstream philosophical texts, they are rarely addressed from the
perspective of being queer and/or trans in the world (Mann 2013; Bettcher
2019). Queering philosophy smuggles figures and ideas from nonphilosophi-
cal or philosophically marginalized and discredited texts into philosophy
classrooms, journal articles, and books, where they are used to create a
ground from which to evaluate canonical texts and create another way of
doing philosophy, an otherwise philosophy of the elsewhere and elsewhen
(Crawley 2017).
Smuggling, one form of which is perverse, slantwise reading, is risky. I
recall the white, gender conforming, straight male faculty member who, dur-
ing an on-campus interview, dismissed my reading of how gender and race
informed Kant’s analysis, saying that he simply didn’t see it. Of course, if
he can’t see it, it doesn’t exist—the “it” in this case being the racialized and
gendered dimensions of Kant’s philosophy.
Smuggling as a method of queering philosophy is the steadfast effort to
resist the erasure of queer perspectives, people, experiences, histories, and
knowledges from that which is deemed “real philosophy.” In this book, I
smuggle texts from many disciplines and strive to demonstrate that reflection
on philosophically-relevant concepts, questions, and problems outside the
bounds of institutionalized philosophy cannot be reduced to a mere shadow of
16 Introduction
3. Recruitment
Queers recruit! Yes, we do, shamelessly! As a method of queering philosophy,
recruitment is about (re)claiming the “others of philosophy” as a site where
philosophy happens. Recruitment is part of the disciplinary promiscuity of
work at the nexus of queer theory and philosophy. Given the fact that, as
previously noted, many feminist, queer, and critical race philosophers are
not currently in philosophy departments, recruitment is a practice of both
refusing to be silent bystanders in the face of their absence from institutional-
ized philosophy and honoring the philosophical contributions of their work.
Through recruitment, queering philosophy brings in work from different
genres and fields. Finally, as a method of queering philosophy, recruitment
aims for expansive, coalitional conceptions of queerness and philosophy,
thinking beyond individual self-identification as queer, a philosopher, or a
queer philosopher, as queer theory itself questions identity as a site of the
operation of normalizing power rather than unmediated description.
Throughout Queering Philosophy, I situate a number of works as queer and
philosophical, regardless of the authors’ sexual and gender identities, disci-
plinary affiliations, or even views about queer theory. In this sense, queering
philosophy builds on queer critiques of identity by focusing not solely on
who authors are but rather on what their work does, the possibilities opened
by their thinking.
I suggest that what makes a text queer is its critical attunement to normal-
ization, both in terms of the problems/questions it poses and explores and
its relation to disciplinary thinking. Furthermore, recruitment as a method
for queering philosophy is about how one directs one’s attention and brings
into philosophical writing insights from non-academic contexts. As a form of
recruitment, queering philosophy resists disciplinary containment and exclu-
sions and aims toward disciplinary transformation. It’s not simply that the
field of philosophy itself is made better through the inclusion of previously
marginalized and ignored people and perspectives; it’s that recruitment makes
possible a philosophy done otherwise, an otherwise-philosophy. Contrary to
the image of the solitary, armchair philosopher, recruitment recognizes that
queering philosophy is a collective effort. Uprisings require recruitment.
Recruitment brings queer studies to bear on philosophy, opening other ways
of doing philosophy.
Introduction 17
BOOK OUTLINE
Chapter 1, “Queer Matters,” focuses on how that which is queer calls into
question philosophy’s institutional habits. I build on Butler’s insights about
performativity and the other of philosophy and Sarah Ahmed’s queer phe-
nomenological analysis of orientation to consider why queer philosophy
has never officially arrived in philosophy. The question of how and whether
queerness matters in philosophy’s mainstream is central to understanding this
phenomenon. This chapter offers an analysis of philosophy’s straight habits.
One of queer theory’s most influential claims is that sexuality delineates an
epistemic rather than a primarily erotic space in Western contexts (Foucault
1990; Sedgwick 1990; McWhorter 1999; Hall 2017a). In chapter 2, “Queer
Knowing,” I discuss work at the intersection of queer, feminist, critical race,
and disability theories that has enabled the emergence of a queer epistemol-
ogy. In addition to explaining how queer theory challenges what is known or
presumed to be knowable about sexuality and gender, this chapter explores
the possibilities of a queer epistemology that is not centered on queer sub-
jectivity but instead opens the possibility of a queer epistemic practice that
reconceives queerness. In addition, I consider what a queer epistemology
contributes to discussions of epistemic ignorance and other forms of epis-
temic injustice in feminist and critical race epistemologies.
In chapter 3, “Power, Life, and Death,” I build on Foucault’s understand-
ing of biopolitics and Mbembe’s understanding of necropolitics to explain
how queering philosophy grapples with the question of whose lives matter
for queer theory and philosophy and how queering philosophy interrogates
what it means for a life to matter in the context of global forces that render
some lives disposable. Important to this discussion is an analysis of recent
queer necropolitical critiques of homo-and trans-normativity that enable the
inclusion of the lives of queer global elites at the expense of the viability of
racialized queer lives. I also present a queer bio/necropolitical reframing of
questions of life and death that inform the story that mainstream Western
philosophy tells about itself. And I consider how queer insights about matters
of life and death place AIDS and COVID-19 in conversation with each other
without collapsing important differences between them.
Queer theory’s denaturalization of sexuality and gender reveals that a
critique of nature, the natural, and what it means to be human have long
been important to the field. In chapter 4, “Queer Ecologies,” I focus on
queer theory’s contributions to ecological thinking and build on work at the
intersection of queer, feminist, critical race, and disability theories to explore
the possibilities of a queer ecology that questions framing assumptions in
mainstream environmentalism and environmental philosophy. In addition to
18 Introduction
NOTES
queer might do, especially in the context of a discipline (like philosophy) that has
never officially recognized it. In so doing, I resist reading queer and queer theory
as against crip, feminist, and trans theories and movements because I want to focus
on meanings of queer and queering that I take to be in solidarity with them. In this
sense, my consideration of queer builds on Lynne Huffer’s contention that queer and
feminist theories need not be interpreted as opposed to each other insofar as both
contribute to anti-foundationalist thinking about gendered and sexual subjectivity
(2013, 6–7). Queer feminism speaks from and to the resonances between these fields.
I suggest that cross-movement solidarity and coalition require questioning the
chronormative assumption that emergent marginalized areas of study necessarily
displace and render passé other marginalized fields of study. One of the things that
queering as a method can still do is call attention to and think from the edges and
spaces between categories and fields, questioning the terms of their internal coher-
ence. In this book, I focus on queer and queering in order to consider its contribution
to the possibility of thinking and doing philosophy otherwise. Queering is never
accomplished once and for all; its mode is the again and again of a perpetual begin-
ning. Thus, queering philosophy is not a bid for recognition but rather a project of
critical intervention into practices of exclusion. As I use the term in this book, the
queer in queering philosophy is not a fixed category of identity or discrete, unified
school of philosophy, but rather that which defies definition and questions the forces
of exclusion that constitute philosophy as a field.
4. Freeman’s use of arrhythmia as a queer temporal mode points to resonances
between queer and crip temporalities and the possibility of queer crip temporalities.
The connection between crip and queer temporalities is central to the understanding
of queering philosophy I present in this book. For further discussion of the many
dimensions of crip time, see The South Atlantic Quarterly’s 2021 special issue on
Crip Temporalities, edited by Ellen Samuels and Elizabeth Freeman.
5. As Jin Haritaworn, Adi Kuntsman, and Silvia Posocco write, “[H]omonormative
and transnormative identities [are] contingent on settler colonialism, anti-blackness
and permanent war” and “provide the conditions of queer ascendancies” (2014, 2).
Thus, they “refuse a view of the past as finished and the present as democratic and
post-genocidal” (2–3).
6. My use of one-dimensional is inspired by Roderick Ferguson’s distinction
between one-dimensional and mutlidimensional queer politics in One-Dimensional
Queer (2019). Ferguson traces the multidimensional history of queer movements in
which injustice against gender and sexual minorities is understood as inseparable
from racial and economic injustice and US militarism and imperialism. This multi-
dimensional history, Ferguson argues, not Judy Garland’s death as the white-washed
origin story goes, was the context for the Stonewall rebellion in 1969. Terms like
multidimensional and intersectional are frameworks that have informed Black femi-
nist and queer analyses of the simultaneity of race, gender, class, sexuality, age, and
ability and the resulting need for a multidimensional politics. For more on the history
of intersectionality, see Gines (2011) and Collins and Bilge (2016).
7. David Halperin defines queer as “whatever is at odds with the normal, the
legitimate, the dominant. There is nothing in particular to which it necessarily refers.
20 Introduction
Queer Matters
Perhaps the habits of institutions are not revealed unless you come up
against them.
—Sara Ahmed, On Being Included: Racism
and Diversity in Institutional Life
21
22 Chapter 1
white, be-suited man did the same thing. Several others followed him. One
even opened and closed the door twice! All were completely lost, their bewil-
derment1 apparent in facial expressions and hurried door-closings. There was
no error in the conference program; those of us gathered there were where we
were supposed to be. Without having to confer with each other, people from
underrepresented groups sitting in the room knew what was going on and
there was a beautiful, sparkling moment of spontaneous laughter. Maybe, I
thought, just maybe, in this room, I could be a philosopher, after all.
Part of the scene described above captures an ordinary experience at any
conference: the experience of wandering through hotel hallways with confer-
ence map in hand, searching for the location of the panel you want to attend,
and discovering that you are in the wrong place. Conference attendees, like
students searching for their classrooms on the first day of class, often lose
their way. How do you discover you’re in the wrong place? Maybe you look
at the map and realize it’s just a matter of taking a right when you should have
taken a left. In this case, the map (or asking for directions) soon reorients you
by putting you back on the right track. But what if you discover you are in the
wrong place because you open the door and are bewildered and disoriented
by the bodies assembled in the room? Moreover, what if the gathering of
some bodies is so disorienting that you become uncertain about whether you
are at a philosophy conference? Under such circumstances, it seems you are
quite lost indeed.
What if we turn this experience around and examine it from the perspective
of the people sitting in the room who discover that they are a source of con-
fusion and disorientation for the people who open only to quickly close the
door, the be-suited white men who are bewildered by the presence of so many
“not-thems” gathered together at a philosophy conference? Having become
habituated in philosophy by the repetition of being taught by and sitting in
classrooms and conference rooms with people who mostly look and comport
themselves like them, the unexpected encounter of a room full of people who
are “not-them” is a shocking disruption to what they had come to expect as
the familiar hum of institutionalized philosophy’s milieu. A shock, Gayle
Salamon explains, brings to awareness that which has been taken for granted
as features of the world and incorporated into one’s habit body. As she puts
it, “A shock is something that happens that causes us to shift our interpreta-
tion and understanding of an event in our world. Such an event seems actu-
ally to change the nature of the world around us, breaking our modes of
understanding, our habits of seeing, our ways of hearing” (2018, 63–64). In
my recounting of an experience at a mainstream philosophy conference, the
taken-for-granted and incorporated understanding of what real philosophy
Queer Matters 23
is and who is really a philosopher that was disrupted and disoriented was its
whiteness, maleness, and straightness.2
In this chapter I build on Butler’s insights about performativity and the
other of philosophy and Sara Ahmed’s queer phenomenological analysis of
orientation to consider the following question: Why, after more than thirty
years of queer theory, has something called queer philosophy never been
established in institutionalized philosophy?3 Wrestling with this question
focuses attention on whether and how queer matters in the institution of
philosophy and how both queer theory and philosophy matter outside phi-
losophy’s institutional walls. To clarify, I’m not suggesting that no philoso-
phers (here, simply people with PhD’s in philosophy who currently work in
philosophy departments) work in something we might call queer philosophy;
obviously, if that were true, I would not be writing this book on queering
philosophy. Instead, I’m focusing on the fact that, with very few (even rare)
exceptions, queer philosophy is not an established area of specialization in
the field. In fact, within the institution of philosophy, a proclaimed specializa-
tion in queer theory is taken to be a specialization in an interdisciplinary field
outside philosophy’s proper disciplinary walls. Puzzling over the distinction
between theory and philosophy, Judith Butler notes,
It turned out that I had become something called a “theorist,” and though I
was glad to accept the kind invitations that came my way, I was somewhat
bewildered and began trying to understand what kind of practice this enterprise
called “theory” was supposed to be. Ah, yes, “the state of theory,” I would say
at the dinner table on such occasions, sipping my Chardonnay, and then look
around anxiously to see whether there might be a kind soul there who might tell
me precisely what this “theory” was supposed to be. . . . [I]t wasn’t clear to me
that what I was doing was “theory” and that that term could and should take the
place of philosophy. (2004a, 243)
QUEER PHILOSOPHY?
After a little more than thirty years of queer theory, why has queer philosophy
never been a recognized subfield in philosophy? This is especially curious
given that people often listed among the field’s founders include well-known
philosophers like Michel Foucault and Judith Butler. While there are philoso-
phers who specialize in queer theory, queer philosophy has not been estab-
lished as a subfield. Let’s consider the evidence.
First, the job market in philosophy. As far as I’m aware, queer philosophy
has not been listed as a required area of specialization or competence in the
vast majority of philosophy job ads. In fact, I can think of only one job ad
that listed queer studies in a long list of other possible areas a candidate might
work in, but it was not the main hiring area. In other words, the appearance of
queer studies in this ad might be categorized as an “it would be fine or nice
if but it’s really not necessary” specialization. Occasionally, one might find
the word sexuality somewhere in a philosophy job description; however, this
reference is typically for jobs in areas (like feminist philosophy or philosophy
of race, for example) where there is a stated desire for someone with an inter-
sectional approach to their area of specialization. In this case, again, there is
no specific requirement or stated desire for a specialization in queer theory.
In addition, it is highly unlikely that a job candidate will be asked about their
competencies in queer theory during an interview (I was asked this only
once, and it was so unusual that it surprised me). In fact, one’s competen-
cies in queer theory will likely be used by interviewers as grounds to doubt
that one’s work is really philosophy (see Salamon 2009). All this suggests
that no philosophy departments in the US perceive the absence of someone
who specializes and could teach courses in queer philosophy (or even queer
theory) as a significant gap in departmental expertise or course development
and coverage. If there happens to be someone who specializes in queer theory
in the department, it is most likely because they also specialize in a more
mainstream analytic (e.g., metaphysics) or continental (e.g., phenomenology)
area or figure. As is often the case with marginalized fields like feminist phi-
losophy, philosophy of race, philosophy of disability, or trans philosophy,4 it
is one’s specialization in a more mainstream canonical area that often makes
Queer Matters 25
one competitive on the job market. Undoubtedly, there are individual mem-
bers of departments who perceive the absence of queer philosophy as a gap
in departmental expertise, but they are most likely outnumbered when their
university gives the department the opportunity to conduct a search for a new
tenure-track faculty member.
Second, queer philosophy tends to be folded into courses, conferences, and
journals in other subfields or disciplines. Very few philosophy departments
offer a course in queer philosophy as a regular part of their course offerings.5
Also, rather than entire conferences focused on queer philosophy, presenta-
tions that engage with queer theory are usually panels or parts of panels at
other conferences, in contrast to entire conferences devoted to work in other
marginalized subfields in philosophy. Let me be clear. These are vital, wel-
come professional spaces for philosophers who specialize in queer theory.
Nonetheless, this phenomenon indicates that queer philosophy has never
emerged as a recognized subfield in its own right.
Third, while there are professional organizations that advocate for the inter-
ests of LGBTQ philosophers, advocating for gender and sexual minorities in
the field is not the same as advocating for the establishment of a new subfield.
To consider one obvious point, that one is lesbian, gay, bisexual, transgender,
or gender nonconforming does not mean that one has philosophical expertise
or is even interested in queer or trans philosophy. There is an APA Committee
on the Status of LGBTQ People in the Profession and an APA Newsletter on
LGBTQ Issues in Philosophy. While incredibly important, the presence of
these organizations has not resulted in the establishment of queer philosophy
as a legitimate-even-if-marginalized subfield in the institution of philosophy.
If queer theory were a recent academic development, this would not be sur-
prising. But thirty years after queer theory’s emergence as an academic field,
and while, at present, some queer theorists are wondering what’s left of queer
theory or whether it’s still queer, the fact that queer philosophy has not arrived
is a real head-scratcher. Despite the long-standing legitimization of queer
theory in academia, queer philosophy has not emerged.
Outside philosophy’s institutional walls, queer theory has been around long
enough that some queer theorists are questioning whether there’s anything
left of it (Eng and Puar 2020). Even early texts in the field, such as Judith
Butler’s “Critically Queer” were already reflecting on the field’s future irrel-
evance as its key term “queer” became replaced by terms not yet in existence
but perhaps more salient to a future as-yet-unknown generation, an unknow-
able term that will be deemed better suited to the political work it will need to
do (1993, 228). As Butler writes, “Such a yielding [of queer for another term]
may well become necessary in order to accommodate—without domesticat-
ing—democratizing contestations that have and will redraw the contours of
the movement in ways that can never be fully anticipated in advance” (228).6
26 Chapter 1
There have and continue to be many important critiques of queer theory, and
my aim in this chapter is neither to rehash nor disprove them. Instead, I want
to focus on why, despite those who have proclaimed or anticipated its end,
queer theory has never arrived in the institution of philosophy. What kind of
strange temporal ontology is queerness such that it seems to be, if taken up,
absent upon arrival or, if not taken up as an area, irrelevant or even nonexis-
tent? And, if queerness is a sort of institutional impossibility, how might we
understand what it is like to be a queer philosopher? Understanding and grap-
pling with these questions, I argue, requires a queer materialist analysis that
grapples with how the being of a philosopher is a becoming habituated in a
discipline and with philosophy not just as a collection of questions, methods,
and ideas, but as a workplace. After all, to become habituated is to become
oriented toward and in relation to something, in this case an academic field.
A queer materialist approach to queering philosophy puts on the table the
institution of philosophy in which the work of philosophy happens.
Queer philosophy describes a wayward orientation in the field, an orien-
tation that refuses, to borrow from Sara Ahmed, the lines of philosophical
inheritance premised on both an indifference to and erasure of queerness. To
pursue these issues, I turn to phenomenology in order to put it to queer use.7
Queer use, Ahmed argues, has a “potential [that] might reside somewhere
between our bodies and our worlds” (2019, 201). As Ahmed explains the
question of who is allowed to use what is entangled with question of value,
or of who or what matters (40). A critically queer phenomenological approach
to philosophy attends to embodied being in worlds with others by focusing
not on the individual habituated body alone, but by tracing the habits of
philosophy.
The epigraphs that open this chapter are about institutions—their value, hab-
its, and effects. The quote by Judith Butler is taken from a chapter of Undoing
Gender (2014a) titled “Can the Other of Philosophy Speak?” in which they
trace what it might mean to think of a queer academic career as a “disciplin-
ary problem,” for example, a career of negotiating judgements about what it
means to do “real” philosophy and, thus, be a “real” philosopher (232–33,
238). Butler reflects on the many feminist and continental philosophers who
left philosophy for more hospitable homes outside its institutional walls.
While such departures have come at some form of professional cost to those
who left, “the institutional foreclosures of the philosophic” have also brought
about “good company and better wine, and so many more unexpected con-
versations across disciplines, such extraordinary movements of thought that
Queer Matters 27
the way things are. As Gail Weiss writes about habits, “Through the process
of habituation, horizons are naturalized, taken for granted as ‘the way things
are,’ and this, in turn, makes these horizons even more resistant to analysis,
much less transformation” (2008, 75). Professionalization is a process of
embodying the cartography of an institution. Institutionalized philosophy’s
cartography establishes who belongs in philosophy, or who counts as a “real”
philosopher and what “real” philosophy is. To return to the example of phi-
losophy meetings, an embodied cartography informs how philosophers move
through the hallways of philosophy conferences and the philosophical radar
that just knows when they’ve encountered something that is not philosophy.
Sullivan and Middleton draw on the theory of gender performativity to
explain how ways of knowing and doing that define institutions are perfor-
matively constituted, or the effect of repetition over time. As is well known,
to say that gender is performative is to say it is materialized through the
repetition of acts in a context of a sedimentation of gendered meaning and
norms (Butler 1990a, 270–71, 275). In other words, gender is not an innate
substance reflective of or fixed by the body’s assigned sex. Moreover, Butler
posits that sex (as in the body’s assigned binary sex as male or female) is
also not a mere fact of the body (1990a, 275; 1993, 1–2). Part of Butler’s
point is that whether one experiences one’s gender as a site of play, pleasure,
agency, desire, or profound alienation, one cannot opt out of gender. Within a
context of compulsory heterosexuality, one is compelled to have a gender and
to make one’s gender known. For Sullivan and Middleton, the practices that
define institutions (like museums, but also disciplines) “are performative . . .
they are shaped by inherited codes and conventions that become naturalized
through repetition, and they reproduce—albeit inadvertently—established
and dominant ways of knowing, doing, and being and the privileges and
exclusions they engender” (2020, 11).
The concept of materialization is central to both Butler’s theory of gender
performativity and Sullivan and Middleton’s analysis of the habitus of the
museum as an institution. For Butler, materialization refers to the process
that constitutes the mattering of matter. Thus, “matter,” they write, is “not [a]
site or surface, but [a] process of materialization that stabilizes over time to
produce the effects of boundary, fixity, and surface we call matter” (1993, 9).
Following Butler, the more distant one’s embodied being from naturalized
norms presumed to be simple facts of nature or the material body, the more
one is deemed not to matter.
One often-expressed critique of queer theory is that it fails to take into
account or even outright denies material reality. For these critics, queer theory
is informed by an idealism in which no material bodies exist, only social,
historical, and cultural norms and the minds that interpret them.10 Judith
Butler has been a favorite target of this critique, but I suggest that this is a
Queer Matters 29
misreading of their work. For one thing, Butler doesn’t deny the existence
of the material body but, rather, focuses on the fact that its meaning is not
a transparent fact legible from its surface. Their work on how bodies mat-
ter is about the meaning of bodies and the real material implications of that
meaning in people’s daily lives. As Petrus Liu asserts, “Butler’s account of
the materiality of the body deliberately (and usefully) conflates the problem
of value (what matters) with epistemology (what we know), and epistemol-
ogy with ontology (what is)” (2020, 27). For Liu, Butler’s understanding
of materiality as a site of materialization forms part of the context of the
development of queer materialism at the intersections of Marxism and queer
theory. Liu writes, “The material in both queer theory and Marxism describes
the process whereby a subject comes into existence by virtue of its constitu-
tive outside—what cannot be known or named in advance, what necessarily
escapes categories of identity politics” (36). Both Marxism and queer theory
critique social relations that have become naturalized, and Liu contends that
both are sites of “subjectless critique” in which the material refers not to fixed
matter or economic determinism, but to a critical attunement to that which is
outside norms, current relations, and categories (40–41). Queer materialism is
attuned to the always incomplete and inadequate nature of identity categories,
to the exclusions that attend the constitution of an “I” or a “we.”
To bring these insights to bear on the matter of institutional philosophy,
we might say that straight philosophy has rigid clarity about the distinction
between the truly philosophical and the nonphilosophical; whereas queering
philosophy understands such clarity to be hubris founded on the failure to
understand such distinctions as contingent and indicative of the vulnerability
of institutional philosophy’s self-understanding. To say that the conventions
of institutions are materialized is to understand them as sites of contingent,
exclusionary norms. According to Butler, queerness politicizes this process of
exclusion in an effort to transform what queerness means or might mean. As
they write in Bodies that Matter,
The direction we take excludes things for us, before we even get there” (14–
15). Orientation is how things—including fields—come to matter, become
reachable possibilities. Whatever else they are, institutions are social gather-
ings, ways of occupying space that are in line with the institution’s aims. How
might we think of the institution of philosophy as a social gathering? How is
one oriented within it as a process of training and professionalization, or, in
phenomenological terms, habituated? When bodies gather within the spaces
of institutionalized philosophy, how are they oriented? What might the habits
that structure those gatherings reveal about the institution’s habits?
Orientations, Sara Ahmed points out, follow lines of inheritance, includ-
ing disciplinary inheritance. One of the things Ahmed says in Queer
Phenomenology is that she is not a philosopher and is, thus, interpreting
phenomenological texts as an outsider to the field. The line of inheritance
in philosophy most often moves paternally from a “great” male philosopher
to another male philosopher deemed poised to take his place, or reproduce a
philosophical line of inheritance. Paternal lines of inheritance give shape to
the universalized Western philosophical canon, the texts that philosophical
training orients one toward, even as one may also specialize in a marginal-
ized area or non-white and non-male figure. Philosophical training involves
habituation to situating questions and figures in relation to a paternal line of
philosophical inheritance. Over time, following these philosophical lines of
inheritance (in their analytic and continental incarnations) orients one in such
a way that one doesn’t notice the field’s exclusions because the process of
habituation naturalizes one’s orientation with the result that one understands
oneself as simply doing philosophy.
To be queer, however, is to be disoriented in ways that make strange the
taken-for-granted horizon of an institution, like philosophy. Queering phi-
losophy is an orientation against the grain of institutional philosophy. “Queer
orientations,” Ahmed writes, “are those that put within reach bodies [and, I
would add, texts, perspectives, fields, and geographies] that have been made
unreachable by the lines of conventional genealogy. Queer orientations might
be those that don’t line up, which by seeing the world ‘slantwise’ allow other
objects to come into view” (107). A queer phenomenological approach to the
institution of philosophy, makes visible that which has been taken for granted
within it, examining it from an excluded perspective, or what Butler (2004a)
calls “the other of philosophy” and opening the possibility of doing philoso-
phy otherwise in ways that resist the constraints of the institution.
Orientations constitute what matters and are sustained by habits. To claim,
as I am, that a straight line of inheritance directs institutionalized philoso-
phy’s orientation is to claim that the institution of philosophy both shapes and
is sustained by habits of heteronormativity. Many (if not most) philosophers
would probably balk at the suggestion that philosophical training/habituation
Queer Matters 33
that enact racist exclusions (2017, 1, 13–26. While Ngo focuses mostly on the
bodily habits of human beings, institutions and disciplines have habits too,
habits that materialize and reproduce the coherence and self-understanding of
a collective (an organization, a profession, a university, etc.).
So, if heteronormativity is an embodied habit and not only a set of oppres-
sive beliefs, what are its features? To get at this, it’s important to first grasp
what heteronormativity is. Heteronormativity is the presumption of natural
and thus normal heterosexual desire and erotic practice founded upon natural
and thus normal binary sex and gender. Heteronormativity is a central compo-
nent of compulsory heterosexuality that works to exclude queerness from the
realm of possibility, intelligibility, and reality. Straight habits are produced by
and sustain heteronormativity and compulsory heterosexuality.
While there are undoubtedly many straight habits, I’m going to focus on
three that shape the institution of philosophy: (1) purity, (2) universalization,
and (3) indifference. These habits, like sexuality and gender themselves, are
racialized and, thus, can manifest in different ways.14 In describing philoso-
phy’s habits as straight, I am not suggesting that these habits are mirrored in
the actions of all heterosexual philosophers. Instead, straight habits structure
the field in which all philosophers are habituated regardless of their sexual
or gender identities. The term straight as I use it here refers to practices, and
ways of knowing and being, that, taken together, inform dominant assump-
tions about what constitutes real philosophy. Straight habits, I suggest, reveal
something about the assumptions that orient the field and inform the standard
stories it tells about itself.
Straight has several meanings, one of which is to be in line. A straight line
is not bent or crooked; it moves from one point to another in a reliable, pre-
dictable way. Straight spaces and bodies are materialized by certain habits,
like the habit of binary oppositional alignment of bodies moving through
space (Ahmed 2006, 92). The alignment functions as a pairing. The binary
pairing of bodies deemed opposite is so frequently repeated in heteronorma-
tive spaces that it recedes into the background. Ahmed writes,
Spaces become straight, which allow straight bodies to extend into them, such
that the vertical axis appears in line with the axis of the body. . . . Our body
takes the shape of this repetition; we get stuck in certain alignments as an effect
of this work. Given this, the work of ordinary perception, which straightens up
anything queer of oblique, is not simply about correcting what is out of line.
Rather, things might seem oblique in the first place only insofar as they do not
follow the line which is already given, or that which has already extended in
space by being directed in some ways rather than others. (92)
Queer Matters 35
Alcibiades’s failure to distinguish between his soul and his body (or heart)
is a failure to train or purify his desires. But, as Marcano contends, it is not
Alcibiades who fails philosophy; it is philosophy that fails him. Philosophy
fails him in turning away from queer love, queer wisdom that refuses to be
straightjacketed.
Philosophy’s straight habit of purity is connected to its straight habit of
universalization. Central to Lugones’s account of the logic of purity is its
insistence on the binary distinction between bodies and minds, and other
36 Chapter 1
I’ll never forget the cis-straight male philosopher who said he was indiffer-
ent. We were talking about homophobia, and, at some point he said, “I guess
I’m indifferent.” I was taken aback by his comment, so much so that I didn’t
know what to say. I found his comment chilling, and I was speechless. Here
was someone who not only felt indifferent but felt empowered to so casually
avow it to a queer colleague. The conversation ended.
say that one is indifferent is to say that one doesn’t care or couldn’t care
To
less about that toward which one is indifferent. To say that one is indiffer-
ent about homophobia is to say that one doesn’t care or couldn’t care less
about discrimination and violence against sexual and gender minorities.15
The casual nature of my colleague’s comment reflects, I suggest, a habitu-
ated indifference that sustains heteronormativity. Habits of thought or action
are things outside conscious awareness. To casually express indifference to
a form of oppression that does not target one is to speak without thinking.
I’ve just offered an example of an individual’s indifference, but what about
an institution’s indifference? What are at least some of the forms and implica-
tions of institutional indifference? Specifically, what are some of the forms
and implications of philosophy’s indifference to queerness? Philosophy’s
habit of indifference to queerness can help to explain why queer philosophy
has never been officially recognized as one of the discipline’s subfields. In
addition, philosophy’s indifference to queerness has informed the exile of so
many queer philosophers from the field who could not find a home in phi-
losophy, who could not be brought in line with disciplinary norms. Of course,
one could say that this sort of gatekeeping happens in all disciplines, but what
makes philosophy so unique is, as Butler suggests, the intellectual contribu-
tions it disavows are recognized, valued, and engaged as philosophy outside
philosophy’s institutional walls (2004a, 246).
Intellectual work that speaks from, and not simply about, marginalized
experiences is the occasion for questioning one’s philosophical credentials.
As many feminist philosophers and philosophers of race have argued, institu-
tional philosophy’s universalized subject is white, male, class-privileged, and
Western (and, I would add, straight and able-bodied). In her critique of that
universalized subject, Bonnie Mann contends that pluralism is not a matter
of demographics alone. Instead, pluralism is accomplished when groups that
have been marginalized in the profession and philosophical canon are able to
38 Chapter 1
offer critiques, including critiques of the discipline itself, from the perspec-
tive of their group history, lives, and experiences and to have those critiques
deemed philosophical (Mann 2013, 737; Hall 2013, 161–62). Philosophy’s
straight habit of indifference functions to disavow and even exclude texts and
people deemed not purely philosophical from the field. But, as Butler sug-
gests, philosophy’s “vitality throughout the humanities” has been occasioned
by its loss of purity outside its disciplinary walls (2004a, 241, 247).
The matter of queering philosophy is not just a question of ideas; it’s also
a question of experience—a queer experience of philosophy that exposes
the walls of an institution and the labor that maintains those walls, walls
designed to keep some in and others out. These walls are forged by habits that
shape movements and gestures and even casual utterances. A queer experi-
ence of philosophy’s orientation is an experience of a heteronormativity that
announces itself as it impedes the passage of queers, or those who deviate
from the norms of the institution. These habits of heteronormativity straighten
the institution of philosophy and, in so doing, exclude queerness by render-
ing that which is queer as absent before it ever even arrives—dead on arrival,
haunting philosophy beyond the institution’s walls.
Common sense names the way in which knowledge is held and transmitted
within an anonymous mode . . .. When consulted, common sense speaks with
one voice. Common sense promises to resolve rather than generate contradic-
tion . . .. It is that which disciplines the otherwise, brings it back when it has
strayed from a collectively agreed upon course of deliberation and action.
(2018, 108–9)
A queer method attends to “what has been designated not much use”
or “useless” (Ahmed 2019, 218). That said, there is a difference between
attending to what has been deemed useless and defining that which is queer
as itself useless or a failure. Queer, as a method and politics, puts what has
been deemed useless to use (Ahmed 2019). Put differently, queer methods
and politics declare that queerness has value against the grain of a world
that declares its uselessness. This is what it means to say that queer matters.
Moreover, the indifference to these concerns might itself reflect certain privi-
lege, the privilege that can afford indifference.
Sara Ahmed’s definition of queer use is particularly poignant: “Queer
uses, when things are used for purposes other than the ones for which they
were intended, still reference the qualities of things; queer uses may linger
on these qualities, rendering them all the more lively” (2019, 26). Putting
one’s education in queer theory and philosophy to queer use involves using
it for purposes not intended by the neoliberal corporatized university. Thus
understood, putting philosophy and queer theory to queer use cultivates the
imagination by critically orienting it not only to ideas but also to how those
ideas are materialized, or matter, in the world and how change is imagined
and realized. This practice is not likely to win friends in high places at the
university or state level, but it is a way to resist the normalizing force of
institutionalization of both queer theory and philosophy.
How something (like an area of study or a body) matters is also about
where it matters. To get a better sense of the connection between the how and
the where of queer mattering, we need to first ask where queer theory and
philosophy are presumed to happen.16 Asking this question orients us toward
grappling with the institutionalized lives of these fields. That such questions
might at first seem to take us far afield from queer theory “proper” highlights
the degree to which, despite its beginnings, some forms of queer theory have
ceased to be queer as they’ve been incorporated into the structures of the
university (see Ferguson 2012, 34–35).
While many scholars have critiqued the unexamined whiteness and
able-bodiedness of queer theory’s founding texts, the classed implications of
queer theory’s embeddedness in the academy has remained largely unexam-
ined. One notable exception is Matt Brim’s (2020) distinction between “rich
queer studies” and “poor queer studies,” a distinction that calls for a reckon-
ing with class and labor issues that structure the everyday institutionalized
life of queer studies. Brim writes,
rooms, elevators, bathrooms, and stairways (for those who take the stairs) of
the main conference site, it is common (at least for those of us who are not
such stars that most attendees recognize us in the absence of a placing name
tag) to encounter people one doesn’t know and to whom one is unknown.
When someone doesn’t know you, they look at your name tag. In these
moments, those of us who work at less prestigious institutions also have the
experience of people who look at the name tag and decide in a split second
that you are not someone worthy of their time. In those moments, one is
aware of having been placed low in the ranking of prestige. A determination
is made, and one is placed in the category of people and institutions that
don’t matter. As someone who works at an institution whose name conjures
stereotypes of shoeless, toothless, uneducated hillbillies, I can attest to that
experience of being discounted in another attendee’s rush to network with
others deemed more worthy of their time and attention. I maintain that this is
an experience of how class structure orients business as usual at philosophy
conferences, enabling the quick dismissal of people’s value, the value of their
work, and the deep inequities that differently structure the conditions of labor
of philosophers and other academics.
While it’s perhaps too tempting to assume that these issues are removed
from philosophy itself—the arguments and ideas put forward in presenta-
tions, articles, and books—I contend that the conditions in which the doing
of philosophy is made possible, or thwarted, are importantly connected to
philosophy’s institutional life. Understanding how queer matters in philoso-
phy involves understanding the class structure of the field and how being
a “real” philosopher involves becoming habituated in philosophy. This
habituation involves developing an embodied map of where good philosophy
happens---where good philosophers are and where they aren’t.
The placing that happens also reflects assumptions about where the back-
waters are. In the context of this chapter’s discussion, backwaters are places
where both queer theory and philosophy are perceived not to happen—that
is, as places where nothing that matters happens, places of no consequence.
While Brim’s analysis makes a crucial intervention into the disavowed mate-
rialism of queer studies’ institutional life, he reproduces another uninterro-
gated assumption about where queer life and queer studies happen—that is, in
urban rather than rural areas. CUNY Staten Island (CSI) may be the presumed
backwater of the CUNY system, but its location enables faculty who work
there to live in or near New York City, one of the world’s major cities. Brim
acknowledges the attraction of this location in his career aspirations:
of the job: it was in New York. Recent work in queer rural studies, had I had
the benefit of it then, would not have made a dent in my single-minded queer
career trajectory. It was gay New York or gay San Francisco or bust. So while I
was delighted to be making my way to Staten Island for my campus interview
. . ., I was initially also a bit dumbfounded to find that there was a Queer Studies
job at a school I had never heard of—a meaningful tautology in this book.
(2020, 26–27)
In a book whose main argument calls for a reckoning with the material condi-
tions of the field, including the professional marginalization and erasures that
are occasioned by assumptions about where queer studies happens and where
it doesn’t, this passage struck me as a stunning contradiction that animated
its own erasures. Admittedly, this is probably a result of my own positionality
as a person whose queer career took me from my tiny, one-stoplight home-
town in the rural US South to my current position as a queer philosopher
at a university in another, though larger, rural town in the US South. Staten
Island may be a “forgotten borough” of the city, but it is nonetheless possible
for Brim to imagine a queer career there because it is within a manageable
distance from the city.
All that said, being within a commutable distance from a major city means
that one lives where queer studies is imagined to happen, even if one’s own
institution ranks low in the hierarchy of prestige. What about queer life and
queer careers in imagined “nothing” and “nowhere” places that don’t appear
on the imagined map of queer theory or philosophy, those places one has
never heard of? In a book that proclaims that coming to terms with the elit-
ism that informs class structures of academia is vital, rather than tangential,
to the real work of queer studies as a field, Brim nonetheless reproduces
an urban/rural distinction that is also classed. Moreover, as indicated in the
passage quoted above, he does so in a way that reflects a certain troubling
indifference to work in queer rural studies—the many insights of this work
wouldn’t have (and presumably still doesn’t) change the desired trajectory of
his queer career.
Emma Goldman once famously quipped, “If I can’t dance, I don’t want to be
in your revolution.” Now, few things seem as far removed from the realm of
academic philosophy as dance (or revolution, for that matter). Philosophers,
after all, are presumed to value the mind over the body, which also means
Queer Matters 43
The body is our general means of having a world. Sometimes it restricts itself
to gestures necessary for the conservation of life, and correlatively it posits a
biological world around us. Sometimes, playing upon these first gestures and
passing from their literal to their figurative sense, it brings forth a new core of
signification through them—this is the case of new motor habits, such as dance.
And finally, sometimes the signification aimed at cannot be reached by the
natural means of the body. We must, then, construct an instrument, and the body
projects a cultural world around itself. (144–45)17
For Merleau-Ponty, habits can be broken, creating possibilities for other ways
to be, “altering our existence” (145). As I conclude this chapter, I want to
reflect on how dance has been a site of materializing a queering of philosophy.
The example of dance underscores queering philosophy (and really all
thought) as an embodied practice. Queering philosophy is not only a result
of the sorts of classes queer philosophers teach or the books and articles they
write; it is also a matter of the creativity of queer movement in official and
unofficial spaces demarcated by philosophy as a profession, by the lived
bodyminds of queer philosophers themselves.
Like queerness itself, dance is a social relation. As Fiona Buckland
observes, “improvised social dancing” in queer spaces is a socially, cul-
turally, epistemically, metaphysically, and politically significant aspect of
queer cultures: it builds on and creates shared cultural knowledge, fosters
pleasure, and participates in a collective process of queer world-making
(2002, 2). Queer dance is, she asserts, an “embodiment of experience, iden-
tity, and community” (2). Rather than eliminate tensions “not only between
constituents of lifeworlds, but between the real, imaginary, past, present and
future [bodyminds] of each participant,” queer dance embodies them (9). As
Buckland puts it, queer dance is an embodied process of creating spaces in a
heteronormative society in which “[m]any people who identify as queer are
made worldless” (3). Careful not to overly romanticize queer clubs, spaces
that have also been sites of exclusions (for example racism and ableism),
Buckland contends that the spaces created through queer dance are spaces to
be critiqued as well as sites from which to critique heteronormative conven-
tions (3). As such, spaces created by queer dance have epistemic significance
in ways that are similar to the conception of standpoint in feminist standpoint
44 Chapter 1
epistemology, or spaces to know and from which to know (Code 2006, 40).
Furthermore, the ethical, epistemic, world-making capacity of queer dance
resonates with María Lugones’s (1987) conception of the crucial role of play-
fulness in non-colonizing, resistant world-traveling. For Lugones, playfulness
is an ethical attitude of communication and relationship across differences
and is an indispensable part of cultivating loving rather than arrogant percep-
tion18 and interaction with others. Playfulness, as Lugones defines it, connotes
not so much fun as it does the absence of a plan or agenda coupled with a
mutual openness toward surprise, toward the other, and the decentering of the
self. Building on Lugones’s conception of playfulness, I suggest that through
playful, improvised dance, queers collectively create spaces for themselves
and ways of knowing and being otherwise.
Naming dance as a practice of queering philosophy helps to explain why
dance is so frequently mentioned in queer academic writing, including queer
philosophical articles and books (see, for example, McWhorter 1999 and
Schalk 2013). Furthermore, so many queer, feminist, and crip conferences
feature a dance, and queer dancing has been a site of critical intervention in
mainstream conferences such as the American Philosophical Association.
When I think about academic conferences that I’ve attended over the years, I
think about how many of them have featured a dance on the last night. Even
when a dance has not been part of the conference program, there has been a
history of feminists and queers creating them. Whether in someone’s home,
at the conference hotel, or out on the town, people made time to dance. For
example, for many years a group of friends and I would go dancing in queer
clubs on the last night of the APA. After spending a few days immersed in
the sea of heteronormativity and stale hotel air, as well as the strange and
stressful process of interviews where one had to prove that one’s work in
feminist and queer theory was really philosophical, dancing was joyful. Much
more than letting off steam at the end of a conference, queer dancing in aca-
demic philosophy conferences builds networks, generates ideas, and makes
a space for queer being and knowing in a disciplinary mainstream that has
steadfastly ignored and excluded queer perspectives and people. In philoso-
phy, dance has been a practice of queer world-making in which the “others”
of philosophy create a resistant relationality that opens the possibility of a
transformed field. Queer dancing makes a space for queerness. Often denied
mainstream philosophical recognition and jobs in philosophy departments,
improvisational movements on the dance floor create spaces of queer joy and
survival and open the possibility of another way of being a philosopher and
doing philosophy.
As a practice of queering philosophy, dance is an embodied mode of
disidentifying with institutionalized philosophy. In his ground-breaking
text, Disidentifications: Queers of Color and the Performance of Politics,
Queer Matters 45
NOTES
society) and negatively affect the professional experiences of people from oppressed
groups, or to use Kristi Dotson’s phrase, philosophy’s “diverse practitioners” (see, for
example, Dotson 2011a; Dotson 2012; Alcoff 2013; Saul 2013; Zurn 2016). In fact,
queering philosophy, as I discuss it in this book, is a project in solidarity with femi-
nist philosophy, trans philosophy, philosophy of race, and philosophy of disability.
As I suggest in this chapter, the reasons for the lack of philosophical legitimization
for something called queer philosophy is twofold: (1) a consequence of philosophy’s
heteronormativity and the straight habits that sustain and reproduce it and (2) the
meaning of queer and queering itself. Philosophy’s heteronormativity makes the field
less than hospitable for philosophers who deviate from its norms. That said, queering
philosophy is a practice of un-disciplining and, thus, is situated outside and between
disciplines. Increasingly, many queer theorists critique queer theory’s institutionaliza-
tion (in other disciplines, it must be said) as rendering the field less, if at all, queer
(see Eng, Halberstam, and Muñoz 2005; Eng and Puar 2020).
5. At present, I can think of only one philosophy department that regularly offers
a queer philosophy course. Sadly, it’s not my department. While in the past I have
offered a queer philosophy course, it was a “special topics” course. When queer the-
ory or theorists are taught in philosophy departments, it is most likely in the context
of other courses in marginalized subfields like feminist philosophy.
6. Some may think that queer theory is now at that stage—having been incorpo-
rated as part of US academic institutions, it is no longer a field that does the political
work it needs to do. Such a view assumes that queer theory is already here, though as I
discuss in this chapter, that’s not the case in institutionalized philosophy. Queer theory
has animated its own exclusions, which need to be critiqued and reckoned with. At the
same time, I believe the terms queer and queering still have important political work
to do. As Petrus Lui contends, queer theory has yet to reckon with its own exclusions
and to understand that reckoning as a part of the political work of queerness. For Liu,
the project of queer theory grappling with its own “constitutive outside” of “unknow-
able others” is part of intersectional, queer materialist analysis, rather than a negation
of the political efficacy of queer critique (2020, 35).
7. In What’s the Use? On the Uses of Use, Sara Ahmed offers many provocative
definitions of queer use, including “to bring to the front what ordinarily recedes into
the background” (2019, 198); using “something for a purpose that is ‘very different’
from that which was ‘originally intended’” (199); and “the work you have to do to
be” (223). While queer use can, over time, lessen the “queer potential” of that which
is put to queer use (44), queer use also identifies potential in what is deemed “use-
less” (218). That said, it’s important to avoid romanticizing the useless. An uncritical
celebration of it (which is not what Ahmed defends) can reflect a privilege that can
afford being deemed useless. Uselessness won’t pay the rent, for example, but criti-
cally understood, a queer use that finds possibility in what has been deemed useless
can be transformative and create spaces for another way to be, to not only survive
but to flourish. Thus, understood queer use is not useless; it puts to otherwise-use
otherwise-valuing that which has been designated as without value.
8. I use exile to highlight the political nature of these departures within institutional
philosophy. Certainly, some chose to leave philosophy for other academic institutional
48 Chapter 1
Queer Knowing
51
52 Chapter 2
these two forms of power. Given the significance of this insight for queer
theory, I’ll quote Foucault at length:
[S]ex . . . was at the pivot of the two axes along which developed the entire
political technology of life. . . . Sex was a means of access both to the life of the
body and the life of the species. It was employed as a standard for the disciplines
and as a basis for regulations. This is why in the nineteenth century sexuality
was sought out in the smallest details of individual existences; it was tracked
down in behavior, pursued in dreams; it was suspected of underlying the least
follies, it was traced back into the earliest years of childhood; it became the
stamp of individuality—at the same time what enabled one to analyze the latter
and what made it possible to analyze it. . . . Spread out from one pole to the other
of this technology of sex was a whole series of different tactics that combined in
varying proportions the objective of disciplining the body and that of regulating
populations. (1990, 145–46)
culture, political, and economic life. It also gave rise to wide-ranging systems
of surveillance designed to ascertain, or make known, the secret of sex lurk-
ing behind the omnipresent closet door. While these systems of surveillance
certainly detect that which is considered normal (cis-heterosexuality), they
are especially focused on knowing that which outlines and gives meaning to
the normal: the abnormal, in this case gendered and sexual deviation from
that which is deemed normal. It is not only that the so-called abnormal must
be made visible and known; every individual must be made to know how they
are situated on the scale of the abnormal and normal. Moreover, this knowl-
edge must take the form of a process of self-discovery—a coming to know
one’s inner truth or true nature.
This chapter focuses on what it means to think of queering as an epistemic
practice. It considers areas of resonance between queer theory and contribu-
tions to epistemology in feminist philosophy and philosophy of race. My
consideration of these issues will focus on the following themes: (1) what it
means to queerly know the self, (2) the relationship between queer knowing
and failure to know, (3) the question of a queer standpoint, (4) queer igno-
rance, (5) institutionalized philosophy’s failure to know itself, (6) the possi-
bility of queer epistemic resistance, and (7) queering philosophy as a practice
of knowing and unknowing philosophy.
SELF-KNOWLEDGE
by hanging our hats on the peg that seems to fit best at least in the moment,
the question never really goes away. The dwelling in the question that never
really goes away, the aspects of life and self that aren’t completely contained
in placeholder categories meant to pinpoint the self (like the pin that sticks
the butterfly to the board) is the no-place/between-place of queer existence.
To be queer is to be in question and, as Alison Kafer asserts about a queer/
crip conception of disability, to understand queerness “as a site of questions
rather than firm definitions” (Kafer 2013, 11, 16; see also Butler 1993, 228).
What does it mean to know that which can’t be fully known, that which tends
to ooze from the seams of the social categories by which we are made to
know our selves?
Even though it is felt more acutely by some than others and at some times
and in some places more so than others, the categories by which we are
known and compelled to know ourselves—gay, lesbian, man, woman, trans,
butch, femme, and so on—are never the whole story. A tenet of queer theory
is that there is always something that doesn’t quite fit, something that escapes
(Butler 1993, 226). That something is a site of possibility, a possibility of
being more, a possibility of being otherwise. Even so, to be known, to trans-
late one’s being-in-the-world to others and even oneself involves either mak-
ing use of available social categories or generating new ones. But, make no
mistake, no matter how many categories, they are never sufficient for captur-
ing the complex multiplicity of life, of living in the world with others. So, the
point for queer theory isn’t to generate more accurate categories. Accuracy
pertains to how well they enable one to understand oneself in relation to oth-
ers in a particular time and place. Instead, the point is that there is nothing
natural and inevitable about how we understand ourselves. Gender and sexual
categories are contingent and, thus, not inevitable, invariable facts of our
being. Given this, queering as an epistemic project is not oriented toward the
capital “T” Truth; it is oriented toward the limitations of our knowledge, that
which is outside the realm of knowability but nonetheless crucial for queer
lives, that which is “at the limits of available ontologies, available schemes
of intelligibility” (224).
Moments of ambiguity are queer moments, moments that characterize
what it means to be situated as and know oneself as queer. For Judith Butler,
queer reflects and enacts a critical orientation rather than a constellation of
acts, desires, and embodiments that solidify a queer identity (226–30). One
criticism of queer theory is that it fails to grapple with the realities of our
social identities, the difference identity makes. I want to suggest that queer
theory’s critique of identity is not a rejection of identity or of its significance
in our lives. As evidence, consider Butler’s assertion:
Queer Knowing 55
Butler’s account of identity as performative includes the use of queer and any
other existing or future sexual and gender identity categories. As social cat-
egories, gender and sexual identity are established in scenes of social recogni-
tion (227). The sense in which being hailed as a particular gender or sexuality
is a site of trouble rather than comfort, affirmation, and social belonging is a
critically queer affect. Following Mariana Ortega (2016), claiming identity,
for queers, is a home-tactic, a way of making do with available categories—
new and old—while navigating their limitations. For these reasons, queer, as
queer theorists understand the term, is critically related to but not reducible
to terms that signify non-heterosexual and non-cisgender identity. This non-
reducibility of queer to being a gender or sexual minority is reflected in terms
like queer lesbian or queer heterosexual to signal something about one’s
relationship to dominant framings and normalizing exclusions of those terms.
Thus, the queer in queer epistemology is best understood as a critical
positionality rather than a substantive, totalizing, fixed identity. As a way
of knowing, queering persistently troubles and is troubled by that which is
not only marginal to but also rendered invisible by the categories by which
we make sense of ourselves, our relationships with others, and the world.
Queer knowing is knowing from a place of non-or not-quite belonging, a
positionality attuned to erasures and violence that sustain the borders that
determine belonging to a gender, a sexuality, a race, a nation, a species, and
so on. As such, queer knowing is located in silences, the biting of the tongue.
Biting of the tongue is often a form of self-censoring to preserve a sense of
togetherness of a group. In such instances, biting one’s tongue is a form of
epistemic oppression that Kristie Dotson (2011b) calls testimonial smother-
ing. In testimonial smothering, one judges an audience as not prepared for
one’s testimony and, thus, as likely to condemn or challenge one in some way.
In these cases, it’s an act of self-preservation, survival, and radical self-care1
to say nothing. Gloria Anzaldúa (1987) describes another form of epistemic
silencing that attempts to discipline/tame what one says as a way of keeping
56 Chapter 2
The academy would begin to put, keep in reserve, and save minoritized subjects
and knowledges in an archival fashion, that is, by devising ways to make those
subjects and knowledges respect power and its “laws.” Put differently, the ethnic
and women’s studies movements applied pressures on the archival conventions
of the academy in an effort to stretch those conventions so that previously
excluded subjects might enjoy membership. But it also meant that those sub-
jects would fall under new and revised laws . . .. The interdisciplines were an
ensemble of institutions and techniques that offered positivities to populations
and constituencies that had been denied institutional claims to agency. Hence
with the interdisciplines connoted a new form of biopower organized around the
affirmation, recognition, and legitimacy of minoritized life. To offset their pos-
sibility for future ruptures, power made legitimacy and recognition into grand
enticements. (13)
I have quoted Ferguson at length because, while his specific focus is the intro-
duction of new areas of study in US universities in response to pressure from
student groups in the 1960s and 1970s, the mode of biopower he describes
is illustrative of how we might understand the incorporation of queer theory
into US universities in the 1990s and beyond.
There are important differences, of course. As many have pointed out,
queer theory was initiated from within academy in contrast to other areas like
race and ethnic studies programs and women’s, gender, and sexuality studies
programs. For one thing, the field was created by scholars who were already
part of the university, even if marginalized due to their gender and/or sexual-
ity. The demand for queer theory programs and courses didn’t come from
outside the university; queer theory was created by academics and academic
committees. More precisely, as Matt Brim (2020) argues, it is epistemically
significant for the field that it emerged from within wealthy US universities.
The theorists who would later be considered founding figures had under-
graduate and graduate degrees from elite academic institutions (like Yale
University). Their Ivy League pedigrees paved the way for employment at
institutions with the kind of teaching loads, service expectations, and research
support that supported the writing of books. All of this gave queer theory an
inroad (at least in certain disciplines) that quickened its academic recognition
and legitimacy.7
Nonetheless, Ferguson’s point is that incorporation disciplines minoritized
subjects and fields within the university. In becoming a recognized disci-
pline, a formerly marginalized area becomes an exclusionary force. As such,
academic recognition of fields is another scene of respectability politics mas-
querading as transformative, revolutionary force. Legitimation, recognition,
62 Chapter 2
the site for emergence of new critically queer subjects and for thinking more
expansively about queerness (2020, 2). These critiques have exposed queer
theory’s failure to know itself queerly. In her critique of the racism of white
feminism, Barbara Smith argued that any feminism that didn’t aim to trans-
form racism, heterosexism and homophobia, ableism, ageism, and classism as
well as sexism was “not feminism, but merely female self-aggrandizement”
(1980/2014, 134). Smith also critiques queer theory and politics for failure
to understand the importance of anti-racism and the analysis of race to their
work (1993/2014, 180–81; 1997/2014). Smith is critiquing, at least in part, a
white and class-privileged self-deception that has shaped mainstream femi-
nist and queer theories and politics.
Queers of color have long critiqued the unexamined whiteness and
Euro-American centeredness of mainstream queer theory’s epistemic frame
through which is has theorized queerness. Despite its project of critiqu-
ing rather than assuming identity, mainstream queer theory has tended to
privilege a US-based, white Anglo subject. Queer studies scholars such as
Roderick Ferguson (2004), E. Patrick Johnson (2001), José Muñoz (1999),
and Keguro Macharia (2016) critique the exclusionary normativity of queer
theory’s queer subject. Muñoz, Johnson, and Ferguson propose a critical
strategy of disidentification that names and thinks from experiences of criti-
cal negotiation of white-centered conceptions and practices of queer identity
and queer community, asking whose ways of being and knowing the world
are reflected in the term queer in mainstream queer studies. Disidentification
is not a rejection of identity or identification with queerness (or any other
category). Rather, to disidentify is to think with and against identity (Muñoz
1999, 11–12; Johnson 2001, 12).
Exclusions animated by the mainstream of queer studies also highlight the
problem of translation, specifically the failure of queer to translate and thus
resonate in non-white, non-Anglo communities within and outside the Global
North. For example, Johnson uses “quare” rather than queer to name an epis-
temic position shaped by and accountable to Black “quare” experiences of
marginalization, including within the field of queer theory. And Macharia cri-
tiques the predominantly Western onto-epistemological perspective embed-
ded within the word queer itself, a perspective that de-racinates him as an
Africa-based queer studies scholar because it bespeaks a perspective that
doesn’t exist in his “present geography” (2016, 183). Macharia writes, “From
Nairobi, even the deracinating power of ‘black queer’ seems inaccessible, and
I must face other illegibilities” (184). As Macharia points out, the term queer,
and thus queer studies, fails to translate across geographies. This raises the
question of how to do queer studies in a way that troubles and resists queer
exceptionalism. One way is to acknowledge the limitations of the term itself,
a limitation that is part of its critical approach to identity. This approach
64 Chapter 2
through a change in one’s own vocabulary, one’s sense of oneself, one’s way of
living, in the extension of one’s collective memory, through developing forms of
communication that signal disruption of the reduction attempted by the oppres-
sor. Complex communication is creative. In complex communication we create
and cement relational identities, meanings that did not precede the encounter,
ways of life that transcend nationalisms, root identities, and other simplifica-
tions of our imaginations. (84)
Knowing with and alongside others involves remaining open to what José
Medina (2013) calls epistemic friction. Medina defines epistemic friction as
the lack of epistemically arrogant certainty that comes from “hold[ing] differ-
ent perspectives simultaneously so that they can be compared and contrasted,
corrected by each other, and combined when possible” (78). It would be a
mistake to interpret Medina’s notion of epistemic friction as another iteration
of the liberal assertion that truth will inevitably rise to the top when all views
are aired. In the era of “fake news,” this assertion is unfounded and naïve. It
ignores the contexts of oppression and privilege that over-value assertions of
privileged knowers and under-value assertions of marginalized knowers. It is
precisely this cauldron of inequality and domination that Medina strives to
address by carving out the meaning and possibility of epistemic resistance.
The seeking out of epistemic friction, he argues, is a key component to
epistemic resistance, to knowing well by knowing differently in contexts of
oppression. The queerness of epistemic friction is animated by its suspension
of epistemic certainty that allows openness to other ways of being and know-
ing. An openness to or even desire for epistemic friction does not render the
knower an epistemic Pac-Man who greedily accumulates all bits of knowl-
edge to their own ends. Instead, epistemic friction deeply unsettles the cer-
tainty of the knower in ways that enable creative and resistant knowing-with
and alongside others that is necessary for epistemic resistance. Epistemic
friction opens access to alternative imaginaries without which resistance and
the realization of an otherwise is impossible (78, 256–57).
Medina’s concept of epistemic friction resonates with María Lugones’s
project of knowing multiply (261–66). Reading Medina with María Lugones’s
project of knowing multiply, the multiplicity of perspectives sustained
through epistemic friction aren’t simply collections of claims or individual
nuggets of wisdom. Certainly, knowledge claims are important, but equally
important is the multiplicity of positions from which one knows, including
the multiple perspectives of the multiple self that, held in epistemic fric-
tion, constitute an ontological and epistemic ambiguity that resists unifica-
tion (Lugones 2003, 74, 123–25; Medina 2013, 262–63). Epistemic friction
informs queer knowledge of self and others. At the level of self-knowledge,
epistemic friction holds in tension how one is known by others, the self one
is in other worlds, and one’s own sense of self, understanding that one is all
those things, even the self one doesn’t want to be. Epistemic friction creates
ambiguity that Lugones describes as “resisting classification” (2003, 125).
Medina describes these insights as important for queer movements not only
Queer Knowing 69
because they open a path for solidarity between and among oppressed groups,
but also because they demonstrate the practical, action-oriented, transforma-
tive effects of a critical relation to identity categories at the heart of queer-
ness (2013, 264). After all, the self and the world cannot become otherwise
unless we know otherwise, and this otherwise-knowing involves epistemic
resistance of practices of purity and domination.
For Medina, epistemic friction is crucial for the cultivation of “kaleido-
scopic consciousness.” Medina defines “kaleidoscopic consciousness” as
“forever open to being expanded” and attuned to “more ways of experiencing
the world than those considered” (200). Kaleidoscopic consciousness is not
access to all perspectives and worlds. Not only is such a position impossible
for any single knower; it would also be a practice of epistemic expansive-
ness,11 a privileged knower’s assumption of absolute comprehension of expe-
riences and knowledge, in other words, an assumption that the knowledge and
experience of others can be rendered completely transparent to the privileged
knower, that nothing worth knowing can elude their powers of comprehen-
sion. As a queer epistemic orientation, kaleidoscopic consciousness is a sen-
sitivity to what one doesn’t and perhaps can never know.12
A kaleidoscopic perspective knows genealogically, which is to say with a
commitment to understanding how the self is situated in the world with past
and present others and the role of epistemic hierarchies in distilling a single
truth from the cacophony of multiplicity in a particular context (see Allen
2017). Queer knowing’s genealogical, kaleidoscopic attentiveness to the rela-
tions of power enacted through the will to a unifying truth offers a conception
of truth more in line with the messiness and complexity of the world. Lynne
Huffer characterizes this attentiveness as a strange eros of thinking-feeling
that is inclined toward that which is something “other than the wholeness of
a philosophical system extending from Plato into its completion in the pres-
ent” (2020, 53). Queer kaleidoscopic knowing is a thinking-feeling at the
edges of a subjectivity, an orientation toward that which remains outside the
grasp of biopolitical categories that delimit subjectivity in the present (53).
For Huffer, the thinking-feeling of strange eros is a border-thinking/feeling
that she identifies as queerly animated in Foucault’s genealogical approach.
There is a common theme in Lugones’s, Medina’s, and Huffer’s critiques of
dominant conceptions of reason and knowledge, a queer epistemic thread in
their analyses of power/knowledge. According to Huffer, border-thinking at
the edge between the philosophical and nonphilosophical “maintain[s] the
difference between them without trying to persuade one into becoming the
other” (53). A queer13 epistemic orientation sustains attention on that which
another frame renders incomprehensible, on that which remains untranslat-
able. Perhaps, from this perspective, a queer philosophy is oxymoronic to the
70 Chapter 2
How does queering philosophy know philosophy? Grappling with this ques-
tion requires thinking about the meaning of genealogy as a queer method.
As a genealogical sensibility honed at the edges between categories and
worlds, queer knowing is sensitive to the failure of social categories (like
the categories of gender and sexuality) to capture the truth about us, as well
as the failure of Western conceptions of truth as universal and timeless. In
looking toward the past, queer knowing attends to the relations of power that
give rise to and support the prevailing episteme and the various subjugated
knowledges that are rendered illegible or erased by it.
In striving to pay attention to that which is silent or erased in the archive,
queer knowing underscores that how we know the past and present and their
relationship could be otherwise; it attempts to listen to the silences, absences,
the unexplained and perhaps unexplainable. That said, it would be a mistake
to conclude from this that a genealogical sensibility enables one to have a bet-
ter, more objective grasp on the past or present, or even a clear picture of an
alternative. Genealogical critique unsettles dominant accounts by highlight-
ing their contingency, a contingency that points toward the possibility of an
alternative, even if it does not and cannot offer a complete accounting of that
alternative. Instead, a genealogical critique reveals and works the cracks in
dominant discourse. As Ladelle McWhorter puts it, “A genealogy functions
as a critique of the dominant view, not merely as a supplement or a thought-
provoking alternative. Genealogy is a critical redescription of a dominant
description” (1999, 43).
Given that queer knowing is an undisciplined knowing, what are the
implications for a queer knowing of institutionalized philosophy? If queering
philosophy, as an epistemic practice, is situated at the edges of philosophy
and is in excess of or outside philosophy, its knowing is also an unknowing of
philosophy to the extent that it critiques institutionalized philosophy’s distinc-
tion between the philosophical and the nonphilosophical. As such, queering
philosophy opens the possibility of an otherwise-philosophy. The otherwise,
according to Ashon Crawley, resists the proclamation of the new—as in a
new area of philosophy (or theology, for Crawley). Thus, rather than herald
something new, as in a new approach, the otherwise indicates how “alterna-
tive modes, alternative strategies, alternative ways of life already exist, and
indeed are already violently acted upon in order to produce coherence of the
Queer Knowing 71
NOTES
1. See chapter 5 for more about radical care (including self-care) as a form of queer
ethics.
2. For Jack Halberstam’s discussion of cripistemology as failure to know, see his
contribution to the Journal of Literary and Cultural Disability Studies virtual round-
table on cripistemology (in McRuer and Johnson 2014).
3. This is not to suggest that all queers have the same experiences and, thus, know
the same things. Again, queer knowing is not grounded in shared identity as much as
it is grounded in shared relationship to practices of normalization. That shared rela-
tionship is a feeling of misfitting. Rosemarie Garland-Thomson describes misfitting
as “an incongruent relationship between two things: a square peg in a round hole”
(2011, 592–93). This experience of misfitting (rather than misfitting in the same
72 Chapter 2
ways and places, etc.) can form at least part of the basis of cross-movement solidar-
ity between oppressed groups (see, for example, Kafer 2013 on the coalitional crip,
queer, trans, and feminist politics of bathroom revolutionaries).
4. See David Eng and Jasbir Puar (2020) on queer theory’s contribution of “subject-
less critique.”
5. See Jack Halberstam, The Queer Art of Failure (2011). Halberstam writes, “[F]
ailure allows us to escape the punishing norms that discipline behavior and manage
human development with the goal of delivering us from unruly childhoods to orderly
and predictable adulthoods. Failure preserves some of the wondrous anarchy of
childhood and disturbs the supposedly clean boundaries between adults and children,
winners and losers. And while failure certainly comes accompanied by a host of
negative affects, such as disappointment, disillusionment, and despair, it also provides
the opportunity to use these negative affects to poke holes in the toxic positivity of
contemporary life” (3). Failure, Halberstam contends, finds space for possibility in
“not succeeding” in the embodiment of prevailing gender norms (4). There is much
possibility in Halberstam’s conception of failure in this text, possibility that, I suggest,
is occluded in some of his later characterizations of failure, for example his discussion
of cripistemology as a failure to know (see McRuer and Johnson 2014). In my view,
queer failure is not a failure to know but instead the possibility of otherwise-knowing
grounded in otherwise-being.
6. For more about the similarities and differences between feminist standpoint
theory and queer epistemology, see my essay, “Queer Epistemology and Epistemic
Injustice” (2017a).
7. This is not to suggest that the biopolitical processes of academic incorporation
that Ferguson analyzes did and do not target queer theory. Part of Ferguson’s argu-
ment about the place of minoritized subjects and fields in the academy is that the
biopolitical forces that discipline are fungible. Queer theory and theorists stood on
the shoulders of feminist, LGBT, and race/ethnic studies programs, but its inclusion
did not herald the end of discrimination against gender and sexual minorities in the
university, no more than feminist studies and race/ethnic studies programs heralded
the end of the academy’s sexism and racism. Instead, power morphed and concealed
itself through circumscribed forms of visibility.
8. I am drawing on Lugones’s (1987) use of multiple worlds—multiple worlds of
sense—dominant and marginalized worlds that must be negotiated by those who are
oppressed as a matter of survival. This negotiation involves understanding how one
is known by privileged knowers in dominant worlds.
9. While many have situated Lugones’s work as part of women of color femi-
nisms, specifically Latina feminisms, and Lugones herself never, as far as I’m aware,
referred to her work as part of queer theory, her work makes important contributions
to queer feminist of color (and even queer crip feminist of color) critique. Lugones
also didn’t situate her work as part of disability or crip studies, but her discussions
of pain and the fractured locus produced by the colonial wound are sites where her
analysis brings together race, disability, gender, and sexuality in ways that resonate
with the consistent effort throughout her work to think from the site of multiplicity
and the multiple oppressions in which we are situated. In reclaiming Lugones as a key
Queer Knowing 73
figure in queer crip feminist of color theory, I build on the work of others who have
reclaimed Audre Lorde and Gloría Anzaldúa as key figures in a queer crip feminist of
color tradition (see, for example, McRuer 2006 and Schalk and Kim 2020).
10. For more on purity politics, see Shotwell 2016 and Lugones 2003.
11. Here I build on Shannon Sullivan’s (2006) concept of ontological expansive-
ness that is a habit of white privilege. As ontologically expansive, white people
assume access to all space—including actual physical spaces and the time/space
allotted for conversation.
12. Importantly, a queer attunement to what is unknown and perhaps unknowable
is not a performance of Cartesian doubt that suspends certainty in all beliefs only
to arrive at the one thing that is clearly and distinctly true (i.e., one’s existence as a
thinking thing).
13. Huffer’s concept of strange eros outlines a queer ontological, epistemological,
ethical, and poetic practice that cannot be reduced to a renunciation of normativity.
Instead, strange eros points to queer disturbances of conditions for intelligibility,
disturbances that occasion “experiments in living” that undo the self and “the philo-
sophical ideal of coherence and unity” (2020, 7, 14). The result of such experiments
in living is neither truth nor lie, but something more.
Chapter 3
I’ve heard of many people who claim they’d as soon their children were
dead as gay. What it took me a long time to believe is that these people
were saying no more than the truth.
—Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick, “Queer and Now”
To oppose violence is to understand that violence does not always take the
form of the blow; the institutional forms through which it operates compel
us to ask: Whose life appears as a life, and whose loss would register as a
loss? How does that demographic imaginary function in ethics, in policy,
and in politics? If we operate within the horizon in which violence cannot
be identified, where lives vanish from the realm of the living before they
are killed, we will not be able to think, to know, or to act in ways that
understand the claim of relational obligations within the global sphere.
—Judith Butler, The Force of Non-Violence
While it may seem at first glance that the rarefied pages of mainstream
Western philosophy have nothing to do with political violence (or, put differ-
ently, that thoughts from the armchair have little to do with violence in the
streets), thinking about conventional Western philosophy from the perspec-
tive of a queer bio/necropolitics raises questions about complicity between
philosophy’s understanding of itself and structures of violence. Violence, as
Butler reminds us, takes many forms, from the use of physical force to the
bio/necropolitical force of ideas that structure a political imaginary (2020,
80 Chapter 3
338). In this section, I consider the political imaginary that structures insti-
tutionalized philosophy as a field. Within this imaginary, whole populations
and geographical regions are deemed either full of philosophical potential
or excluded as sources of philosophy whether in the past, present, or future
(see, for example, Hall 2021). As Uma Narayan writes about the role of care
in colonial discourse, “While I do not endorse reducing any moral theory
to its ideological uses, I would argue that we must attend to the ideological
functions served by various . . . theories. Pervasive structural relationships of
power and powerlessness between groups, such as those between colonizer
and the colonized, tend to foster ideological justifications for the maintenance
of such relationships” (1995, 136). This means that the contexts of structural
violence in which Western philosophy’s social, political, and ethical theories
have been developed affects both their content and how they circulate in the
world in ways that rationalize structures of bio/necropolitical violence. As
Narayan emphasizes, the rights-bearing agent of Western political theory was
also the agent of colonization (136). A queer critique of Western philoso-
phy’s complicity with bio/necropolitics begins with questioning its framing
assumptions about the meaning of life and death and their relationship.
Through discussion of Socrates’s trial and death, students in introductory
philosophy classes are presented with an image of philosophy as the disci-
pline that both questions all dogmas and is concerned with wisdom rather
than opinion and, despite its critical questioning, remains loyal to the state
whose deified laws are understood abstractly as separate from the people who
make and enforce them. As Socrates argues, one’s obedience to these laws is
grounded in the fact that the state has nurtured and supported one since birth
by such acts as legitimating the marriage of one’s parents, nurturing one since
birth, and providing for one’s education (Plato 1961b, 35–36). It is perhaps
an understatement to say that such pious proclamations ring hollow for mem-
bers of marginalized populations who have been targeted by various forms of
state-sanctioned neglect and violence. Consider Socrates’s account of what
the Laws would say in response to those who would break them:
Come now, what charge do you bring against us and the state, that you are try-
ing to destroy us? Did we not give you life in the first place? Was it not through
us that your father married your mother and begot you? Tell us, have you any
complaint against those of us laws that deal with marriage? . . . [H]ave you any
against the laws which deal with children’s upbringing and education, such as
you had yourself? Are you not grateful to those of us laws which were insti-
tuted for this end, for requiring your father to give you a cultural and physical
education? . . . [D]o you imagine that what is right for us is equally right for
you, and that whatever we try to do to you, you are justified in retaliating? You
did not have equality of rights with your father, or your employer—supposing
Power, Life, and Death 81
that you had one—to enable you to retaliate. You were not allowed to answer
back when you were scolded or to hit back when you were beaten, or to do a
great many things of the same kind. Do you expect to have such license against
your country and its laws that if we try to put you to death in the belief that it
is right to do so, you on your part will try your hardest to destroy your country
and us its laws in return? . . . Do you realize that you are even more bound to
respect and placate the anger of your country than your father’s anger? That if
you cannot persuade your country you must do whatever it orders, and patiently
submit to punishment that it imposes, whether it be flogging or imprisonment?
(Plato 1961b, 3–36)
Who but the most privileged could read these words and conclude that the
benefits they received from the cis-heteropatriarchal family and the white
supremacist, cis-heteronormative, ableist, capitalist state justifies whatever
the state determines should be done with them, including their death? Who
but the most privileged could read this passage and conclude that, yes indeed,
the many benefits and protections they’ve received from the family and state
justifies their position as the state’s “child and servant,” and that the only just
response to this whole state of affairs is one’s “gratitude” (36)? This chilling
passage underscores that it’s not just, as Marx famously put it, that “philoso-
phers have only interpreted the world,” but “the point is to change it.” It’s that
the project of changing the world is written out from the start in mainstream
philosophy’s imaginary.
Building on Charles Mills’s description of white ignorance in The Racial
Contract, passages like Socrates’s imagined conversation with the Laws of
the state reveal that, as with white ignorance, mainstream Western philosophy
is unable to understand both the nature of the field its foundational fictions
have produced and reproduced, as well as the world it aims to understand. As
a result, mainstream Western philosophy still fancies itself a gadfly, while it
continues to marginalize and exclude the gadflies in its midst (e.g., feminist,
queer, and trans philosophers, philosophers of race, Latinx philosophers,
Indigenous philosophers, and philosophers of disability). As Mills asserts
about Western philosophy’s fiction of the social contract that has been used
to argue that the origin of the state maximizes the freedom and secures the
protection of all citizens, Socrates’s agreement with the Laws is “not worth
the paper it was never written on” (1997).
Another framing assumption at the heart of institutionalized philosophy’s
social and political imaginary concerns whose life counts as a life and the
relationship between life and death. To say that the unexamined life is not
worth living presumes that it is only the presence or absence of individual
philosophical questioning that distinguishes between a frivolous and a worth-
while, purposeful life. Framed in this way, mainstream Western philosophy
82 Chapter 3
assumes as its subject one whose life already counts as a life in dominant
imaginaries and worlds. This is one way to understand mainstream Western
philosophy—not as a collection of figures and their ideas, but as a way of life
or practice of living that reflects and supports privileged being in the world.9
The enduring legacy of violence against sexual and gender minorities has
also left a too-often unacknowledged mark on the profession of philosophy.
For example, rejection and violence in families of origin, school, the work-
place, and in public spaces are among the many forces that keep trans people
out of the university in general (Zurn 2016, n.p.).10 For trans academics, Perry
Zurn writes, “the university is quite often a place of isolation, alienation, pre-
carity, and silence” (2016, n.p.). These grim, devastating realities of power,
life, and death for queer and trans people underscore the continued relevance
of Eve Sedgwick’s observation nearly thirty years ago: the survival of
LGBTQ philosophers—let alone the completion of high school, undergradu-
ate, and graduate school, and a job in philosophy—is a miracle (Sedgwick
1993; Zurn 2016). While we may all sit together in classrooms and at con-
ferences, our being in those spaces, what queer and trans people have done
and continue to do to be there, is very different. Miracles, all of us, indeed.
Nonetheless, it’s important to emphasize that miracles alone do not and will
not ensure trans and queer survival, let alone flourishing. Only the creation
of infrastructures to support queer and trans lives and the lives of all from
other groups underrepresented in philosophy will do that. For philosophy,
this entails a reckoning with its past and an understanding that the enduring
legacies of anti-queer, anti-trans, settler colonial, imperialist, ableist, capital-
ist, and racist violence aren’t separate from institutionalized philosophy but,
instead, are endemic to it.
In his insightful book on the enduring legacy of McCarthyism11 in the dis-
tinction between “analytic” and “continental” philosophy in US philosophy
departments, John McCumber (2001) writes about US philosophy’s time
spent “in the ditch” and imagines its future out of it. McCumber’s use of the
ditch as a metaphor for McCarthy-era conceptions of “real” philosophy draws
from yet another story often told in philosophy classrooms. As the story goes,
in his search for timeless, universal truth, Thales of Miletus looked up in
order to focus on the stars rather than the ground and at his feet while walk-
ing and, as a result, fell into a ditch. Upon witnessing his fall, an old woman
wondered how Thales could understand the heavens if he knew nothing of
the ground beneath his feet (xv). For McCumber, the ditch is a metaphor for
political ideologies that influence and ultimately derail philosophy’s pursuit
of the truth. Even though McCumber himself does not subscribe to a notion of
truth as abstract and universal, his conception of a lower-case “t” truth is pre-
mised on an understanding of the work of philosophy as pursuing those truths
and as best able to do so when it is able to dust itself off and get out of the
Power, Life, and Death 83
The ditch ought not be our end. Yet I stay in the place of violence, in the muddy
abjection of the drainage ditch, precisely because it offers no recuperation, no
rescue beyond decomposition. If we start here with an understanding that escape
is not possible and that against the dreams of liberal democracy there may be no
outside to violence, how might we also articulate a kind of near life that feels
in the ontological capture that life might still be lived, otherwise? (2011, 15)
The ditch, Stanley emphasizes, shouldn’t exist, but it is only race, class, and
gender privilege that might allow some queers to believe not only that they
are or can get out of it but that they can also forget it. While not all queers
have “the same relation to violence” (2), understanding queerness requires
thinking from the significance of what Stanley calls the “archive of queer
death” (18). The archive of queer death of which Stanley speaks refers to anti-
queer and anti-trans violence that, while integral to the state, must be made to
disappear in order to normalize the state. Even the spectacular emergence of
anti-queer and anti-trans violence in the mainstream (for example Matthew
Shepherd and Latisha King)12 serves to erase its ordinary everydayness in
white supremacist, ableist, cis-heteronormative, ableist global capitalism.
Staying in a ditch that should not exist involves grappling with normalizing
practices as a bio/necropolitical site of making live and making die.
Roderick Ferguson (2004 and 2019) highlights the foundational role of
theoretical and activist work by feminists and queers of color. More than
demarcating another approach or direction in queer theory, Ferguson reframes
the field in a way that decenters the white, male, and class privileged fram-
ing that has characterized most of queer theory’s institutionalized academic
life—the origin stories told about it, the lives and deaths that are proclaimed
to matter for it. As Ferguson notes in his analysis of institutional inclusion
84 Chapter 3
Ungrievable lives are those that cannot be lost, and cannot be destroyed, because
they already inhabit a lost and destroyed zone; they are, ontologically, and from
the start, already lost and destroyed, which means that when they are destroyed
in war, nothing is destroyed. To destroy them actively might even seem like a
kind of redundancy, or a way of simply ratifying a prior truth. (2010, xix)
Butler’s point about frames in the context of war are also applicable to how
threats to public health, societal norms, and even disciplines are conceived
and responded to. In the remainder of this chapter, I focus on the bio/necrop-
olitics animated by frames of life and death that inform practices of exclusion
within discipline of philosophy, societal norms, and conceptions of threats
to public health (specifically HIV/AIDS and COVID-19). In queering these
issues, I seek to reframe them, conceiving of them from the perspective of
those deemed disposable within dominant frames. When dominant frames
define one’s life out of existence by relegating it to the realm of disposability,
Power, Life, and Death 85
nonbeing, and ungrievability, the forms of violence and exclusion that one
experiences don’t register within the dominant frame as violence and exclu-
sion at all. To be counted as harmed, one would have to be counted as existing
in the first place.
Queering philosophy reframes mainstream philosophy from the experience
of those whose lives are deemed not worth living and whose deaths are not
deaths. If, following Socrates, the practice of mainstream Western philosophy
is tied to a life deemed worthy of life, a critically queer philosophy from the
perspective of lives deemed not worthy of living is the practice of an other-
wise-philosophy.14 The practice of an otherwise-philosophy is not a practice
of dying, as Socrates characterizes philosophy, but rather experiments in
thinking and living that open otherwise ways of understanding reality and
possibilities for being in relation with others. The practice of the otherwise is
founded on an other-wisdom, not the abstracting and universalizing wisdom
founded on the myth of purified rationality.15
As Butler notes, reflecting on the obituary can reveal a lot about where,
when, and how lives are valued and deaths are counted as grievable losses
(2004, 34). Within a cis-heteropatriarchal society, life = binary gender =
heterosexuality = marriage = children, a conception that casts queerness and
transness as outside life and has implications for those who are queerly situ-
ated in the world, even if they don’t or don’t yet identify as a member of a
gender or sexual minority group. In “Queer and Now,” a foundational text in
queer theory, Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick begins with the still-all-too-relevant
and real fact of lesbian and gay suicides. She writes, “I’ve heard of many
people who claim they’d as soon their children were dead as gay. What it
took me a long time to believe is that these people are saying no more than
the truth” (1993, 2). Queer lives are those lives that are cast out of concern,
lives that are deemed to be without value, if they are considered at all, in the
mainstream. While such contexts of devaluation and erasure give rise to many
forms of resistance, they also give rise to many forms of queer grief.
partner and I spent the long weekend after my father’s death attending
My
the wake, the funeral, and the burial, spending time with family members
grieving in their own ways. I haven’t wanted to talk to many people about
all this. Like queer lives in general, too much of what I feel and want to say
has no place in prevailing Western conventions of obituaries and funerals.
Queer grief is erased in the obituary form, a form that tends to center all
the things that count as a life in heteropatriarchal society: nuclear families,
deeds deemed good. Like the silences of the archive so carefully tracked by
Foucault, the silences of obituaries enable their account of the life well-lived.
Obituaries mark a life well-lived in the estimation of a society’s or group’s
86 Chapter 3
dominant norms and values. And yet, the lives of so many remain unacknowl-
edged, erased from the very text of the obituary itself, unmourned.
My father’s obituary listed me as among those who have “survived” his
death. Yes, I survived. I survived him, his life. What does it mean for a queer
person to survive the death of a parent who could never accept you, who
would have preferred your nonexistence? My partner was listed too, though,
unlike straight spouses, by first initial and surname (rather than full first
name only)—as I understand it, a compromise to avoid making uncomfort-
able those who would have preferred to not mention Jill at all.
What does it mean to survive a parent who said that if he had known you
were queer while you were growing up, he would have sent you somewhere to
fix you? I’m thankful for the winds that must have carried some radical faerie
sparkle dust to create a force field around me while growing up. I’m thank-
ful that I grew up with a mom who was able to leave a toxic marriage and
continues to love me as I am. I/we survived him. I thank all the queer bars for
the space and joy. I thank all the queer and feminist bookstores. I thank queer
feminist crip communities for helping me redefine family and for continuing
to give me a language to name what needs to be named.
At the funeral, so many people described my father as a good man. Maybe
he was good to them. I wish I could say my father was a good man. From the
moment I was able to think for myself, my father and I clashed. He thought
I was “bad” and ruining my life for so many reasons—because I chose to
study philosophy, because I’m a feminist, because I’m queer, because I think
the Confederate flag is a racist symbol, because . . .. In my last conversation
with my father, he said he didn’t raise me to be “that way,” that I was going
to hell, and that there was nothing more that he wanted to say to me.
Sometimes, in low moments, I think maybe if I were a better queer, none
of this would bother me, none of it would hurt. But this wound is part of the
rage-tinged grief that I feel. I grieve for a relationship I never had. I grieve
because, despite all the bad, I have some good memories of him. I’m glad he
took time to read to me when I was a child. I’m glad he was willing to catch
while I practiced pitching baseball when he got home from work. I’m glad
he took me for walks in the woods and fishing. I wish these things had been
enough to help him want to work toward a change of heart.
Even in the case of a loss of a parent or a parent’s funeral, something experi-
enced as intensely private and solitary, no matter how many others feel/regis-
ter the loss, there is a politics that frames its significance (Butler 2004b, 24).
In posing the question, What does it mean to mourn?, Butler aims to bring
into view the bio/necropolitics16 in which lives and deaths are apprehended.
It’s not that lives and deaths aren’t personally experienced; it’s that one’s
Power, Life, and Death 87
experience of them is never one’s experience alone, and not only because
others also mourn. Butler writes,
For Butler, one of the ways we can track bio/necropolitical power is through
the obituary, which is ultimately about how we imagine community, whether
marginalized or dominant (34). In other words, the experience of loss, both
one’s sense of what is lost and the significance of that loss, is about how we
understand the scope of “we” (34). Thus understood, obituaries perform the
work of moral repair and community-or nation-building (34). When a life
passes without remark in an obituary, “it is not quite a life . . .. It is already
the unburied, if not unburiable” (34). One of the things that stands out in
this remarkable claim is Butler’s insistence that we must ask about the bio/
necropolitical function of the obituary—what it means and what it does—not
once, as if one eloquent argument could settle the matter and we could get
over it and move on, but again and again, lest lives deemed worth living
become monumentalized, foreclosing what our being-in-relation with others,
our being in community, could become—a community in which the unfa-
miliar is valued rather than annihilated in the name of self-preservation (38).
to the US death toll. While there is, obviously, little that can be done about
a virus to which no one has immunity, the coronavirus death toll that we are
seeing around the world is not a result of the natural influence of a novel
virus. Instead, it is a result of systemic, deepening injustices in the world and
neoliberal policies that have devastated social infrastructures, thus exposing
those whose are more precariously situated, those who are more vulnerable,
to coronavirus infection and death.
Along with COVID, there have been massive, sustained global protests
in the wake of the police murders of George Floyd, Breonna Taylor, and too
many others. While largely focused on protesting anti-Black racism, there
have also been protests against the wave of anti-Asian racist violence in
the wake of COVID-19. In the US, while former president Donald Trump
deployed the national guard in response to peaceful protests of police mur-
ders of Black people, he sat by and watched as white nationalists stormed
the US capital in an effort to stop the certification of Electoral College votes
that would declare Joseph Biden to be the next president. The difference in
police and military response could not be starker: tear gas, beatings, rubber
bullets, low-flying military helicopters, and arrests in response to unarmed
people protesting against anti-Black racism versus delayed deployment of
the National Guard and police officers who stood by while white nationalist
Trump supporters, with strip ties and various weapons, stormed the US capi-
tal to stop the process of Electoral College vote certification in a presidential
election. This is what fascism looks like.
While it is important to avoid collapsing HIV/AIDS and COVID-19, it is
also true that, as I witnessed these events while trying, somehow, to complete
this book, I couldn’t help but think of the lack of official response to HIV/
AIDS and the death toll of AIDS that was an important context for work
being done in queer theory in the late 1980s and early 1990s.17 After all,
Foucault, who also died of AIDS in 1984, listed epidemics, illness, and heath
as biopolitical sites of the management of the life and death of populations.
And, important to queer AIDS critique during this time was the Foucauldian
observation that the terms population and public, whose health the state
wanted to protect and preserve in its response to AIDS, did not include
minoritized and stigmatized groups like queer and trans people, intravenous
drug users, sex workers, people from sub-Saharan Africa, and others deemed
more at risk. In fact, the early response to HIV/AIDS (initially called GRID,
or Gay-related Immunodeficiency Disorder, by the Centers for Disease
Control and Prevention [CDC]) cast queer people and queer practices as the
cause of the HIV/AIDS threat to “public health,” and there were proposals to
quarantine queer people to protect the rest of the population. ACT-UP (AIDS
Coalition to Unleash Power) chapters emerged in the US and elsewhere to
demand a response.
Power, Life, and Death 89
As I read, listened, and watched the news about COVID-19 in the US, the
fact that many of the main players are the same is uncanny: the CDC and Dr.
Anthony Fauci, for example. It was Dr. Fauci who worked at the National
Institutes of Health (NIH) when ACT-UP stormed the NIH, demanding
inclusion of communities impacted by AIDS in clinical trials and access to
experimental drugs. Fauci worked with ACT-UP representatives to enable the
involvement of HIV/AIDS impacted communities in the process of research
and planning for treatments. Now, Fauci is called America’s doctor.
While the standard account of ACT-UP’s emergence is that it consisted
of mostly white gay men responding to a disease that was killing mostly
white gay men, in fact, AIDS activism of this period also focused on hous-
ing, poverty, access to health care, access to clean needles, the safety of sex
workers, women and AIDS, the affordability of drugs, access to food, and
access to care. Thus, ACT-UP was an organization that included within it
many subgroups focused on particular projects, and there were many tensions
within it. Like all coalitions, there was much disagreement and in-fighting
(see Gould 2009). Many groups within ACT-UP were deeply critical of those
members who were single-mindedly focused on the goal of “drugs into bod-
ies,” as if access to drugs would end the AIDS crisis (France 2012). But,
like COVID-19, the AIDS crisis is also deeply informed by racism, ableism,
global capitalism, homophobia, and transphobia. Until these forms of sys-
tematic injustice are eliminated, neither health crisis can be solved even if
vaccines and treatments are found.
Another oft-repeated story about HIV/AIDS is that it is “over,” that AIDS
is no longer a death sentence due to access to preventative treatments. But
AIDS continues to kill many people worldwide every year, and AIDS con-
tinues to be a crisis in African American communities, poor communities,
and the Global South (see Shahani 2016; Cheng, Juhasz, and Shahani 2020;
Cheng 2020). So, getting drugs into bodies (or vaccines into arms), whether
in response to HIV/AIDS or COVID-19, isn’t the solution to epi/pandemics.
The question isn’t whether scientists find drugs that work; the question is,
Who has access to these drugs? What are the underlying systemic injustices
that continue to make others die so that some may live? As Che Gossett and
Eva Hayward write, there seem to be “echoes” between COVID-19 and
AIDS, echoes that suggest that “[p]erhaps what AIDS and COVID-19 share
is antiblackness and racism” (2020, 527). By resisting the reduction of one to
the other and, instead, placing epi/pandemics “into conversation” (as Gossett
and Hayward put it), we can highlight the fact that long-lasting solutions to
existing and future epi/pandemics can’t happen in the context of bio/necropo-
litical forms of injustice. We can make visible how “discourses of contagion”
and cure (528) inform ongoing legacies of bio/necropolitics.
90 Chapter 3
NOTES
different and even contradictory discourses within the same strategy; they can, on the
contrary, circulate without changing their form from one strategy to another, opposing
strategy. (1990, 101–2)
discipline of philosophy and not infrequent refusal to call himself a philosopher (see
McWhorter 2016).
10. Using data from the National Center for Transgender Equality, Zurn specifies
that “57% of trans people experience significant family rejection. Without family
support, they report significantly higher rates of drug and alcohol use, homelessness,
incarceration, and attempted suicide. When they enter grade school, 78% report being
harassed, 35% physically assaulted, and 12% sexually assaulted. Roughly 15% drop
out of school. Once out, 90% report experiencing harassment, mistreatment, or dis-
crimination in their place of work; 26% report losing their job because of their gender
identity. 53% report everyday harassment in public accommodations” (2016, n.p.).
11. Importantly for my focus on queering philosophy, McCarthyism’s
anti-intellectualism combined with the House of Un-American Activities Commit-
tee’s designation of homosexuals, Jewish people, and black and brown people as
enemies of the state played an unacknowledged role in the silencing or outright purg-
ing of queer philosophers, whether or not their work was situated within a Marxian
philosophical lineage (see McCumber 2001, 22, 53–54). During the 1950s in the US,
homosexuality was criminalized, and homosexuality was deemed an illness in need
of a cure. While this history of pathologization and criminalization has typically been
part of standard accounts of gay and lesbian US history, trans theorists and historians
have reclaimed it as also part of trans history because the state’s investment in sur-
veilling and punishing so-called deviant desire was and is linked to its investment in
surveilling and punishing so-called gender deviance (see Stryker 2008, 50–52).
12. For a critical phenomenological analysis of transphobia in the life and death of
Latisha King, see Salamon 2018.
13. Here I build on Alexis Shotwell’s (2016) discussion of the politics of memory
and the critical intervention of remembering that which dominant discourses bury and
assign to the realm of the forgotten.
14. I borrow the term otherwise-philosophy from Ashton Crawley (2017).
15. As every student of philosophy learns, the Greek meaning of philosophy is love
of wisdom. In the Phaedo and Symposium, Socrates characterizes this love of wisdom
as founded on the separation of the soul/mind from the body.
16. I refer to bio/necropolitics rather than biopolitics and necropolitics to highlight
the mutually reinforcing nature of these strategies. While these strategies take dif-
ferent forms—making live and making die, respectively—they work together. Some
populations are made to live while other populations are either allowed to die or
subjected to a death-in-life (Foucault 1990; Mbembe 2003).
17. My intention is to note AIDS as an important part of the context for queer
theoretical work. I do not wish to repeat the AIDS-as-origin story of queer theory.
18. UNAIDS, “Global HIV and AIDS Statistics—2020 Fact Sheet,” https://www
.unaids.org/en/resources/fact-sheet, accessed May 16, 2021.
Chapter 4
Queer Ecologies
Wonder and humility are wholesome emotions, and they do not exist side
by side with a lust for destruction.
—Rachel Carson, “Remarks at the Acceptance of
the National Book Award for Nonfiction”
In general, queer theory does not turn to the past in order to find identity
categories familiar from the present, but instead grants the past the poten-
tial to conjoin its undeniable intimacy to a surprising alterity. Queerness is
at its heart a process of wonder.
—Jeffrey J. Cohen, Medieval Identity Machines
Nature is a thorny issue for queers. Given the history of its use against gen-
der and sexual minorities—to criminalize our erotic practices, to try to cure
us, or lock us up—a queer wariness about nature is understandable. After
all, ideas about nature and the natural have long been weaponized against
those who are queerly positioned in the world: entanglements of compulsory
heterosexuality, compulsory able-bodied-mindedness, white supremacy, and
capitalism have structured a differential racialized and classed diagnostic sys-
tem in which disability and queerness have been deemed sick, abnormal, and
perverse.1 While this is one way nature has been a concern for queer, disabled,
and trans people, it doesn’t exhaust the ways in which nature is a queer mat-
ter. Thus, a framing question for this chapter is: How might we understand
the nonhuman natural world, and our environmental relationships and respon-
sibilities, in ways that don’t reproduce anti-queer violence—in other words,
violence against all deemed unnatural, abnormal, sick, and perverse?
Queer ecology queers mainstream environmental philosophy and environ-
mentalism by putting their central categories (human, animal, plant, nature)
into crisis, revealing and critically interrogating the structures of power that
97
98 Chapter 4
create and sustain the distinctions at the heart of their meaning. Such catego-
ries do more than simply describe the world (and, for queer ecologists, they
don’t do that very well); these categories are performatively constituted (see
Barad 2011, 125). That is, their deployment is a form of doing that constitutes
their being. In critically attending to what mainstream environmentalism’s
categories do, queer ecology also seeks to undo them. As a critically queer
strategy, such undoing is indebted to Judith Butler’s understanding of undo-
ing of the self. To be undone, according to Butler, is to understand that the
question of a livable life is not reducible to the question of the livability of
lives that count as human. For Butler, undoing puts categories like the human,
gender, sexuality, and nature “into crisis” (2004a, 10). In fact, dominant
understandings of the human and the natural have produced and rationalized
precarity of oppressed groups by casting them either to the margins or com-
pletely outside of those categories.2 Undoing calls into question mainstream
environmentalism’s reliance on concepts that assume and reproduce, even if
unwittingly, regimes of binary gender, heterosexuality, patriarchy, whiteness,
ableism, and colonialism (Butler 2004a, 11–13; Lugones 2010; Clare 1999
and 2017; and Taylor 2017).
Thus, queer ecology focuses not on a nature or wilderness as a separate
entity that deserves human recognition and concern, but rather on the rela-
tions of power that hold in place the distinction between human and nature,
or human and animal, and in so doing define some humans out of the cat-
egory of human and life. How this line is drawn varies, but attending to how,
where, and when it is drawn and its effects is a social and an environmental
issue. From a queer ecological perspective, our ecological concern needs to
be larger than the categories of human, animal, plant, nature, and wilderness
allow. This enlargement of concern is a practice of wonder.
Critically queer ecology does not take for granted the categories of human,
animal, plant, nature, or life that, even when critiqued, tend to remain central
in environmental philosophy. Put differently, queer ecology does not seek a
more expansive or inclusive category of the human or even a biocentric or
ecocentric approach. All such approaches, from a queer ecological perspec-
tive, ask the wrong questions. The question isn’t, “Who is human or nonhu-
man and how should we treat or value them or how can we extend our moral
concern to include the nonhuman?” The question is, “What do mainstream
environmentalism’s categories and the distinctions between them do? And
how might we forge a critically queer ecological critique from the non/
human wreckage these categories have wrought?” A critically queer ecology
is a politics that seeks to destabilize the borders between mainstream envi-
ronmentalism’s binary categories (e.g., the human and the nonhuman, animal
and plant, culture and nature, civilized and wild, life and non-life, animate
and inanimate) in order to expose and contest their role in varied forms of
Queer Ecologies 99
The turn to the inhuman in queer ecology is a realization that it’s not only
nature, but also the human, that has been weaponized against queers. In
their introduction to their GLQ special issue on Queer Inhumanisms, Donna
Luciano and Mel Chen note that queer ecology is grounded in a deep know-
ing of the precarity of all deemed queer (2015). In developing this point,
Luciano and Chen underscore the connection between dehumanization,
queerness, and mestiza consciousness in Gloria Anzaldúa’s work, noting that
queerness is a site of dehumanization and that the experience of dehumaniza-
tion shapes a way of knowing and navigating the world that Anzaldúa names
mestiza consciousness (see Luciano and Chen 2015, 186; Anzaldúa 1987).
Of course, this is not to conflate LGBTQ identity with mestiza conscious-
ness, a move that would erase significant differences among LGBTQ people.
Following Luciano and Chen, the queerness of Anzaldúa’s perspective is
her understanding of mestiza consciousness as a way of knowing/being/
navigating the world that, while rooted in the experience of being different,
other, and therefore lesser within dominant contexts, is not an inevitable
100 Chapter 4
outcome of one’s identity (2015, 186). Both context and privilege matter.
Luciano and Chen situate Anzaldúa’s work as foundational for a critically
queer ecology, noting that the concept of mestiza consciousness tells a
story of self and consciousness, belonging and non-/un-belonging in which
the infrastructures of queer mestiza life are more than human and situated
within histories of human-soil, human-parasite, human-plant, human-animal,
human-landscape intimacy.
Yet, while also sites of violence, the dehumanization of minoritized sub-
jects also opens the possibility for critical interrogation of the category of the
human and the generation of non/human intimacies, kinship, and relationship
with the more than human world, which is both other and a part of who we
are. Luciano and Chen name this critical perspective “queer inhumanisms,” a
queer ecology from the perspective of the inhuman of queer subjectivity that
seeks an anthro-decentric ecology rather than a mere reversal of anthropo-
centrism (192). Given the precarities caused by institutionalized racism and
transphobia, queer of color and trans scholars have been at the forefront of
queer ecological analyses of the precarities produced by, not only the human-
animal binary, but the category of the human itself:
[W]e are marking a specific kind of situation—a desire to persist in the face of
precarity—as the primary catalyst for queer thought in general. That situation,
moreover, is particularly generative for queer inhumanist thought, since the
intensification of precarity tends to push putatively “human” subjects to the
critical edge of that category. (It is therefore no accident, we think, that many
of the most generative queer critiques of the human have emerged from queer
of color critique and transgender studies). Queer ecology and many other queer
engagements with the nonhuman also engage in the contemporary context, as
a response to precarity, as the effects of climate crisis extend that condition to
encompass all of humanity, and numerous other species as well. All life, we
might say, is now precarious life. (193)
Such a critically queer ecology does not focus on the human as both distinct
from nature and in need of reconnecting with it; to theorize environmental
problems in these terms, for Chen and Luciano, serves to reinforce the pre-
sumed binary relation between them. Instead, a queer ecological practice of
wonder opens to something more; it is attuned to that which exceeds and
calls into question the categories of human and nature that inform mainstream
environmentalism.
Jane Bennett’s term for the ethical and political posture of this wonder is
loafing, a suspension of absolute verdict informed by a more-than-human
sensibility (2020, 59, 116). Bennett isn’t suggesting that judgment is never
appropriate. Indeed, the devastating realities of social, economic, and envi-
ronmental injustice demand judgment and response. Instead, Bennett is
Queer Ecologies 101
NATURE, WILDERNESS
While a focus on human practices seems more promising from a queer per-
spective than an approach that uses nature as a moral compass, these debates
still don’t get to the heart of the matter regarding mainstream environmental-
ism’s orientation toward nature. For one thing, the question of whether there
is an independent nature that is being harmed by human practices, or whether
nature is nothing other than human practices all the way down, ignores the
issue of whose practices.
As Kyle Powys Whyte, Chris Cuomo, and Axelle Karera have shown,
the emphasis on human practices perpetuates the assumption that it is all
humans, rather than the social and economic practices of particular humans
in the past and present, that have created climate chaos in concert with other
social and environmental harms. Moreover, the curiously decontextualized
debate about nature tends to mark the Industrial Revolution as the beginning
of climate change. This temporal framing willfully ignores7 the destruction
of climate change occasioned by voyages of conquest, the Middle Passage,
settler colonialism, plantation slavery, and their enduring legacies (see Whyte
2017 and Karera 2019). These practices must be reckoned with in order to
address the mutually reinforcing practices of environmental, social, and eco-
nomic injustice.
In its failure to address colonialism and slavery, mainstream environmen-
talism and philosophy can become a tool in the service of colonialism and
racism in the world, all in the name of protecting the environment, or nature
(Liboiron 2021, 11). As Max Liboiron argues, pollution is produced by a
colonial relation to land (6). An example of this colonial relation to land is
enshrined in the concept of wilderness. Wilderness is created by forcible
removal of poor and Indigenous people all over the world from ancestral
lands in order to transform it into a consumable object for the enjoyment of
green-minded global elites, or ecotourism (Guha 1989, 72–74). Following
Ramachandra Guha, the conception of the wild as empty playground for
global elites is materialized in colonial and settler colonial contexts through
the violent expulsion of people from their ancestral lands and means of sub-
sistence (72–73).
If queerness signals that which is disorderly in its defiance of categories
used to organize and know the world, the wilderness, contrary to its enduring
allure as a zone of untamed freedom, is conceived as a space whose untram-
meled purity is ensured by natural, if not human, law. As a space of natural
law, the wilderness is rendered a heteronormative zone whose machinations
are shaped by a logic of repro-futurity (Mortimer-Sandilands and Erickson
2010). In fact, some environmental philosophers conceive of the wilder-
ness as a site for the cultivation of environmental virtues (like humility and
patience) precisely because of its separateness from the everyday world of
human existence (see, for example, Aaltola 2015). For them, getting back to
Queer Ecologies 105
wilderness is conceived as getting back to not only how things really are, but
how things are supposed to be (see Aaltola 2015). Queer ecology seeks to
unsettle this account.
REWILDING QUEERNESS?
Some queer theorists argue that, despite its historical enmeshment with het-
eronormativity, patriarchal masculinity, settler colonialism, and whiteness,
the wild can and should be reclaimed as a queer space. I’ll call these efforts
queer rewilding projects. One type of queer rewilding project is the effort
to locate queers in nature. Examples include identifying same-sex eroticism
among nonhuman animals; identifying gender transformation and other
forms of beyond-the-binary gender among nonhuman animals and plants;
and queer farming, communes, and other forms of queer being in nature,
including queer forest fucking (Bell 2010). Curiously, these forms of find-
ing or returning queers to the wild have, I suggest, much in common with
mainstream rewilding projects that aim to restore the wilderness. While on
the face of it, these activities seem quite different, both share a certain kind
of response to loss.
Consider, for example, rewilding projects in environmentalism. Rewilding
is a project that involves reintroducing species to their natural habitat and,
thus, restoring the ecosystems of those places. Rewilding is a project moti-
vated by concerns about the devastating impact of human activities in wild
places—that is, the erosion or loss of wild places and their flora and fauna
as a result of climate change, hunting, ranching, extractive industries, and
human habitation. Rewilding aims to restore the wilderness as a place where
humans visit and leave with no trace. While well-intentioned, rewilding is
informed by a number of problematic assumptions. Rewilding is a form of
eco-engineering that is shaped by a mechanistic conception of nature that
rationalizes human domination over nature and the domination of other
humans that have been historically and conceptually differentially associated
with nonhuman nature or conceived as closer to nature in some way (e.g.,
women of all racial groups, men of color, and people of all genders in the
Global South). As such, rewilding’s framing belief in the power of (some)
human reason to control the nonhuman natural world reflects not only a fail-
ure of humility regarding human finitude and interdependency with the rest of
planetary life, but, perhaps more profoundly, a failure to reckon with the loss
and devastation wrought by (some) human activities. The “we can rebuild it”
outlook also ignores the violence of rewilding projects themselves, projects
106 Chapter 4
that can involve making poor people poorer by removing access to sources of
food, water, fuel, and other necessities.
Within queer studies, some have argued for what I call a rewilding of
queerness. While not identical with rewilding projects in mainstream envi-
ronmentalism, queer rewilding also depends upon a problematic fiction of
wilderness that is ultimately, I suggest, counter to the possibilities of a queer
ecology rooted in the complexities of our planetary situation. One example
is the move to reclaim the wild as a queer orientation toward that which is
beyond the human/nonhuman binary. Consider Jack Halberstam’s definition
of wildness as “the order of things we have left behind, the anticipatory mood
that accompanies all claims of coming after something, and the unknown
future that, for now at least, still beckons from the horizon. Wildness is all at
once what we were, what we have become, and what we will be, or even what
will cease to be in the event of postnatural collapse” (2020, 7). Wilderness,
he continues, is “an orientation to the void, an ontology ‘beyond the human,’
and a disorder that reminds us of a time . . . ‘before the world fell at our
feet’” (7). There is much to think about in and with this passage, though what
stands out most to me is the “we” who is oriented toward wildness in the way
Halberstam describes. Who is this we?
Since Halberstam’s exploration of wildness is motivated by a desire to
know (or at least wonder) “what specifically queerness might be after nature”
(6), one obvious candidate for the “we” might be queers themselves. But
who are these queers for whom the call of the wild beckons from the void? It
would seem to be those for whom the wild or wilderness is a place where they
aren’t—those who visit where the wild things are (or at least are purported
to be) but would never dream of living there—rural, remote places without
the New York Times, The Guardian, or a decent $10 cup of matcha tea. In
other words, global elites whose sense of freedom requires the existence of a
wilderness beyond the frontier of the human. This is an all-too-familiar story.
Consider Halberstam’s account of agreeing to a speaking gig on the
Faroe Islands because he wanted to see the islands and the puffins while
such wild places and wild animals still exist (2020, xi–xii). Despite a val-
iant effort through turbulent seas, there were no puffins to be found. Nature
just wouldn’t cooperate, meaning that the wild that he encountered wasn’t
the wild he had in mind. No puffins. Wasted trip. Stuck in a nowhere place
where there is nothing to do. While he acknowledges the risks of reclaiming
a category, like wildness, that has long informed racialized dehumanization
of people deemed uncivilized and the West’s civilizing missions, Halberstam
nonetheless unwittingly reproduces this meaning of the wild in his efforts to
reclaim it as a key word for queer studies. A wildness oriented toward the void
is a wildness that continues to be premised on the disappearance of people,
histories, and relationships, rendering once again the wild as the playground
Queer Ecologies 107
or site of self-discovery and transformation for global elites. This is, as Guha
argues, wilderness as commodity for the enjoyment of global elites.
There is an important difference between such forms of queer eco-tourism
and queer ecology. Here it is helpful to recall María Lugones’s distinction
between tourism and world-traveling as a practice of knowing-with (1987).
For Lugones, world-traveling is a concept for analyzing and thinking with
the survival strategies of those who are oppressed, how one can be oppressed
and privileged differently in different worlds, possibilities of solidarity across
difference, and “ontological confusion” of multiple selves, selves who belong
in, are undone by, and are at the edges of various worlds of sense. But the
concept of the wild as destination does not disorient dominant conceptions
of the wild founded on human/nature and other binaries. When tourists,
including eco-tourists, travel, they consume the people and places they visit,
enfolding them into their own individual life dramas. Such world travel-
ing does not threaten to undo the self who travels. As Jasbir Puar (2002;
2007) argues, homo/trans-national tourism opens the world for queer and
trans global elites while sustaining the closure of borders to those who are
oppressed and excluded by citizenship norms. Eco-tourism participates in
this same dynamic, opening the wilderness for global elites while removing
poor and Indigenous people in the world from sources of cultural and material
sustenance. Informed by the interests and agency of global elites, the focus
on wilderness ignores and exacerbates the causes of environmental and social
degradation. As Melanie Bowman writes in her analysis of Lugones’s concept
of world-traveling, a key feature of non-exploitative world traveling is feeling
ill-at-ease; feeling ill-at-ease is the affective attitude that registers that one has
indeed traveled (in Lugones’s sense) to a different world, that one is open to
surprising, unsettling difference (2020, 480).
Now, some might think of wilderness experience as an excellent example
of world-traveling. After all, it involves leaving the comforts of one’s every-
day life and foregoing many of the things a privileged traveler might take for
granted (running water, air conditioning or heat, refrigeration, a comfortable
bed, television, cell phone reception, etc.). In fact, for Sarah Pohl (2006),
it is precisely the disorienting distance from the everyday occasioned by
wilderness experience that creates the opportunity for cultivating various
environmental virtues that one takes from the “backcountry” to the world
of one’s creature-comfort-filled daily life. Connecting wilderness experi-
ence with the cultivation of environmental virtue, Elisa Aaltola (2015)
argues that wilderness experience opens the possibility for the cultivation
of attentiveness. Furthermore, according to Aaltola, attentiveness is a neces-
sary condition for the possibility of experiencing the wilderness at all. But
what is it about the wilderness, for these authors, that makes it such fertile
ground for environmental awareness and virtue? For Aaltola, the answer is
108 Chapter 4
With so much that queer ecology is against, what might it be for? After all,
queerness as a critical political project is also utopian in José Muñoz’s sense
of “a backward glance that enacts a future vision” (2009, 4). The ecological
resonance of Muñoz’s utopian temporality is, I suggest, both importantly
110 Chapter 4
different from and in solidarity with what Kyle Powys Whyte’s (2017, 156)
description of Indigenous conceptions of climate change as “back to the
future,” an understanding that resists settler colonial conceptions of climate
change as unprecedented. Going back, in the context of queer ecology’s
nonlinear temporality resists nostalgic conceptions of the past, a nostalgia
that is a feature of nationalisms of all kinds (see Gopinath 2018). Instead,
Muñoz’s concept of queer utopia is unruly and untimely, queerly sitting with
the imperfections of layers upon layers (Clare 2017) in which normalizing
demarcations between past, present, and future cease to make sense. Like the
tree that imperceptibly and simultaneously reaches out, above, and below,
these layers upon layers of deep non/human relational time are given at once.
Rather than a restoration or reclamation of nature or the wild, critically
queer ecology is a form of what Mel Chen calls “feral theorizing”—theoriz-
ing that challenges and resists the disciplinary boundaries and forces that can
“defang” radical theories when they are institutionalized (2012, 18). As a
form of feral theorizing, a queer ecology that queers environmental philoso-
phy seeks more than the addition of a queer perspective to the field or the res-
toration of queers to a place called nature or wilderness. Instead, it grapples
with complex, entangled genealogies of materialization—the myriad ways
nature, life, and non-life come to matter. This coming to matter of queerness
is, in part, what Chen means by animacy:
NOTES
alternative terms. For example, Jason Moore (2016) suggests “Capitalocene” would
be a better description.
7. Here I am building on Charles Mills’s (1997) description of white ignorance
as white people’s failure to understand the world they have created through their
practices, or an “agreement to misinterpret the world” (1997, 18). Part of what Mills
critiques is the white ignorance (or “collective hallucination”) that posits the social
contract as the origin of human society and politics. According to Rousseau, the social
contract explains the origin of government as the mutual agreement to exchange
freedom in the state of nature for a more restricted, but mutually advantageous, set
of civil liberties. As Mills points out, Western political philosophy has persisted in its
retelling of this myth of the origin of government, a myth that conveniently forgets
that even though not all whites were signatories of this mythical contract, all whites
were beneficiaries of it (11). As a result, Mills asserts that the social contract is best
understood as a racial contract that secures a white polity at the expense of nonwhites.
Just as there is no social contract, there is no state of nature. I suggest that the nature
at the heart of the myth of the state of nature is also a “collective hallucination” in
the service of a white, heteronormative, patriarchal, settler colonial, ableist, global
capitalist polity.
8. I’m sure the motivations and intentions of both human rewilding camps are
quite different. For example, I’m sure there are advocates for rewilding the human
gut who would not align themselves with principles of deep ecology and may even
offer serious critique of them. That said, my focus is on connections between these
views and deep ecology despite the consciously held beliefs and commitments of
their defenders.
9. Jeremy Bentham proclaims that the capacity to suffer marks “the insuperable
line” between beings that are morally considerable and those that are not (quoted in
Singer 2015).
10. Angela Willey (2020) examines how the real/fake distinction informs critiques
of the place of “fake meat” in vegan diets and the queer politics of inauthenticity,
including foods deemed processed or fake. In addition, Lisa Bergin (2009) uses María
Lugones’s critique of purity to advance her own critique of discourses of purity that
inform critiques of genetically modified foods.
11. Here I draw on Kelly Oliver’s observation, “If subjectivity is the process
of witnessing sustained through responsibility, then we have a responsibility to
response-ability, to the ability to respond. We have an obligation not only to respond
but also to respond in a way that opens up rather than closes off the possibility of
response by others” (2001, 18).
Chapter 5
Queer Ethics
What does loving and living the questions mean in everyday terms? It
means, again, allowing the threads of self to loosen and engaging ethics as
experiments in living.
—Lynne Huffer, Foucault’s Strange Eros
two meanings. As is perhaps most obvious by now, the term critical signals
that the queer of queer ethics names a politics that is not restricted to minori-
tized gender and sexual identities and an understanding of queer itself as in
question rather than a locus of certainty. But additionally, I use the word criti-
cal to signal political urgency. In the midst of global climate change, pandem-
ics, ableism, the destruction wrought by the extractive logic of global racial
capitalism, as well as misogynist, racist, and anti-trans violence, we urgently
need a queer ethic that can speak to the entanglements of these destructive
forces and offer other ways of being in relation to non/human others. We
need to cultivate practices of radical care in the face of interrelated systemic
injustices, for without radical care for the myriad precarities produced by
systemic injustices, we won’t work to resist them or create better worlds and
better forms of being in relation. A critically queer ethic is about how we can
care, differently.
In addition, a critically queer ethic queers ethics. What might this mean?
To be clear, queering ethics is not a rejection of ethics, or an anti-ethics. After
all, a critically queer ethic of radical care is an ethic. That said, there is an
important difference between an ethic and capital “E” Ethics. Ethics, as I use
it here, refers to the traditional Western philosophical area concerned with
developing and evaluating a system of principles that govern behavior and
policy. By contrast, an ethic is concerned with a more foundational philo-
sophical question of how to live and understands that this question cannot be
answered by adhering to a set of rules that apply to all dealing with similar
circumstances. What it means to radically care in a queer sense will be dif-
ferent in different circumstances; in fact, practices of radical care may not
always resemble conventional Western notions of care. As queer and trans
people who have been rejected by families of origin know well, queer care
can mean breaking rather than trying to mend relationships when the mending
is contingent upon annihilation of one’s self.
Still, a queer critique of Ethics is not a rejection of ethics (lowercase “e”).
For one thing, to assume that queering ethics is anti-ethics would be to surren-
der all possible insights about how to live, or of ethics, to the mainstream—
including the mainstream of Western philosophy. That is neither my objective
nor in the interest of flourishing queer lives. Instead, a critically queer orien-
tation in the world is an ethical practice of creating new values. In this sense,
queer ethics reflects a Nietzschean transvaluation of values and genealogical
approach to morality, or an ethics beyond good and evil (Nietzsche 1967).
Queer ethics, like queer theory in general, is profoundly influenced by
feminist theory, especially feminist philosophical critiques of the abstractions
and omissions of mainstream ethics and the development of a feminist ethics
of care (see Held 2006; Kittay 1999). In the past forty years, feminist phi-
losophers have developed a conception of ethics grounded in and accountable
Queer Ethics 117
The depressing thing about the Christmas season—isn’t it?—is that it’s the
time when all the institutions are speaking with one voice . . .. The thing hasn’t,
finally, so much to do with propaganda for Christianity, as with propaganda for
Christmas itself. They all—religion, state, capital, ideology, domesticity, and
discourses of power and legitimacy—line up with each other so neatly once a
year, and the monolith so created is a thing one can come to view with unhappy
eyes. What if instead there were a practice of valuing the ways in which mean-
ings and institutions can be at loose ends with each other? What if the richest
junctures weren’t the ones where everything means the same thing? (1993, 5–6)
queer feeling that registers the not-enoughness of this world and longs for
something other and more opens the queer possibility of creating new value,
a new ethic. The critical disruptions of dominant meaning and value that are
occasioned by a queer ethic makes room for other things to be thought, other
ways of living that can be sources of new value. Queer ethics unravels the one
voice with which dominant institutions speak and condemn queerness, thus
opening the possibility for lives lived otherwise.
This one voice with which dominant institutions speak informs how applied
ethics courses are conventionally taught in US classrooms. Such courses aim
to be responsive to social concerns of the day, which is good because they
can help students understand the relationship between the things philosophers
like to think and write about and their lives. However, such courses tend to
approach questions of social justice (for example, questions of racism, sex-
ism, homophobia, transphobia, and ableism) in ways that are often alienating
to students whose lives are on the line in the discussion, in other words, stu-
dents for whom the topic of the day is not and cannot be an abstract thought
experiment without dissociating from their affective investment in their very
lives. This was my experience as an undergraduate queer student who had
been raised in a milieu that constantly communicated the wrongness, the
immorality, of my very being. While this message was certainly religiously
inflected in my growing up experience, both secular and religious institutions
were in alignment and invested, it seemed to me, in smearing the queers.
While some might be tempted to think such experiences are all in the
past now that the US and many other countries have legalized lesbian and
gay marriage, this extension of legal rights has been accompanied by efforts
to eliminate legal protections for queer and trans people. Many queer and
trans kids continue to be rejected by their families, and despite the American
Psychological Association’s rejection of conversion therapy, as well as the
disbanding of Exodus International, many religious institutions continue to
sponsor these therapies and encourage parents to send their LGBTQ kids to
them, ignoring the evidence of how harmful, how damaging, these practices
are to LGBTQ people. People still want to kill LGBTQ people, and do.
LGBTQ youth continue to have higher suicide rates than other groups. And
LGBTQ philosophers are still all-too-often the first and only one in their
departments. As feminist and anti-racism movements have learned, legal
protections are important, but never the end of work to be done.
All this means that queer and trans students (and professors) come to the
philosophy classroom carrying ongoing homophobic and transphobic trau-
mas with them. Just traveling across campus to go to class can expose one
to subtle and overt homophobic and transphobic hostilities. It is tough to
concentrate when it’s clear that so many don’t care (including people who are
supposed to care because they brought you into the world), when politicians
120 Chapter 5
debate your life, your very existence in the world. Like many LGBTQ people,
I know the sting of all these rejections. When I was an undergraduate student
and newly declared philosophy major, the one parent who could have sup-
ported my education, didn’t. For this person, a philosophy degree, like my
feminist queer self, was deemed worthless. Consequently, being queer and
being a philosopher, indeed being a queer feminist philosopher, has involved
learning not only the ropes of a field—whatever they may be—but also, and
more importantly, how to care about and for what dominant culture deems
worthless.
Learning how to care about and for that which is deemed worthless is
central to queer ethical practice, a form of queer care.4 The care in question
here isn’t a warm, fuzzy, romanticized notion of care. Instead, queer care is
raw, radical care crucial for survival, and it is through practicing this sort of
care that experiments in new ways of thinking and being are forged. Practices
of queer care are practices of resistance. As Audre Lorde writes, “Caring
for myself is not self-indulgence, it is self-preservation, and that is an act of
political warfare” (1988, 130).
For queer and trans people who find themselves somehow caring about
philosophy, that care is especially difficult when the field’s mainstream seems
to care so little about you.5 Given the obstacles both in and outside academia
with which queer and trans students, faculty, and staff are forced to contend,
the presence of any one of us, to paraphrase Eve Sedgwick, is truly a miracle.6
One way institutionalized philosophy demonstrates its lack of care for queer
and trans people is by reducing queer and trans lives to abstract thought
experiments, or by talking about rather than with or to queer and trans people
and communities or from the perspective of queer and trans lives.7 Ableist
conceptions of disability, along with heteronormativity, work together to
frame queer and trans people and experience as abnormalities and curiosities8
that add spice to whatever abstract philosophical problem is being considered.
Another site of alienation occurs in the debate model that so often structures
the mainstream philosophy classroom.9 In this model, complex social and
political issues are reduced to two sides—for and against. I’ll never forget the
senior colleague who approached me in my first year in the department and
expressed interest in hosting a department event to debate “homosexuality,”
a debate in which I would present the “for” side and he would present the
“anti” side. Of course, I declined his invitation. Still, the experience illustrates
the absurd and alienating environment of conventional ethics classrooms
in which LGBTQ students and faculty are required to take seriously and
engage debates about their lives, all ostensibly in the name of learning how
to do philosophical ethics. Is homosexuality moral—for or against? Should
LGBTQ people be allowed to adopt children—for or against? Should trans
girls and women be allowed to play on girls and women’s sports teams—for
Queer Ethics 121
itself. As Sara Ahmed writes, “Queer use might refer to how things can be
used in ways other than how they were intended to be used or by those other
than for whom they were intended” (2019, 44). While this doesn’t exhaust
what Ahmed means by queer use, such putting to unofficial, unanticipated,
and undisciplined use captures what is at work in queering philosophy in gen-
eral and queering philosophical ethics in particular. Queering ethics makes
use of philosophy, but not by putting it back into circulation (that is, not by
widening its disciplinary reach). Instead, in being put to queer use, doing eth-
ics becomes something else and in the service of solidarity across difference
rather than an abstract conception of the good. Queer ethics is a practice of
forging the good in relation to and with others, with the aim of promoting
the flourishing of non/human beings and the planet. Thus understood, queer
ethics is a practice of radical care, which involves, to borrow from Gloria
Anzaldúa, a tolerance for contradiction and ambiguity (1987, 101). As such,
queer ethics is something other than judgment in the name of moral principle.
Queer ethics is attuned to spaces and movements where judgment is sus-
pended in an effort to be open to and sit with ambiguity and the unknown.
To be sure, there are times when judgement is needed, and rights need to be
projected. Even so, the suspension of judgement is also necessary for thinking
with and through what is lost in translation between worlds of marginalized
experience. At its heart, ethics is about how to live, and grappling with the
question of how to live cannot be reduced to rule following. Rather than rule
following, queer ethics engages in experiments in living, experiments in how
to live in the world with others in ways that enable the flourishing of those
whose lives have been relegated to the margins of (if not completely erased
by) the mainstream of institutionalized philosophical ethics. The point of eth-
ics, or the point that matters for queer engagements with philosophy, is not
how to live in one’s head (e.g., in the world of runaway trolleys and other
abstract thought experiments)13 but instead how to live with others and in
the world in ways that respect rather than flatten non-dominant differences.
From a queer ethical perspective, experiments in living are also practices of
self-making and un-making (see Huffer 2020). In this sense, the radical care
for others, the world, and self that constitutes queer ethics is a practice of
otherwise-being in the world that also transforms the world.
“You and I are estranged,” he said. These were the first words my father
said to me the last time I saw him. While our paths had crossed at various
events that had forced us together, it had been over a decade since we had
Queer Ethics 123
spoken more than a few passing words to each other. He was dying, and that
knowledge brought me to his doorstep that day, to a place that was not (and
never was) my home. The heteropatriarchal norm/ideal of the nuclear family
established a relationship between us that was supposed to, but never did,
create a feeling of kinship between us. Yes, he was my father according to the
laws of the state, but neither of us felt kinship. While he never spoke about his
feelings with me (unless it was anger), we were oil and water. Yes, we were
estranged indeed—always were from the moment I could form and voice my
own thoughts about the world. Nonetheless, I showed up, hoping for a dif-
ferent conversation between us, but the moment he rounded the corner at the
sound of the front door opening, I knew that was just false hope. I watched
his face fall and his expression harden the moment he realized that I was
the unexpected visitor. I was neither the guest nor the child he expected or
wanted. Like so many queers, I know intimately the sting of rejection, of being
disowned by the very people who have known you from your first breath,
the people who, according to all the heteronormative images of smiling and
happy families, will always love you and be there for you no matter what.
Like so many queers, I know the lie of that image. Queers know it’s not only
strangers who call you faggot. As I stood in the doorway that day, my father’s
face said it all: as far as he was concerned, I was repulsive, a faggot, a no one
and nothing. He had nothing to say to me except to repeat that he was going
to heaven, and I was not.
Queer ethics begins from a place of estrangement from all that is equated
with happiness and the good in heteropatriarchy: nuclear families, gender
conformity, heterosexuality, reproductive futurity, and so forth. Within het-
eropatriarchal conventions, while the rejected child is deemed immoral or
bad, the parent who disowns the queer child is deemed good because they
are doing the difficult but virtuous thing. A queer child’s estrangement from
a parent or family of origin is also an estrangement from a life that dominant
culture deems good and desirable. For LGBTQ people, those rejections from
families of origin are often religiously motivated. As Gloria Anzaldúa writes,
Religion always sides with those in power. If you deviate, you’re burned as a
witch, as a faggot, as a lesbian. The great guilt forced on us is that they want us
to merge with the normal, to cut off the unacceptable parts of ourselves—you
know, our sexuality. We have to keep silent and can’t say who we are. I really
believe that religions have to be gotten rid of. (2000, 97)
Black people, indigenous people, [disabled people], queer and trans people,
prisoners, and poor people face enormous targeting in child welfare systems.
Seeking “family recognition” rights through marriage, therefore, means seek-
ing such rights only for queer and trans people who can actually expect to be
protected by that institution. . . . The framing of marriage as the most essential
legal need of queer people and as the method through which queer people can
obtain key benefits in many realms, ignores how race, class, ability, indigeneity,
and immigration status determine access to those benefits and reduces the gay
rights agenda to a project of restoring race, class, ability and immigration status
privilege to the most privileged gays and lesbians. (2011, 61–62)
For Spade, centering marriage equality in queer and trans ethics and politics
is a one-dimensional strategy that approaches problems of homophobic and
transphobic discrimination and violence by assuming that dominant legal
institutions, but for one’s gender and sexuality, work to protect one. Thus, a
Queer Ethics 127
queer ethics and politics focused on extending recognition and legal rights
and protections is ultimately a white, nondisabled, and class-privileged
politics. In order to further demonstrate this point, Spade considers the dif-
ference between solutions to problems offered by the mainstream gay and
lesbian rights movement and those offered by queer and trans political move-
ments. For example, the former has sought carceral solutions to the problem
of homophobic and transphobic violence: “Pass hate crime legislation to
increase prison sentences and strengthen local and federal law enforcement;
collect statistics on rates of violence; collaborate with local and federal law
enforcement to prosecute hate violence and domestic violence” (63). By
contrast, a critically queer and trans proposed solution to the same problem
would “[d]evelop community-based responses to violence that support col-
lective healing and accountability [and] join with movements addressing the
root causes of queer and trans premature death: police violence, imprison-
ment, poverty, lack of health care and housing” (63). The latter’s, multidi-
mensional politics is informed by and gives rise to a multidimensional ethics
that does not take as given prevailing ethical frameworks of the status quo.
Race, class, and gender privilege are the grounds for the possibility of pro-
tection through assimilation and inclusion. Critically queer and trans theorists
have critiqued this strategy as a politics of homo-/trans-nationalism. Rather
than eliminating homophobia and transphobia, homo-/trans-nationalist ethics
and politics moves the boundary of exclusion elsewhere, leaving queer and
trans people who are more precariously situated vulnerable to violence from
the state and bigots. Even as the ethics and politics centered on rights and
recognition establishes a moral threshold for acceptable treatment, it comes
at the expense of those on the “wrong” side of that boundary, who continue to
experience various forms of oppression for which they are blamed.
STAR worked in solidarity with other groups demanding justice for all
oppressed people. Their work—from protests at Bellevue Hospital to work
with the Black Panthers and Young Lords—refused single-issue approaches
to queer and trans revolution by highlighting areas of common struggle
against dominant institutions that policed and sought to restrict their move-
ments in so-called public spaces. “The takeover at [NYU’s] Weinstein Hall,”
Ferguson writes, “represents refusal of the fable, given to us by Plato, that in
order for society to function ‘everyone’—as Rancière states—’must stay in
his [sic] proper place’” (29; Rancière 2004, 90, quoted in Ferguson 2019).
Queer ethical practices aren’t oriented toward identifying and applying
principles that can help us live in the world as it is; queers know that game is
rigged against us. Just when you think you’ve achieved some room to move
and breathe, the next election cycle takes it away, with each side pointing to
the progressive nature of the state, the temporary set-back at your expense.
Queers call bullshit on that. Queer ethics is a world-creating practice aimed
at deep transformation, not reform and mere inclusion. Inclusion is a rigged
game, as far as queers and other oppressed groups are concerned.
Mari Ruti (2017) calls this stance a queer ethics of “opting out,” a queer
ethics founded on rejection of dominant norms. This opting out can take vari-
ous forms—for example, practices of kinship that aren’t organized around the
hetero-reproductive nuclear family and state legitimization. If opting out is
to be more than a stance of ressentiment, it must do more than simply say no
to the status quo. That said, the significance of saying no is often too quickly
dismissed. Rejecting a way of life that has been extolled as the incarnation of
all that is natural and good from the moment of one’s birth is difficult indeed.
This sort of saying no risks certainty in favor of forging paths with no pre-set
guardrails. Saying no in favor of one’s own survival and flourishing is what
enables queers to be in the first place. There is no development of an other-
wise that doesn’t first involve this rejection. That said, the otherwise-world-
creating potential of queer ethics necessitates that it be more than simply
nay-saying to the status quo. And, in this chapter, my aim is to show that
it does. Queer ethics opts out and, in opting out, it does something else—it
values queer lives, relationships, and worlds.
While opting out tends to get the most attention as a queer ethical practice,
a less considered but nonetheless important queer ethical practice is one we
might call making do. At first glance, it may seem as if making do is a strat-
egy of giving up, selling out, or assimilation—a throwing up of one’s hands
in the face of overwhelming obstacles to one’s flourishing. But I suggest
that making do is a queer ethical world-creating practice that makes some-
thing out of nothing or, in this case, makes value where value is ignored or
denied, values that which is deemed to be without value and puts it to queer
130 Chapter 5
use. Consider, for example, what Mariana Ortega says about making do as a
hometactic for those who are between worlds of sense and belonging:
a feminist ethics of care that has maintained that the underlying similarities
between traditional Western ethical theories are greater than their differences
(2006). For example, Virginia Held focuses on their shared framing assump-
tions about the nature of persons (that they are isolated, autonomous, indepen-
dent, and rational) and the distinction between the public and private, which
is both profoundly gendered and establishes that ethical issues, policies, and
decisions pertain to the public not the private realm where heteropatriarchal
authority is left unchallenged (12–13). In other words, it is in the public realm
where we are expected to cooperate by acting in accordance with a set of uni-
versal, moral rules, including principles of equality; however, in the private
sphere, inequality is taken as a matter of fact and all are expected to be subor-
dinate to heteropatriarchal authority (as Held puts it, the man in his castle [12]
or as bell hooks describes it, the fear she experienced as a child hearing her
father’s footsteps at the end of the working day [hooks interviewed in Riggs
1995]). In the heteropatriarchal nuclear family household, it is the father who
is the disciplinarian who enforces his rules.
Instead, a queer ethics builds on work in recent feminist ethics of care.
Within contemporary feminist care ethics, focusing on care calls for analysis
of the social, political, and economic implications of interdependency, as
well as the interpersonal and transnational dimensions of care labor (Tronto
2015; Kittay 1999). Care, as defined by the Care Collective, encompasses
everything necessary for the flourishing of all beings (2020, 5). For their
part, Joan Tronto and Berenice Fisher define care as “a species activity that
includes everything we do to maintain, continue, and repair our world so that
we may live in it as well as possible” (quoted in Tronto 2015, 3). As Virginia
Held asserts, “The social changes a focus on care would require would be as
profound as can be imagined” (2005, 20).
The reliance on the individual and the nuclear family is a key feature
of neoliberalism, and the justification for privatization and austerity has
depended on a conception of the private individual who bears most respon-
sibility for meeting their needs. Sarah Jaffe describes the “always individu-
alizing” dynamic of neoliberalism by quoting Margaret Thatcher who said,
“‘[W]ho is society? There is no such thing! There are individual men and
women and there are families’” (2021, 9). Thatcher’s claim reveals the binary
gendered logic at the heart neoliberal conceptions of the individual and the
family. Foucault proclaimed that, far from standing outside relations of
power, the individual is both the effect and target of power that sorts, ranks,
trains, and rends the individual hypervisible (1979). What I have been calling
carceral ethics prioritizes the rationality, autonomy, and responsibility of the
individual, who is understood to enter into relationship with others but not to
be constituted by those relations. By contrast, an ethics of care begins with an
understanding of the self as relational, a fact that raises important questions
132 Chapter 5
for justice because not all relationships are good or chosen/desired; relation-
ships, even those that purport to be caring, can also be sites of injustice (Card
1990; Narayan 1995; Silvers 1995; Tronto 2015; Piepzna-Samarasinha 2018;
Care Collective 2020). Certainly, there are times when ethics needs to be
concerned with individual actions; however, a queer ethic attends first and
foremost to the myriad relationships that constitute the self and the creation
of possibilities for the flourishing of caring relationships to the self, others,
and the planet.
Unfortunately, while care is crucial for the flourishing of selves, rela-
tions, and the planet, we are surrounded by evidence (from the COVID-19
pandemic to the rise of white nationalism to consequences of climate chaos),
that carelessness prevails in our world (Care Collective 2020, 1). In response
to narrow conceptions of the scope of care, the Care Collective argues for
an ethics and politics of “promiscuous care.” Promiscuous care, they con-
tend, is not
queer, trans, disability, and feminist perspectives (see, for example, Malatino
2020; Piepzna-Samarasinha 2018; Spade 2020; Care Collective 2020). These
works focus on the importance of recognizing care as work that should be
adequately compensated and supported by state policies, as well as strategies
for navigating the fraught terrain of care inequities that make care a site of
ambiguity. Even though we all need care throughout our lives, care labor is
frequently hard, exhausting work. Caring in a careless world can wear one
down. In addition to policy suggestions, these works present models for how
individuals and communities can build caring networks. These models aren’t
products of abstract thought experiments; they are products of practices in
marginalized communities who have had to forge networks to meet their own
care needs because the dominant context does not meet them.
Those who care promiscuously also need promiscuous care from others.
A queer ethics is a practice of creating experiments of care to address needs
of those who fall outside the dominant context’s realm of caring concern.
Placing care at the center of queer ethics acknowledges that vulnerability is
both a shared condition of life, even though that vulnerability does not result
in an equally shared condition of precarity, and a condition of ethical action
in the world (Butler 2020).
As this book comes to a close, I want to think about the extent to which
promiscuous care, along with Lynne Huffer’s Foucauldian ethics of eros, sug-
gests the possibility of a queer care for philosophy. Huffer shares Foucault’s
Nietzschean suspicion of the norming function of ethics in society—a func-
tion that ultimately preserves the position of the powerful and conceals state
violence even as it claims to promote the good for all (2020, 13). Huffer’s
concern illuminates the significance of an ethics of eros for queering philoso-
phy as a practice of queer promiscuous care for philosophy. To care queerly
for philosophy is to aim at something other and more than philosophical
respectability in the form of inclusion or legitimization. Queer thinking
resides at the edges between fields, calling into question their terms for
inclusion. Queering philosophy, I suggest, is a form of promiscuous care
that pushes against institutionalized philosophy’s efforts to contain critical
practices of curiosity, wonder, and questioning, in other words, what doing
philosophy might mean.16
Huffer describes Foucault’s attention to the “murmurs” in the archive as an
“erotic poetic method [that] is also ethical. Like Audre Lorde’s conception of
the power and uses of the erotic, Huffer understands the erotic as not reduc-
ible to the sexual but instead as a relation to that which is outside the self that
134 Chapter 5
both undoes the self and is a source of invention (2–3, 11, and 15). An ethics
of eros, she argues, is not an ethics of finger wagging and the exclamation
mark (the “thou shalt” and “thou shalt not” of institutionalized theological
and philosophical approaches to ethics). Instead, an ethics of eros is an ethics
of the ellipsis (5). Such an ethics is informed by an openness to that which is
outside and other to the self in a way that undoes the self (37).
While conventional ethics attempts to discipline wayward desire, an ethics
of eros suspends discipline and instead emphasizes the possibility of wonder.
Following Huffer, an undisciplined ethics of eros suspends certainty, includ-
ing self-certainty:
Might eros teach us to veer off course: to get lost? Foucault’s eros undisciplined
offers a way to approach these questions, to keep living by holding living open
as a question: one that loosens us, that leaves us with more questions. . . . [A]s a
poet, Foucault thinks from [the] border—that line as suspended relation—where
the philosophical touches the nonphilosophical but maintains the difference
between them without trying to persuade one into becoming the other. (33)
The practice of suspending and holding in tension rather than collapsing and
resolving the difference between the philosophical and the nonphilosophical
is, I suggest, a practice of radical queer care for philosophy. Huffer makes
this connection to care when she relates Foucault’s understanding of “that
nonphilosophical excess of philosophy as a small, humble ‘light which kept
watch,’” or, in other words, cared.
And so I end where I began, with questions about the meaning of phi-
losophy. Mariana Ortega is right that mainstream philosophy has been a
love of exclusion, not a love of wisdom (2016). Queering philosophy is
an otherwise-love of wisdom, a practice of radical care for philosophy that
understands the possibilities of philosophy outside institutionalized philoso-
phy’s exclusions. This is, it seems to me, at least part of what Butler means
when they refer to the other of philosophy. What it means to otherwise-love
wisdom, is to practice philosophy against itself—that is, against its exclu-
sionary tendencies. Radical queer care for philosophy is attuned to those
who are silenced and subjugated in the name of philosophical coherence and
certainty. To practice radical queer care for philosophy means to ask who’s in
the room, on the syllabus, in the department, or any of the other places where
the philosophy deemed official gets done; and it asks this question again, and
again. Queer promiscuous, radical queer care for philosophy thinks against
the forces of institutions that seek to contain it. Queer promiscuous, radical
care for philosophy demands a philosophy that understands the border that
divides the philosophical from the nonphilosophical as an occasion to become
Queer Ethics 135
less, rather than more, certain of itself. Only then, perhaps, can philosophy
intervene in, rather than reproduce, the carelessness of the world.
NOTES
1. A number of important books and special journal issues on queer, trans, crip, and
feminist radical conceptions of care have been recently published. See, for example,
Piepzna-Samarasinha (2018), Malatino (2020), the Care Collective (2020), Spade
(2020), and Hobart and Kneese (2020).
2. Lynne Huffer discusses Foucault’s understanding of ethics as experiments in
living (2020, 14). I’ll discuss this as a queer ethics of radical care later in this chapter.
3. See the Care Collective’s use of Douglas Crimp’s concept of “promiscuous care”
(2020, 40–44). They define promiscuous care as “an ethics that proliferates outwards
to redefine caring relations from the most intimate to the most distant. It means caring
more and in ways that remain experimental and extensive by current standards” (41).
4. See also Matt Brim’s discussion of students at lower-tier, under-resourced, pub-
lic institutions for whom survival requires fighting for their LGBTQ identities and,
thus, their lives. The fact that these students seek out queer studies courses to help
them negotiate that rough terrain must, Brim argues, temper queer theory’s critique of
identity lest queer studies becomes a field that can speak to only privileged LGBTQ
experience (2020, 67–68). Brim’s point is that queer and trans identity for less privi-
leged students can be a fragile tether to a possibility of another, flourishing life.
5. To take just two examples, consider the debates about “homosexuality” and les-
bian and gay marriage and adoption that are often part of courses like “contemporary
moral problems.” Also, consider the use of trans lives as a thought experiments in phi-
losophy, a practice Talia Bettcher (2018 and 2019) rightly critiques. In both examples,
queer and trans people and experience appear as “problems” for philosophy to tackle,
rather than lives that flesh and blood queer and trans people are living. A related point
can be made about people of color and other marginalized groups in philosophy. In
such cases, members of marginalized groups appear as diversity puzzles for philoso-
phy (and universities in general) to solve rather than as philosophers who can offer
critical insight on the mainstream of the field itself.
6. Eve Sedgwick’s (1993) point about the presence of lesbians and gays in aca-
demia still rings true today. See, also, Perry Zurn (2016) about trans people’s experi-
ences of transphobia in and outside of academia, all of which impacts whether and
how many trans philosophers are in the profession.
7. See Robin Dembroff’s discussion of mainstream philosophy’s lack of engage-
ment with trans lives and trans philosophers writing about trans experience. They
argue that a factor that contributes to “philosophy’s transgender trashfire” is not only
that most have not troubled themselves to read gender theory, they also don’t think
they have to read gender theory to participate in and evaluate philosophical work in
gender theory (2020, 400). Dembroff writes, “Thinking—and speaking—before read-
ing is not merely tolerated in philosophy; it is advised. At the very least, it is assumed
a standard way of doing serious and original philosophical work. Five minutes of
136 Chapter 5
reflection will tell us that this methodology creates a disciplinary culture in which
so-called common sense is self-justifying and universalized” (402). Dembroff’s
remarks are directed at trends in mainstream analytic philosophy; however, one could
also say reading gender theory is not a prerequisite for participating in the mainstream
of continental philosophy.
8. There are many ways to think about curiosity and many forms it can take. As
Perry Zurn writes, curiosity can work to maintain oppressive societies or transform
them (2021, 3). My point about how queer and trans lives are positioned as curiosi-
ties, or a parade of the abnormal, within institutionalized philosophy, draws on the
racist, ableist, and heteronormative history of curiosities. See, for example, Eli Clare’s
(1999) discussion of the history and legacy of freak shows. In treating queer and
trans lives as curiosities, institutionalized philosophy fails to realize its own potential
as a critique of prevailing, taken-for-granted norms, values, and attitudes. In such
moments, rather than being attuned to the lively multiplicity of the world, it reduces
the diversity of life to calcified, abstracted conceptual nuggets.
9. For more on the problem with “for and against” approaches to social issues in
philosophy, see Hall 2013. I’m not claiming that issues are presented this way in
every classroom, but the debate form of ethics textbooks and conventional approaches
to teaching contemporary moral problems, coupled with ongoing efforts to either roll
back extensions of citizenship rights to LGBTQ people or double down on legalizing
discrimination against us, makes LGBTQ experience the sort of “issue” or “moral
problem” that appeals to those invested in these sorts of approaches.
10. As Heidi Grasswick demonstrates in her analysis of the impact of a bifurcated
flow of information on knowledge about climate change, reducing the complexity of
an issue to two sides can have an ultimately conservative (that is, status quo sustain-
ing) effect (2014, 546).
11. As Judith Butler (2010) argues, frames of war cast some lives as worthy of
protection and grievable and other lives as non-lives beyond the realm of concern.
12. Here, I build on the Care Collective’s (2020) discussion of capacities of caring
and imagination that must be expanded if we are to change the disastrous, careless
world in which we live.
13. Lisa Schwartzman (2012) also critiques thought experiments in philosophy for
their presumption of a shared position of privilege in the world.
14. According to Michael Warner (1999), queer ethics begins with dignity founded
on a bedrock of shame. Taking the shame of the world and throwing it back or refus-
ing it is the queer beginning of crafting a life otherwise-lived.
15. As Ladelle McWhorter writes, “Unless you’re straight-straight-straight, if
you’re honest about your sexuality, liberation is not what follows; lockup is. The truth
does not make deviants free” (1999, 13).
16. Perry Zurn builds on Foucault’s discussion of curiosity to describe curiosity as
a form of “‘care’ [for] ‘what exists and what might exist’” (2021, 93). Thus, curios-
ity can be a queer practice of care for the possible, a form of care that Zurn argues
constitutes a “critical, philosophical practice . . . that resists institutionalization of
knowledge” (93).
Bibliography
137
138 Bibliography
Gopinath, Gayatri. 2018. Unruly Visons: The Aesthetic Practices of Queer Diaspora.
Durham and London: Duke University Press.
Gossett, Che, and Eva Hayward. 2020. “Trans in a Time of HIV/AIDS,” TSQ 7 (4):
527–53.
Gould, Deborah B. 2009. Moving Politics: Emotion and ACT UP’s Fight Against
AIDS. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.
Grasswick, Heidi. 2014. “Climate Change Science and Responsible Trust: A Situated
Approach,” Hypatia: Journal of Feminist Philosophy 29 (3): 541–57.
———. 2021. “Feminist Epistemology.” In The Oxford Handbook of Feminist
Philosophy, eds. Kim Q. Hall and Ásta, pp. 198–212. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Gruen, Lori. 2015. Entangled Empathy: An Alternative Ethic for Our Relationships
with Animals. New York: Lantern.
Guenther, Lisa. 2020. “Critical Phenomenology.” In 50 Concepts for a Critical
Phenomenology, eds. Gail Weiss, Ann V. Murphy, and Gayle Salamon., pp. 11–16.
Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
Guha, Ramachandra. 1989. “Radical American Environmentalism and Wilderness: A
Third World Critique,” Environmental Ethics 11 (1): 71–83.
Halberstam, Jack. 2011. The Queer Art of Failure. Durham and London: Duke
University Press.
———. 2005. In a Queer Time and Place: Transgender Bodies, Subcultural Lives.
New York and London: New York University Press.
———. 2020. Wild Things: The Disorder of Desire. Durham and London: Duke
University Press.
Hall, Kim Q. 2013. “Philosophy, Religion, Race, and Queerness: A Question of
Accommodation or Access,” Philosophical Topics 41 (2): 157–73.
———. 2017a. “Queer Epistemology and Epistemic Injustice.” In The Routledge
Handbook of Epistemic Injustice, eds. Ian James Kidd, José Medina, and Gaile
Pohlhaus Jr., pp. 158–66. New York and London: Routledge.
———. 2021. “On Being Slow: Philosophy and Disability in the US South.” In
Thinking the US South: Contemporary Philosophy from Southern Perspectives, ed.
Shannon Sullivan, 181–201. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
Halle, Randall. 2007. “What is Queer Philosophy?” In Philosophy in Multiple Voices,
ed. George Yancy, pp. 81–108. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Halperin, David. 1995. Saint Foucault: Towards a Gay Hagiography. New York:
Oxford University Press.
———. 2003. “The Normalization of Queer Theory,” Journal of Homosexuality 45
(3–4): 339–43.
Hamby, Chris. 2020. Soul Full of Coal Dust: A Fight for Breath and Justice in
Appalachia. New York: Little, Brown and Company.
Harding, Sandra. 2004. “Introduction: Standpoint Theory as a Site of Political,
Philosophic, and Scientific Debate.” In The Feminist Standpoint Reader: Intellectual
and Political Controversies, ed. Sandra Harding, pp. 1–16. New York: Routledge.
Haritaworn, Jin, Adi Kuntsman, and Silvia Posocco, eds. 2014. Queer Necropolitics.
New York: Routledge.
142 Bibliography
Liu, Petrus. 2020. “Queer Theory and the Specter of Materialism,” Social Text 145,
38 (4): 25–47.
Lloyd, Genevieve. 1984. The Man of Reason: “Male” and “Female” in Western
Philosophy. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Loggins, Jared. 2021. “The House that Charles Built,” Dissent, September 24. https://
www.dissentmagazine.org/online_articles/the-house-that-charles-built.
Lorde, Audre. 1984. Sister Outsider: Essays and Speeches. New York: The Crossing
Press.
———. 1988. A Burst of Light. Ithaca, NY: Firebrand Books.
Love, Heather. 2014. “Queer,” TSQ: Transgender Studies Quarterly 1 (1–2): 172–76.
Luciano, Dana, and Mel Y. Chen. 2015. “Has the Queer ever been Human?” GLQ: A
Journal of Lesbian and Gay Studies 21 (203): 183–207.
Lugones, María. 1987. “Playfulness, ‘World’-Travelling, and Loving Perception,”
Hypatia: Journal of Feminist Philosophy 2 (2): 3–19.
———. 2003. Pilgrimages/Peregrinajes: Theorizing Coalition Against Multiple
Oppressions. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
———. 2006. “On Complex Communication,” Hypatia: Journal of Feminist
Philosophy 21 (3): 75–85.
———. 2010. “Toward a Decolonial Feminism,” Hypatia: Journal of Feminist
Philosophy 25 (4): 742–59.
Lugones, María and Elizabeth Spelman. 1983. “Have We Got a Theory for You!
Feminist Theory, Cultural Imperialism, and the Demand for ‘The Woman’s
Voice,’” Women’s Studies International Forum 6 (6): 573–81.
Macharia, Keguro. 2016. “On Being Area-Studied: A Litany of Complaint,” GLQ: A
Journal of Lesbian and Gay Studies 22 (2): 183–89.
Malatino, Hil. 2020. Trans Care. Minneapolis and London: University of Minnesota
Press.
Mann, Bonnie. 2013. “Three White Men Walk into a Bar: Philosophy’s Pluralism,”
Radical Philosophy Review 16 (3): 733–46.
Marcano, Donna-Dale L. 2012. “Re-reading Plato’s Symposium through the Lens of a
Black Woman.” In Reframing the Practice of Philosophy: Bodies of Color, Bodies
of Knowledge, pp. 225–34. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
———. 2014. “Race/Gender and the Philosopher’s Body.” In Living Alterities:
Phenomenology, Embodiment, and Race, ed. Emily S. Lee, pp. 65–78. Albany,
NY: SUNY Press.
Marvin, Amy. 2019. “A Brief History of Trans Philosophy,” Contingent Magazine
(September 21), https://contingentmagazine.org/2019/09/21/trans-philosophy/.
Mbembe, Achille. 2003. “Necropolitics,” trans. Libby Meintjes, Public Culture 15
(1): 11–40.
McCumber, John. 2001. Time in the Ditch: American Philosophy and the McCarthy
Era. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
McKibben, Bill. 1989. The End of Nature. New York: Random House.
McRuer, Robert. 2006. Crip Theory: Cultural Signs of Queerness and Disability.
New York: New York University Press.
144 Bibliography
Saul, Jennifer. 2013. “Implicit Bias, Stereotype Threat, and Women in Philosophy.” In
Women in Philosophy: What Needs to Change, eds. Katrina Hutchison and Fiona
Jenkins, pp. 39–60. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press.
Schalk, Sami. 2013. “Coming to Claim Crip: Disidentification with/in Disability
Studies,” DSQ: Disability Studies Quarterly 33 (2).
Schalk, Sami, and Jina B. Kim. 2020. “Integrating Race, Transforming Feminist
Disability Studies,” Signs: Journal of Women, Culture, and Society 46 (1): 31–55.
Schwartzman, Lisa H. 2012. “Intuition, Thought Experiments, and Philosophical
Method: Feminism and Experimental Philosophy,” Journal of Social Philosophy
43 (3): 307–16.
Sedgwick, Eve Kosofsky. 1990. Epistemology of the Closet. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
———. 1993. “Queer and Now.” In Tendencies, pp. 1–20. Durham and London:
Duke University Press.
Shahani, Nishant. 2016. “How to Survive the Whitewashing of AIDS: Global Pasts,
Transnational Futures,” QED: A Journal of GLBTQ Worldmaking 3 (1): 1–33.
Shotwell, Alexis. 2011. Knowing Otherwise: Race, Gender, and Implicit
Understanding. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania University Press.
———. 2016. Against Purity: Living Ethically in Compromised Times. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
Silvers, Anita. 1995. “Reconciling Equality to Difference: Caring (F)or Justice for
People with Disabilities,” Hypatia: Journal of Feminist Philosophy 10 (1): 30–55.
Singer, Peter. 2015. Animal Liberation, 40th anniversary edition. New York: Open
Road Integrated Media.
Smith, Barbara. [1980] 2014. “Racism and Women’s Studies.” In Ain’t Gonna Let
Nobody Turn Me Around: Forty Years of Movement Building with Barbara Smith,
eds. Alethia Jones and Virginia Eubanks, with Barbara Smith, pp. 132–36. Albany,
NY: SUNY Press.
———. [1997] 2014. “Where Has Gay Liberation Gone? An Interview with Barbara
Smith,” interviewed by Amy Gluckman and Betsy Reed. In Ain’t Gonna Let
Nobody Turn Me Around: Forty Years of Movement Building with Barbara Smith,
eds. Alethia Jones and Virginia Eubanks, with Barbara Smith, pp. 184–86. Albany,
NY: SUNY Press.
———. [1993] 2014. “Blacks and Gays: Healing the Great Divide.” In Ain’t Gonna
Let Nobody Turn Me Around: Forty Years of Movement Building with Barbara
Smith, eds. Alethia Jones and Virginia Eubanks, with Barbara Smith, pp. 179–83.
Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Sommerville, Siobhan B. 2000. Queering the Color Line: Race and the Invention of
Homosexuality in American Culture. Durham and London: Duke University Press.
Spade, Dean. 2003. “Resisting Medicine, Re/modeling Gender,” Berkeley Women’s
Law Journal 18: 15–37.
———. 2011. Normal Life: Administrative Violence, Critical Trans Politics, and the
Limits of Law. New York: South End Press.
———. 2020. Mutual Aid: Building Solidarity During this Crisis (and the Next).
New York and London: Verso.
Bibliography 147
Stanley, Eric. 2011. “Near Life, Queer Death: Overkill and Ontological Capture,”
Social Text 107, 29 (2): 1–19.
Stockton, Kathryn Bond. 2009. The Queer Child: Or Growing Sideways in the
Twentieth Century. Durham and London: Duke University Press.
Stryker, Susan. 2006. “(De)subjugated Knowledges: An Introduction to Transgender
Studies.” In The Transgender Studies Reader, eds. Susan Stryker and Stephen
Whittle, pp. 1–17. New York and London: Routledge.
———. 2008. Transgender History. Berkeley, CA: Seal Press.
Sullivan, Nikki. 2003. A Critical Introduction to Queer Theory. New York: New York
University Press.
Sullivan, Nikki, and Craig Middleton. 2020. Queering the Museum. London and New
York: Routledge.
Sullivan, Shannon. 2006. Revealing Whiteness: The Unconscious Habits of Racial
Privilege. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.
Tarver, Erin. 2013. “The Dismissal of Feminist Philosophy and Hostility to Women in
the Profession,” APA Newsletter on Feminism and Philosophy 12 (2): 8–12.
Taylor, Sunara. 2017. Beasts of Burden: Animal and Disability Liberation. New York
and London: New Press.
Treichler, Paula A. 1991. “AIDS, Homophobia, and Biomedical Discourse: An
Epidemic of Signification.” In AIDS: Cultural Analysis, Cultural Activism, eds.
Douglas Crimp, pp. 31–70. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Tronto, Joan C. 2015. Who Cares? How to Reshape Democratic Politics. Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press.
Tuana, Nancy. 2021. “Feminist New Materialisms.” In The Oxford Handbook of
Feminist Philosophy, eds. Kim Q. Hall and Ásta, pp. 385–94. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Turner, William B. 2000. A Genealogy of Queer Theory. Philadelphia: Temple
University Press.
Vogel, Steven. 2002. “Environmental Philosophy after the End of Nature,”
Environmental Ethics 24 (1): 23–39.
———. 2015. Thinking Like a Mall: Environmental Philosophy after the End of
Nature. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Warner, Michael. 2012. “Queer and Then?” Chronicle of Higher Education 58 (B6–
B9) (January 6).
———. 1999. The Trouble with Normal: Sex, Politics, and the Ethics of Queer Life.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Weigman, Robyn. 2012. Object Lessons. Durham and London: Duke University
Press.
Weiss, Gail. 2008. Refiguring the Ordinary. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana
University Press.
Weiss, Gail, Ann V. Murphy, and Gayle Salamon. 2020. “Introduction: Transformative
Descriptions.” In 50 Concepts for a Critical Phenomenology, eds. Gail Weiss, Ann
V. Murphy, and Gayle Salamon, pp. xiii–iv. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University
Press.
148 Bibliography
149
150 Index