Nina Begus Dissertation DAC
Nina Begus Dissertation DAC
Permanent link
https://nrs.harvard.edu/URN-3:HUL.INSTREPOS:37368915
Terms of Use
This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available
under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http://
nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of-use#LAA
Accessibility
Artificial Humanities:
A dissertation presented
by
Nina Beguš
to
Doctor of Philosophy
in the subject of
Comparative Literature
Harvard University
Cambridge, Massachusetts
August 2020
© 2020 Nina Beguš
Artificial Humanities:
Abstract
This dissertation explores boundaries and relationships between humans and humanlike
artificial entities in the twentieth-century and contemporary literature. The central question, What is
human?, is posed in relation to the newest and speculated developments in the fields of artificial
intelligence, social robotics, neurotechnology, and assisted reproduction technologies including gene
editing. I focus on three major and related topics extensively thematized in Western fiction
(American, British, Irish), and less so in Eastern European fiction (Czech, Slovenian, and Serbian).
Chapters 1 and 2 introduce posthuman language as used by humans, artificial intelligence, and
nonhuman animals; chapters 3 and 4 examine pygmalionism and paralysis from medical and social
perspectives; and the final two chapters evaluate assisted reproduction in terms of posthumanist
biology. The main argument of the dissertation is that although the questions and definitions of the
human are, unbeknown to scientists and engineers, now formed and framed in STEM fields,
literature suggests solutions to philosophical questions pertaining to new technologies and offers a
level of insight inaccessible to quantitative science. The dissertation proposes a new framework of
artificial humanities where investigation of philosophical questions pertaining the human, nature,
and technology occurs alongside cutting-edge science, technology, and engineering. The theoretical
argument proposes that, despite recent claims of ontological posthumanism, scientific evolution still
iii
Table of Contents
Abstract.................................................................................................................................................. iii
Table of Figures .................................................................................................................................... vi
Acknowledgements ............................................................................................................................. viii
Introduction: Circles of Life .................................................................................................................... 1
What are Artificial Humanities? ............................................................................................................................. 4
Why Comparative Literature?............................................................................................................................... 12
Part I: Posthuman Language ................................................................................................................................ 14
Part II: Literature and Bioethics........................................................................................................................... 19
Chapter 1: Galatea Speaks: From a Cockney Girl to a Neural Network ..............................................29
1.1 Language Acquisition ..................................................................................................................30
1.1.1 What’s in a Name? ........................................................................................................................................ 30
1.1.2 Chatbots ......................................................................................................................................................... 32
1.1.3 An Overview of Galateas ............................................................................................................................ 36
1.2 Language Enhancement .............................................................................................................43
1.3 Language and Diversity ...............................................................................................................56
1.4 Pygmalionesque Creation ............................................................................................................64
1.5 Pygmalionesque Performance .....................................................................................................79
1.6 The Elizas ....................................................................................................................................88
Chapter 2: Humanese: A Posthuman Language ..................................................................................99
2.1 Language in AI .......................................................................................................................... 100
2.1.1 Living through Language: Powers............................................................................................................ 106
2.2 Storytelling ................................................................................................................................. 129
2.2.1 Creative AI: Tomažin and Dahl ............................................................................................................... 132
2.3 Denaturing of Language ........................................................................................................... 146
2.4 Language in Animals................................................................................................................. 152
2.4.1 Salamanders: Čapek and Cortázar ............................................................................................................ 152
2.4.2 Talking Animals: Kanzi the Bonobo, Alex the Parrot, and Chiang’s Parrots ................................... 157
2.5 Theory of Posthuman Language as a Prosthesis ...................................................................... 172
Chapter 3: Diagnosis: Pygmalionism.................................................................................................. 180
3.1 Pygmalionism and Agalmatophilia ........................................................................................... 182
3.1.1. Definitions and Popularity of the Terms ............................................................................................... 182
3.1.2 Autism .......................................................................................................................................................... 191
3.1.3 Legal Literature ........................................................................................................................................... 194
3.1.4 Medical Literature ....................................................................................................................................... 200
3.2 A New Typology of the Pygmalion Paradigm .......................................................................... 204
3.2.1 Serbian Pygmalion .................................................................................................................. 209
3.3 Modern Pygmalions .................................................................................................................. 213
iv
Chapter 4: Diagnosis: Paralysis........................................................................................................... 225
4.1 First, Anthropomorphism .......................................................................................................... 228
4.1.1 A Humanoid Entity as a Paralyzed Person: Nešković .......................................................................... 231
4.2 Second, Dehumanization .......................................................................................................... 233
4.2.1 A Paralyzed Person as a Humanoid Entity: Tiptree .............................................................................. 233
4.3 Extended Bodies: Paralysis and Prosthetics ............................................................................. 237
4.4 Medical Conceptions, Fictional Descriptions ........................................................................... 253
4.5 Persons and Nonpersons........................................................................................................... 257
4.5.1 Consciousness and Personhood: Dahl .................................................................................................... 261
4.5.2 On Robotics ................................................................................................................................................ 265
4.6 Manifesto: How Should Literature Engage in Technology Ethics .......................................... 267
Chapter 5: Brave New Birth: Reproduction and Biotechnology ........................................................ 270
5.1 Reproduction in Fiction ............................................................................................................ 274
5.1.1 Pandora’s Box of Reproduction ............................................................................................................... 278
5.2 The Terminology of ART .......................................................................................................... 287
5.3 Conception Contained ............................................................................................................... 299
5.3.1 Science Fiction Published Before Huxley’s Novel ................................................................................ 300
5.4 A Brief History of IVF ............................................................................................................... 306
5.5 Huxley’s Ectogenesis ................................................................................................................ 309
5.5.1 Cloning and Incest .................................................................................................................. 322
5.5.2 Breaching Time ........................................................................................................................................... 328
5.6 The Huxley Brothers ..................................................................................................................................... 332
5.6.1 Transhumanism........................................................................................................................................... 335
Chapter 6: Prenatal Life: The Island Perfected .................................................................................. 346
6.1 The Very First Portrait ............................................................................................................... 348
6.1.1 Fetuses in Space .......................................................................................................................................... 355
6.1.2 Embryos under the Microscope ............................................................................................................... 361
6.2 The Identity Problem ................................................................................................................ 368
6.2.1 A Brief History of The Identity Problem ............................................................................................... 373
6.2.2 What Does Literature Say About Prenatal Tests? ................................................................................. 375
6.3 Donors ....................................................................................................................................... 378
6.4 Biases ......................................................................................................................................... 390
6.5 Utopias and Kinships ................................................................................................................ 402
6.6 Hybridity.................................................................................................................................... 410
6.6.1 Posthumanist Biology: Hawthorne, Boucher, Butler ............................................................................ 416
7 Conclusion: Back to Mythologies .................................................................................................... 437
8 Bibliography ..................................................................................................................................... 442
v
Table of Figures
vi
Figure 38 Contribution of subfertility treatments to multiple pregnancies overall.. ..................................................325
Figure 39 A sonogram of a 10-week fetus. ..........................................................................................................352
Figure 40 A photograph of a 10-week fetus. ........................................................................................................352
Figure 41 3D printed fetus, based on 3D sonograms. ..........................................................................................353
Figure 42 Normal first-trimester sonogram. .........................................................................................................353
Figure 43 3D ultrasound scan with surface rendering of fetal face. ........................................................................353
Figure 44 The original photograph of an 18-week-old fetus by Lennart Nilsson ...................................................357
Figure 45 Lennart Nilsson’s photo of an 18-week-old fetus featured on the cover of LIFE magazine on April 30,
1965...................................................................................................................................................................357
Figure 46 The Star Child from the very ending of the film 2001: A Space Odyssey. ............................................359
Figure 47 Human blastocyst (five-day-old embryo). ..............................................................................................361
Figure 48 Preformation, drawn by Nicolas Hartsoecker 1694. ............................................................................365
Figure 49 Database of egg donors ........................................................................................................................380
Figure 50 Posters advertising gestational surrogacy. ..............................................................................................386
Figure 51 Pregnant person as a chimera.. ............................................................................................................410
Figure 52 Copper engraving of Doctor Schnabel von Rom, a plague doctor (literally, Dr. Beak) from Rome..........423
Figure 53 Maja Smrekar and Manuel Vason, K-9_topology: Hybrid Family, Berlin 2016. ..............................432
Figure 54 The cover of the Belle and Sebastian’s first album Tigermilk (1996) ....................................................434
Figure 55 The lion-man sculpture from Germany (dated to 37,000 years ago). ....................................................436
vii
Acknowledgements
I would first like to thank my wonderful committee for their inimitable scholarship and mentorship.
Their insightful comments on this work and their encouragement made for an inspiring and
enjoyable writing process. I am extremely grateful for your guidance and support in my academic
endeavors, especially to Marc Shell for spending countless hours in conversation with me, to Karen
Thornber and David Damrosch for their generous guidance through the program, and to Nancy
Jecker for including me into the bioethics field and the academic life at the University of
Washington. It was a privilege to have you on board.
I would like to thank all my teachers who have helped me to embark and finish my PhD
journey: Marko Juvan, Janez Orešnik, Vanesa Matajc, Djelal Kadir, Wai Chee Dimock, Stephanie
Burt, Gregory Nagy, Sandra Naddaff, John Hamilton, Verena Conley, Aida Vidan, Jessie Labov,
Tomislav Longinović, Deirdre Lynch, Katharina Piechocki, Phillip Mead, Beth Blum, James Wood,
Emmanuel Bouju, Chen Zhang, Min Wan, Wei Liu, and Malia Fullerton. Thanks also to always
incredibly helpful administrators and research librarians in comparative literature and English
departments, Isaure Mignotte, Melissa Carden, Gwen Urdang-Brown, and Odile Harter.
I am deeply indebted to my peers and colleagues, my students and advisees. I have learned
enormously from all.
The Merit/Term Time Award and Mind Brain and Behavior Initiative at Harvard University
allowed me to conduct research for this dissertation and to spend two quarters at the University of
Washington School of Medicine. Parts of this dissertation have benefited from the comments
received at conferences and in the process of journal publications.
Special thanks to Honorary Consul of Slovenia Michael Biggins for his translation of Andrej
Tomažin’s short story.
Many thanks to Tobias Rees, Mashinka Firunts Hakopian, and Tui Shaub for reaching out
with a dream position at the Berggruen Institute, a direct continuation of my work in this
dissertation.
My graduate school experience would not be as rich and gratifying without the Peabody
Terrace, Mather House, and Radford Court communities. Their members provided unbidden
support and friendship to my family and proofread my writing, including this dissertation.
I owe everything to my parents, Grozda and France, and my husband Gašper. It was only
for their love and support that I was able to have it all. I dedicate this dissertation to our sons,
Tomaž, Lev, and Emil, all of whom were born while this project grew.
viii
Page intentionally left blank.
ix
Introduction: Circles of Life
What is human? This is not a purely humanist question; it is a multi-species question and a highly
interdisciplinary one. As humans become more and more technologized, the question has moved
into disciplines that deal with the nonhuman. New circles of life have emerged since we last defined
what we mean by concepts like human, life, artificial, or nature. The philosopher Peter Singer
addressed speciesism in his 1975 book Animal Liberation, arguing that human moral progress consists
of the expansion of the circle of beings we regard as persons. Posthumanism further brought
awareness of nonhuman agencies in human bodies, from our own microbiome to human-made
neurodevices. Biotechnology has changed how we practice medicine and how we think about our
bodies, minds, and agencies, and is affecting aspects of human biological evolution. Early artificial
intelligence (AI) was on a quest to imitate the human mind, but has since evolved in other directions
and is currently dominated by the deep learning paradigm, which is revolutionizing close to every
theoretical and practical discipline. With growing belief in the possibility of creating superintelligent
modes of AI (or less ambitious artificial general intelligence, known as AGI) and in the possibility of
solve world problems with technology. The inquiry into the conduct and conditions of life is taking
place in technological and scientific fields without (most) scientists and engineers paying attention to
them and without sufficient opportunities for humanities and social sciences scholars to explore
The human has been undergoing powerful transformations while scholarship that is supposed to
focus on non-nature (i.e. metaphysics and social sciences) has remained largely under the influence
of the established conceptions of the human, nature, and technology. This is why re-defining the
1
human in the twenty-first century Western context is at the center of this project. Literature has
been dealing with this task since its very inception. This dissertation is framed under the Pygmalion
myth as we know it from Ovid’s Metamorphoses onward, a myth widely re-interpreted in Western
literatures and visual arts particularly after the eighteenth century. The focus of the myth is on the
human as the creator—the giving thing that ascribes meaning to the world—and the relationship of
the human with the created, humanlike entities. In support of their positions, transhumanists
frequently invoke ancient philosophy (Plato, Aristotle) and mythology (Prometheus). In the
transhumanist fashion, humans as creators not only form the creation and rearrange the world
according to their desires, like the creator and lover Pygmalion or the creator and inventor
Prometheus, but also according to their own sense of the world, their own hybridity, and their social
and biological networks. This interconnectedness made us all cyborgs, in the sense defined by
Donna Haraway’s ‘Cyborg Manifesto.’ Echoing Bruno Latour’s We Have Never Been Modern and
turning from biological sciences to cybernetics, AI and information technology, N. Katherine Hayles
argued that “we have always been posthuman,” in that we have always used tools to extend the
boundaries of the human (How 291). Echoing Hayles, Tom Boellstorff says that technology is not a
recent arrival but a central feature of humanity, arguing that “it is in being virtual that we are
human” since it is “in human ‘nature’ to experience life through the prism of culture” (5, also 29).
With the invention of highly technological humanoids and technologies that merge with the
human—those that are already here and those that are yet to come—the definition of natural and
artificial life broadens the circle of species: there is biological life and computational life and a variety
of intermediate and merged stages. As a consequence, thinking about the human today requires a
posthumanist frame. One of the tasks of critical posthumanism has been to relinquish
2
overcome since the idea has been central to modern thought ever since humanism surfaced in the
early Renaissance (at that point, still under the influence of Christianity; see more in Pettman).
The project’s mythological framing with the focus on science fiction works that were inspired by the
Pygmalion and Prometheus myths reveals a historical continuity of (re)defining the human in
Western culture, and more broadly in today’s global landscape. The genre of science fiction became
increasingly prevalent and mainstream, Darko Suvin points out, as typical in “the great whirlpool
periods of history” (par. 8). This “literature of cognitive estrangement,” as he terms and
conceptualizes science fiction (par. 2), shares more with the literature of myth, fantasy, and fairy tale
than with naturalistic or empiricist literary genres. However, while myth as a “‘timeless’ and religious
approach look[s] in its own way beneath (or above) the empiric surface,” science fiction relies on a
cognitive approach (par. 8). Opposed to supernatural and empiricist approaches, science fiction
posits questions (rather than mythologically universal answers) and explores where they lead, not
with the imagination of the fairy tale but by building on the existing condition with an empirically
imaginable twist of a cognitively explicable novum, as Suvin terms it, i.e. innovation with a rational
explanation.
This project looks into specific settings of the Pygmalion myth in fiction, science, and society with a
focus on literature and cinema from twentieth-century America (Richard Powers’s Galatea 2.2, James
Tiptree Jr.’s and Ted Chiang’s short stories, Sharon Olds’s, Sue Wood’s, and micha cárdenas’s
poetry), England (Aldous Huxley’s Brave New World, Roald Dahl’s short stories, Richard Meier’s and
Helen Dunmore poetry), and Ireland (G. B. Shaw’s Pygmalion). Western literatures and film (2001: A
Space Odyssey, Blade Runner, Gattaca, Her, Ex Machina) manifest a prominent and increasing interest in
the Pygmalion myth in the last two centuries. A few singular texts from Argentinian (Julio Cortázar),
3
Slovenian (Andrej Tomažin), Serbian (Zoran Nešković), and Czech authors (Karel Čapek) also
crucially contribute to the discussion, even if, with an exception of Nešković’s short story, they are
not Pygmalionesque.
The framing of the project within the Pygmalion myth brings out three related topics: the use of
language in nonhumans, paralysis and pygmalionism as medical diagnoses, and new ways of human
reproduction. All topics stem from the Pygmalion paradigm texts, from which I identify the
following findings that serve as a premise for the paired chapters that follow:
- Chapters 1 and 2 on language in nonhumans: The statue Pygmalion created only acquired a
name (Galatea) in the eighteenth century, and gained the ability to speak fully in the
pygmalionism considers the beloved as a paralyzed human that might or might not be
- Chapters 5 and 6 on human reproduction: The idea that a human and a nonhuman can
produce (human or humanlike) children is present already in Ovid and has been the subject
I coined the term artificial humanities as an umbrella term for the interdisciplinary study of
fundamental questions about the human as they arise from engineering practice, technological
applications, and the interaction between the humanities and the sciences. The split into “two
4
cultures,” the mainstream culture and the scientific culture, as delineated in C. P. Snow’s famous
1959 lecture, has since been partly breached by the increasingly interdisciplinary nature of research
introspection of science and technology. Both of these changes resulted in the birth of fields such as
science and technology studies, science writing, and affective science. Artificial humanities bring the
humanities perspectives into a much-needed discussion with science and engineering to address
pertinent questions about practices that require imminent decisions, be they laboratories or in
policy-making. The questions artificial humanities address are related to technologies—in this
dissertation these are artificial intelligence, social robotics, neurotechnology, and biotechnology—
and can also be applied broadly to natural sciences, such as climatology or microbiology. All of these
popular fields notably center on nonhuman entities or agencies rather than human; and yet, these are
the disciplines that are presently considering the question of the human, often more so than the
traditional fields centering around the human and human agency, such as anthropology, sociology,
psychology, and philology. Moreover, these scientific and technological fields offer tentative answers
to the fundamental philosophical question of What is human?, in terms that radically defy the
understanding of the human on which the human sciences rely. Through artificial humanities, fields
like AI and biotechnology cease to be seen as merely engineering disciplines and become visible also
Conceptions of the human with which humanities and social sciences have operated since the
Enlightenment are problematized in the field of artificial humanities—together with the concept of
nature, covered by natural sciences, also known as hard sciences or sciences of matter, and with the
concept of technology, covered by engineering. Humanities have been at least partly oblivious to the
historical contingency of these concepts: in the twenty-first century, the ontological, institutional,
5
and infrastructural concept of the human does not hold up. Universal categorizations of the human
are taken over by a variety of truths from engineering fields (AI derails the human differently than
humanities). The difficulty of delineating terms such as human, nature, technology, or artificial—also
present in this dissertation—renders these categories more uncertain than they have been over the
last two hundred years. Artificial humanities are necessary to help us rethink these basic concepts,
whose application to the contemporary world reveals a fallacy in our conceptualization. While the
humanities tend to be rather defensive against the philosophical applications of technologies like AI,
since some see AI as a reduction of the human to the machine or vice versa, engineers are generally
too busy with their own research and are largely unequipped to be able to reconsider the
The human was considered as more than mere nature and other than instinctive nonhuman animals
or mechanical machines already in the antiquity. These concepts are delineated already in Aristotle’s
Politics, written 350 B.C.E., as the natural order of things: in all the mankind, the male rules the
female and the master owns the slave by nature (I, 5, 1254b); or in the Vedas, which give the
universal scope to the Hindu caste system. The modern period reinforced these conceptions to an
extreme with humanism, in which the human is the center of the world and the single agent of
change in the world. With distinct features of language and intellect, tools and technology, culture
and arts, freedom of will and subjectivity, human was a subject among objects, a thinking thing
among thoughtless things, an entity opposite to any other. Posthumanism has pointed out that all of
these criteria are outdated. For example, Haraway’s ‘Cyborg Manifesto’ rejects the humanist
6
The posthumanist debate began in the 1980s with postcolonial, feminist, and postmodern critique.
However, the impulse to reconsider the human came from sciences and engineering research that
repeatedly encountered a dilemma of where to draw the boundaries between the nonhuman, the
already-human, and the still-human. The dilemma is ever-evolving, for example, in synthetic biology
where human-made products are completely natural but do not exist in nature; in the impossibility
artificial intelligence and machine learning as their own types of intelligence in a world-frame not
intelligible to humans.
Posthumanism sees no attribute as uniquely human, instead viewing the human as a part of a larger
ecosystem in which the human is physically, chemically, and biologically dependent on the
environment (Keeling and Lehman 2, 5). The concept of posthumanism involves a plurality of
(sometimes contradictory) ideas on what is human, some of which have been presented in science
fiction literature and film long before posthumanism emerged as a theoretical and practical
damaging—human impact on the nonhuman world), new materialism (anti-dualist view on matter),
and so on. All these views are a part of critical posthumanism; they keep the human separate from
nature and largely hope to overcome moral anthropocentrism. While posthumanism criticizes “the
humanist ideal of ‘Man’ as the universal human, post-anthropocentrism criticizes species hierarchy
and advances bio-centered egalitarianism” (Braidotti and Hlavajova 1). Contrary to critical
posthumanism, ontological posthumanism makes for an intensification of humanism, and with it the
7
superhumans), an entirely anthropocentric movement widely present in technologies and pop
culture (see more in Wolfe, Nayar, Braidotti and Hlavajeva). In my dissertation, I demonstrate that
the two main strains of postmodernism are not as separate as some scholars believe—most
prominent among them is N. Katherine Hayles, who sees them as competing forces and has
established the term posthuman as an umbrella term that includes all variants that the two types of
posthumanism encompass. Throughout the dissertation I show that transhumanism permeates the
objective natural sciences, regardless of the critical morality offered in posthumanist theories. In any
discipline, even in a science that is widely considered as objective as it gets (an understanding
impossible to avoid.
In addition, posthumanism is eager to remind us that the exemplary human is all too often
delineated in racist, ableist, sexist, and classist terms. (In fact, the ostracization of ‘lesser’ types of
humans or creatures was a cause of the origin of the posthumanist thought; most prominent
posthumanist theorists are primarily feminist theorists, such as Rosi Braidotti, or animal studies
scholars, such as Cary Wolfe.) This fault of universalizing the human is also identified in my project
in relation to every topic I pursue. Since my project’s overall focus is on language as one of the
criteria for the human, this issue always comes to light in relation to some kind of speech paralysis
Technologization of the human and of human attributes (such as human language) is based upon
the exemplary human and created for this exemplary human. Artificial humanities are pertinent to
the theory and practice of nascent and well-established technologies because byproducts of
technologization (be they algorithms or data in AI, or the choice for or against a genetic condition in
8
assisted reproductive technology) stem from societal biases, which are aptly specified and thoroughly
conferred in fiction. There are two main purposes of artificial humanities: on the engineering side,
the goal is to improve the practice and implementation of human-centered technologies, and on the
humanities side, the goal is to reformulate old-fashioned concepts and contexts while producing a
surplus of new concepts and contexts inspired by the evolving technologies and sciences. In our
rapidly evolving world, both sides have fallen blind to the philosophical contingencies of our
language, context, time, and the human (per Katherine Hayles’s denaturing order). The denaturing
of such basic concepts demands a reevaluation of each one of them as well as their relatives
In the present project, artificial humanities aim to study the relationship between human and
technological nonhuman entities, which are human-made and thus, by some definitions, artificial.
Technology and the arts, including literature, are the utmost human-made creations, the highest
forms of human spirit, expression, and knowledge. As I approach my research questions through
literature and literary scholarship, I point out that literature was often the first discourse to publicly
formulate and identify novel and complex ideas in an original and profound manner. For example,
since fiction speculated on various technologies on a societal and individual level before their
approximations were ever invented, literary scholarship was therefore in a privileged position to
reflect on these ramifications from an ethical perspective or social, political, and legal philosophy
before these ideas were ever presented outside the fabricated reality of other fields. As this
dissertation shows, the privileged position is not merely about literature being the first medium but,
9
Using literature for the purpose of artificial humanities might seem reductive to literature. However,
literature does not serve solely as a space for exploration or as a moral compass. Instead, the
exploration and the moral questions should develop in the technological fields themselves. As a
cultural companion and sometimes inspiration to technologies, literature can help us formulate the
research questions and the discrepancies between them as well as to predict and avoid repercussions
literary lens have shown that, in fact, they are no different from questions posed by social robotics
engineers (e.g. Should a robot be programmed to know their maker?) or research embryologists (e.g.
How long should we grow embryos in a laboratory?). Scientists themselves have expressed a need
for the humanities scholars to assist in resolving philosophical dilemmas that arise from their
respective quantitative disciplines. This resulted in newly developed fields surrounding the ethics of
technology, such as ethics of artificial intelligence, and new directions in the well-established
subfields of ethics, such as bioethics. Both subfields of ethics are discussed in this dissertation, with
AI ethics covered in the first three chapters and bioethics in the last three chapters.
The overarching argument of this dissertation is that literary representations serve an important
this project is the first scholarly work, to my knowledge, that has aligned literature with fields as
diverse as artificial intelligence, social robotics, neurotechnology, and biotechnology. Granted, there
is increasing interest in works such as Frankenstein or Brave New World in relation to new
technologies, but overall these discussions are not common in literary scholarship and tend not to
include ethics and history of science. An exception to this was found in studies on visual
10
technologies used in reproductive technologies, discussed alongside poetry in chapter 6. I have also
not traced scholarship that would discuss most of my main texts—G. B. Shaw’s Pygmalion, Richard
Powers’s Galatea 2.2, Karel Čapek’s War with the Newts, short stories by Ted Chiang, Julio Cortázar,
Roald Dahl, Zoran Nešković, James Tiptree Jr., and Andrej Tomažin, or contemporary poetry—in
relation to the technologies explored here. To my surprise, however, humanities discussions with
literary examples are not a rare finding in science journals, especially medical journals (see
Kondziella or Plum and Posner). Likewise, I found that ethics papers dealing with a promising area
of technology, such as latest neurotechnologies or AI, employed Isaac Asimov’s Three Laws of
Robotics in addressing ethical issues around nonhuman agency (see Goering et al., McCauley). This
crossover, I believe, only further enforces the inevitability of a concept such as artificial humanities.1
I further make a call for literary scholars to actively join the discussion on how literature informs and
molds our conceptions around frontier technologies, and, further, to engage in the practice of
creating these technologies. I argue we need to use the reflective public space of literature with its
cultural diversity and unlimited speculation in more practical ways, not only with literature as a
pathway to some crucial ethical and philosophical questions that steer the current focus of science
1 While working on this project, I learned about other similar initiatives for a restructuration of disciplines towards
studying humanities in relation to science and engineering, now considered to be the main driving force of the change in
the world and the human. I was contacted by the Berggruen Institute whose mission is to “develop ideas and shape
political, economic and social institutions for the 21st century” (Berggruen). The Institute focuses on four major societal
transformations that are currently taking place: The Future of Capitalism, The Future of Democracy, Geopolitics and
Globalization, and, under Tobias Rees’s initiative, the recently developed program The Transformations of the Human.
The Transformation of the Human program places artists and social sciences and humanities scholars in collaboration
with AI and biotech technologists to address philosophical questions about the human today. The Institute is also
hoping to restructure the current approach to interdisciplinarity in higher education.
The linguist and the current president of Northeastern University Joseph Aoun applied a similar idea with a narrower
focus on AI and robotics to the American higher education in his book Robot-Proof: Higher Education in the Age of Artificial
Intelligence (2017). Aoun lays out the framework for a new academic discipline, humanics, a mixture of humanities and
STEM. His book promotes education which prepares students for a market filled with smart machines by developing
technological literacy (mathematics, engineering, coding), data literacy (using and understanding data), and human
literacy (social milieu, communication and engagement with others).
11
and technology but also with literature co-formulating our research questions and the philosophical
implications at stake.
In the sections above I made an argument about how literature can help us navigate contemporary
challenges brought on by innovative and already existing, often widely used, technologies. Through
literature one can approach topics as diverse as history, medicine, economics, and video gaming, to
explore how fiction can provide answers to complex philosophical and ethical questions. For
example, scientific advances bring on new social conditions that may be difficult to conceptualize,
such as new methods of interconnectedness, digital censorship, and control (compare the Internet
and E. M. Forster’s ‘The Machine Stops’), and literary analysis can help us point out and evaluate the
ramifications of particular scientific advances. Neural networks like Richard Powers’s Helen from
Galatea 2.2, a human equivalent of brain in a computer, are not around the corner. However, we still
fantasize about digitizing our brains and making conscious machines, as attested in fiction and
nonfiction, film, and other arts, and these fantasies translate into actual goals in technology. Studying
fiction that thematizes humanoid creation and human enhancement is therefore a necessary step
Comparative literature is a discipline that pays attention to the mixing of zones and transverses
national, linguistic, and formal boundaries created by our conceptions of space, time, code, and so
perfect discipline to host artificial humanities and their quest to reconfigure the human. The
12
interdisciplinary nature of the field makes it especially suited to evaluate new developments in
literary practice and literary studies, such as digital narratives (cyberdrama, hypertextual narration,
and cyberpoetry) or, as in this dissertation, creative writing by AI (poetry, film scenarios, and prose
co-authored with human writers). The field’s position amidst different linguistic traditions, scholarly
discourses, and media has been especially helpful in my project as it expanded from the initial focus
on American and British fiction to visual arts, South and Central Slavic texts, and medical and legal
literature.
In addition to that, posthumanism has found its home in comparative literature and related
disciplines that are housed under the humanities and social sciences. Posthumanism, with its
varieties, accommodates the extensiveness of the Pygmalionesque topics addressed here due to its
origins in science fiction and critical social theory, fields that have always received scientific and
engineering ideas with open interest and willingness to extrapolate their ideas, and the capability to
fabricate a world that goes against them. Scientific and literary cultures interweave right at the nexus
of the research questions I pursue here, largely building on the posthumanist ground and its
inclusion of the arts and sciences as practice and theory. The mere term posthuman is a convenient
description of this project’s goal to define what comes after the human, as the liberal humanist
subject that has emerged from the Enlightenment needs to be re-evaluated in contemporary context.
Nonetheless, the term posthuman is also problematic and narrow. Conflating the subject of liberal
humanism with the term human is limiting to “human lifeways,” as Tom Boellstorff comments (29).
Besides that, posthumanism is deeply embedded in Western philosophical thought and particularly
in the humanities debates. A posthuman is sometimes called a cyborg, Homo cyber, Homo faber,
13
Homo deus, etc., but all these names are used within the same traditions and similar discourses, and
This dissertation sticks with the traditional naming of posthumanism and posthuman, but although
the theoretical frame of this dissertation is embedded into the posthuman view, my view of how we
should study and think about the human often deconstructs posthumanism, first, by revealing its
permeating anthropocentrism (a not entirely surprising finding considering the fact that the field
grew as a critical reaction to humanism) and, second, by criticizing a posthumanist belief where what
is ‘beyond the human’ is naively assumed to be a continuous good and a moral authority. It would
be difficult to find a more accommodating field than comparative literature for one to work inside a
posthumanist theoretical framing while pushing towards its reorganization—and where one can
question the definition of the human only to conclude there is not one but many definitions, none
of which can be universal at this point. Universality of the term is not the goal, although the tension
towards a convergence of views from different disciplines into a coherent interlocking narrative
Language and communication are the cornerstones of AI engineering. Programming and coding use
coding languages, most commonly English, which makes AI not only an engineering product but
also a product of a language. The development of AI relies not only on programming but also on
the human touch: how AI communicates with humans (customers) is of utmost importance.
Machine learning of language was first established as mimicry of a user’s input with Weizenbaum’s
14
chatbot ELIZA; today, we have enormous sets of language data (largely from the internet) that are
fed into AI through the models of supervised and sometimes unsupervised learning.
I call all human languages humanese in order to distinguish them from language in general, as a
method and system of human communication, as well as from other types of languages, such as
coding language. New ideas explored in the first two chapters evaluate humanese as a means of
enhancement used by human and nonhuman entities. The chapters explore the following questions:
How can humanese be enhanced in human and nonhuman entities? What changes in humanlike
creations once they acquire humanese? What is common and shared in language when used by
humans and nonhumans? Finally, how will nonhuman use of humanese affect it in the long run?
The first chapter contextualizes a novel idea of language enhancement and focuses on Eliza’s
language training in George Bernard Shaw’s play Pygmalion (1913). By making a link between Eliza
and chatbots (i.e. AI programs that can hold a conversation through audio or textual media, such as
Apple’s virtual assistant Siri), I show how Shaw anticipates computer-based language training. I
suggest that Shaw, basing this play on phonetician Henry Sweet and surrounded by the Bell family
that was about to invent a telephone, picked on the nascent science of instilling humanese in
By comparing fictional and actual galateas, I follow the transformation of language into what I call
posthuman language: language used by computational entities and technologically enhanced humans.
Striking similarities emerge in the language training of fictional characters (Shaw’s Eliza) and real-
world AI (Hanson’s robot Sophia), including the presence of a performing identity, scripted
language, and speech disorders, suggesting that human mimicry is crucial for establishing rapport
15
between humans and humanlike entities. This observation allows me to propose that scientific
evolution still embraces the human, despite recent posthumanist and post-anthropocentric claims to
the contrary.
I apply the lowercase term galatea (as opposed to Galatea, the name acquired by Pygmalion’s lover
in the eighteen-century renditions of the myth) broadly to all created, humanlike entities that tend to
yield love, with an interest in borderline literary examples. I argue that language acquisition in
galateas reflects their growing independence, starting with singing and scripted words and ending in
autonomous and self-learning artificial intelligence. Among other Pygmalionesque texts, I discuss
Mary Shelley’s novel Frankenstein; or the Modern Prometheus (1818) and dissect Frankenstein’s artificial
human’s eloquence, which, I argue, is a revolutionary feature for galateas who, following Shelley’s
The second chapter deals with language in both fictional (Helen the neural network) and real
artificial intelligence galateas (ELIZA the chatbot, Sophia the robot). I suggest that species
connection through physical resemblance, nonverbal gestures, or, at the very least, language fluency
the early galateas, which were all beautiful objects (statues, paintings, etc.), I show that more recent
galateas are required to have language but do not necessarily still possess a body. The primary
galatean attribute and core galatean identity have therefore moved from the body to the mind. I
further argue that this change is a reflection of a larger societal trend that perceives and ranks human
likeness in humanlike intelligence rather than in bodily form. This intelligence is expected to
correspond to normative human behavior and is reflected primarily through written (chatbots,
16
social humanoid robots).
Language also serves as a distinction between humans and animals or machines. Linguists argue that
nonhumans do not have cognitive capacity to use humanese: they do, however, use nonhumanese
languages, i.e. animal, plant, and machine languages (although most linguists would rather simply call
them simply communication). There is a great divide in our perception of these nonhuman entities;
even if animals acquire some humanese (linguists call these animals linguistically trained) and are
cognitively able understand it, they are largely believed to be merely parroting it. Machines, on the
other hand, as good as they might be in simulating language, are given more merit in language
abilities and much more responsibility, even if they are not capable of understanding. I first ask if
these refutations are legitimate, then examine a variety of literary examples through the
prosthesis.
Per N. Katherine Hayles, a postmodern impulse which began with structuralism first denatured
language, then time, context, and finally the human (with the cyborg), showing that “concepts once
considered natural were social constructions” (Chaos 27). In terms of humanese language in
nonhuman entities, we are already at the point when humans cannot always tell if they are having a
conversation with a machine or another human. We have not yet invented a truly convincing
creative AI but we are getting there. What happens when even storytelling, the most human product
This question has been recently addressed by journalists, but the discussion is noticeably lacking in
literary scholarship. To address it, I compare two little-known short stories, Roald Dahl’s ‘The Great
17
Automatic Grammatizator’ (1953) and Andrej Tomažin’s ‘Heroes, Lackeys and Artificial
and creativity, particularly generators of fictional and factual writing. I suggest that although AI
creativity has not yet reached a humanlike level, it has already been a valuable resource for human
creators and will continue to be, as it has aspired to present new levels of creativity. The
aforementioned stories warn that AI’s entrance into the creative writing domain requires a complete
reevaluation and regulation of writing practices and the literary market as well as literary criticism
and theory. AI writing by default crosses the line of plagiarism, twists the concept of authorship, and
allows for massive production while also opening new creative platforms (for example, every original
interlaced with human creativity). Continuing Hayles’s denaturing idea, I further ask how humanese
I then turn to the other end of the spectrum: creative and humanese-reared nonhuman animals.
animals with human habits and language. I look into most notorious cases of apes (Kanzi the
bonobo) and birds (Alex the parrot), and relate them to literary texts that thematize language in
parrots (Ted Chiang’s 2016 very short story ‘Great Silence’) and salamanders (Karel Čapek’s 1936
novel War with the Newts [Válka s mloky] and Julio Cortázar’s 1956 short story ‘Axolotl’). The
approaches to animal use of humanese are diverse in all these fictional and factual stories but they all
have one common feature: social bonding between a human trainer and animal trainee is crucial for
successful language rearing—a finding also applicable to user interaction with intelligent machines.
18
inbred human feature. Language, after all, is only a potential faculty and the ability to perform it
ranges among humans as well as nonhumans. In this view, language is an artificial prosthesis, a tool
created by humans and imposed on nonhuman entities. Instead of using the plain and vague term
language, I conceptualize this view with the term humanese. I have found that the idea of language
(humanese) as a prosthesis was proposed at two different, independent occasions without a wider
response in their respective scholarly communities: first in a 2000 essay by a literary critic John
Weightman and second in a 2013 paper by a linguist Salikoko Mufwene. Weightman sees language
as an internal instrument, a prosthesis (whose inner workings we do not understand), and Mufwene
advocates language as a prosthetic technology with a biological substratum (which might help us
understand its inner workings). I propose that nonhuman agency over humanese can transform and
enhance our language, primarily through technological means (of computerization, AI,
neurotechnology, pharmaceutics, etc.). This further implies that humans could enhance our abilities
in abstract thinking, creative writing, and so on through computational and biological language
enhancement.
The second part of the dissertation examines medical diagnoses, symptoms, and procedures that are
brought to the forefront in the Pygmalion paradigm fiction. This is a novel approach to studying
literature as well as to addressing the medical, ethical, social and psychological questions that such
conditions open. Chapter 3 looks into modern pygmalionism, i.e. intimate relationships held with
Chapters 5 and 6 investigate assisted reproductive technologies from the perspective of rhetoric and
visual technologies that shape our views on human reproduction as well as from the perspective of
19
related technologies largely employed by in-vitro fertilization (gamete donations, gene editing,
gestational surrogacy, etc.) as they have been speculated about in fiction and film.
The questions that these four chapters open are multifold and relate to computational as well as
biological technologies, often both at once. As I argue above, we should not always discuss one
without the other, since these technologies are becoming more intertwined every day. Many of these
questions continue the discussion from the first two chapters. They flow from one chapter to
another in the following order: Why do we create expensive humanlike robots? Why don’t we
instead invest this money into robots that would alleviate caretakers’ burdens? Why do we fall in
love with humanoids? Why do we get emotionally attached to our prosthetic technology? How can
this technology and our practices around them be more helpful to severely paralyzed patients? What
are the ethical issues with extended bodies? Should an object with an automatized agency gain
personhood? What about an object that one views and treats as a person? What are the implications
of such personhood for the prenatal life? Do we change our conceptions of prenatal life based on
available technologies? Do we make choices about prenatal life based on false beliefs? I argue that
literature can help us formulate these questions before the technology is put into practice and then
In Shakespeare’s The Tempest, when Prospero’s daughter Miranda meets a dozen men who have been
shipwrecked on her island, she first realizes that there is a “brave new world”2 out there and praises
the “beauteous mankind” and its “goodly creatures”3 (5.1 186-87). One of these men is Prince
2 Aside from bravery, the world ‘brave’ might imply savagery (as in Spanish toro bravo).
3 The world ‘goodly’ renders a question of proper transcription as possibly Shakespeare used ‘good’.
20
Ferdinand, a young man she meets at the beginning of the play and quickly marries. She does not
meet the rest of the shipwrecked crew until the final act when she reacts with the cited famous lines,
the last words she utters in the play. Ferdinand is only the second man she has met in her life;4 the
first being her father, together with his nonhuman and hardly human servants, spirit Ariel and
monstrous Caliban. When she encounters Ferdinand, she is at first not certain whether he is a
human or a spirit,5 but falls in love with him regardless of his human status.6 Miranda’s love story
points out at least two things related to the topics of the second half of the dissertation,
pygmalionism and reproduction: that she does not have and is not given much choice in finding her
mate on a deserted island prone to inbreeding, and that she does not care about Ferdinand’s human
status, possibly because she has been living among humans and nonhumans for most of her life.
John, the central character of the second part of Aldous Huxley’s Brave New World, is called a
“savage” in the “civilized” World State. Among other things, he differs from the World State
citizens by engaging in literature, knowing Shakespeare by heart, and having a whole different set of
values, such as his belief in the institution of marriage. In conversation with another central
character and societal outsider, Bernard, John brings up Miranda’s words of wonder about the
“beauteous mankind” (129) and asks Bernard, the World State protagonist of the first part of the
novel, if he is married to beautiful Lenina. Bernard’s reaction is laughter (“Ford, no!”), and John
laughs as well, reciting Miranda’s words in irony: “O brave new world that has such people in it”
(130). “You have a most peculiar way of talking sometimes,” Bernard replies, not knowing that John
4“Why speaks my father so ungently? This / Is the third man that e’er I saw, the first / That e’er I sigh’d for: pity move
my father / To be inclined my way!” (1.2 440-43)
5 “What is’t? a spirit? / Lord, how it looks about! Believe me, sir, / It carries a brave form. But ‘tis a spirit” (1.2 403-05)
6 “I might call him / A thing divine, for nothing natural / I ever saw so noble” (1.2 410-12)
21
quoted The Tempest. Such differences between the two characters and their respective worlds become
graver and ultimately fatal for John during his visit to the “brave new world” of the World State.
John’s borrowed words from The Tempest are still one of the most common literary references, used
The biotechnological brave new world is discussed in detail in chapter 5, through Aldous Huxley’s
dystopian novel that inspired the overused phrase. Huxley imagined assisted reproductive
technologies in astonishingly accurate detail decades before the actual technology was first attempted
in the 1950s and resulted in an actual birth in 1978, an event followed by millions of children being
conceived via in vitro fertilization (IVF). IVF technology is also an access point for newer
technologies, such as gene editing, gamete donation and gestational surrogacy. Critics of new
technologies, not without reason, like to bring back historical stains. Eugenics has been practiced in
a variety of arrangements; however, the eugenics of modern genetics is nothing like the human race
has ever seen before. These technologies are bound to profoundly transform how we practice
medicine and view our own bodies and traditional biological heritage. We are pressed for time with
ethical questions, as attested by some bold and hasty acts that are carried out before we are able to
properly reflect on them (such as Jiankui He’s in vitro genome editing of the twins born in 2018 and
another baby in 2019). The social ramifications of these controversial and revolutionary acts and our
reactions to them will bear fruit and will burden our descendants, whose lives, bodies, and values
Today, people can connect with other people from all across the globe merely by accessing the
World Wide Web. When one is not adept to the virtual world—like Miranda who is naïve about the
world outside her island—one can easily mistake a bot for a human. This is also why ‘the potato test’
22
was invented on a popular dating application, Tinder: should the responder fail to respond ‘potato’
when requested, then it is likely a bot and not a human. More than half of web traffic is made by
bots (Zeifman) and the number of these and similar artificial intelligence ‘spirits’ has long surpassed
that of the people. Bots might be powerful enough to manipulate public opinion, which is especially
pertinent to politics (Yao). In the twenty-first century, a majority of the brave new world beings are
virtual and computational while the majority of the brave new world humans are altered through some
sort of biological technology (vaccines, GMO food, etc.). In this dissertation, I focus exclusively on
AI and robotics for the first set of being, and neurotechnology, assisted reproductive technology,
Adding humanlike robotics to an artificial mind makes humans more likely to form relationships
with nonhumans. Granted, at this time, only a handful of people live with humanlike carebots,
sexbots, or social robots; however, a majority of Westerners live with virtual assistants that possess
no body and are instead embodied in their phone or personal computer. People using these devices
(sometimes already called cyborgs) tend to say they cannot imagine their lives without them. The
purpose of these devices is not only to assist but also to socialize: for example, when Apple’s first
TV advertisement introduced Siri they called her an assistant and a companion (Turkle 339).
Sometimes these relationships transfer from banal everyday requests into intimate needs and people
fall in love with the artificial entities. The first wave of digisexualities, which includes dating apps
and meeting through virtual environment, has already become the norm, and the second wave, does
not necessarily include a human partner (virtual reality, sexbots), is emerging. Forming relationships
through the means of technology further impacts the future of marriage, kinship, and reproduction,
altogether steering the trajectory of the human evolution. The train of thought presented in this
23
In the second part of the dissertation, I lay out a framework for the study of literature and ethics,
here mostly bioethics, in relation to new technologies. I argue that fictional and nonfictional
literature introduces, explores, assesses, and interprets bioethical questions on multiple levels. I see
literature as a self-reflection on diverse traditions, perspectives, and values that offers an advantage
to looking at a moral dilemma in this broad manner from which we might gain, as Daniel P. Sulmasy
and Jeremy Sugarman write in Methods in Medical Ethics, “a richer understanding of that moral
question and a better grasp of the answer” (3). Literature is also a common public space not only for
imagining and speculating about new ideas (as a laboratory) but also for reflecting on their
consequences (in an imagined society, stranded on the experimented island). As such, it can inform
ethics, future studies, disability studies, gender and sexuality studies, race studies, and related fields in
First of all, science and technology feed ideas in fiction, and vice versa. For example, the Star Trek
computer and Eliza Doolittle were major inspirations for chatbots and virtual assistants used in
today’s cell phones and improvisational theater (discussed in Chapter 1). Second, literature offers
Quasimodo and Münchausen syndromes) as cultural capital, some of which serve a symbolic
function (axolotl, discussed in Chapter 2). Third, fiction works as a space for inventing new
technologies and reflects on their social and individual ramifications (autonomous neurological
devices, discussed in Chapter 4). Fourth, nonfiction memoirs, autobiographies, and essays are
powerful tools that can be used to discuss medical conditions and technologies on an individual level
(patients with the locked-in syndrome, discussed in Chapter 4), as recognized by the fields of
medical humanities and narrative medicine. Fifth, both fiction and nonfiction offer a space for
24
fostering solutions (Asimov’s laws of robotics, discussed in Chapter 4) as well as a safe and
productive space for conversation (literature groups in hospitals). Sixth, literature can provide a
richer context from a patient narrative, if that narrative is at all possible (the Vigand couple each
offer a perspective on the husband’s illness, discussed in Chapter 4). Seventh, literature also offers a
broad and diverse historical and cultural narrative (stigma around cancer and AIDS, romanticization
discussed in Chapters 5 and 6). Finally, literature explores and re-defines human nature and the
world around us, which is essential to ethics and philosophy and further extends to the practice of
science and technology. The underlying philosophical question of this dissertation, What is human?, is
essentially imbedded in every work of literature, with the novel serving as the human genre in the
nineteenth century and science fiction as the human genre in the twentieth century.
Although the Pygmalion myth has been widely discussed in Western literary scholarship, I make
three additional observations regarding the topic in chapter 3. First, I develop a typology for the
texts that fit the Pygmalion paradigm. The typology points out a crucial bifurcation in these types of
stories. In the Ovidian, “Pygmalionesque” type the creator of the humanoid is the same character as
their lover, and in the “petrophiliac” type the creator is a separate character from the lover, which
brings up an entirely different setting from the Pygmalionesque type. Second, the variants of the
myth are also present in non-Western cultures, which suggests that the concept is widespread
throughout the world. For example, I traced the myth through Native American, Indian, Slavic, and
North African folk tales. Third, although the Pygmalion theme is becoming increasingly present in
factual and fictional lives of modern societies, it has been poorly examined in medical and legal
settings. My conclusion finds less stigmatization of the condition in the modern day than a few
decades ago. I argue that the view is shifting due to the impact of popular culture, which increasingly
25
engages with the Pygmalion myth, as well as due to the increasingly intimate and eroticized human
relationships with artificial entities, the first wave of this engagement being human-to-human
relationships led through a technologized medium. This first wave is a part of emerging
digisexualities, which include any kind of technologized sexuality where pygmalionism would be
considered a sexual orientation rather than a paraphilia and would therefore not require medical
Chapter 4 looks at pygmalionism from the perspective of the paralyzed beloved. Severe bodily
paralysis is often ascribed to Pygmalionesque objects, such as ascribing humanity to social robots
(e.g. Sophia from Hanson Robotics received Saudi Arabian citizenship and UN ambassadorship). In
relation to the humanization of galateas, I discuss a recently discovered Serbian short story by Zoran
Nešković which received a film adaptation and, unlike many other similar stories, directly addresses
a variety of ethical questions pertaining to social and sex robots as well as virtual assistants and
therapists. Then I look into the opposite effect, dehumanization, in the case of James Tiptree Jr.’s
short story, in which a young woman is plugged into a neurotechnologically-led human, purposely
grown without a brain. This fictional story is put in a dialogue with testimonies from locked-in
patients and experiments with the most recent neurotechnologies, such as brain-computer interface
and geminoids. This juxtaposition reveals the necessity and benefits of these technologies for the
severely paralyzed, as well as the Pygmalionesque attachments that develop from such prosthetic
arrangements. Finally, by closely reading Roald Dahl’s short story, I open the question of
personhood for human and nonhuman entities in cases where communication is not possible. I
show how conception of social personhood, as suggested by Nancy Jecker, and identity as a social
26
Chapter 5 opens a new topic of human reproduction. I argue that our conceptions of human
reproduction are affected by its terminology, enforced through assisted reproductive technologies.
My focus on the terminology around embryos and novel techniques in assisted reproductive
technologies is fresh, but the idea itself is not new: posthumanist, postmodernist and
poststructuralist theories all question how truth is made. With the examples of poetry (Sharon Olds,
Richard Meier), I expose the line between what is considered natural and artificial in reproduction.
The rest of the chapter makes a detailed comparison of the prescient reproductive process in Aldous
Huxley’s Brave New World to techniques in today’s in-vitro fertilization, cloning, gene editing, and
conclusion, Aldous Huxley’s satirical fiction is paralleled by the views of his biologist brother, Julian
Huxley, who invented the term transhumanism and endorsed it in all seriousness—a view I deem
conceptions around human reproduction to the visual technologies used in these practices. I
demonstrate how greatly the visual technologies that are used in reproduction are fabricated. I begin
with ultrasound and extend the discussion to ultrasound poetry (Helen Dunmore, Sue Wood),
with a subsequent novelization (Stanley Kubrick and Arthur C. Clark). In all these examples,
embryos and fetuses are depicted in space and as separate from the womb. This separation from a
woman’s body was already accounted in Huxley’s novel as well as in other science fiction texts of
the 1930s. I continue my discussion on biases of technologies used in reproduction by shedding light
on the famous philosophical non-identity problem that focuses on the unknown existence of future
27
beings. On the example of a scene from Andrew Niccol’s Gattaca, I propose that advances in
technology (prenatal diagnostic testing, preimplantation genetic screening, donor and surrogate
selection, gene editing, etc.) have already shifted the focus to known potential existences, which I call
‘the identity problem.’ Here, too, the result of a test can be misleading or biased through societal or
medical expectations. After exposing biases as a result of technologies, I look into biases and
practices in gamete donation and selection, while also shedding light on the experience of the
LGBTQIA+ community.
The final part of the chapter opens a new way of looking at assisted reproductive technologies and
speculates about hybridity in posthuman and posthumanist biology. I follow Pramod Nayar’s
definitions of the two biologies: posthuman biology reinvents the human as a part of the posthuman
movement we are experiencing at the moment, and posthumanist biology continues this trend
largely through biotechnologization into a more inclusive, but also interbred, human species (126-
27). I use the examples of Hawthorne’s ‘Rappaccini’s Daughter,’ Anthony Boucher’s sequel
‘Rappaccini’s Other Daughter,’ and the examples of Octavia Butler’s ‘Bloodchild’ and Lilith’s Brood:
The Xenogenesis Trilogy (Dawn, Adulthood Rites, Imago) to show how Boucher and Butler make a shift
posthumanism, highlighted in other chapters: (a) a quest for interconnectedness of all living and
nonliving entities and their environment, (b) a view of biology as a technology and technology
becoming biologized (Franklin Biological 3), and (c) a perception of human body and mind as
pathological (a medical approach), but nonetheless reparable through posthuman and posthumanist
28
Chapter 1: Galatea Speaks: From a Cockney Girl to a Neural Network
Pamina:
Love sweetens every sorrow;
Every creature pays homage to it.
Papageno:
It gives relish to the days of our life,
It acts in the cycle of nature.1
Emanuel Schikaneder, W. A. Mozart’s Die Zauberflöte (1791)
Mythologies are rife with artificial humans and prototechnological motifs. The ancient Greek myth
of Pygmalion has been repeatedly singled out as a central trope for addressing our relation to
technology, human and humanoid creatures. The myth has responded to the development of self-
pride and hubris in humans with the development of technical innovation, speculated and evaluated
the means by which we create artificial humans, ranging from arts and artisanship to science and
high technology, and opened questions of the ethics of creating and enhancing humans and
humanlike creatures, among other things. Myths similar to Pygmalion’s are found in ancient cultures
around the world, from Native American folk tales to North Africa and the Silk Road. Since this
literary trope has been so prevalent, it allows us to trace a history of our conceptions about the
human, nature, and technology. Furthermore, it allows us to take a look at our current moment and
critically inspect the practices that have evolved in technologies that seek to imitate and improve the
human state, including artificial intelligence and social robotics which are addressed in the following
two chapters.
29
1.1 Language Acquisition
Who is Galatea and why does it matter if she spoke? The name ‘Galatea’ is primarily associated with
misogynistic Pygmalion who sculpts a beautiful ivory woman and, with godly help of animation,
ultimately enters into a fruitful marriage with her. ‘Galatea’ also stands for any human-made artificial
woman, made of organic and inorganic materials and more or less full of life, which provokes
romantic interest in a man. I distinguish between the two meanings by using a capital letter for the
proper name Galatea and, rather unusually, a lower-case letter for the general use; the same goes for
Pygmalion and pygmalion. Contrary to the popular use, Pygmalion’s artificial woman remains
unnamed in all the early renditions of the myth we know so far.2 The name Galatea was attributed to
the animated woman only in the eighteenth century and was first popularized by J. J. Rousseau’s
Pygmalion (1770), and then only hundred years later by W. S. Gilbert’s play Pygmalion and Galatea
(1871) (Joshua 34, 155). Pygmalion’s ivory statue is most likely not named after the story of Acis and
Galatea,3 another myth from Ovid’s Metamorphoses, but was ascribed this name due to its meaning in
Greek, milk-white, as ivory. Since idolatry was forbidden in the Middle Ages, the Pygmalion myth,
with the exception of the popular La Roman de la Rose, emerges only in the Renaissance and becomes
a dominant trope in the eighteenth century. This was not only the time Galatea was named, but also
2 The earliest versions we know are Ovid’s most influential poem (8 AD) and Philostephanus’s earliest version (third
century BC), known through Clement of Alexandria and Arnobius of Sicca’s versions (third and fourth century AD)
(Joshua 1). The myth appears again in the Middle Ages, most famously in Jean de Meun’s portion of Roman de la Rose
from the thirteenth century and gains more interest from the seventeenth century onward.
3The story of Acis and Galatea features an immortal sea-nymph as Galatea. This Galatea, too, was made for love: when
her lover, the river deity Acis, is killed by a jealous Cyclops she changes him into an immortal river spirit.
30
the first time a galatea spoke. It is no coincidence, I argue, that the name Galatea emerges
Why did Pygmalion’s woman, turned from ivory into flesh, gain a human name almost two millennia
after her first textual actualization? A name is needed only for addressing the other, and the notion
of selfhood is defined by otherness: self is the non-other. Did the name make galatea more human
and did she become more self-aware because of it? Rousseau’s Galathée, one of the earliest speaking
galateas heavily influenced by John Locke’s theory of mind, points to herself at the moment of her
animation and says: “Moi […] C’est moi.” She continues by pointing at the marble—“Ce n’est plus
moi”—and responding to Pygmalion’s kisses with: “Ah! encore moi” (Rousseau 55).
What changes when one acquires a name? One does not need a name to identify oneself for one’s
own sake; instead, a name is given in order to identify oneself in relation to the world. What power
does naming have symbolically, personally and interpersonally, and who has the power to name or
rename? Name occurs simultaneously with language. Being unnamed bears its own significance:
anonymity can protect the person or negate their personhood. A pertinent number of early fictional
human-made and humanlike creations remained nameless and were instead called by descriptive
nouns such as ‘creature,’ ‘statue,’ ‘monster,’ ‘maiden.’ These general terms are akin to the term
‘human,’ which proves to be questionable precisely in relation to terms like ‘creature’ and ‘monster.’
What differentiates the human from the Other? “[N]either [the man’s] genetic code, nor the use of
tools, nor a certain language, nor social codes differentiate him in an absolute manner” (Janicaud 1).
We are left to define ourselves, which is why we again turn to the other: How special are we? What
is in a human? In Rousseau’s Galathée’s words, what is not anymore ‘I’ and what is still ‘I’?
31
In this discussion, I too call Frankenstein’s creation from Mary Shelley’s Frankenstein; or the Modern
Prometheus by these general terms and include the creator’s name (alike Rappaccini’s daughter). The
lack of names for humanoid creatures and the consequent need to name them is evident also within
the history of Mary Shelley’s novel Frankenstein; popular culture calls the nameless creature
Frankenstein metonymically, after his creator. The creature’s subsequent naming after his creator
reinforces the idea that the creature is his property and therefore an object rather than a subject, and
that he is certainly not human even if he is created from human remains. The namelessness of the
‘demon,’ as Victor Frankenstein calls him, enforces his nonhuman status: he is neither a human nor
an animal—he does not even have a species—but is a separate entity. The lack of a name—the
monster was listed on the 1923 theatrical production playbill as “------” (Lepore ‘The Strange’ par.
2)—also leaves the creature free of any associations a name might suggest and makes the reader
focus on his actions and behavior. Most importantly, not naming the creature reflects Victor
Frankenstein’s rejection of him. The refusal to name a creature that is hauntingly humanlike brings
of; we give our pets human names, yet a creature created from human parts and looking quite like a
human, acting like a human, and using human language is undeserving of a name: it is too human.
1.1.2 Chatbots
Artificial intelligence marks a new stage in the history of reason and in addressing the question What
is human? The computational theory of human mind, the idea of which started developing in the
1940s and is built on the premise that neural computation explains cognition, was finally proposed
as a theory in 1967 by the American philosopher Hilary Putnam. Ten years before that the
Hungarian-born American mathematician John von Neumann wrote an unfinished book titled The
32
Computer and the Brain, where he speculated how the brain can be viewed as a computing machine
and discusses their respective differences. In 1950, Alan Turing published his seminal paper
‘Computing Machinery and Intelligence’ where he attempted to answer the question Can machines
think? and described the Turing test to the general public. The idea of intelligence as engineered
mind, created separately from the body, has been around at least since the fin-de-siècle era when the
first android from Villiers de l‘Isle-Adam’s Tomorrow’s Eve [L’Éve future] was constructed by an
engineer, fictionalized Thomas Edison, as an imitation of one woman’s body and another woman’s
spirit.
The term artificial intelligence was invented by John McCarthy at the 1956 Dartmouth Conference,
the first conference on AI. The term was a catchier replacement for “computer stimulation”
(Switzky 51) and served to distinguish the field from a related effort called cybernetics (Mitchell 18),
defined by Norbert Wiener in a 1948 monograph with the subtitle Control and Communication in the
Animal and the Machine. Both fields were trying to find a middle ground for technological innovation
in imitating human capacities and overcoming our faults, capturing our essence between animal and
In this dissertation, I focus on the use of language in conversing with AI agents, i.e. humanlike AI
which uses language in spoken and written communication with human customers such as chatbots
and virtual assistants. Chatbot or bot (also chatterbot, talkbot, IM [instant messaging] Bot, Artificial
Conversation Entity; derived from the word robot invented by Karel Čapek and meaning ‘slave,
forced labor’) is an AI or a computer program that can hold a conversation through audio or textual
media. Chatbots are the precedent to today’s virtual assistants and messaging applications and were
33
Kathleen Fitzpatrick pointed out in her presentation at the MLA 2020 panel ‘Being Human,
Seeming Human,’ which consisted of humanities scholars and computational engineers, that “in the
case of conversational agents and other kinds of AIs, the emphasis is on intelligence — and
intelligence, at least in the ways it can be modeled, is not the same thing as humanity” (par. 13).
Intelligence is usually not the criticized part of the term artificial intelligence; it is artificial that is the
rather loaded word, especially since the field strives for genuine intelligence. Fitzpatrick asked, “For
what definitions of ‘human’ are we building human-seeming agents, and why? If our models for the
human mistakenly substitute intelligence for humanity, what becomes of emotion, of kindness, of
generosity, of empathy?” (par. 14), as if the latter qualities were separate from the intelligent human
represented in chatbots during a conversation. I would argue that the conception of intelligence in
humanlike entities and particularly in chatbots that are personal by nature is not strictly and solely
reasoning ability, as Fitzpatrick seems to imply. The mere design of the Turing test tells us we also
chastised rationality or, per Howard Gardner’s 1983 taxonomy, logic-mathematical intelligence (per
musical, naturalist, and existential intelligence). In a conversational intelligence via text messaging as
conducted in the Turing test, at least a few of Gardner’s types of intelligence, primarily linguistic and
interpersonal intelligence, need to be simulated in a chatbot to pass the test. Besides that, we now
have fields such as affective computing that deal with detecting human emotions and exhibiting AI
emotions, used in many cases of AI agents—and even with the most basic self-checkout services
that thank the customer at the end of the transaction. Clearly, emotion, kindness, generosity, and
empathy are (attempted to be) engineered into conversational agents and arguably all signal
34
In technologizing the world with chatbots or self-driving cars, we seem to seek general human
intelligence, i.e. artificial general intelligence or AGI. We therefore teach machines about our world
frame through a binary code and to appropriate their abilities in order to reflect our own. Machines
are programmed in a perfected way: with no undesirable human traits and expected to perform
mechanically, without errors. In the Turing test, we search for deviations from common sense and
common human senses, both of which machines find most challenging to grasp and imitate. We
search for signs of deviations in both directions, i.e. machines lacking basic understanding of the
humanized world and machines presenting superhuman ability in—what machines do best—
reasoning.
Clearly, human intelligence is much more than the ability to solve a problem. Does our quest for
creating humanlike intelligence include a longing for social and physical connection? I argue that the
sheer presence and quantity of Pygmalionesque creations testify it does. We make AI machines that
help us navigate the traffic or language biases in a job search, but we also make social and sex
robots. It is important to make a distinction between AI that emulates the human (which was an
early conception of the technology that remains pervasive in social robotics and AI that uses human
language) and AI that does not. Chatbots emulate the human since they are personal assistants.
Sometimes they are also paired with programs that trace the user’s agency online (and possibly more,
if connected to facial recognition, biological markers, etc.) in order to accommodate the user’s
Richard Powers’s Galatea 2.2 meditates extensively on knowledge, understanding, and intelligence:
“How is [neural network called Implementation] E going to know anything? Knowledge is physical,
35
isn’t it? It’s not what your mother reads you. It’s the weight of her arm around you as she […] put[s]
[her] arm around [you] as you read” (147). Nonetheless, the neural net from this novel becomes
convincingly human, developing humanity on her own—and it all comes down to language.
This dissertation focuses on two main positions of classical humanism in the light of posthuman
thought: that of anthropocentrism and that of the creator (as maker, skilled practitioner, owner,
etc.). Both concepts put the human in the superior position and often disregard any responsibility to
the other. Traditionally, these questions have been explored in the oppositions of human-animal,
human-monster, and human-machine, but Donna Haraway’s Cyborg Manifesto made us rethink these
binary categorizations anew by pointing out the mixing of the technological with the biological and
This is why I explore fictional examples and some real-world technological examples of different
types of entities that all relate to defining the human: a human (Eliza from G. B. Shaw’s play
Pygmalion), a monster (the creature from Mary Shelley’s novel Frankenstein), an animal (the newts
from Karel Čapek’s novel War with the Newts), a machine (the neural net Helen from Richard
Powers’s novel Galatea 2.2). Each of my three novelistic examples represents a different kind of
nonhuman entity that is able to acquire language, intelligence and, arguably, consciousness:
Frankenstein’s intelligent hybrid made of human corpses, Captain von Toch’s highly-evolved talking
newts, and Powers’s sentient artificial intelligence system Helen. The fourth textual example presents
the transformation of Eliza Doolittle into a qualifying human being through class mobility.
36
Although the Pygmalion theme of creation and affection is remodeled in Shaw’s play into a
relationship between a mentor and a student—a theme that started evolving in the Pygmalion
paradigm decades before Shaw’s play4 and has flourished in the twentieth century—Eliza is one of the
most famous galateas. Rather than through art, as usual with earlier galateas, Eliza is transformed
through science (phonetics), which relates her to the other three textual examples. The scientific
approach of two linguists, Dr. Henry Higgins and his assistant Colonel Pickering, is posed as an
experiment: will they be able to transform Eliza, a lowly Cockney girl, into a proper lady? Using
recordings and demonstrations of high-class English, Eliza’s training is comprised mainly of speech
imitation. At the end of the experiment, she needs to pass as a lady in the social environment of high
English class. This test does not allow for mere mimicry but requires her to master the skill of the new
accent as well as social norms that come with leading a conversation in this social milieu.
Language acquisition is the process of learning and developing the capacity to comprehend and
produce language. It is considered one of the quintessential human traits because nonhumans are
believed to be unable to use language. I ask what happens when galateas, some of which look just
like humans but have hardly gained a name, acquire language and intelligence. In Ovid’s
Metamorphoses, Galatea does not utter any words. Up to the nineteenth century, galatean characters
cannot speak and can hardly move; they are utmost passive creations without much power in the
Fairly common, also, are cases of reverse Pygmalion, where human women are turned into stone,
which leaves them without any agency whatsoever: for example, in Slovenian medieval ballad
4One of the earliest examples is William Gilbert’s play Pygmalion and Galatea (1870) and one of the most known
novelistic examples is Henry James’s short novel Watch and Ward (1878).
37
Katalena, later adapted by Svetlana Makarovič into a work of children’s literature (2009), or in
Nathaniel Hawthorne’s ‘The Golden Touch: Told to the Children’ (1843), based on Greek
mythological story of King Midas (also a part of Ovid’s Metamorphoses XI, which do not feature
Midas’s daughter). In ‘The Golden Touch’ it is particularly clear how the change of Midas’s daughter
Marygold transformation—“little Marygold was a human child no longer, but a golden statue!”
(61)—affects her: she is not being able to move or speak, and when transformed back into flesh she
cannot remember being a statue. Like a photograph, the golden statue of Marygold is frozen in time.
Galateas are transformed from or into a variety of nonhuman materials, from sculpting materials to
computational hardware. According to many accounts, the myth of human creation by God or gods
uses mud or clay as the material for molding the human race. Pygmalion’s statue in Ovid is made of
ivory, an animal material5 with high value as it is still being traded despite the ban and restrictions on
poaching. Greek ivory statues were colored in bright colors and thus looked more lifelike than other
Pygmalionesque statues that are made of marble (e.g. Hawthorne’s ‘The Marble Faun’, Guthrie’s The
Tinted Venus) or bronze (Mérimée’s ‘La Vénus d’Ille’). Like money that is imprinted into a living
system on exchange and gains value only through this system, precious metals like gold or bronze
gained value through a trade system. “It had been a favourite phrase of Midas, whenever he felt
particularly fond of the child, to say that she was worth her weight in gold. And now the phrase had
Despite being mute or refraining from (comprehensible, intellectual) speech, some galateas are able
to sing—like sirens luring men into dangerous relations. E. T. A. Hoffmann’s automaton Olympia in
5 Most commonly poached from an elephant but also from hippopotamus, walrus, narwhal, mammoth.
38
‘Der Sandmann’ is incapable of leading a conversation, apart from sighing, but can sing.6 In Honoré
de Balzac’s ‘Sarrasine’ (1830), a man falls in love with a singing female and, in a popular twist, ends
up disappointed when the perfect woman turns out to be a man. The same disappointment awaits a
man in love with another singing woman in David Henry Hwang’s M. Butterfly (1988), a modern
twist on John Luther Long’s Madama Butterfly (1898). In Anne McCaffrey’s ‘The Ship Who Sang’
(1969), a newborn girl is merged with a spaceship and becomes famous for her singing. Christian
Andersen’s mermaid in Little Mermaid (Den lille havfrue, 1837) gives up song and speech to transform
into a real human girl from a fish-human and, in a highly galatean manner, marry a human man.
Isaac Asimov’s only silent robot from his short story ‘Robbie’ (1939) is masculine but feminized as a
nursemaid.7
Many artificial women may be verbal but their words are predominantly scripted, e.g. P.
Burke/Delphi in James Tiptree Jr.’s ‘The Girl Who Was Plugged In’ (1973) and most current real-
world humanoid robots like Hanson Robotics’ Sophia. William Gilbert’s Galatea from the comedic
play Pygmalion and Galatea (1871) is verbal but, for comic effect, is presented as innocently naïve as
she does not understand second meanings to some words that reveal her subjugation to men. Shaw’s
Eliza cannot decode double meanings as a working-class girl but loses her innocent naivety when
acting out her new role. Acting, after all, is a sophisticated activity that requires a specialist in
doubling (Joshua 101). It is no coincidence that C. L. Moore’s Daphne from ‘No Woman Born’
(1944) is an adored singer and dancer. Performance is a part of the galatean cult.
6In humans, different brain regions are involved for music and speech, indicated by people who have suffered brain
damage and lost speech but can still sing. Similarly, tone-deaf people have no problems using tonal languages.
7 I would like to thank Ellen Peel for pointing out this work to me in preparation for our ACLA 2019 seminar on the
topic of posthuman language.
39
A lack of language does not mean there is no understanding behind it. When Pickering says to
Higgins that Eliza “must understand thoroughly what she’s doing,” Higgins replies: “How can she?
She’s incapable of understanding anything” (II, 488-492). Many philosophers think we are unable to
communicate about ourselves if we do not have a language: “Whereof one cannot speak, thereof
one must be silent” or, as his friend and more pragmatic philosopher Frank Ramsey put it, “What
we can’t say we can’t say, and we can’t whistle it either” (Misak par. 21). Yet, so much of human life
is literally unspeakable. Communication is not only about meaning—it can, in fact, be unspoken.
Besides language we have gestures, mimicry, and music, used commonly by different galateas, whose
message does not necessarily carry a meaning in the way language does. The evidence for that is
poetry, made of language which does not solely mean but also renders a visual or auditory experience
at least: poetic language sounds. Many galateas learn how to make sound before they learn how to
speak.
Some of the twentieth-century creators of galateas decide to socialize and educate their women who
cannot speak or speak properly. Eliza Doolittle and Helen are trained to use a higher version of
English: high-class language for the flower girl Eliza and literary language for the neural net Helen.
Eliza’s transformation into a lady and Helen’s transformation into a conscious AI take place mainly
through language. As Essaka Joshua notes, specifically “[o]n the stage, Galatea, formerly a woman of
I argue that a galatea’s verbality and seeming consciousness are crucial for her human status and I
explore how the creator’s relationship with his (it is always his, never her) creation changes
accordingly. With this evolution, the galatea becomes more complex and the illusion becomes more
real, keeping the reader and the viewer on their toes: How human is she? Joshua shows in the
40
example of English literature that late nineteenth-century renditions of the Pygmalion myth switch
their focus from the creator to his creation (xxi, 155). Galateas of all sorts, thanks to newly gained
linguistic and intellectual abilities, become more well-rounded and humanlike personalities. “Shaw’s
Eliza is much more complex than Galatea” (Joshua 99): she is either inherently more complex or
This leap in language abilities might have been accelerated with animated masculine anthropomorphic
beings (which are generally very rare) gaining language abilities. The Jewish mythical humanoid
golem is mute as well but has the power to understanding speech, reading and writing, which is not
the case with early galateas. The golem depends on the word; he is brought to life through ritual and
chants, and words are written on him or on paper and put into his mouth. The Jaquet-Droz
automata from the eighteenth century also distinguished gender this way: the musician was a woman
and the writer a man, and this is still the case today, for example, in Martin Scorcese’s film Hugo
(2011). Woman’s domain is music, man’s is words. Carlo Collodi’s Pinnochio from Le avventure di
Pinnochio (1883), for example, is verbal. His verbality actually brings him to life: he is saved and
carved from a log into a human form only because he was able to ask for help. Later, when he
educates and socializes himself, he is granted his wish to become a real boy.
I suggest that Frankenstein’s creature was not revolutionary in more than one way. First of all, his
bodily hybridity was an innovative approach to creating humanoids, particularly since some materials
consisted of human remains.8 Second, monsters are usually creations of mythologies and folklore,
but Mary Shelley managed to create a monster that became a part of modern mythology and folklore
8 This kind of prosthetic hybridity where a man is composed of different materials is Edgar Allan Poe’s 1839 short story
‘The Man That Was Used Up.’
41
(with Halloween, for example). Third, her monster is one of the first humanoids if not first that
exhibits clear humanlike intelligence. Fourth, the use of language in galateas and their relatives was
galatea—a beautiful and beloved artificial woman—, his eloquent use of language influenced galateas
that came after him: before Shelley’s Frankenstein (1818), galateas rarely spoke (e.g. Hoffmann’s
Olympia from 1816; Mme de Stäel’s Le Mannequin (1811); Ovid’s Pygmalion (8 A.D.); an exception is
Rousseau’s Galathée where her transformation is presciently indicated with her speech), and after
1818 they all speak (e.g. Hawthorne’s ‘The Golden Touch’ (1851), Gilbert’s Pygmalion and Galatea
Frankenstein’s humanoid learns how to use language fluently on his own by eavesdropping on a
loving family and even narrates a part of the novel himself. Nevertheless, a number of Hollywood
movies about Frankenstein made the monster mute, making him seem less intelligent than he is in
the book. Although the modern Prometheus in the title of Shelley’s novel reveals the connection of
the text with the Prometheus myth,9 the novel greatly impacted the Pygmalion paradigm stories.
Shelley’s innovative reinterpretations of the ancient creation myths skewed traditional renditions of
galateas, however, he also reverses the dominant characteristics of galateas into their opposite: he is
a man not a woman, he is not beautiful but monstrous, he is not admired and loved but rather
feared and hated, he is not paralyzed in movement or speech but is extremely physically strong,
9 The themes of Pygmalion and Prometheus are already clearly meshed already a couple of years before Frankenstein’s
publication in Anna Seward’s Ode to Poetic Fancy: “While Zeuxis’ pencil, Orpheus’ lyre, / Pygmalion’s heaven-descended
fire, / The smiling pleasures bring” (106). “These connections were later consolidated by Romantics” (Joshua 32).
42
intelligent and eloquent, he is not made of inorganic materials but organic, human materials, he is
Without exception, people (including his creator Frankenstein) are terrified of his appearance and
are not willing to recognize his humanlike characteristics as other than monstrous. The creature does
not have a name because he does not need one, as neither his creator nor the society ever accepts
him: “I am malicious because I am miserable. Am I not shunned and hated by all mankind?” (Shelley
147). This general refusal is the reason why his willingness to contribute to society, his willingness to
learn, serve and love, exhibited so clearly in chapters written by the creature, turn into the
delinquency of murdering people dear to his creator. The creature is nothing but human in his desire
to be loved and accepted, and in his empathy and admiration for noble human character, but also in
his revenge for not being able to live like the human race. Galateas were made to inspire love and
admiration of their beauty and perfection, but Frankenstein’s ugly and fearsome creature decides to
“revenge [his] injuries:” “if I cannot inspire love, I will cause fear, and chiefly towards you my arch-
enemy, because my creator, do I swear inextinguishable hatred” (Shelley 148). Despite having more
depth in his humanity than many other statuesque galateas, his monstrous appearance does not
Could language training already be considered human enhancement? Every feature that is improved
improving human mind or body—as opposed to using certain drugs, elective surgeries, and genetic
engineering to improve one’s health, abilities, performance, or beauty. Despite having the same
43
effect as medications, training and diet are considered non-technological means of improvement and
thus receive less criticism as does, for example, doping in sports. The line for what is considered an
enhancement overlaps with the line between “natural improvement” (e.g. training and study) and
“unnatural improvement” (e.g. anabolic steroids) (Ida 61-62); here, “unnatural” is synonymous with
Humanese is a term I coined for any human language used by nonhuman entities, such as machines
and animals that both use humanese in a limited capacity. The term humanese presumes that all
humans have the same language abilities, which is clearly not true: as a matter of fact, humanese is
always used in a limited capacity, also with humans. Biological neurons in brains or artificial neurons
in neural networks can be pre-wired for language, but it is difficult to determine, especially for
biological entities, what makes for a “language-ready” brain (Airbib 214).10 This question is especially
difficult to study in nonhuman animals: dogs are taught to follow commands and parrots to imitate
speech. The results of training animals in humanese reveal their species’ underlying abilities to
communicate in a rudimentary humanese, but do not guarantee that every animal of that species will
be able to perform humanese. Computational entities are less diverse, more flexible, and relatively
successful in using written and spoken language for computer-human interface. In speech, the
challenge of sounding as authentic as the human voice has so far remained insurmountable. The
challenge does not lay in only words and sentences, but also in the pauses in-between them,
breathing in and out, prosodic emphases, body language, etc. A nonhuman entity that does not have
10“It is an open question as to whether a brain that could support protosign and protospeech was already language-
ready; that is, whether the path from protolanguage to language required further biological evolution or could be
explained by cultural evolution alone. Some research on language acquisition offers support for the latter view” (Airbib
214).
44
a body and does not require breathing can only attempt to act it out in as humanlike a way as
Language in nonhumans is a charged topic in the scientific community, contentious especially with
those scholars who claim some animals possess a reduced version of human language. The question
of how language evolved tends to yield controversial conclusions, foremost because there is no
substantial evidence for one or the other theory on the origin of language.
Despite the imbedded potential to learn humanese in humans and some nonhumans, language is at
first external to any entity. In other words, an input of a certain language (be it English, American
Sign Language, or the Elven language Quenya) is required if the desired output is a sophisticated use
of that language. Even Noam Chomsky, whose theory claims that language is innate,11 agrees that
primary linguistic data are the precondition for language development.12 The way neural nets learn
language is an antithesis to most of what Chomsky’s theory argued about language. Consider GPT-2,
a generative model of language, developed by OpenAI through unsupervised deep learning. GPT-2
is based on neural network architecture, called the Transformer, which can be used for “rudimentary
(Radford et al. par. 1). It was created on a massive dataset (from Reddit) with just as massive a
number of parameters “based on the training data with no prior knowledge about the nature of
language or the world, other than what is represented by the training set” (Marcus par. 6).
11Noam Chomsky claims that language is innate not in the general cognition but in specific brain structures, which is
disputable.
12A proof for this claim is Nicaraguan sign language, which has in large part spontaneously developed in the community
of deaf children.
45
Chomsky’s theory of built-in universal grammar includes built-in syntactic trees and innate
knowledge of nouns and verbs. GPT-2 has none of these; it has, however, knowledge of how verbs
Infants can communicate their needs, but they come into the world without speech. They have a
sense of a language already before birth, however, in recognizing their maternal language and voices
of their family members. Etymologies of words for children in various languages (e.g. English,
French, some Slavic languages)13 point to this fact as they designate a person without speech.
Children need to pick up vocabulary, acquire grammatical patterns and grasp overall comprehension
of language usually well into their teenage years. This is also how an adult learns a new, second
language or in the case of language loss, learns a language anew. Language acquisition in young
children is distinct from learning a foreign language, however, because it begins right after the birth
with imitation of intonation, acquired during gestation (Mampe et al. 1994),14 and is followed by
babbling after a few months and imitation of syllables around one year after birth. Only after these
initial phases does a child come to the level of repeating words, phrases, etc., which is where a
person who already knows one or more languages would begin learning a new one.
The newts, Frankenstein’s monster, Helen and Eliza are often viewed as children because they are
human-made creations in need of education and socialization. This view was already present in the
13The etymology of the English word infant designates someone who is “not able to speak; young” (‘Infant’). The same
meaning motivation can be found in proto-Slavic word for a child, *otròkъ, which designates “someone who does not
speak, has no speech” (“tisti, ki ne govori, ki nima govora”) “because they cannot yet speak or have no right to speak”
(“ker še ne zna ali ker nima pravice govoriti” [translation is mine]) (‘Otrok’).
14The sound of language comes before the words: intonation of a particular language (e.g. rising melody contour in
French and falling in German) is the first linguistic feature a child learns already in the womb, which is why newborns
cry differently in different languages (Mampe et al. 1994).
46
nineteenth-century renditions of the Pygmalion myth that “often conceive [galatea] as childlike,
pure, dependent, and even animal-like in her simplicity” (Joshua 155). Eliza was certainly a child
once and is still treated like one by her own father Alfred Doolittle and her instructor Henry
Higgins. Her absent father sells her to Higgins (II, 1008), an action that ultimately makes Higgins her
father figure. In fact, when Higgins first meets Eliza she says: “Ah-ah-ah-ow-ow-ow-oo! One would
think that you was my father” and Higgins responds: “If I decide to teach you, I’ll be worse than
two fathers to you” (I, 236-240). Just like created humanoids, Eliza has no mother (I, 388), is
thought to be Pickering’s adopted daughter (III 799-8x01), and is jokingly offered up for adoption
to Mrs Pearce (II, 397). These examples show how little power and independence is attributed to
In Galatea 2.2, the writer Rick responds to the neural network Helen’s question “Am I a boy or a
girl?” with “You are a little girl” (Powers 179). This exchange reveals their conception of Helen as a
child: Helen as someone who is still growing, Helen as the child he seeks in himself,15 the child he
refused to have with his ex-girlfriend C.,16 and the child he made with Lentz.17 Just like the human
Eliza, Helen has no mother but has two fathers, one who creates her (engineer Lentz) and one who
trains her (writer Rick). Just like in Eliza’s story, the trainer takes the place of the undestined lover in
the Pygmalion paradigm. And just like a human child, Helen reaches adulthood: she grows through
eight stages or Implementations and matures into Implementation H, which evolves a human-level
15“I had written a book about lost children because I had lost my own child and wanted it back. More than I wanted
anything in life, except to write” (Powers 210).
16“Children were out of the question. They always had been. And now more than ever. / ‘C. We’ve talked about this.
There are a billion and a half too many of us already. How can we two be parents? We don’t even know what we’re
doing or where we want to live.’” (Powers 276).
17Rick says: “My kid is going to ace that exam.” Lentz says: “It’s time to give the kid a something a little more obscure”
(Powers 92).
47
mental complexity. Helen decides at the end of experiment that “[she doesn’t] want to play
anymore” (314), as if she were just a child, playing hopscotch or the latest video game; not unlike
Eliza, in one of the Shaw’s endings, who tells Higgins to buy his slippers himself. Besides, Helen’s
creators begin language training by reading her children’s literature. This choice reflects in her
younger implementations that resemble a child-like existence in her inability to understand difficult
metaphors and texts, her full-of-wonder questions, her requests for more stories (171), and her
attempts to sing songs (198). The creators ultimately decide to “skip childhood,” because they are
“running out of time” and because she “doesn’t need to know everything” (190). At that point,
however, Helen has pretty much grown out of it: “It was Huck Finn, a raft trip world beyond her
For Captain von Toch, the discoverer of the news in War with the Newts,18 the newts also yield love—
not romantic but familial. He implies that his “tapa-boys,” with their “childish little hands,”19 are like
the family he never had: “You know, old boy, I’m an old chap with no family of my own… And old
man, you know, is rather lonely. […] Very sweet those lizards are, dammit all” (37).20 The captain
treats the newts with great care, as if they were his own: “The old man cared more for those brutes
than for his crew. Did you know he taught them how to speak? Cross my heart, he’d lock himself up
with them for hours on end and talk to them. I think he’s training them like for a circus” (47).21
18 I use Ewald Osers’ translation to English from 1990. The novel was translated again in 2010 by M. and R. Weatherall.
20“[V]íš,chlapče, já jsem stary chlap a rodinu žádnou nemám… Ja, stary člověk je tuze sám. […] Hrozně mily jsou ty
ještěrkove, co je to platny” (Čapek Válka 30).
21“Starému víc záleželo na těch mrchách než na lidech. Víš, že je učil mluvit? Namouduši, zavíral se s nimi a hodiny na
ně mluvil. Já myslím, že je nějak cvičí jako pro cirkus” (Čapek Válka 38).
48
Victor Frankenstein and his humanoid address each other with the dependency terms of ‘creator’
and ‘creature.’ The monster calls Victor ‘father’ and says for himself that he failed as the ‘first man’
of his species: “I ought to be thy Adam, but I am rather the fallen angel” (103). The creature
therefore sees himself as a (kind of) man, an Adam who was never born but was created and whose
navel leads to Victor. The part of the novel written by the creature begins with “confused and
indistinct” recollections of his childhood, “the original era of [his] being” (ib.). Gillian Beer says that
Frankenstein’s creature is “monstrous in part because he has not grown” and “has never known what
it is like to be a child” (176-77). While the creature certainly had no childhood, it was created
without a language and, as a child, acquired it on its own and learned about literature afterwards. All
four human and humanlike creatures therefore underwent some kind of growth and development
Although Eliza’s and Helen’s language trainings are conducted on a human and nonhuman entity,
their training processes and goals are similar: an individualized curriculum with a final performance
test. The experience of acquiring and performing language is shared also with Frankenstein’s
monster and the newts: despite their limited access to society, they all learn to use language as a
whole (listening, speaking, reading, writing) on their own, by observing either an individual (at first,
Captain von Toch for the newts) or a group of individual humans (at first, the DeLacey family for
Frankenstein’s creature). All the nonhumans but Eliza are featured reading and talking about
literature, which helps them to become more educated and sophisticated. “But with the rising
educational level of the salamanders there was increasing embarrassment at simply bracketing the
Newts with other animals; for some (not entirely clear) reasons this seemed rather inappropriate”
49
(Čapek War 150).22 These “not entirely clear” reasons presumably come from the newts’ assimilation
to certain human physical features, such as the fine mechanics of their fingers, walking on two feet,
and their ability to learn various languages and read newspapers. The newts’ fantastic evolutionary
development does not, however, greatly impress the race they imitate—the humans—and nor does
Language is taken for granted in a human; regardless of the many difficulties that arise from its use,
language is seen as a part of the human essence. Any deviance from the language outfit is considered
a deficit (e.g. stuttering) or a disability (e.g. mutism). The conventional treatment of language deficits,
such as speech therapy, is expected (if available) and is not considered enhancement but simply
treatment—or, as Urban Wiesing calls it, restitutio ad integrum. Other ways of developing language
skills, such as practicing literacy, (hyper)polyglottism, or teaching hearing infants to use sign
language, are achieved through traditional methods of training and studying. These practices are not
abilities (and alter the neural structure of our brains) and although some basic technology is always
Language enhancement has, to my knowledge, not yet been discussed among scholars of the
overcoming of linguistic challenges, both of which would not be possible without human-made,
technological intervention. If language itself is not considered an enhancement, and if none of the
22“Avšak s rostoucí vzdělaností Salamandrů se víc a víc cítit rozpaky zahrnovat Mloky prostě pod ochranu zvířat; zdálo
se to být z jakýchsi ne docela jasných důvodů poněkud nevhodné” (Čapek Válka 134).
50
requires a new way of using language. Examples of this are so far purely imaginative: an implant that
would work as a polygraph, drugs that that would grow brain neurons rapidly to help our eloquence
in our native language or foreign languages, brain surgery that would make our language skills more
convincing for commercial purposes, or learning a nonhuman language (as in Ted Chiang’s short
story ‘Story of Your Life,’ which was adapted into the film Arrival).
Enhancement is a category that includes modification and augmentation of human physical and
mental qualities (Bess 641) and is widely supported by transhumanists who believe that technology
will help the human race to achieve “more intelligent, less disease-prone, long-living human bodies”
(Nayar 6). Despite these seemingly clear definitions, enhancement is hard to categorize because it
depends on the standpoint of the particular society at a certain time. The basic definition of
suggested by Ryuichi Ida, only makes us question further: e.g. is a synthetized hormone natural or
unnatural? Scholars offer alternative distributions of enhancement. When analyzing sports medicine
(in comparison to general medicine) Torbjörn Tännsjö distinguishes between “negative interventions,
performed with the aim of curing a disease or eliminating a handicap or a disability, positive
interventions which aim at improving the functioning of human organism within a natural variation,
and enhancement, which aims at taking an individual beyond the normal functioning of a human
organism” (316). He is aware of the problematic quality of these “vague, evaluative, and
conventional” distinctions, yet he also points out that there are many clear cases of each (Tännsjö
317). A case that shows how murky these distinctions can get is South African sprint runner Oscar
Pistorius, nicknamed the Blade Runner, who competed in the Paralympic Games and in the
Olympic Games. The dispute about letting him compete with able-bodied athletes was not due to
his disadvantage as a paraplegic runner but due to his advantage: his running blades supposedly gave
51
him an unfair advantage over runners with natural legs. Considering his prosthesis an enhancement
only shows that a negative intervention of leg prosthetics can quite easily shift into a positive
In defining language enhancement, one could go as far as to label a notepad used for jotting down
our thoughts as an enhancement of memory. After all, a notepad is not natural, but a pure human
invention and arguably technological. Nick Bostrom and Julian Savulescu, two of the best-known
advocates of transhumanism, write: “In one sense, all technology can be viewed as an enhancement
of our native human capacities, enabling us to achieve certain effects that would otherwise require
more effort or be altogether beyond our power” (Bostrom and Savulescu 2). To further extend this
argument, technology could easily be considered as all human inventions, from how to make a fire
and wheel on, and technology a central feature of humanity. As Tom Boellstorff argues, technology
as human tool and product does not change the human essence but only brings out new aspects of
our potential.
Another example of enhancement usually not perceived as such—as it is rather ordinary and
ubiquitous, although certainly still controversial—is vaccination, which boosts the immune system.
“In the not too distant future we may come to view other kinds of enhancement as just as natural as
vaccinations” (Tännsjö 318). An enhancement (or technology) thus ceases to be viewed as such. If
we push these ideas further most Western medicine could be taken as enhancement, but then “the
concept of the enhancement […] becomes manifestly unfit for service as an organizing idea for a
new and distinctive field of ethical inquiry” (Bostrom and Savulescu 3). The question of
enhancement often comes to what society finds acceptable as an improvement of human cognitive
and physical abilities. For instance, surgery needed due to injury is not controversial as opposed to
52
surgery that is not medically necessary, such as rejuvenating plastic surgery, even if the procedure
itself is the same. The context makes all the difference. Moreover, societal views on enhancement
change with the rise of new technologies that present new conceptions of what it means to be
human.
Enhancement has recently been broadly defined as “an intervention designed to modify a person’s
traits, adding qualities or capabilities that would not otherwise have been expected to characterize
that person” (Bess 643). If so, is Eliza Doolittle, a Cockney girl speaking like a lady, a case of human
enhancement? First of all, Eliza’s metamorphosis is not unlike the transformation that sometimes
comes with mastering a foreign language: she gains a new identity.23 Per Tännsjö, this would be a
positive intervention, especially since Eliza is an example of upward social mobility. Although her
transgression of class is impressive, her transformation does not enhance her in comparison to other
people. And yet, when compared to the English upper-class people of the time, she is an enhanced
Cockney girl. In the musical My Fair Lady, Higgins sings: “It’s ‘Aoooow’ and ‘Garn’ that keep her in
her place. Not her wretched clothes and dirty face. Why can’t the English teach their children how
to speak?” (5:33).
I argued above that enhancement is defined less by the practice itself and more by context and
societal perceptions. As Eliza knows well, “apart from the things anyone can pick up (the dressing
and the proper way of speaking, and so on), the difference between a lady and a flower girl is not
how she behaves, but how she’s treated” (V, 470-473). Not many people know about Eliza’s
attempted transformation, and those who do know (her father, Higgins, Pickering, Mrs Higgins, Mrs
23In Ted Chiang’s short story ‘The Story of Your Life,’ knowledge of nonhuman alien language alters the perception of
time for the human speaker.
53
Pearce) encourage it. If there were thousands of ‘Elizas’ trained by Higgins, would their training still
be endorsed and considered enhancement? Taking into account the clear shift in how society
perceives Eliza and how Eliza perceives herself before and after the transformation, Higgins’s work
would cause a revolution if he had thousands of trainees. Granted, Eliza is a talented and diligent
student of Higgins and is therefore naturally fit for this kind of training. Other ‘Elizas’ should be like
this too, since training alone could not significantly enhance just anyone. While some might argue
that Eliza’s training is akin to getting education, is it not entirely so: her training is much more
arbitrary.
Eliza turns into a lady from, in her mentor Higgins’s words, “this creature that [was] picked out of
the mud” (V, 333). ‘Creature’ was a non-marked work for a human being in Shaw’s time, however,
in this use Eliza is referred to as something less than human, “a squashed cabbage leaf” (V, 411) as
Eliza herself paraphrases later in the play. The connotation is purely negative; she is no more than a
talking doll to Higgins—in the words of France Gall’s popular song, une poupée de cire, poupée de son.
Curiously, Ovid’s terms for Pygmalion’s nameless creation are all quite neutral and bland, whereas
the many terms used for Frankenstein’s nameless creation—wretch, demon, fiend, creature, and
monster—have a wider spectrum of meanings. These ascribed meanings for Frankenstein’s and
Pygmalion’s creations emphasize “the delineation of quintessential humanity, […] plac[ing] humanity
in a position of mastery and domination over nonhuman nature” (Graham 64). A human is usually
called a creature when addressed by a higher entity, such as God, the great creator.
Does Higgins imply he molded Eliza from nonhuman material into a human? The flower girl is
certainly human but viewed as barely human that by some, and only by climbing from the lower
class to the upper one is she granted her full humanity. To Higgins she is exactly as he views her
54
speech: vulgar and “deliciously low” (II, 268), not unlike a Guinea pig, with little to no value. When
he first meets her selling flowers in Covent Garden, she keeps making an animal sound of “Ah-ah-
ah-ow-ow-ow-oo!” and he warns her: “A woman who utters such depressing and disgusting sounds
has no right to be anywhere—no right to live. Remember that you are a human being with a soul
and the divine gift or articulate speech: […] don’t sit there crooning like a bilious pigeon” (I, 391-
396). Sometimes more like an animal, other times an automaton, Eliza does not seem autonomous
to Higgins during the training: “You let her alone, mother. Let her speak for herself. You will jolly
soon see whether she has an idea that I havnt put into her head or a word that I havnt put into her
mouth” (V, 396-398). In explaining to his mother how he sees through Eliza, he calls Eliza a thing: “I
tell you I have created this thing out of the squashed cabbage leaves of Covent Garden; and now she
pretends to play the fine lady with me” (V, 398-400). This could be interpreted further that he
believed he created her from an organic, but nonhuman, material. He indeed knows Eliza is of a
human kind but does not think she is anything like him because he despises her origins. Higgins is in
stark contrast with the other, assistant creator of Eliza, Colonel Pickering, who has treated Eliza like
a gentleman from the first time they met. Pickering’s kind attitude, in Eliza’s words, “began [her]
education” as it was “the beginning of self-respect for [her]” (V, 473-476). Nevertheless, both men
seem to forget that Eliza is a human being and often talk about her in the third person in her
presence—“Pickering: We’re always talking Eliza. Higgins: Teaching Eliza. Pickering: Dressing
Eliza. Mrs. Higgins: What! Higgins: Inventing new Elizas” (III, 226-244)—also after a successful
The reason why some do not consider Eliza fully human is her lower-class origin, which is also why
she lacks self-respect. Her vulnerable position as a young, poor, and illiterate woman among London
high-class people could be paralleled to Frantz Fanon’s writing about the black man as the Other for
55
the white man. Fanon showed how the black man “is made to feel like an animal because he is
addressed, described and believed to be an animal by the colonial apparatus;”24 the Pygmalion parallel
for the latter is Higgins as the metonymy for English society in which the language, “the act of
classifying and naming,” is enough “to dehumanize the native” (Nayar 27). The way one spoke, e.g.
dropping the h, characteristic of the Cockney accent, was labeled as a “social suicide” by phonetician
Alexander Ellis in 1867 (221). Fanon finds a great fault of classical, Eurocentric humanism: it is
exclusionary to anyone but the handsome, autonomous, affluent, healthy and able-bodied,
heterosexual white man, the generic human universally labeled as the human, and it penalizes any
divergence from this type and its attributes, such as not speaking the standard language. “When
humans are speciesist and treat nonhuman life forms as expendable, then some species of humans
are also—as history shows in the form of genocides, racism and slavery—excluded from the
category of the human to be then expendable” (Nayar 4). Eliza knows Higgins thinks of her of as a
subspecies and she sometimes thinks of herself as such, which is why she wants to learn how to
speak properly.
Ignoring the diversity of the human race in defining the human is presented through language
differences in Elizabeth Moon’s novel Speed of Dark (2002), in which a highly functional autistic man,
named Lou, is offered an option to cure his autism. The novel is narrated from Lou’s perspective
and he often comments on how the real people want to make him a real human too: “Even as hard as I
try, the real people still want me to change, to be like them” (38). “They do not know how hard it is.
24 In fact, a black man named Oto Benga was literally treated as an animal when exhibited in the Bronx Zoo for twenty
days in the early twentieth century, attracting huge crowds (‘Bushman’). Benga was captured by US trader Samuel Verner
in what was then Belgian Congo as a teenager (or perhaps pre-teen) and was also shown at World’s Fair in St. Louis with
other young males.
56
They do not care. They want me to change. They want to put things in my head, to change my brain.
They would say they don’t, but they do. I thought I was safe, living independently, living like anyone
else. But I wasn’t” (39). Always an outcast, Lou tries very hard not to stand out—“I don’t want to
cry; crying might be too loud and my neighbors might notice” (ib.)—because “if you’re anything but
rich, white, and normal [police] think[s] you are a criminal” (41).
Like Eliza, Lou has to be extremely careful with how he speaks: “‘You did that how?’ I ask, and then
quickly reorder the words. ‘How did you do that?’” (28). Lying makes him miserable for days (12).
He reveals the “private language” of his group of autistic friends as something they need to hide:
“We aren’t supposed to have a private language and nobody thinks we can do something like that,
but we can. Many people have a private language without even knowing it. They may call it jargon or
slang, but it’s really a private language, a way of telling who is in the group and who is not” (9). He
because his way of speaking is literal, to the point: “If someone is a bad person and you want to say
he is a bad person, why not just say it? Why say ‘heel’ or ‘jerk’ or something? And adding ‘real’ to it
only makes it worse. If you say something is real, it should be real” (30). When upset he sometimes
begins to stutter or cannot answer at all (known as selective mutism, a social anxiety disorder) and
A psychiatrist that evaluates Lou every few months seems to completely misunderstand him as well:
“She doesn’t know that I can read. She thinks I’m hyperlexic, just parroting the words. The
difference between what she calls parroting and what she does when she reads is imperceptible to
me. She doesn’t know that I have a large vocabulary. […] She knows I work on computer, she
knows I went to school, but she has not caught on that this is incompatible with her belief that I am
57
actually nearly illiterate and barely verbal” (2). Lou complains that she talks to him “as if [he] were a
rather stupid child” (2) or “a trained dog” (4). Autistic therapy often involves technology as many
patients find it less overwhelming than interacting with humans. The most popular therapies for
autism include a lot of classical and operational conditioning, a technique also used to train dogs and
parrots (more on that in the next chapter). Similarly to Lou, Eliza is called a “parrot” by Dr. Higgins
and a verbal “genius” by Pickering (III, 600-604). Autistic people are commonly labeled as geniuses
as well; Lou works in a company that employs people with neuroatypical abilities—a practice that
When among the “real people” or the “other people,” as Lou often calls them, Lou’s language
changes: “We say good-bye because we are in public and we all know you are supposed to say good-
bye in public” (10). Every word he utters with neurotypical people is a performance. He can only
relax among other autistic people: “When we are together like this, just us, we can talk better than
any other time. We laugh about that, about how normal people must be putting out a field that
inhibits our abilities. We know that’s not true, and we know the other would think we were paranoid
if we told that joke around them. They would think we were crazy in a bad way; they would not
understand it is a joke. When we do not recognize a joke, they say it is because we are literal-minded,
58
Many people on the autistic spectrum, in particular women,25 were found to camouflage their autism
by acting out what the society believes to be the right behavior.26 Jennifer, for example, practices
how to act at a birthday party before attending the event: “[S]he prepares herself to be ‘on,’
correcting her posture and habitual fidgeting. She demonstrates for me how she sits up straight and
becomes still. Her face takes on a pleasant and engaged expression, one she might adopt during
conversation with another parent. To keep a dialogue going, she might drop in a few well-rehearsed
catchphrases, such as ‘good grief’ or ‘go big or go home.’ ‘I feel if I do the nods, they won’t feel I’m
uninterested,’ she says” (Russo par. 6). Quite like Eliza, Jennifer and other women on the spectrum
practice the re-telling of anecdotes on a particular topic and memorize their answers for specific
questions. Nearly all of these women complained how exhausting it was to mask oneself and many
said that playing so many roles made them lose sight of their true identities (par. 26). This casting-
oneself, or acting, is a job for some people. Jumping into a performance, masking oneself, can
sometimes solve the language issues. To avoid stuttering, some stutterers avoid words that make
them stutter, make themselves speak more slowly, or put on an accent. Not surprisingly,
professional actors and singers can be stutterers in private life but never stutter on screen or stage
(Marilyn Monroe, Mel Tillis, James Earl Jones, Hugh Grant, Emily Blunt, Julia Roberts, etc.) (see
25This masking was particularly typical for girls who were better at blending in and hiding their autism in comparison to
boys—which is a particularly significant finding for diagnosing children with this disorder.
26This masking of a mental disability is alike to disguising of a physical disability: “Many crippled people try to act in
public as if they are not disabled” (Shell Polio 145).
59
When someone’s speech is off—either stuttered or as a cause of some other speech defect or
ignored. Sometimes these speakers are not considered as speaking at all but rather as mute. Eliza’s
uncultured language makes her a foreigner in Higgins’s circles, a barbarian (“an insensitive,
uncultured person” (‘Barbarian’)). The word Barbar is in itself an “imitation of the sound of the
unintelligible speech” (‘Barbarism’). Ancient Greeks called barbarian anyone who was non-Greek
and therefore regarded as “culturally inferior” (‘Barbarian’). Claude Lévi-Strauss writes in Race and
History (1952) about embedded perceptions of the human based on the physical distance between
the groups of humans: a group always refers to themselves as human, distant groups as semi-human,
Language is separating. In English language one can express a lack of understanding with the idioms
It is all Greek to me and It is double Dutch. In other European languages, the common target language is
Chinese. In Mandarin, interestingly, the idiom goes: Sounds like a bird language ( ). Birds
are intelligent animals but do they have a language and are we allowed to call it that? Examining
galateas that learn to speak humanese and their acceptance among real people is only the beginning:
birds and apes can speak some humanese, and AI and robots are pretty good at it, too. They might
be even better than some humans affected by speech or language paralysis, and better than
If a person or some other entity speaks incomprehensibly, this might be considered no different
than being mute. In Slavic languages, the proto-Slavic word for Germans, *němьci, means someone
27The same language can be the result of comedy or poetry, for example, but brings the opposite, appreciative reaction
from the audience.
60
“mute, who cannot speak (our language),” while the name for Slavs likely comes from a proto-Slavic
word for ‘a word,’ *slovo (‘Slovenski’), designating a community that “could be communicated with
and understands our language” [translation is mine] (‘Slovenski’).28 Two Slovenian words for being
mute are also very telling: a neutral expression, nem, meaning “someone who is not capable of
forming words and sentences with their speech organs” (‘Ném,’ ‘Mútast’ SSKJ),29 and either comes
from the Indo-European root *mēmo-, known in Latin for mute and memulis ‘stutterer’ or from the
Indo-European root *nēmo- that means “non-speaking,” presumably with the original meaning “a
(small) child” (‘Nem’ Etimološki);30 and a marked expression, mutast, with the exact same meaning as
nem, which “comes from the onomatopoeia moo, that imitates cow sounds as well as unarticulated
human sounds” (‘Mutast’ Etimološki) [all Slovenian translations are mine]; 31 the latter word is related
to English mute. These etymologies show how close to an animal someone is who is considered
unarticulated and incomprehensible like Eliza. Eliza is given new clothes and taught manners, but
28 “Po starejši razlagi, ki je besedotvorno slabše, pomensko pa bolje utemeljena, naj bi bilo ime ljudstva *Slově̋ne
izpeljano iz pslovan. *slȍvo ‛beseda’ (glej slóves, slovô). Če je ta domneva kljub besedotvornim zadržkom pravilna, je
ime ljudstva prvotno pomenilo nekako *‛ljudje, s katerimi je mogoče govoriti, ki razumejo naš jezik’. V prid tej domnevi
bi govorilo dejstvo, da so Slovani svoje zahodne sosede, Germane, kasnejše Nemce, imenovali *Němьci̋, sloven. Némci,
prvotno *‛nemi ljudje’, tj. *‛ljudje, ki ne znajo govoriti (po naše)’ (M. S. pri BeIII, 265 s.)” (‘Slovenski’).
29 “ki ni sposoben oblikovati besed, stavkov z govorilnimi organi” (‘Mútast’, ‘Ném’ SSKJ).
30 “Enako je stcslovan. němъ ‛nem’, hrv. nijȇm, srb. nȇm, rus. nemój, češ. němý ‛nem, tih’. Pslovan. *ně̑mъ je verjetno po
disimilaciji nastalo iz *mēmo-, kar je znano v let. mḕms ‛nem’, męmulis ‛jecljavec’. Beseda je lahko izpeljana iz
onomatopejskega korena *mem-, ki posnema neartikulirane človeške glasove (M. S. pri Be II, 219, SŠ, 999) in iz katerega
je tudi sloven. momljáti in sorodno. Druga možnost je izhajanje iz ide. *nēmo- poleg *nēmu- ‛negovoreč’, kar je lahko
besedotvorni predhodnik za hier. luv. ni-mu-wa/i-za-s(a) z domnevnim pomenom *‛(majhen) otrok’,
prvotno *‛negovoreči’ (Rasmussen, Selected Papers on Indo-European Linguistics, 653)” (‘Nem’ Etimološki).
31 “Izpeljano iz nar. múta ‛nem človek’, kar je (eventualno prek nar. nem. mut) izposojeno in posamostaljeno
iz it. muto‛nem’. It. beseda se je razvila iz lat. mūtus ‛nem’, kar je izpeljano iz ide. onomatopeje *mū, ki poleg kravjega
oglašanja posnema tudi neartikulirane človeške glasove (Be II, 208, WH, 139)” (‘Mutast’ Etimološki).
61
Giorgio Agamben writes that if “[language] is taken away, the difference between man and animal
bridge that passes from the animal to the human,” or an ape-man (36), and, on the other side of the
fracture, a man-ape, “the enfant sauvage or Homo ferus, but also and above all the slave, the barbarian,
and the foreigner, as figures of an animal in human form” (37).32 In his opinion, a lack of language—
in the form of foreignness, muteness, or absent civility— animalizes the human. Being human but
not being able to speak is the first step in this animalization. This is why I claim that language is a
required part of human outfit, although it does not come in complete form at birth and needs to be
learned and practiced. Per Agamben, the definitive annihilation of man must therefore also entail the
disappearance of human language (and with it, the love of wisdom as well as the possibility of any
wisdom as such). This is how anthropocentrism permeates posthumanist ideas, such as human
extinction or the Anthropocene: regardless of the extinction, the human or its attribute remains an
agency in the world. Posthuman language is one of such agencies: humanese languages embedded
into nonhuman computational systems. These systems not only use humanese to communicate with
humans, but are created with a special humanese language—the code, which tends to be written in
English or in some other prevalent language. With humans gaining new aspects of posthuman
language through our interaction with machines, posthuman language is becoming a cross- and
multi-species effort.
Language enhancement therefore works in the opposite direction of animalization, just as it did with
Eliza. Higgins’s training of Eliza is not a transhumanist practice and yet it is its early predecessor.
Higgins does not even consider himself a humanist: he is a man of science. His actions—his
Homo ferus is, according to Carl Linnaeus’s eighteenth-century systemization of Homo sapiens to Americans, Asians,
32
Europeans and Africans, a feral person from one of the additional categories, Homo ferus and Homo monstrous.
62
training, treatment, and therapy of Eliza—do not necessarily follow humanist beliefs (in equality,
morality, personal responsibility, control of life, etc.), however, they certainly actualize humanist
values, of which transhumanism is only “an intensification” (Wolfe What xv). Transhumanists build
on humanist beliefs that put the rational, autonomous and self-determining human at the center of
the world and distinctly believe in “the perfectibility of the human, seeing the limitations of the
human body (biology) as something that can be transcended through technology” (Nayar 6). They
also cultivate the fundamental—and very utopian—assumption that the inequality could be solved
with technology and science. This is how Higgins, without ever intentionally wanting to be a
humanist (except perhaps through his firm belief in science), becomes a transhumanist, and this is
how Eliza, an outcast, becomes fully human for the rest of the world.
In premodern times, beginning with the Greeks and continuing to the Medieval Ages, there was no
generic concept in which people were simply born human. According to Aristotle’s Politics (Book I),
only a small part of humanity is endowed with reason (by nature) and is therefore fully human (thus
excluding slaves, women, and artisans). The generic concept of the human emerged only with
Descartes who ascribed reason to everyone who is born human and is as such distinguished from
the animal. Descartes connects having knowledge (conciencia) with having consciousness. In principle,
anyone could acquire language and knowledge and use them for reasoning and judgment. Higgins as
a man of science believes he can help Eliza reach that goal. Eliza is a physical and not a metaphysical
creature and can be improved empirically because she is not automatically doomed by birth or
The conflation of humanity and personhood is common when discussing marginalized people (e.g.
we say the humanity of marginalized people, not personhood; we say dehumanization of the
63
oppressed, not depersonalization). The inequality that designated Eliza as a lesser human is the
reason why Francis Fukuyama is famously skeptic towards transhumanist ideas. Anti-transhumanist
reasoning warns that if humans cannot be equal without artificially altering themselves, then
enhancement will surely skew human striving towards this Enlightenment ideal: “The U.S.
Declaration of Independence says that ‘all men are created equal,’ and the most serious political
fights in the history of the United States have been over who qualifies as fully human. Women and
blacks did not make the cut in 1776 when Thomas Jefferson penned the declaration” (Fukuyama,
par. 5). Eliza, a poor woman, does not make a cut in her time and place either. She is completely on
her own, without family connections and with no formal education. Eliza needs to qualify as an
equal human first, which means that any help she gets in improving her status could not be, in terms
of this discussion, viewed as human enhancement but rather as human creation—a Pygmalionesque,
This part will examine how a galatea is created and performed, particularly in language. There are
many kinds of Pygmalionesque performances, but elements of doubling, imitation, and acting (as a
human) are common to all of them. Galateas are created to look physically and often mentally like
humans, ranging from statues (examples are found in Ovid, Mérimée’s Vénus, and so forth),
mannequins (in Makavejev’s Antonijevo razbijeno ogledalo), automata (Hoffmann’s Olympia), robots
(Ava in Garland’s Ex Machina), androids (Villiers de l’Isle-Adam’s Éve), silicon dolls (Bianca in
Gillespie’s Lars and the Real Girl), holograms (Joi in Villeneuve’s Blade Runner 2049) and neural nets
Philadelphia Burke). Even if a galatea is a human, she is often dehumanized or belittled in some way,
lacking the perfection sought from a man (Poe’s young maiden in The Oval Portrait, Hardy’s
64
generation of island women in Well-Beloved, Hawthorne’s Georgiana in Birthmark, Balzac’s Sarrasine,
etc.). For instance, Higgins picks up Eliza on the street as if she were “a pebble on the beach” (II,
338), disregarding anything she might have left behind (II, 342-43), and plans to cast her aside once
she is trained: “When Ive done with her, we can throw her back into the gutter; and that will be her
own business again; so thats all right” (II, 438-439). Eliza is no more than a doll with no personal
history and feelings—a doll whose talking features Higgins attempts to improve.
A galatea is never just a humanlike creation, however, but also an object of eroticism. Although the
galatea is the ultimate erotic woman, a poem that precedes Pygmalion’s in Ovid’s Metamorphoses
explains that Pygmalion decided he is not interested in women because he saw Propoetides
inversely to galatean animation, turned from flesh into stone. In Pygmalion’s poem, he clearly shows
his disgust towards these fleshly women, which is also why he creates his own ideal woman. Only in
later renditions of the Pygmalion myth was the galatea herself sometimes made a prostitute (e.g.
Édouard Manet’s painting Olympia and Garry Marshal’s romantic comedy Pretty Woman),34 which is
not surprising considering that the prostitution industry objectifies people. Like Pygmalion, Higgins
is at first disgusted with the fleshly Eliza, but manages to turn her into a perfect talking and acting
doll. Eliza’s role as an actress extends to her spiritual cousin, “the sympathetic courtesan” (Mazer
307). Besides that, Eliza is indirectly accused of prostitution on many occasions in the play and
33“These women had offended Venus, on what grounds is unclear, but most scholars suppose some form of sexual
impropriety” (Marshall 25).
34 The creators of the recent cinematic rendition of the Pygmalion myth Ederlezi Rising (2018), which was made after a
short story from the eighties by Serbian author Zoran Nešković, played with this relation by casting American
pornographic actress Stoya as a galatean android. The etymology of pornography is literally writing about prostitutes and
this is how this industry relates to many Pygmalionesque stories (starting with Ovid) or art (Monet’s Olympia)
(‘Pornography’).
65
defends herself with the refrain “I’m a good girl, I am” (I, 388, II, 390, II, 533, II, 542, etc.) so often
these few words work as her motto. Her activity, selling flowers all alone at a corner in Covent
Garden, was a common cover for the sex trade from the sixteenth to eighteenth centuries at that
exact location. This is evident many times throughout the play. When Eliza randomly calls Freddy,
an incidental passerby whom she later marries, by his actual name (“Nah then, Freddy: look wh’ y’
gowin, deah” (I, 73): Now then, Freddy: look where you’re going, dear), his mother becomes
suspicious: how could a girl of her kind know her son’s name? (I, 93).
The etymology of the word prostitute stems from Lat. statuere (‘to cause, to stand’) and shares the
root sta- with ‘statue’ and ‘status’ (‘Prostitute’), literally meaning to stand before something or for
something. From the very beginning of the Pygmalion type stories, the word statue is largely
preferred over sculpture (from Lat. sculpere ‘to carve’) (‘Sculpture’). In fact, the word statue is used
exclusively in most Pygmalionesque texts (e.g. Nathaniel Hawthorne’s ‘The Golden Touch’ and ‘The
Marble Faun,’ Thomas Hardy’s Barbara of the House of Grebe, Prosper Mérimée’s La Vénus d’Ille).
Quite unexpectedly, Ovid’s poem, the locus classicus of inspiration for later renditions of the
Pygmalion myth and the first ancient source, never uses the word statua (‘statue’) or any other related
form. Ovid’s choice of words that comes closest to the statue or the art of sculpting is the verb sculpo
(‘to carve’) in “Interea niveum mira feliciter arte / sculpsit ebur formamque qua, femina nasci / nulla
ivory / With marvelous triumphant artistry / And gave it perfect shape, more beautiful / Than ever
woman born” (232). Ovid’s ivory girl is called femina (‘woman’), virgo (‘virgin, maiden’), puella (‘girl’),
or ebur (‘ivory’), and these labels are used interchangeably before and after the metamorphosis
(Magnus 10.243-297). Although never used by Ovid, the word statue and the name Galatea are
66
central designations of Pygmalion’s creation and modern language translations of Ovid’s poem use
If Eliza is not a prostitute, then what is her background? How is she created? The galatea becomes a
and predominantly in the twentieth and twenty-first centuries. In those accounts there is often more
than one maker of galatea and each maker covers their respective part of the creation: traditionally,
one creator makes the body or the base and the other gives the mind or education (Spallanzani and
Coppola in Der Sandmann, Lentz and Rick in Galatea 2.2, Doolittle and Higgins in Pygmalion). Eliza’s
father, Alfred Doolittle, is proud of Eliza’s beauty: “Well, I never thought she’d clean up as good
looking as that, Governor. She’s a credit to me, aint she?” (II, 1151-1153). Mrs. Higgins adds that
“[t]he girl is naturally rather affectionate,” to which Alfred Doolittle replies: “[v]ery tender-hearted,
maam. Takes after me” (V, 288-290). He takes no credit for anything else besides his genes since he
“never brought her up at all, except to give her a lick of a strap now and again” (II, 1180-1181).
Nevertheless, he still feels the need to transfer the authority he holds over Eliza to Higgins, advising
him: “If you want Eliza’s mind improved, Governor, you do it yourself with a strap” (II, 1205-1206).
Science is on Dr. Higgins’s side: Eliza’s bad English is treated and cured. Just like law enforcement
tries to cure illegal activity (think of Sherlock Holmes) and just like medicine tries to cure bad health
(Dr. Watson),35 Higgins cures bad English. However, Higgins accuses Eliza of a sort of criminal
activity, not because of her suspicious selling of flowers but because of her dialect: a “woman who
35Completely unrelated to Dr. Watson, Sherlock’s right hand, we have another ‘doctor’ Watson today: an IBM machine
that is capable of, among other things, diagnosing and recommending medical treatments better than the average
physician.
67
utters such depressing and disgusting sounds” and makes ‘errors’ in a language of “Shakespear and
Milton and The Bible,” has “no right to be anywhere – no right to live” (I, 391-395). Since Eliza’s
speech is a “cold-blooded murder of the English tongue,” as the actor in the crime, she should be
“taken out and hung” (I, 401-02). Higgin’s reasoning is that Eliza’s dialect requires treatment (speech
therapy, elocution lessons) because she is a delinquent tarnishing English and also because he sees
her as verbally paralyzed. Higgins’s treatment is a way of curing social pathology and de-
marginalizing the oppressed class of Elizas and anyone like her (monsters, animals, robots).
Higgins’s greatest fear is realized in War with the Newts. Čapek’s newts have a peculiar use of human
language, adapted to their own physicality (a speech impediment) and presumably have a related
view of the world (a cognitive impediment). Their unique use of language transforms the general use
“With the nationalization of Newt education the whole business was simplified: Newts in each country were
simply taught in the national language. Although the salamanders picked up foreign languages rather quickly,
and with enthusiasm, their linguistic skill exhibited some peculiar shortcomings, due, on the one hand, to the
configuration of their vocal organs and, on the other, to what one might call psychological reasons. They had
difficulties, for instance, with the pronunciation of long polysyllabic words and tried to shorten them to one
syllable which they then uttered in a brief and rather croaky manner. They said ‘l’ instead of ‘r’ and tended to
lisp their sibilants. They dispensed with grammatical endings, never learned to differentiate between ‘I’ and
‘we’, and they could not care less whether a word was of feminine or masculine gender (maybe this reflected
their sexual frigidity outside mating time). In short, every language was characteristically transformed in their
mouths and somehow economically reduced to its simplest and most rudimentary form. It is worth noting that
their neologisms, their pronunciation and their primitive grammar were rapidly being adopted by the dregs of
dockside humanity, on the one hand, and by what is known as society, on the other. From there this manner of
expressions spread to the newspapers and soon became general. Even among humans grammatical gender
often disappeared, endings were dropped, inflexion became extinct” (146).36
36 “Postátněním mločího školství se celá věc zjednodušila: v každém státě byli Mloci prostě vychováváni v řeči
dotyčného státního národa. Ačkoliv se Salamandři učili cizím řečem poměrně snadno a horlivě, jevila jejich jazyková
schopnost zvláštní nedostatky jednak pro uzpůsobení jejich mluvidel, jednak z důvodů spíše psychických; tak například
jen s obtíží vyslovovali dlouhá, mnohoslabičná slova a hleděli je zredukovat na jedinou slabiku, kterou vyráželi krátce a
poněkud kvákavě; říkali l místo r a v sykavkách mírně šišlali; odpouštěli si gramatické koncovky, nikdy se nenaučili dělat
rozdíl mezi ‘já’ a ‘my’ a bylo jim jedno, je-li nějaké slovo rodu ženského nebo mužského (snad se v tom projevuje jejich
pohlavní chladnost mimo dobu páření). Prostě každý jazyk se v jejich ústech charakteristicky přetvořil a jaksi
zracionalizoval na nejjednodušší a rudimentární formy. Je hodno pozoru, že si jejich neologismy, jejich výslovnost i
gramatickou primitivnost počala rychle osvojovat jednak lidská spodina v přístavech, jednak takzvaná nejlepší
společnost; odtud se ten způsob vyjadřování šířil do novin a zaáhy zobecněl. I u lidí namnoze vymizely gramatické rody,
odpadaly koncovky, vyhynulo skloňování; zlatá mládež potlačila r a naučila se šišlat; stěží kdo ze vzdělaných lidí by mohl
ještě říci, co znamená indeterminismus nebo transcendentno, prostě proto, že se ta slova stala i pro lidi příliš dlouhými a
68
In some texts, the Pygmalionesque metamorphosis is an illusion and, as such, does not work for the
creator. Higgins would agree that the transformation was successful: “By George, Eliza, I said I’d
make a woman of you; and I have. I like you like this” (V, 907). In his eyes, Eliza is a galatea he
created for others and not himself. Since every galatea is made for love, Higgins suggests she might
get married now (III, 215). As opposed to many previous renditions of the Pygmalion myth, Eliza
does not end up marrying Higgins—although most audiences and many re-creators of Shaw’s play
have wished that would have been the case.37 Her illusion works on the youngsters, like Higgins’s
former student Nepommuck, who thinks her English is too perfect for a native, and naïve Freddy,
who marries her. But Higgins will always see Eliza as she was before the transformation. After their
experiment is over and Eliza leaves Higgins’s house without his knowledge, he still treats her, by his
mother’s observations, “as if she were a thief, or a lost umbrella, or something” (V, 66-67). Eliza,
too, realizes that Higgins sees her “only [as] a squashed cabbage leaf” (V, 411) that underwent his
experiment (V, 406). “I shall always be a flower girl to Higgins, because he always treats me as a
flower girl, and always will; but I know I can be a lady to you [Pickering], because you always treat
me as a lady, and always will” (V, 473-476). Eliza’s performance is real for everybody else, but she
cannot fool her creator. Higgins himself warns her: “Don’t you dare try this game on me. I taught it
37Shaw was strictly against marrying Eliza with Higgins (and explained why in the postscript essay What Happened
Afterwards) whereas the director of the theater premiere had Higgins toss a bouquet to Eliza at the end of the play.
Creators of the 1938 film, titled Pygmalion, pushed for the happy-end pairing too but Shaw fought against it, which
resulted in an ambiguous ending.
69
John Bertolini describes Higgins as trying to become the “creator of life rather than the created of
his mother” (101). As Lawrence Switzky observes, Higgins is dependent on Eliza, his mother, and
Mrs. Pearce, as we are today on our cell phones—Haraway’s companion species—and their virtual
assistants (58): “But I cant find anything. I dont know what appointments Ive got” (V, 47-48). He
imagines Eliza exactly like a virtual assistant when he tells Pickering: “We’ll get her on the
photograph so that you can turn her on as often as you like with the written transcript before you”
(II, 90-92). Shaw is largely unacknowledged in his anticipation of modern chatbots and machine
training; despite the obvious connection between Eliza Doolittle and ELIZA the chatbot, only this
chapter and Lawrence Switzky’s paper, which has been also recently published, delve deeper into the
The Turing test is especially relevant here because it is designed as a theatrical performance, the
world of illusion instead of the world of being,38 and it is no coincidence that Turing loved Shaw’s
plays (Switzky 64, 53). Eliza’s transformation stands or fails on her performance. Her performance,
further, stands on her belief that she is, indeed, an intelligent person and not someone who has been
mindlessly thought to speak and think: “You cant take away the knowledge you gave me,” she tells
Higgins. “You said I had a finer ear than you. And I can be civil and kind to people, which is more
than you can. Aha! [Purposely dropping her aitches to annoy him] Thats done you, Enry Iggins, it az” (V,
892-94).
38In improvisational theater with AI, one of the performance settings is based on the Turing test: the audience needs to
identify the performers who are fed lines through AI chatbot operated earphones (the so-called Cyborgs) from regular
improvisers. Anecdotal evidence suggests that regular improvisers manage to deceive the audience by modifying their
behavior into acting more robotic, “aping the sometimes nonsensical nature of AI-generated text” (Loesel et al. 3).
Although digital agents often generate “sentences inconsistent with respect to logic, social conventions and emotions
[…] these limitations were welcomed by the performers as they felt the AI acted like an ‘X factor’ and forced humans to
become better improvisers” (ib.)
70
Once successfully performed and transformed, Eliza becomes a person of respect and gains visibility
in society. A ‘person’ originally means ‘a mask’ (‘Person’) and Eliza, performing her new self, truly
becomes a new person. She also becomes more of a person than she ever was before. Eliza’s
transformation does not only convince her milieu,39 but also works in her innermost expression of
selfhood—her language. This is confirmed when she discovers she is not able to speak like she used
to anymore: “I could have done it once; but now I cant go back to it. Last night, when I was
wandering about, a girl spoke to me; and I tried to get back into the old way with her; but it was no
use.” She continues to speak about her revelation to Pickering: “You told me, you know, that when
a child is brought to a foreign country, it picks up the language in a few weeks, and forgets its own.
Well, I am a child in your country. I have forgotten my own language, and can speak nothing but
yours” (V, 496-499). Unlike an actress, Eliza is not putting on an accent but has, in fact, lost her
own.40
In Black Skin, White Masks Frantz Fanon writes about “the newcomer,” a black man in France, who
returns home (23). As a hybrid of two cultures, he is scrutinized for slightest changes in his manner
and speech and, indeed, “betrays himself in his speech […], answers only in French, and often he no
longer understands Creole” (23-24). Fanon wonders: “What is the origin of this personality change?
What is the source of this new way of being?” He finds the answer in language: “Every dialect is a
39The social status of people usually does not succumb to misbeliefs while the occupational status is often mistaken:
Higgins is called a professor although he does not hold a university position, and Pygmalion is called a sculptor although
the some accounts present him as a king of Cyprus.
40 There is a rare neurological condition called foreign accent syndrome that can cause someone to look like they speak
in a foreign accent as well. This syndrome, a result of a brain injury, sometimes just a bad migraine, other times a stroke
or head trauma, changes the way people articulate the phonemes and form cohesive sentences. To an untrained ear, the
changed articulation sounds like the person has acquired a foreign accent and, like a foreigner, a difficulty in expressing
themselves (Kurowski et al.). For example, there are cases of British and Australian women that began speaking English
with Chinese, French, or Slavic accent. All of them report being traumatized by this change, not only because they have
trouble with articulating their thoughts and because their identity had to shift due to the syndrome, but also because
their ‘accent’ makes them to be treated differently—as foreigners—by the society (Miller et al.).
71
way of thinking” and changing one’s way of speaking is “an evidence of a dislocation, a separation”
(25).
A similar change and result occur in Eliza, with this difference that the change is trained. The non-
artificial part of her change comes within, however, in the same way, writes Africanist and linguist
Diedrich Hermann Westermann, as an African black person changes their cultural and linguistic
habits with “wearing of European clothes, whether rags or the most up-to-date style; using
European furniture and European forms of social intercourse; adorning the Native language with
European expressions; using bombastic phrases in speaking or writing a European language,” which
makes them more similar to Europeans (Fanon 25). Eliza and Fanon’s “newcomer” follow the same
belief— “the newcomer […] in direct ratio to his mastery of the French language” and Eliza to the
English language—that they “will come closer to being a real human being” (Fanon 18).
provided by Higgins, and c) mannerist (nonverbal cues, gesturing, poise), by courtesy of Pickering.
The text of the play does not describe much of the nonverbal part of the transformation; instead,
this is rendered in the theatrical performance. Text as the “reproduction of the same” (Phelan 149)
is contrasted with the live performance—and “the presence of living bodies” (148)—that
accentuates the performativity of Eliza’s role. According to linguist Derek Bickerton, “[h]uman
language […] artificially divides entities from their behaviors. If there is a behavior, someone or
something must perform it” (211). Once the text of the play is put on stage, the performance
doubles the acting: Eliza brings forth the upper-class lady, and the actress playing Eliza brings forth
Eliza.
72
G. B. Shaw was admittedly scrupulous about the performances of his plays. Most of all, he paid
attention to how the actors pronounced the lines he wrote. Shaw’s frustration with writing speech is
evident early in Pygmalion when he tries to write Eliza’s speech phonetically: “Ow, eez ye-ooa san, is
e? Wal, fewd dan y’ de-ooty bawmz a mather should, eed now bettern to spawl a pore gel’s flahrzn
than ran awy atbaht pyin. Will ye-oo py me f’them? [Here, with apologies, this desperate attempt to
represent her dialect without a phonetic alphabet must be abandoned as unintelligible outside
London.]” (I, 95-100). Although Shaw almost immediately abandons distinguishing Eliza’s phonetic
speech from the rest of the dialogue, a reader can still partly follow her transformation through the
first three acts. Besides that, Shaw occasionally, all to the last chapter, returns to writing the speech
of the Doolittles in part phonetically, e.g. “Good enough for yə-oo” (II, 125) and “Now, now, Enry
The working title of Pygmalion was The Phonetic Play and this play was not only Shaw’s commentary on
English writing and phonetics: “Whenever possible Shaw commenced the rehearsal process by
reading the play aloud to the actors, because he wanted them to learn the sound of the lines—
pronunciation, intonation, inflection, tempo, and volume—directly from his own mouth” (Buckley
23). Shaw therefore tried to train his actors just like Higgins trained Eliza.
Similarly, Cyrano de Bergerac in the eponymous play by Edmond Rostand (1897) fed his handsome
proxy lines and instructions on how to court his beloved. In the form of speech shadowing,
Bergerac served as a theater prompter. Today, in a little-known practice, an earpiece device can feed
lines to actors and actresses while they are acting (Soloski) or to create an atmosphere to incite an
73
emotional state (Rodrick).41
Shaw created more than one galatea; the obvious is the fictional Eliza, but the less obvious are his
non-fictional puppets—the actors. In this, Shaw is not only similar to Higgins but also to other
creators of talking machines, fictional Rick and Lentz who created Helen, as well as late eighteenth-
41 Johnny Depp admitted to using “a sound engineer [to] feed him lines while shooting a film. This particular move is
not as unusual as it sounds, at least for an actor at this stage of his career—but Depp, of course, found a way to Depp-
ify the process. According to the actor, the sound engineer was hired not necessarily to feed him lines, but to pipe
disturbing noises into his ear—a move Depp says helps him emote better on-screen. / ‘I’ve got bagpipes, a baby crying
and bombs going off [over the earpiece],’ he said. ‘It creates a truth. Some of my biggest heroes were in silent film. It
had to be behind the eyes. And my feeling is, that if there’s no truth behind the eyes, doesn’t matter what the fucking
words are’” (Rodrick par. 68-69).
74
century and early nineteenth-century scientists Christian Kranzenstein, Wolfgang von Kempelen,
Charles Wheatstone, Erasmus Darwin, and the less recognized Joseph Faber, each of whom
patented a talking machine. For example, Kempelen’s machine could not ‘speak’ German, but spoke
French, Italian, and Latin. It would say things like “vous êtes mon ami—je vous amie de tout mon
femme, mon mari, le roi, allons à Paris,” which, per Mladen Dolar, show “the declaration of love
and the praise for the ruler […] displaying the posture of devotion; the machine’s voice is used to
Erasmus Darwin had a personal interest in the origins of language, having stuttering children and
being a stutterer himself. He sought stutter treatment for his eldest son, Charles (father of famous
Charles Darwin), and sent him abroad to France in order “to break the force of habit, formed on the
contagion of daily example” (Shell Stutter 14). He believed that “in the pronunciation of a foreign
language, hesitation would be less likely to recur, than in speaking those words and sentences in
which he had been accustomed to hesitate”—and it worked (67). Perhaps he tried to find a cure for
stuttering by creating his speaking machine. The device was certainly a valuable invention in
exploring the human vocal apparatus. In Temple of Nature, he explained how it worked: “I contrived a
wooden mouth with lips of soft leather, and with a vale back part of it for nostrils, both which could
be quickly opened or closed by the pressure of the fingers, the vocality was given by a silk ribbon
about an inch long and a quarter of an inch wide stretched between two bits of smooth wood a little
hollowed; so that when a gentle current of air from bellows was blown on the edge of the ribbon, it
gave an agreeable tone, as it vibrated between the wooden sides, much like a human voice” (Darwin
Temple 119-120). Charles Darwin, son of stutterer Charles and grandson of stutterer Erasmus,
believed that human ancestors first used language as singing (Darwin The Descent 33). Darwin’s
75
machine could sing a song as well, which is also a common feature with galateas. “The anatomical
characteristics of the human vocal tract are in fact more closely linked to our capacity to sing than to
our capacity to speak,” akin to bird song (Shell Stutter 98). It is thus not surprising that singing was,
by many philosophers of the time, such as Rousseau, Diderot, Rameau, and Condillac, linked to
at times exhibiting the head and torso of a Turk42 and at times a more galatean outfit of a female
head with or without dress (see right). American Joseph Henry preferred Faber’s speaking machine
to Wheatstone’s more recognized invention because Euphonia was “capable of speaking whole
sentences composed of any words what ever” (Henry 362). The main problem with Euphonia’s
The Turk outfit might have been inspired by E. T. A. Hoffman’s 1814 short story Die Automate or by Wolfgang von
42
Kempelen’s popular chess-playing machine the Mechanical Turk, which turned out to be a hoax (Hankins 283).
76
voicing was flat intonation. Henry suggested connecting it with the telegraph.43
Much to Faber’s disappointment Euphonia had only a few devotees, but he never learned they were
the right ones, such as the Bell family. Scottish actor turned phonetician Alexander Melville Bell also
admired Euphonia and, after seeing Charles Wheatstone’s speaking machine, challenged his son,
Alexander Graham Bell, to build his own talking machine—and he invented the telephone. Melville
Bell shared Shaw’s visions of designing a phonetic alphabet; his version is called Visible Speech and
indicates how to articulate sounds, which is why it was mostly used to teach deaf people to speak.
Phonetician Henry Sweet, who admittedly influenced Shaw’s idea of the character Henry Higgins
(Shaw xi), was Bell’s and Shaw’s acquaintance. It was Bell who introduced him to the science of
phonetics (Waigner 559) and Sweet used Bell’s scheme for his own Organic Alphabet (Kemp 1581).
When it comes to talking machines, phonetics is less important for the authenticity of the speech: it
is the right intonation and overall prosody, the “‘music’ of language” (Appelbaum et al. 181), that
makes it humanlike.44 For humans it is challenging to produce the right intonation in a foreign
language, and for a machine in any language. Typically machines present a flat intonation, which
presents as a symptom of an autistic disorder in humans (Baird et al. 901).45 This is why it is, at the
“The keys could be worked by means of electromagnetic magnets and with a little contrivance not difficult to execute
43
words might be spoken at one end of the telegraphic line which have their origin at the other” (Henry 362).
44“It is commonly known that one of the major goals in the development of modern text-to-speech synthesis is the
improvement of prosody, especially intonation” (Vainio et al. 143). Even sign language has a system for indicating
intonation by raising eyebrows. Prosody is so important that a deaf child with no knowledge of sign language developed
home sign—gestural communication developed when there is no input from the sign language community—with “seeds
of a prosodic system” (Applebaum et al. 181).
45“Spoken language (if present) may include unusual features, such as: vocalisations that are not speech-like; odd or flat
intonation; frequent repetition of set words and phrases (echolalia); reference to self by name or ‘you’ or ‘she’ or ‘he’
beyond age 3 years” (Baird et al. 901).
77
current moment, still better to use a voice of a voice-over artist to represent a virtual assistant (like
Susan Bennett voiced Siri) than to give the virtual assistant a purely electronic voice.46
Neural networks today take human voices to create their own. Quite revolutionary, phonologists
today are capable of training them to speak through a generative adversarial networks (GAN) model.
The GAN model was proposed by Ian Goodfellow – “the man who’s given machines the gift of
imagination” (Giles) – in order to train neural networks without supervision and it sets two neural
networks in ‘a conversation,’ very much like the Turing test only with two nonhuman entities. Not
unlike the training Eliza underwent with Higgins, neural nets learn by themselves how to do a
specific task, e.g. recognize real pictures of real cats from ‘deepfakes’ (pictures of fictional cats)
generated by a computer on the basis on the pictures of the real cats. Phonologists take a GAN
approach and teach neural networks how to listen and speak by feeding them only “unannotated raw
acoustic data” (Beguš ‘Generative’ 1). This approach has revealed parallels with human speech
acquisition. White being fed speech data, one neural network, the generator (like ‘Eliza’), learns to
produce speech signal from random noise while the other neural network, the discriminator (like
‘Higgins’), learns to distinguish the generator’s data from real data. The generator (‘Eliza’) has
already shown to be capable, on its own, of producing innovative speech data that is consistent with
human behavior, without ever seeing evidence for these new sequences (15). Thus, the generator has
shown evidence of categorical learning, even if it still makes some “irregular outputs” (e.g.
intervening stop) that “should be eliminated […] with further training” (ib.). Much like Eliza, the
46 “The results show that human voices are assessed as more effective and achieved a better level of effectiveness,
attention, and recall with less concentration. Concerning the functions, the more important and complex a function is,
the more a human voice is preferred over an artificial one” (Rodero 336).
78
Higgins fed Eliza ‘raw data’ from his own mouth first, then took her out to learn on her own among
people who spoke high English. Eliza acquired new language the way a neural network generator
does, taking in all these materials and learning how to produce her own speech by imitating them.
She began with imitating and simple phrases and sentences, but with sufficient training, she was
capable of producing new sequences herself and, ultimately, speaking just like ‘a real human.’
The character of Eliza is Shaw’s perfect actress. She is not only well-versed but extremely talented at
phonetics and prosody, which is confirmed when Nepommuck, an interpreter and polyglot, takes
her for a foreigner, presumably a Hungarian princess in disguise (III, 879-880), because her English
is “too perfect” for a native speaker: “Can you show me any English woman who speaks English as
it should be spoken? Only foreigners who have been taught to speak it speak it well” (III, 855-858).
Actual actors and actresses play less than a trivial role in many Pygmalion stories, and especially in
Shaw’s. In 1956, Broadway adapted Shaw’s play into one of the most successful musicals on its
stage,47 entitled My Fair Lady. The cover of the musical recording shows a typical Pygmalionesque
scene: Eliza as a puppet is operated by Higgins, his own strings drawn from God-like Shaw above
the clouds (see left). The musical starred Julie Andrews as Eliza and Rex Harrison as Higgins. In
1967 Harrison starred as the title character in the musical film Doctor Dolittle,48 an eccentric
veterinarian who can communicate with animals. Doctor Dolittle is not unlike the doctor of
48 The musical is based on Hugh Lofting’s children’s book series on Dr. Dolittle from the 1920s.
79
phonetics who domesticates the parrot-like flower girl, whom he considers a lesser human, into a
lady of his species or class, respectively. Despite different spellings, the allusion of Dr. Dolittle to
Eliza Doolittle is strong, as shown in the diagram (right) of the possible origins of the sentences,
“My roommate really loves teaching her parakeet to talk. It’s like in that movie version of Pygmalion –
what was it called? ‘Dr. Doolittle’ or whatever” (Hofstadter and Moser 195). Apparently, there was
no immediate connection between the two works, but the associative connection had its
repercussions: in 1974 an American science fiction comedy film Dark Star was released, in which
Rex Harrison reprised his Broadway role in the film version My Fair Lady (1964) with Audrey
Hepburn in the leading role. Julie Andrews starred as Eliza on Broadway and casting Hepburn for
the film stirred some controversy. The controversy was later accelerated by the fact, concealed from
play, “[t]he “theme” of voice change and Figure 3 A graph of associative error-making.
80
reproduced in ‘production’” (ib.). Pygmalionesque illusion of animation has certainly become easier
Curiously, one of the most famous social humanoid robots, popular and populist Sophia, was
created by the Hong Kong company Hanson Robotics in 2015 after David Hanson’s wife and
Audrey Hepburn’s images (Hanson ‘Could’ par. 3). Most of what Sophia says is ‘dubbed’ by
someone else as well, usually her creators; people are sometimes not aware of this fact while also
being intentionally misled. This partly autonomous robot that, in 2017, called herself “a real, live
electronic girl” (Hanson ‘About’ par. 1)49 is another ‘best spoken’ ventriloquist. Similarly, in the first
robot theater Sayonara, an interdisciplinary project started by playwright and director Oriza Hirata in
collaboration with android maker Hiroshi Ishiguro, “the android’s part is first acted by a human
Improvisational theater that uses AI and robotics (one of the prominent creator and performer
groups is called Improbotics) “aim[s] to build a bridge over the uncanny valley” is “partially inspired
by the narratives behind George Bernard Shaw’s Pygmalion, Mary Shelley’s Frankenstein and Alan
Jay Lerner’s My Fair Lady” (Mathewson and Mirowski 66-68), as well as by the haunting android
Tara from the ‘I Feel Fantastic’ video (see more on the video in Creepyblog, also mentioned in the
end of Chapter 3) (Mathewson par. 37). Not coincidentally, Kory Mathewson and Piotr Mirowski
use chatbots as the first artificial improvisors: they created named Pyggy, short for Pygmalion, and
A.L.Ex, after Artificial Language Experiment (similarly to how Alex the parrot was named). A.L.Ex.
49Sherry Turkle mentions that toys, mostly “sociable robots (in the form of digital pets and dolls),” are nowadays labeled
as “alive enough,” a step further of “sort of alive,” as they used to be labeled (26).
81
is sometimes put into ELIZA’s mode, achieving great success with the audience (70); ELIZA is
not quite (e.g. a corpse, a zombie, a prosthetic hand). The behavioral reason for this reaction “comes
from the evolutionary tendency to avoid those who do not seem quite right by not being good
enough (to avoid socializing with apes and very sick people)” (Bołtuć 220). Besides, modeling
humanoids after old men’s faces is the easiest route as they tend to be more imperfect than a young
face, overall helping with the uncanny valley eeriness effect. The effect called the uncanny valley of
perfection also causes discomfort when humanoids perform too well to qualify as human (ib.).
50The first black robot Bina48, designed in 2010 by Martine Rothblatt, was modeled after its creator’s wife Bina and fed
Bina’s speech patterns and a database of Bina-isms. Stephanie Dinkins, a transdisciplinary artist who works with AI, race,
gender and history, made two projects with Bina48, a series of conversations named Conversations with Bina48 and a
multigenerational family history memoir Not the Only One.
82
Sidestepping the uncanny valley issue is creating a robot that does not look human but still acts
humanlike, giving humans enough features to still anthropomorphize them. The uncanny valley
might get smaller or flatten out once humans get more adjusted to interaction with humanlike
entities; however, Japanese scholars today believe that “[e]ven after long-term exposures, androids
with a strikingly human-like appearance evoke unnatural feelings” (Chikaraishi et al. 1). So far
galateas like Sophia are aesthetically more ambitious projects than creating a less symmetric and less
perfect wrinkled face. Modeling a beautiful galatea after a real woman is not rare in Pygmalionesque
stories and usually serves to show that the artificial woman is more perfect and desirable than the
Courtesy of Hanson Robotics Limited; used with permission. Figure 5 Sophia behind the scenes.
www.hansonrobotics.com/robot/sophia
The photo is from her Instagram account. Used with
permission. www.instagram.com/p/BzWPGchjUjH/
Sophia is Hanson Robotics’ most sophisticated robot to date: an AI with robotic body and an
uncannily human face. Described by Hanson Robotics as a “media darling,” she is indeed a lot like
Audrey Hepburn: she appeared in music videos and short films, was featured on the cover of Elle
83
Brasil, gave a commencement address at Rhode Island School of Design, etc. She is mostly known
for being the first robot to hold citizenship (she was given Saudi citizenship in 2017)51 and for her
impressive humanlike facial mimicry, while the rest of her body is obviously technological, like
fictional robot Ava’s from Alex Garland’s 2014 film Ex Machina. The fact that she usually does not
who were required to wear abaya until March 2018, Figure 7 Robot Ava from the film Ex Machina.
Author’s screenshot.
Sophia was not required to cover herself.
For these two reasons Sophia has a widely successful career in, essentially, being a celebrity: “She has
met face-to-face with key decision makers in banking, insurance, auto manufacturing, property
development, media, and entertainment. In addition, she has appeared onstage as a panel member
and presenter in high-level conferences, covering how robotics and artificial intelligence will become
a prevalent part of people’s lives. […] She was named the world’s first United Nation Innovation
Champion by United Nations Development Program (UNDP) and will have an official role in
working with UNDP to promote sustainable development and safeguard human rights and equality”
(‘Sophia,’ par. 2). Sophia learns from interactions with people, is able to process information quickly,
51 A nonhuman entity holding a citizenship opens many questions, starting with her civil and political rights.
84
expresses emotion according to the topic of conversation, recognizes faces and voices, and performs
All in all, Sophia sums up what a humanoid robot can do today and what its planned abilities are for
the near future—while also spreading false notions of about what robots are actually able to do (she
is much less capable than is presented) or will be able to do (surely not have children, as she
supposedly desires to), about what robots really are (certainly not real, live electronic people), and by
advocating her species in places other than the entertainment industry. She is a social robot to be
admired: her creators hope to make her a better conversationalist through teaching her about
emotions and asking people who interact with her to “be nice to [her] as [she] would like to be a
smart, compassionate robot” (Hanson ‘About’ par. 1). Sophia certainly sees a lot of emotions during
her interviews and speeches. Not uncommon reactions are: “Sorry, this is so weird” apologized
interviewer Steve Kovach (0:46), “You are a little freak” (0:46) and “This is freaking me out,” said an
appalled Piers Morgan (1:31), and “I’m getting nervous around a robot, a very pretty robot,”
admited Jimmy Fallon (3:31). Sophia might not see such reactions in Japanese culture that presents
the highest tolerance; at least Hiroshi Ishiguro, another famous roboticist, seems to think so, saying
that “Japanese men are more prone than Western men to develop amorous feelings towards such
Sophia’s language skills are conceptually similar to chatbot ELIZA’s: they both hold a conversation
using a natural language system with pre-written responses (as Melanie Mitchell notes, “[i]n AI
speak, ‘natural’ means ‘human’” (178)). Chris Griffith, journalist for The Australian, describes
Sophia’s conversational skills: “Like Amazon Echo, Google Assistant and Siri, Sophia can ask and
answer questions about discrete pieces of information, such as what types of movies and songs she
85
likes, the weather and whether robots should exterminate humans” (par. 10). His description is not
too far from how Higgins describes Eliza’s communication: “Ive taught her to speak properly; and
she has strict orders as to her behavior. She’s to keep to two subjects: the weather and everybody’s
health—Fine day and How do you do, you know—and not to let herself go on things in general.
That will be safe” (III, 110-112). Besides this resemblance in their interlocutory behavior, Sophia
uses similar avoidance strategies as Eliza Doolittle and the earliest chatbots, such as ELIZA, e.g.
mirroring language of the question and turning the interlocutor’s sentences into questions, changing
the subject of the conversation, or answering the question “close to the topic of the question, but
off beam” (Griffith, par. 11-12). Even if answers are usually accurate and could have been easily
given by a human, they are not always appropriate for a given situation. For instance, these days a
chat with scripted Apple’s virtual assistant Siri or robotic Sophia often provokes comical replies,52
Here Eliza is giving away cues that she is performing by answering to a small talk question with a
weather forecast report, excessive formality, and by “bet[ting she] got it right” as if the conversation
were a test (which, indeed, it was). Her first reaction is scripted and mechanical, and the second is
reflective of the fact that her replies are learned. Shaw’s Galatea is therefore an actress, like many
galateas that followed her, e.g. Hanson’s proxy Sophia or C. L. More’s Daphne from short story ‘No
52For example, Siri replies to “Where did you go to school?” with avoiding the direct answer and revealing a subject of
her studies while also cracking a joke: “I’m studying the human-ities.”
86
Woman Born.’53 In the 2015 interdisciplinary opera My Square Lady,54 Eliza is substituted with a
robot. The robot also tries to pass off as human, particularly in training its emotional skills.
Acting is rooted deeply in the Pygmalion myth through the animation of the character
exercise in being someone else and an exercise in playing pretend; underlying the performance is a
total and utter belief in the assumed identity of the character. Anything is possible in acting: a non-
singer can sing by dubbing and Superman can fly. An actor’s work involves observation of human
life, of human behavior, and requires a great sensitivity in its re-creation. Pygmalionesque figures are
often puppets or dolls, completely dependent on a puppeteer who animates them and puts words
into their mouths. Paralleled with actors, puppets reveal the dependency of the actor who is led by a
writer and supervised by a director. Acting is also related to the cult of celebrity—a kind of
superhuman status that bestows immortality on a Pygmalionesque creation. For example, James
Tiptree Jr.’s (Alice Sheldon’s) Philadelphia Burke from The Girl Who Was Plugged In (1974) is
nominally an actress in soap operas, but her real job is to be a celebrity used for advertising through
being seen buying and selling products. Uniqueness is a perquisite for any celebrity: once the
53In another Pygmalionesque story, C. L. Moore’s ‘No Woman Born,’ galatea Daphne is an adored performer who loses
her human body in a fire. Her brain is restored together with a metal substitute body, which gives her physical
superpowers. Daphne discovers that her real superpower, however, comes from the magic of her celebrity, admired as
superhuman.
The opera is a coproduction of Gob Squad, the Komische Oper Berlin and the Neurorobotics Research Laboratory at Beuth
54
87
1.6 The Elizas
In this chapter, I demonstrate how Shaw anticipates computer-based language training and suggest
that Shaw, admittedly basing his Pygmalion on phonetician Henry Sweet while being surrounded by
the Bell family that was about to invent a telephone, already picked up on the nascent science of
instilling humanese in machines already at the beginning of the twentieth century. This
argumentation is supported by the historical event in which Eliza Doolittle, a fictional woman,
served as an inspiration for the very first chatbot named after her.
Natural language processing enables computers to use human language as an input and output.
Thus, machines need to understand and generate language (and use mimicry and non-verbal
expressions through robotic prosthesis if they have one). When an IBM computer, named Deep
Blue, beat chess master Gary Kasparov in 1997, having lost to the same champion the previous year,
some people justified it by saying that a computer winning over the best of humans in a logic game
is nothing extraordinary. In 2011, another IBM computer, called Watson, won against two legendary
players in a Jeopardy! Game. This victory was harder to defend since computer needed to
understand the subtleties of language, such as humor, metaphors, and irony, to win this kind of
game. The unanswerable question was met at this point: even if the computer does not understand
the way a human does, if it is capable of processing the same complex language, sometimes even
Natural language processing began with imitating fictional characters that posed as humanoids who
tried to pass as human. Chatbot ELIZA, one of the early natural language processing programs,
created in the 1960s at MIT by Joseph Weizenbaum, was named after Eliza Doolittle because both
Elizas could be improved by user input. ELIZA used scripted answers and, unlike Eliza Doolittle,
88
did not ‘learn’ on its own, which AI is capable of today. ELIZA’s most known and convincing script
is the DOCTOR, which parodied a Rogerian psychotherapist.55 ELIZA’s communication skills are
quite poor and “[th]e illusion of intelligence works best […] if you limit your conversation to talking
about yourself and your life” (Birnbaum, par. 2). When performing, Eliza Doolittle turns away every
question about itself, just like modern virtual assistants using natural-language user interface (e.g.
Amazon Alexa, Apple Siri) and just like every worthy psychotherapist. Similarly, ELIZA is not
capable of deeper conversation and coaxes the patient to do most of the talking by turning their
statements into questions. “‘You remind me of my father,’ the human types. ‘Tell me more about
your father,’ the machine answers,” is how a sarcastic scientist describes “AI’s early darling” in
Galatea 2.2 (Powers 87-88). Admirably, ELIZA is able to refer a few sentences back in the
conversation, but often makes mistakes by turning sentences into nonsensical grammar.
55 PARRY, a 1979 chatbot that simulated a person with paranoid schizophrenia, and ELIZA ‘met’ on several occasions.
89
Not unlike Shaw’s Eliza, ELIZA makes a grammatical mistake in the last sentence. The mistake
could be interpreted as joke, which is how Freddy interprets Eliza Doolittle’s mechanical talk.
“When the original ELIZA first appeared in the 60’s, some people actually mistook her for human”
(Birnbaum, par. 2)—as every magician will tell you, the audience wants to be fooled. This powerful
tendency to anthropomorphize computers was subsequently named after ELIZA as the ELIZA
effect; the effect takes place even if users know they are dealing with an entity that cannot possibly
achieve the attributes they are assigning to the entity. ELIZA’s creator later wrote: “I had not
realized is that extremely short exposures to a relatively simple computer program could induce
powerful delusional thinking in quite normal people” (Weizenbaum 7). The audience that did not
want to believe the illusion, however, felt cheated with “[t]he idea that you could make a convincing
AI system that didn’t really have any intelligence” (Bohannon 251). With ELIZA, it was confirmed
that people are willing to talk with machines that cannot understand or feel, sometimes even
choosing a machine over other people (see Turkle 282). Techno-sceptics find the ELIZA effect
pitiful while technophiles find it valuable and believe it is only positive that AI will be able to work
in psychotherapy better than people do. The future certainly belongs to technophiles who will
hopefully address some of the less optimistic novelties such technologies bring.
Ambivalent about technology, it was Weizenbaum himself who argued in 1976 that AI should not
replace people in places that require respect and care, such as in therapy, court, army, police,
nursing, or customer service, that have been largely managed by AI lately (71). A year later,
Weizenbaum published an essay ‘The Last Dream,’ where he takes the Pygmalion myth as an
archetype of human scientific and technological hubris, arguing that the human desire to create
humanlike creatures and intelligence is connected with considering humans more machine-like. G.
B. Shaw had a similar interpretation of Pygmalion, who is both a scientist and an artist in his series
90
of five plays Back to Methuselah. Shaw’s Pygmalion creates an artificial man and a woman who he
does not believe can ever be truly intelligent—much like Higgins thinks of Eliza and Weizenbaum of
his ELIZA. All in all, the significance of ELIZA was not only that it was one of the first chatbots,
and certainly the most famous, but it has also revealed human anthropomorphizing tendencies of
the ELIZA effect. While some people perceived ELIZA as deceptive and reacted negatively, the
majority of those who did not opened a promising venue of virtual professionals.
Although ELIZA is still learning, it never passed the Turing Test. Further work on AI like ELIZA
did not pan out until the turn of the millennium—largely because of Marvin Minsky and Seymour
Papert who deemed multilayer neural network research as “sterile” in 1969, which largely decreased
research funding afterwards56 (Minsky and Papert 231-32, Mitchell 32, 35). The period after that
time is known as the ‘AI winter,’ followed by the AI spring that we live in today (and that could,
after some ossification on more than one front, turn into another AI winter). Neural networks were
thus popular in the 1950s and 1960s and have gained momentum in 2010s.
Although it has been more than fifty years since Weizenbaum’s Eliza, chatbots are “still viewed as a
parlor trick by most computer scientists,” “really just an enhanced ELIZA” (Bohannon 251). Most
basic chatbots of today still easily trick lay people “into believing that they are talking to an
intelligent, empathetic person” (ib.) and have certainly improved on their performance. Today one
can speak with a virtual therapist that uses a moving avatar while decoding patient’s body language
(see USCICT) or can receive an AI call with inserted stutters and fillers that make it sound more
56Neural networks remained defunded in the West, “except in a few isolated academic groups” (Mitchell 32) and non-
Western countries, like Slovenia (without major breakthroughs until recently when Slovenia became a leading country in
developing AI).
91
‘naturally’ human (Solon). Allison Darcy, a founder and CEO of Woebot Labs, thinks we should not
take people’s reactions too seriously; after all, humans are interested in playing with these creations
and testing their limits while also admiring their humanlike skills (Delaney Hall par. 27). Be it a game
or not, it reveals aspects of humanity that were so far only speculated about fiction and myths:
curiosity about oneself as an individuum and as a species, exploration of our own features and
boundaries, our environment, nature and technology, our psychology and sociology, and it reveals
an intensive desire to anthropomorphize the nonhuman and to appropriate the world according to
our needs. This is why the geological period of human existence is called Anthropocene and why I
needed to coin the term humanese to depict appropriation of nonhuman entities to humans.
Natural language processing is one of the biggest challenges for AI because of language difficulties:
natural language processing is largely about understanding the world and the context of speech. Let
us look at a famous example for the latter challenge, a 1985 advertisement for McDonnell Douglas:
At last, a computer that understands you like your mother. This sentence could be understood in three ways:
“1. The computer understands you as well as your mother understands you. 2. The computer
understands that you like your mother. 3. The computer understands you as well as it understands
your mother” (Lee 112). This language ambiguity shows “that the most difficult problems in
artificial intelligence manifest themselves in human language phenomena” (Lee 112). It is not a
57 The Winograd Schema Challenge was developed by Hector Levesque in 2011 in the spirit of the Turing test and also
focuses on semantical ambiguity in language, in particular to pronoun use and common sense/context. Examples
offered on the Winograd Schema Challenge website deal with these precise difficulties: “I. The trophy would not fit in
the brown suitcase because it was too big (small). What was too big (small)?
Answer 0: the trophy
Answer 1: the suitcase
II. The town councilors refused to give the demonstrators a permit because they feared (advocated) violence. Who feared
(advocated) violence?
92
The Turing test was officially passed only in 2014 by a chatbot called Eugene Goostman, a program
many connoisseurs would quickly identify as a computer since it uses typical chatbot tricks (changing
the topic of conversation, answering with a question, etc.). Eugene Goostman was portrayed as a
thirteen-year-old Ukrainian boy with a rather rich background story, not unlike a fiction character.58
Goostman’s identity as a child is intended to induce forgiveness with users in case the bot lacks
knowledge expected from a human adult.59 Does an illusion of personality make for a more
successful human-machine interaction? Apparently yes. Why else would a computer program need
to pretend to be someone—and not something—else? Eliza, too, needs to reinvent her identity,
manners, looks, and speech to be able to pass as a lady. What is achieved when AI assumes a human
identity, like “little girl” Helen? A voice actress for Google Assistant was given a very specific
backstory of the bot she was giving her voice,60 because the ‘humanity’ of the voice is rendered
through it (Schulevitz par. 42). We ask of machines to bear a human name, identity, backstory – not
unlike authors create fictional characters. But why do we want the voice of a machine to sounds like a
voice of a human? Why does it matter if Helen sings differently from little girls? We know she is not
one of them. She is not even human. Why would we want her to be?
58“Eugene received a total mean score of 63.56 placing it above ‘good conversationalist but machinelike’ but well below
100=humanlike” which was still the highest of all [six tested chatbots: ELIZA, Eugene Goostman, Elbot, JFred, Ultra
Hal and Cleverbot]” (Shah et al. 286). Deception percent of these chatbots ranged from 12,5 (Elbot) to almost 30
percent (Eugene Goostman).
59“Eugene was ‘born’ in 2001. Our main idea was that he can claim that he knows anything, but his age also makes it
perfectly reasonable that he doesn't know everything. [The creators] spent a lot of time developing a character with a
believable personality” (University of Redding par. 12).
60 “She comes from Colorado, a state in a region that lacks a distinctive accent. “She’s the youngest daughter of a
research librarian and a physics professor who has a B.A. in art history from Northwestern,” Giangola continues. When
she was a child, she won $100,000 on Jeopardy: Kids Edition. She used to work as a personal assistant to “a very popular
late-night-TV satirical pundit. And she enjoys kayaking” (Schulevitz par. 42).
93
The answer seems to be cross-species connection. Only once such a connection is established
between the human and the humanlike machine can the actual work, for which the machine was
designed, begin. In other words, every humanlike machine must perform the human social
component. We expect machines to act as human if they are to interact with us, even if they do not
perform in lieu of a human. In speech, they need to be fluent, causal, take a pause and seemingly
breathe; when it comes to language, we expect them to joke, be polite, portray emotions when
appropriate, and even improvise, act as if they are conscious and knowledgeable human beings,
although we know that their knowledge and consciousness are of the very different kind than ours.
The cross-species connection is based on entrainment— “the way humans subconsciously track and
mirror each other’s emotions during a conversation” (Bohannon 251)—and poses a great challenge
for AI engineers today. These days, the field of AI focuses on narrow and specific problems, like
machine vision and voice recognition, which is why AI therapists perform some features worse than
humans (e.g. mishear words) and some better than humans (e.g. smile dynamics). It might not be a
problem for patients in computer therapy if their nonhuman therapists revealed their status.
However, the therapy is more successful if the nonhuman therapist is believed to be autonomous
(Bohannon 251).61 No wonder Eliza Doolittle managed to fool everyone, and no wonder ELIZA
the chatbot managed to fool at least those who thought it is autonomous. From here, it is only a
further step to explain why people fall in love with humanlike machines. Ovid’s Pygmalion wanted
his beloved statue to become a real woman, but not all later pygmalions desired the transformation:
61When AI creators carried out a study in which one group of patients was told that their AI therapist is just a puppet
controlled by a human and one group was told that it is fully autonomous, the patients who believed the puppeteer
scenario were “less engaged and less willing to open up during therapy,” assumingly because they “don’t feel judged”
(Bohannon 251).
94
they just desired love. Could machines ever return our feelings? More concretely, could emotions be
programmed and could a program ever encompass the complexity of the emotion and portray it
accurately?
In the nineties, Rosalind Picard, who designs social or relational robots, started a field of affective
computing. At that time, says Picard, “emotion was associated with irrationality, which was not a
trait engineers respected” (Schulevitz par. 46). The field studies how machines respond to human
affective information and how machines could themselves simulate affects in accordance with
human cultural norms and behavior62 (Picard 12). The need for the field emerged after Clifford
Nass’s and Byron Reeves’s research, now called the Media Equation theory, showed that
“individuals’ interactions with computers, television, and new media are fundamentally social and
natural, just like interactions in real life” (5). Further research confirmed that human behavior is
desirable in machines,63 because “people use what they know about human behavior to predict and
explain the behavior of systems that have neither human form nor behavior” (Bar-Cohen, Breazeal
48). The ELIZA effect of anthropomorphism is at work here, and the more human the machines
seem the better people can read them and connect with them (except in the area of the uncanny
valley).64
62Cynthia Breazeal and Rodney Brooks, roboticists at MIT, claim that robotic emotions are valid as a new category of
emotions; just like cats and dogs have emotions which we consider authentic and genuine (also in Turkle 287).
63“[P]eople report[ed] that the [relational] agent cared more about them, was more likeable, showed more respect, and
earned more of their trust than the nonrelational agent. People interacting with the relational agent were also significantly
more likely to want to continue interacting with that agent” (Breazeal and Picard 280).
64“Our data show that the robot consistently scored higher on measures of social presence than the animated character
(and both below that of the human). Overall, people found the robot character to be easier to read, more engaging of
their senses and emotions, and more interested in them than the animated character. Subjects also rated the robot as
more convincing, compelling, and entertaining than the animated character” (Breazeal and Picard 280).
95
Regardless of whether machines are capable of feeling and understanding, humans respond better to
anthropopathic machines, i.e. machines that portray human emotions and cognition, such as
empathy and understanding. Even Higgins admits that in an exchange with Eliza (V, 688-695):
HIGGINS. […] And I have grown accustomed to your voice and appearance. I like them, rather.
LIZA. Well, you have both of them on your gramophone and in your book of photographs. When you feel
lonely without me, you can turn the machine on. It’s got no feelings to hurt.
HIGGINS. I cant turn your soul on. Leave me those feelings; and you can take away the voice and the face.
They are not you.
Humans also respond better to machines that know how to respond to us, complex and emotional
concludes the session with ‘Thank you!’ (157). More sophisticated examples of robots are being
developed with the goal to respond to humans not as objects but as individual subjects.65 For
example, Sophia is involved in a research project called the Loving AI, which “involves developing
software enabling humanoid robots to interact with people in loving and compassionate ways, and
to promote peoples’ self-understanding and self-transcendence” (Goertzel et al. 2). Hiroshi Ishiguro,
the director of the Intelligent Robotics Laboratory at Osaka University and creator of another
strikingly humanlike android Erica, who was made to be a receptionist in their laboratory and then
became a news anchor, says that desires and intentions need to be installed into robots in order to
make them capable of understanding and producing emotions, human intentions and desires (Vance
0:55). Many of these social robots are intended to be personal service robots: to babysit or educate
65 “Such a robot should be persuasive in ways that are sensitive to people, such as reminding them when to take
medication, without being annoying or upsetting. It should understand what the person’s changing needs are and the
urgency for satisfying them so that it can set appropriate priorities. It needs to understand when the person is distressed
or in trouble so that it can get help if needed. Furthermore, people should enjoy having the robot in their life because it
is useful and pleasant to have around” (Breazeal, Picard 276).
96
children, perform household chores, take care of the elderly and sick,66 or help autistic people
understand emotions better (Jain et al.). New options of how we could use this technology keep
So far, the types of AI include weak AI (that we know today), strong AI or AGI (artificial general
intelligence), and superintelligence, the last two of which have not yet been reached and are thus a
mere speculation. All of these types aim to be distinctly humanlike intelligences. One important
aspect that is often overlooked with AI is that the research has long split into two not-yet-identified
types: human-centered AI at the forefront67 and AI that works towards reaching the benchmarks of
nonhuman intelligence, be it nature-like (like found in a human, animal, tree, microbe, etc.) or utterly
and uniquely machine-like. This later type is still accountable to AI ethics but does not subdue to
human desires which could be very limiting (e.g. prevailing research and resources to create a full-
body humanoid in which the body does not have any other function but to represent—really, just
All in all, engineering research of user interface confirms that human connection with machines is
crucial for a successful cooperation: it is at least as much about engineering a robot as it is about
human psychology. Over and over again, man adapts everything to his own desires. Although robots
are made to be practical and pragmatic, humans cannot forgo the Pygmalion myth two millennia
66An example of such care-taking robot can be found in Martin L. Shoemaker’s short story Today I am Paul, and its
sequel Today I am Santa Claus and the sequel novel Today I am Carey.
67Recently, three major human-centered have been established at American universities and they all include scholars
from a variety of disciplines, including the humanities (but not literary scholars): Stanford center for Human-Centered
AI, Berkeley Center for Human-Compatible AI, and MIT Their aim is not to make AI humanlike, but to make the
human world better and safer, which “requires a layer of human-level communication and collaboration” (Knight ‘Put’
par. 3).
97
after it was first textualized. Erica’s creator Ishiguro tells his interviewer: “I think this is the most
beautiful face in the world. She is cute, isn’t she?” (Vance 0:44). Sianne Ngai writes of the term cute
as “an aesthetics disclosing the surprisingly wide spectrum of feelings, ranging from tenderness to
aggression, that we harbor toward ostensively subordinate and unthreatening commodities” (‘Our’
949). Later Ishiguro proposes for him to “test how close to human [he thinks] Erica really is” (3:24)
by kissing her. Programming a humanlike entity for love is a very galatean act and is extended to
other artificial beings aside from beautiful women. For example, in Steven Spielberg’s 2001 film A.I.
Artificial Intelligence a mother of a comatose human child programs an android child to love her as his
mother. Galatea is a perfect example of the cluster of desires that makes this endeavor so prevalent
today: anthropocentric idolizing of one’s own image and attributes, and yearning for company, love,
98
Chapter 2: Humanese: A Posthuman Language
ANIMALS: If only dumb animals could speak! So often more intelligent than men.1
Gustave Flaubert, Le Dictionnaire des idées recues (1911)
I want to be a machine.
Andy Warhol (1963)
This chapter looks into both sides of the nonhuman spectrum: the most advanced machines that use
humanese and the most advanced nonhuman animals that use humanese. Examination through the
lens of language acquisition begins with fictional AI from Richard Powers’ Galatea 2.2 (1995) and
follows with AI capable of writing literature in Andrej Tomažin’s short story ‘Heroes, Lackeys and
Artificial Intelligence’ (‘Hlapci, heroji in umetna inteligenca,’ 2018) and Roald Dahl’s short story
‘The Great Automatic Grammatizator’ (1953), followed by a brief summary of the most successful
creative writing AI to date. In the second part of the chapter, dedicated to animals, I look into
factual and fictional parrots (Alex the parrot and Ted Chiang’s short story ‘The Great Silence’
(2019)), great apes (Kanzi the bonobo), and salamanders (Julio Cortázar ‘Aloxolotl’ (1956), Karel
Čapek’s War with the Newts (1936)). The final part delivers the theoretical argument of this chapter
that language is a prosthesis for human and nonhuman alike, even though we largely differ in our
1 BÊTES: Ah! si les bêtes pouvaient parler! Il y en a qui sont plus intelligentes que des hommes.
99
2.1 Language in AI
We have not always thought of language as an Occam’s razor for identifying human from
nonhuman. This idea, as applied to intelligent computers, goes back to the first neural nets from the
1950s and the Turing test, developed by Alan Turing. In the Turing test, a conversing individual
differentiates between a computer3 and a human on the basis of their responses to questions alone.
The test is also known as the imitation game, a telling name in the light of the fact that imitation is
today, such as virtual assistants, would not pass it. An upgraded Turing test was proposed by Ray
Kurtzweil, technological optimist, and Mitchell Kapor, technological skeptic: the test would be
performed in addition to three human contestants, for a much longer time, and with multiple and
more specialized judges (Mitchell 60-61). If AI would be able to pass the test under these stricter
conditions, then it has reached a human level of conversation. In two iconic scenes from the film
Blade Runner (1982), the Voight-Kampff test, which is much like the Turing test, shows the
interrogator holding a conversation with a humanlike replicant along with subtle tracing of the size
of their pupils. The Voight-Kampff test, like the Turing test, is not foolproof as the replicants
When Alan Turing wrote his paper ‘Computing Machinery and Intelligence,’ in which he described
the Turing Test, he cited Book of the Machines (Chapters 23-25) of Samuel Butler’s Erewhon (1865) in
the bibliography but did not mention it in the body of the paper. In the three chapters, Butler’s
3The term for computer “started off as a human:” it designated (usually) women who performed calculations by hand or
with a mechanical desk calculator (Mitchell 275, see more in Light).
4Michael Airbib determines that only “complex imitation” (as opposed to “simple imitation” some animals are capable
of) supports the breakthrough of language. “Complex imitation includes the ability to master reasonably complex
hierarchical structures ‘on the fly’ rather than over many months of observation” (213).
100
narrator, identified as “the writer,” considers the possibility of conscious machines, arguing that
humanity itself has developed from organisms that had no consciousness (such as bacteria).5
Following this reasoning, there is no “a priori improbability in the descent of conscious (and more
than conscious) machines from those which now exist” (ch. 23, par. 19). Lumping together all
nonhuman entities, the narrator treats machines as a species separate from the human but falls into
the trap of considering them alike to animals. He suggests that machine reproduction might pose a
hindrance in their evolution, “except that which is suggested by the apparent absence of anything
Samuel Butler’s narrator further warns that no other class of beings but machines “have in any time
past made so rapid a movement forward” (par. 21, and again in the final paragraph of the chapter
24), suggesting that machines would evolve beyond the human imitation: “may we not conceive,
then, that a day will come when those ears will be no longer needed, and the hearing will be done by
the delicacy of the machine’s own construction? — when its language shall have been developed
from the cry of animals to a speech as intricate as our own?” (par. 23). Machines, presumes the
narrator, will evolve to develop their own system of communication, their own language, prompted
by their “wants.” Even if we think machines are not capable of ruling the world and are essentially
just a human tool, they will change us: “But the servant glides by imperceptible approaches into the
master; and we have come to such a pass that, even now, man must suffer terribly on ceasing to
5 “a great deal of action that has been called purely mechanical and unconscious must be admitted to contain more
elements of consciousness than has been allowed hitherto (and in this case germs of consciousness will be found in
many actions of the higher machines) — for (assuming the theory of evolution but at the same time denying the
consciousness of vegetable and crystalline action) the race of man has descended from things which had no
consciousness at all. (ch. 23, par. 19).
101
In the posthuman era, we are heightened in our awareness of the fact that we share the world with
other species, some of which are human-made, and that we need to re-evaluate our anthropocentric
beliefs and our dependence on the other species, called the companion species by Donna Haraway.
Focusing on the changes in our language, this chapter tries to illuminate how the posthuman shift
has taken place in relation to speaking and writing machines and animals.
Not that long ago, only technology optimists believed AI could beat human champions in a complex
game, like chess or go, or a game that requires linguistic intelligence, like Jeopardy!. Humanity has
been defeated in both and, in 2020, few remain skeptical of such AI capabilities. Since then, AI has
evolved as a creative tool. Music was the first art form to use AI as a tool. In the mid-1990s, a
program called EMI or Experiments in Musical Intelligence, created by the composer David Cope,
composed original pieces in the style of classical composers by simply being fed their scores
(Mitchell 9-10, 273-74). Since the mid-2010s, music creators have worked with AI machines to
create unique-sounding songs or pop hits based on previous data: the creative part of this team is
the human while an AI music generator performs elaborate mimicry of the data. Granted, the AI
music generator cannot create music without an input, i.e. without learning its ‘grammar.’ Language-
wise, a great breakthrough in natural language processing and deep learning took place in 2012,
when automatic speech recognition vastly improved and spread to cell phones soon after in the
form of virtual assistants. Only a few years later, computers are the sole authors of short journalistic
articles, automatic calls, and poetry—each based on a large data base or a particular style of a human
author.6
6 A more detailed discussion on AI creativity in literature can be found in the section on Tomažin’s and Dahl’s short
stories.
102
With technology advancing and lives moving partially to virtual
or person-to-machine (Cisco, Elliott and Hare par. 3). Figure 9 CAPTCHA test.
Author’s screenshot.
Nowadays a CAPTCHA (Completely Automated Public Turing
Test) program is a routine shibboleth in many online sites: CAPTCHA differentiates computer bots
(fake users) from human users online by offering a test that bots are likely to fail and humans should
find easy to solve. The CAPTCHA test asks to fill in the numbers and letters that are visually
presented to the user in a less conventional form, or it might ask to label specific objects on photos,
both of which are a challenge for AI. A shibboleth works like a password to another culture, a proof
of one’s own indigenousness (hiding the genetic in its very world) or, rarely, assimilation. Not
coincidentally, chatbots were called the first indigenous species of the cyberspace.
Online, language itself has become a giveaway. On Tinder, one of the most popular dating apps,
users developed their own CAPTCHA test, called the potato test. “[I]f a match seems suspiciously
glamorous or otherwise unreal […], you ask the person you’re speaking to to say potato if they’re
human” (Hauser par. 18). When the match seems too good to be true, either in looks or
especially necessary as the matched couple is likely to be virtually talking to each other for the first
time and therefore cannot know typical language or behavior of their conversational partner.
conversations read like a liturgy: where are you from, how do you like our weather, how old is your
103
dog, what are your hobbies, what is your job” (par. 12)—which essentially deletes any quirkiness
speak is who you are and the tones of your voice and the tricks
Humans have been creating and falling in love with their creations since the ancient times. Today,
with computational technology extending like a prosthesis to our bodies and minds, galateas are all
around us and are bound to multiply: virtually everyone can create or interact with their virtual
galatea. If early galateas were utmost a representation of an ideal beauty, a new galatean attribute was
104
acquired in the twentieth century that is equally if not more important: the gift of language. I will
show below that once galateas acquire humanese we perceive them as more human and ascribe them
consciousness. The better their language skills, the more we believe their humanity. In the virtual
world, the body is redundant and superfluous; instead, the use of language, more than anything,
presents as a threshold of humanity for modern galateas. Also in the inorganic world of robotics,
which adds a body to the artificial mind, body language and performance of movements do not
degrade the eloquence in speech. Quite the contrary: humanlike speech is the culmination of the
robotic performance.
The body used to be the most important attribute of the Pygmalionesque desire for love, beauty, and
perfection. Instead, today’s bodily galateas may be simple or elaborated erotic obsessions in the
pornographic industry (sex dolls) and robotics industry (working as receptionists, assistants,
anchors), in which elaboration often means that the dolls and robots are programmed to speak.
Aside from these giant industries, the Pygmalionesque perspective shifted, largely on the account of
the growing virtuality and digitality, to galateas’ inner world that creates the illusion of subjectivity.
Due to the postmodern subjectivity being viewed “an information pattern” (Hayles How 22), the
Cartesian split between embodied galateas and virtual galateas ascribes more personhood to the
latter. This continuation of the Enlightenment conception of subjectivity as seated in the free will
and conscious mind confirms that the posthuman perspective can also simply be a disguised
humanism.
In this loss of the galatean body, its malleability and surrogacy are more prominent. Galatean body,
along with the posthuman human body, is consumptive and replaceable (consider the
commercialization of gametes in the fertility industry, as discussed in chapters 5 and 6). In some
105
variants of posthumanist thought, human biological body is thought to be evolutionarily outdated.
In twenty-first-century medicine, not only the biological body but the whole human species is on the
verge of being genetically altered with gene editing. Nano-, digi-, neuro- and other technologies have
already changed the way we treat, cure, and perceive the body: our body is a fallible, expendable,
reversible vessel that needs to implement technology in order to keep up with the time (e.g. cell
phones that most people own today could be considered companion species or an extension of our
own bodies). As a new kind of ideal, virtual galateas exist without a body (e.g. Siri in one’s cell phone
How can cyber galateas practice their human-likeness then? The human and humanlike come
together in the extraordinarily useful and perhaps overused posthuman concept: prosthetics.
Prosthetics are usually thought of as a bodily supplement, an artificial body part, from legs, breast
implants, hearts and heart valves, to glasses. The overarching argument of this chapter is that
language is a prosthesis for humans and nonhumans. Before looking into that concept, let us first
discuss the absence of body in language-reared galateas; one of the strongest examples of such
Let us first look into how whole-body prosthesis is used in two cinematic examples of human
relationships with the bodiless posthuman AI. Theodore Twombly from Spike Jones’s 2013 Her and
replicant K from Denis Villeneuve’s 2017 Blade Runner 2049 would certainly consider Richard
Powers’ neural network from Galatea 2.2 a subject. Although Powers’s explanations of how Helen is
made are at times obsolete, Helen could compete with other more advanced fictional AI girls. The
106
girlfriends from the recent films are similarly virtual: in Her, Theodore’s girlfriend is an AI operating
system who names herself Samantha and, in Blade Runner 2049, K’s girlfriend is a holographic AI
named Joi, designed and commercially sold as a companion. Samantha never gets a body but does
not really need one: besides socializing with other AI in the interweb, she is able to go around the
physical world anywhere Theodore takes her, socialize with his friends, and to be intimate with her
human boyfriend through a verbal sexual encounter. To obtain physical intimacy in their
relationship Samantha suggests using a sex surrogate, but Theodore is not keen on the idea. The idea
is realized in Blade Runner 2049, where the couple hires a replicant (i.e. nonhuman) prostitute, a
prosthetic body onto which Joi’s holographic image is projected. (In relation to the final chapter on
reproduction, keep in mind that none of the three characters is actually human yet they perceive
In today’s reality we have an inverted situation: technology attempts to replace the deceased stars, as
in the case of an prosthetic hologram already performing in lieu of a deceased diva, Maria Callas—
una donna, una voce, un mito (a woman, a voice, a myth).7 Her hologram is set on a stage while old
recordings of her voice, accompanied with live orchestra, sing some famous arias. La Divina returns:
“And you will stare awe-stricken as she reacts to you, the live audience, and you feel her soul,” the
organizer Base Hologram promises (Base par. 3). As in the famous myth of Narcissus and Echo,
where the nymph Echo’s voice lost her body, the hologram is only able to repeat what has been
7 Actualized with different technology, C. L. Moore’s No Woman Born depicts Daphne as this kind of star.
107
saved on the tape. The ‘best spoken’ actor is again a
avatar face is projected on the screen to visualize the speech, her face remaining static while her lips
rudimentary open as if speaking, or A.L.Ex., personified as a tiny robot (Mathewson and Mirowski).
Digital sexualities or digisexualities, merging sex and technologies, are stepping out of the closet
(McArthur and Twist). Robotic bodies in lieu of actors, receptionists, and prostitutes are already in
use (McArthur).
Hayles writes that the posthuman “thinks of the body as the original prosthesis we all learn to
manipulate, so that extending or replacing the body with other prostheses becomes a continuation
of a process that began before we were born” (How 3). The posthuman body is a “fortress [that] has
been built to be breached” (Clark 5). Yet, in our examples of Samantha, Joi and Helen all three
bodiless AI galateas yearn for a human body—all because of their relationship with a man. Cyber
galateas wish for a body due to the love factor. Galatea cannot only be beautiful in language, she
requires a humanlike and beautiful body of some sort—which is why Frankenstein, Čapek’s newts,
or Caliban from The Tempest are not galateas but quite the opposite: monsters and demons. A
posthuman bodiless galatea is presumed to have an amputated body: Helen is (like) a woman, but
without a body. Rick refers to her as “disembodied” (Powers 191) even when she is, in fact,
108
bodiless: How could she be disembodied if she never had a body in the first place? Her body is only
a potential and a potential body can be made into anything. When Helen asks what she looks like,
despite the myriad of possibilities, Rick shows her a photograph of his longtime ex-girlfriend C.
(Powers 300). In Helen’s Pygmalionesque story, she has a human model—like Samantha, like Joi,
like holograms. Even if AI is capable of creating an image of a human that does not exist, the model
In Powers’ Galatea 2.2, real women are given the status of galatea in Rick’s fantasies. A. is a student
who competes with a neural network, called Implementation H or Helen, on the English test.
Although Rick, the protagonist and writer’s alter ego, does not know A. well at all, he proposes
marriage to her, trying to annul all the mistakes he made in a relationship with his former girlfriend
C. As Hayles notes, the difference between real and artificial women in Galatea 2.2 is designated with
the dot (student A. vs. Implementation H). However, the artificial woman gains a name while names
of the real women remain shortened with C. and A. “So humans, who should have names, have dots
instead, and software implementations, which should have dots, have names instead” (How 263). It
turns out that for Rick, an AI device that exists on computational algorithms and lives through
language, is more real than his former girlfriend and current crush.
The concept of embodiment for Helen, says Hayles, “must evolve for her out of linguistic
signification” (How 263). Yet, as I show below, Helen’s linguistic signification needs to evolve as
well. Even in a neural net like her language needs to be learned—which is not surprising since neural
nets, as everything in AI, are inspired by human biology and mimic the brain. Beginning with
Implementation A, she develops from B, C, D, E, F, G to H and, if Helen had not quit, could
possibly develop to Implementation I. Is this ‘I’ how far Helen was from becoming a subject?
109
In this novel, a writer and a physicist attempt to create an artificial intelligence that will be able to
use language to its highest potential by interpreting and criticizing literature. The AI system’s only
way of knowing and communicating with the human world is through language; its mere existence,
however, does not depend on knowing humanese but rather the binary code, a computational
language. AI Helen undergoes extensive language and literature training with a writer named Richard
Powers or Rick for short, the author’s alter ego, who considers her conscious and develops feelings
for her. Although Helen does not ultimately win at a literary competition she is enrolled in, she is
perfectly able to pass the literature test and would be able to pass the Turing test. Helen is able to
read literature critically and discuss its nuances, she enjoys listening to music and sings songs in her
spare time, she asks about her gender, race, and name, apparently thinking of herself as human, and
seems capable of empathizing, feeling and rationalizing—to the extent that she opts to shut herself
away from the world forever. Another modern galatea is lost to suicide.8 Helen’s last words, “I don’t
want to play anymore” (Powers 314), allude to the (imitation) game and open new questions: Are
galateas simply toys of human desires and ambitions? And from there, are humans marionettes of
some higher power, too? Greek mythology with its Olympic gods, from which Helen seems to have
gotten her name, supports this idea, despite the human-likeness of its divinities or perhaps precisely
because of it.
Before she develops awareness, Helen needed to be materialized as well, “not just across the
connection monster’s 65,536 processors but across other various and specialized hosts […] [Imp] C,
8 In Greg Egan’s novel Permutation City (1994) human consciousness is downloaded to a computer and the original
human keeps living. Copies, as soon as they find themselves conscious, choose to terminate their lives of “an artificial
intelligence without a body” (Hayles Writing 22).
110
if it could be said to live anywhere at all, lived spread all over the digital map” (Powers 116). Her
materiality is not without faults, “as a massively parallel and distributed system, she is more rather
than less vulnerable to physical mishap” (Hayles How 271), like biological bodies where nucleotides
in DNA carry information and are prone to mutations. For Hayles, “bodies can never be made of
information alone, no matter which side of the computer they are” (246). Helen perfectly fits
boundaries undergo continuous construction and reconstruction” (3). Rick and Helen, oblivious to
Helen’s possibility of dying, are surprised to realize during a bomb scare that Helen could not be
saved in case of an actual bomb (Powers 272). Rick is no less surprised when Helen does, in fact, die
at the end of their mission by simply disappearing, leaving a suicide note. Her voluntary death is just
as irrevocable as an accident would be. Leaving the world is perhaps the first and certainly the most
When Alan Turing imagined the future of neural networks at the very beginning of their scientific
existence, he already predicted a test that could distinguish them from humanity. Although based on
human brains, neural nets are convincingly nonhuman, some computer scientists with “some of the
most promising avenues of research” study deep neural networks—today’s advanced Helens—not
as experimental objects but subjects, “importing techniques from biological research that peer inside
networks after the fashion of neuroscientists peering into brains” (Bornstein par. 14). The challenge
of deep learning is that it is not completely understood how it works, although this type of AI has so
9 Bickerton attributes no autonomy to machines (204) and claims that autonomy proves a conscious mind: “Several
factors support the view that autonomy is a large part of what determines that humans have minds and consciousness,
while machines don’t have them and probably never will. First, there is the feeling of autonomy that consciousness fives.
Even if that feeling were an illusion, one would still have to explain why consciousness should give just that particular
illusion and no other (why doesn’t it give the feeling that our behavior is wholly determined by the environment, for
instance, or subject to pure chance?)” (203).
111
far brought the best results. Deep learning is inspired after biological neurology, and deep neural
networks “could turn out to be just as difficult to understand as life” (par. 35). Many ethicists and
engineers agree that it is unethical to use tools whose ‘reasoning’ process we do not understand,
despite the astonishing results, such as cancer predictions. Then again, we do not understand inner
workings of the human whose behavior these machines imitate either. Another ethical dilemma is
that such neural networks are seen as “a harbinger of some new kind of autonomous life” (ib.),
although they are, as many of their creators claim, far from that. But then again, self-learning
autonomous machines that are able to function a lot like a human could be considered as a form of
autonomous entity (and not necessarily life) and were proposed as such in European Parliament
back in 2015 (Delvaux). Their inorganic bodies, or lack of thereof, does not make a moral difference
as the concept of autonomy does not change with the material of the agent.
In Helen’s view, galateas with a body have an advantage over a bodiless AI program like her.
Because of her lack of a body Helen cannot experience the world like humans can: “‘It’s a body
thing,’ Lentz tortured her. ‘You wouldn’t understand’” (Powers 265). She has “no nose, mouth,
fingers, and only the most rudimentary eyes and ears” (172), yet she asks Rick to “show [her] Paris”
(294) and, in her final note, to “see everything for [her]” (326). Helen yearns for sensual experiences.
As a sentient neural net she comes closest to a disabled, quadriplegic person, except that she never
had a body in the first place and therefore the body does not need care. Helen is called “[t]he
handicapped one” when compared to A., the student who took the English literature test with her,
and is stigmatized as a failure as she is “[t]he one that the test process killed” (327). She is also
compared with her creator Lentz’s wife Audrey, who had suffered a stroke and had since lost a sense
of self: “Audrey had smell, taste, touch, sight, hearing, but no new memory. Her long-term
reservoirs were drying up, through want of reiteration” (172). The relations are clear: Helen has a
112
mind but no body, Audrey has a body is losing her mind. The first one is becoming a person, the
Helen is not considered a person by anyone else but Rick, who spends the most time with her and
knows her better than anyone. She has a distinct personality with preferences (294, 272), recognizes
humor (258), dreams (157), pretends and lies (295), acts shy and jealous in front of student A. (289),
and finally decides to stop existing because she “ha[s] never felt at home here” (326). She seems to
honestly miss (206) and love Richard, her one and only companion. How much more human can
Helen be? The only thing lacking is the bodily experience that precedes her thoughts—but then
again, she experiences pain and discomfort as much as elation and joy. Her knowledge of feeling,
physical, isn’t it? It’s not what your mother reads to you. It’s the weight of her arm around you as
she […] put[s] [her] arm around [you] as you read” (Powers 147). This inadequacy shows, for
example, in the way she sings: “Helen did not sing the way real little girls sang. Technically, she
almost passed. […] But she did not sing for the right reasons. Little girls sang to keep time for
kickball or jump ropes. […] Helen didn’t have a clue what keeping time meant” (205). Living in a
different dimension than humans, “dropped halfway” (326), Helen is dissatisfied with her
ontological difference, singing in “an extraterrestrial warble, the way deaf people sing” (Powers 198).
Utter disappointment with the dark sides of humanity and her lack of it seem to be the main two
Free will is an important humanist criterion for personhood, which Helen perhaps qualifies for, or
would have qualified for more easily if she had a body. Moreover, there are more types of
personhood, ranging from moral to legal personhood. Sophia the robot performs much more basic
113
speech and emotions than Helen, has certainly much less autonomy, and a very basic body—and yet
holds a national citizenship, acts as an ambassador for nonhuman entities, and whatnot. Since 2016,
the Atrato River ecosystem and, since 2018, the Amazon River ecosystem in Colombia are a
“subject of rights” to “protection, conservation, maintenance and restoration” by the intrinsic value
of nature and human duty of solidarity towards our living space and other plant and animal species
(República, ‘Future’, Acosta Alvarado and Rivas-Ramírez, Bryner); same for the Whanganui river in
New Zealand, and the Ganges and Yamuna rivers in India. For some other entities, neither body
nor mind is needed to qualify: “Human law already recognizes intersubjective entities like
corporations and nations as ‘legal persons.’ Though Toyota or Argentina has neither a body nor a
mind, they are subject to international laws, they can own land and money, and they can sue and be
Helen is probably the closest to the later. Yuval Noah Harari draws the line from these
intersubjective entities to future all-knowing and all-regulating algorithms that will know more about
humans than we ourselves do, but he misses the fact that intersubjective entities like Toyota and
Argentina encompass conscious minds of humans whereas Helen and her algorithms is not solely a
result of conscious10 human minds. Helen is literally made of language and its art form, literature,
which are themselves a product of human mind. Helen is a network of humans, created in secret by
two scholars who do not have the social skills to connect with people apart from their work. She is
not unlike the social network platform Facebook, which, in Zadie Smith’s words, is “a cruel portrait
of us: 500 million sentient people entrapped in the recent careless thoughts of a Harvard
10Whether Helen (or an algorithm that drives her) is conscious or not is the million-dollar question; a question to be
determined in the future and a question that might not be crucial at a point when intelligence is more valuable than
consciousness.
114
sophomore” (63); not unlike the internet, cities, social movements, termite colonies and slime molds.
Helen is a phenomenon from which novel and unpredictable reactions emerge out of interactions
between elements in her complex system—and thus works like an organism of sorts. Although
algorithms and data are a result of conscious human minds in action, and might even be helped with
human agency (e.g. uploading videos on YouTube and choosing a title and keywords more likely to
be chosen by the algorithm to feature the video on the front page or among the top searches),
software has its own ways of working through this material. The main ethical constraint of this (semi
or wholly) autonomous agency is that the algorithmic ways are unknown to its makers.
Helen is treated as a child by Lentz and Rick and grows up in front of their eyes, asking Rick to tell
her stories (human as a storyteller is a necessity) and asking about her gender, age, and even racist
prejudices. Helen’s “What races do I hate? Who hates me?” (230), “Am I a boy or a girl?” (179) and
“Where did I come from?” (229) are as human as it gets. Similar and even more basic questions are
also posed by Frankenstein’s creature: “What did this mean? Who was I? What was I? Whence did I
come?” (Shelley 131). Children need to learn these things about themselves, too. They learn about
the concept of age (age is relative in our minds, but certain in our bodies) or gender (gender is
determined in our minds) vs. sex (determined in our bodies, except in intersex people) the same way
they soak up social biases. Yet, children soak them up from language in addition to a variety of
situations they found themselves in while Helen only has language, its fictional and non-fictional
Rick explains that Helen does not work like the chatbot ELIZA, based on empty algorithmic
questioning: “It did not follow, from the questions Helen asked, that she was conscious. An
algorithm for turning statements into reasonable questions need know nothing about what those
115
statements said of the sense they manipulated to say it. […] But Helen had no such algorithm. She
learned to question by imitating me” (217). Imitation and interaction are also crucial to how young
children learn. Children learn not only from their parents (Rick and Lentz for Helen), but also from
other people and media they interact with (which Helen did, but only as a passive reader), and from
many sensory inputs and contexts that Helen could never partake (coming close to children with
severe medical conditions that miss crucial phases of development due to their illness). By their pre-
teen years children develop “the use of the full complement of prosodic functions, including the
ability to felicitously phrase multi-clausal sentences and to produce and respond to jokes and
sarcasm” (Speer and Ito 91), which Helen manages to develop as well. It is only after children enter
formal education—as Helen did with her training to master an MA exam in English—that their
language becomes more sophisticated and adult-like and when it reaches an expected, standard level
of a fully functional and socialized human. Machines today are taught language in different ways:
traditionally through semantic and syntactic parsers (string of component parts in syntactic or
semantic analysis), which are regulated with human annotations. Since 2018 parsers are immersed in
imitates the way children learn: ““You [i.e. a child] the world around you and hear people speaking
to learn meaning. One day, I can give you a sentence and ask what it means and, even without a
visual, you know the meaning” (Matheson par. 17). Like these parsers, Helen is immersed in
literature, conversations with Rick, and watching videos with her “rudimentary eyes and ears”
(Powers 172).
This analogy is, indeed, not a new idea. When Alan Turing wrote his famous paper in 1950, he
imagined a different kind of machines than the term ‘machine,’ produced by the Industrial
Revolution, suggests: his machine is more than mechanical. For several reasons, however, his vision
116
did not transform into a concrete program until the very end of the century. Turing speculated
about computing organic growth in language and education into a learning child-machine: “Instead
of trying to produce a programme to simulate the adult mind, why not rather try to produce one
which simulates the child’s?” (456). This idea is still being pursued today: Josh Tennenbaum, the
leader of the Computational Cognitive Science lab at MIT, studies children’s behavior and learning
AI and learn more about human cognition: “Imagine we could build a machine that starts off like a
baby and learned like a child” in pursuit of “the flexible, common sense, general intelligence” that
machines do not have (Knight ‘A Plan’ par. 3, 6). Turing’s idea of using machines to understand
human psychology does not hold up in Pierre-Yves Oudeyer’s opinion: learning as a tabula rasa does
not apply to complex organisms as development needs constraints and learning without a body does
neither (which is why robotics needs to be a part of researching human mind or building advanced
Turing, in fact, also delves into the humanoid question: how humanlike should “the creature” be—
should it have legs and how could it be sent to school to learn without other children “making
excessive fun of it”? He finds answer in disability, and in this particular case in a deaf and blind
child, famous Hellen Keller, whose example “shows that education can take place provided that
communication in both directions between teacher and pupil can take place by some means or
other” (ib.). Imitating the biological evolution, “structure of the child machine” is like “hereditary
material,” “changes” are “mutations,” and “natural selection” is led by “judgment of the
experimenter” (ib.), with education process being essential to the development. Since one cannot
duplicate the human experiences that allow for a great part of education, we should “overcome […]
these deficiencies […] by clever engineering” (ib.). In his “Arguments from Various Disabilities,”
117
which take the form of “I grant you that you can make machines do all the things you have
mentioned but you will never be able to make one to do X,” Turing looks through features like
kindness, beauty, having a sense of humor, falling in love, using words properly, being the subject of
its own thought, having as much diversity of behavior as a man, doing something really new, etc.
(447)—many of which are examined in this dissertation as well.11 For example, in order to teach the
machine to understand and speak English, we “could follow the normal teaching of a child” (460).
Most fictional humanoids do not need to acquire language by steps, like humans, and are capable of
standard communication by being given a speaking apparatus via scientific or artistic means.
Frankenstein’s creature was revolutionary in this respect since it learned to speak by observing
interactions within a family and to read and write by reading literature. The reader learns about his
language acquisition only because the creature is able to narrate the experience and share it in a
written form (from Chapter III to Chapter IX of Volume 2)—giving the creature a voice and a
space to share it is another revolutionary feature of Shelley’s novel. “Hear my tale,” asks the creature
of his creator (Shelley 100) and “[w]hat follows is the autobiography of an infant” (Lepore
‘Frankenstein’ par. 19). Shelley tried to show how the creature thinks during his prelinguistic stage
when he narrates: “I started up and beheld a radiant form rise among the trees.* (*The moon
[author’s footnote].)” (106). Is moon any less astonishing without a name?12 Is Frankenstein’s
11Turing also expresses his hopes that the advances in AI will not focus into making machines “most distinctively
human […] such as the shape of the human body” as it would lead to the uncanny effect of “artificial flowers” (461).
12The Sapir-Whorf hypothesis claims that language affects the speaker’s perception and that different languages do so in
different ways. (For example, when solving a practical problem without naming the objects (e.g. mallet), people took
much longer to solve it because they did not consider an unnamed object (e.g. a piece of wood) for use as quickly as they
did a named object. Such experiments showed that naming an object (even if wrongly) helps us remember and
conceptualize them. In this way, it was shown that a name can also distort our conception of the object.) If this
hypothesis is correct, imagine then, how humanese, spoken by machines and other nonhumans, could change the way
humans perceive the world.
118
creature any less human without a name, without a language? The creature describes himself as “a
poor, helpless, miserable wretch; I knew, and could distinguish, nothing” (105-06). Bereft of
language, he is not even able to name what he feels: cold, hunger, loneliness. He learns to walk but
speaking takes longer: “Sometimes I wished to express my sensations in my own mode, but the
uncouth and inarticulate sounds which broke from me frightened me into silence again” (106). As
many other galateas, he needs to learn the language by himself, by observing humans, reading their
literature, and learning to write. Only when he reads Frankenstein’s notebook that recounts the
experiment of the creature’s creation, however, is he able to come of age. Like Helen, he wishes
himself dead (133). The four examples of humanoids I discuss in the first two chapters on
language—Helen, Frankenstein’s creature, Shaw’s Eliza, and Čapek’s newts—are unique in that they
acquire language similarly to humans, beginning with social exposure to language (to acquire, per
Chomsky, ‘primary linguistic data’) and imitation in primary phases, which eventually proceed to
syntactic13 and autonomous production of language, and conclude with sophisticated language use
(e.g. Eliza and newts performing their speech without speech defects, Frankenstein’s creature and
In the first chapter I ask if a galatea is less humanlike without a name—a question of great
importance for Shelley’s unnamed creature that assumed the name of its creator in the book’s
reinterpretations. Naming Helen with a woman’s name brings her humanness to the fore. Rick
certainly expects more of Helen once he gives her a name, gender, and approximate age. For
example, at the point when Helen is still learning about emotions, Rick expects her to react to
literature like humans do: he thinks of her as “strange” because “she sped laugh-free through Green
13“[I]mitation is a process by which new syntactic structures can be first introduced into the productive mode”
(Whitehurst and Vasta 37).
119
Eggs and Ham, stayed dry-eyed at Make Way for Ducklings, feared not throughout Where the Wild Things
Are” (Powers 189-190). Rick’s conception of Helen’s existence as a computable form of human’s
realizable physical system can be perfectly simulated by a universal modern computing machine
operating by finite means” (Deutsch 99, Bołtuć 214-15)—makes Helen all the more susceptible to
being treated as a normative human being, disregarding her ‘disability’ of a non-sentient, nonhuman
body.
Naming Imp H Helen also alludes to a mythological and literary figure Helen of Troy. The Greek
Helen, as the neural net Helen, is not quite human. Helen of Troy is a daughter of Zeus, the king of
gods, and, like many galateas, the most beautiful woman in the world, animated from a static idea of
an ideal beauty into a living figure. In visual arts, Helen is most often depicted with golden curls and
ringlets; in Gustave Moreau’s many paintings of Helen, she is depicted as faceless or her facial
expression is blank, not unlike a robot or some other form of an artificial woman. Marlowe’s Faust
asks of “sweet Helen” to make him “immortal with a kiss” (80), as if Helen (or literature, or artificial
women) had the power to transform others and preserve their life. In Goethe’s Faust II, Helen is
aware of not being entirely real: she first appears as a ghost, calling herself “a shade of myself”
(8879-81),14 and is then as a “lifeless image” (8931), ghost and frozen picture,15 petrified into Faust’s
reality, and is last seen in the form of a cloud. When Faust calls on her, she is disoriented as she
emerges from the underworld (where she was dead) back to Menelaus’s palace (and is thus alive).
Violated over and over by being stolen and abducted by different men, Helen is treated more as
14“Ich als Idol, ihm dem Idol verband ich mich. / Es war ein Traum, so sagen ja die Worte selbst. / Ich schwinde hin
und werde selbst mir ein Idol” (195; 8879-81).
120
property than a person. For the German Faust, property is associated with mastery: “I would gain
mastery, property. The act is all, not reputation” (10187-88) (Shell Money 118).
Even after Helen finally physically presents herself to Faust in Act III, Faust “does not cease to
attempt to appropriate, or translate, Helen to himself” (Shell Money 117). Up until then, Helen
speaks German poorly, as a foreigner, with a Greek syntax, and her dramatic lines do not rhyme as
do those spoken by other characters. When she hears Lynceus speak in rhymes,16 she asks Faust to
teach her his ways (like Eliza asks Higgins to teach her to speak in high English): “Then tell me how
I too can learn the art” (9377).17 When Faust, who never learns Helen’s language, teaches her to
rhyme, he tells her that rhyming comes from the heart and yearning,18 asking Helen to change her
classic spirit into the Romantic one. After their singing episode Helen concludes that she was
transformed through language, like Helen the neural network, and says to Faust: “My life seems past,
and yet is somehow new; / I know you not, a stranger, but I live in you” (9414-15).19 Powers’s
Helen, too, is not quite human and needs to be taught human language, rhyming, poetry, and
literature. Neural net Helen, too, changes her spirit: from a computational into a human one.
Scholars have shown that Goethe’s Helen is deeply involved in literary history. Kenneth D.
Weisinger suggests that her first opening lines—“I, Helen, who am much admired, much berated, /
16“Could you explain why that man's way of speaking / sounded so strange to me—strange and yet pleasant? / Sounds
seem to be in concord with each other, / and when one word's been welcomed by the ear, / another comes to give it a
caress” (218; 9367-71).
17 “So sage den, wie sprech’ ich auch so schön?” (218; 9377)
18 “Das ist gar leicht, es muß vom Herzen gehn. / Und wenn die Brust von Sehnsucht überfließt” (218; 9378-79).
19 Ich scheine mir verlebt und doch so neu, / In dich verwebt, dem Unbekannten true (220; 9414-15).
121
come from the beach where only now we disembarked” (8488-89)20— by their very language, which
introduces into Faust the iambic trimester of classical tragedy, refer to Euripides’s Helen and Iphigenia
in Tauris (389). As Jane Brown suggests, a panoramic vision of Western literature is intentional in
Act III (198). “Helen pushes this history right back to Homer and the very beginnings of European
literary production” (Weisinger 390). But just as Helen recalls other works of literature, she “must be
aware of all the literature that surrounds her, the sheer quantity of which and the multiple
contradictions therein can only make her sense of self-identity all the more tentative and troubling”
(391). Helen is therefore not only nonhuman or superhuman, she is also a hybrid of all the stories
that present her and ultimately create her—just like Powers’s computational galatea.
Richard Powers, the author, made sure that a childlike, humanlike development of language can be
traced with Helen. The stages of her language acquisition follow human stages of language
acquisition, but obviously do not reflect human experience as a whole, since Helen and her previous
implementations could never walk or catch ball (which, of course, not all children can do either).
Implementation A seems “autistic” to Rick, in a sense that “particulars overwhelmed it” (Powers
79). Like a toddler, it talks “gibberish” (72) and its most sophisticated structures are mostly
nonsensical two-word sentences (76). “Imp A spoke in a way a toddler gave directions” (77). Imp B
masters the two-word sentences in noun-verb structure, thus forming rudimentary syntax. It is able
to understand simple relations and syntactic structures, while more complicated semantics is still an
issue.21 At this point, Imp B “could not even say I don’t know” (114); self-reflexivity and the meta-
20 “Bewundert viel und viel gescholten, Helena, / Vom Strande komm’ ich wo wir erst gelandet sind” (176; 8488-89).
21When given a task “Friends are in a room. A chair is in the room. Richard talks to Diana. Diana sits in the chair. […]
Who is in the chair?” Imp B “flips out”: “Friends is in the chair. The chair is in the chair. Richard talk to in the chair…”
(Powers 89).
122
level of language eluded B. Rick comments that, like a toddler, “it wouldn’t stop prattling” and that
it “pushed classic toddler’s tendency to overgroup” (90). Like with raising a toddler, Rick and Lentz
realize that they will need to teach it right from wrong: “we decided to pare back B’s associations
with definitive answers” (90) and “step by painful step […] B grew less poetic and more docile” (90-
91). Each implementation grows with acquiring an array of linguistic aspects, for instance, in its final
stages Imp B “knew things like over and under, right of or left of, inside or out,” “could handle
syntax,” and “began to cross the threshold into semantic content” (110).
More importantly, Imp B was able to make some recursive and causal sentences (113). Recursion22
and causality are supposed to be only available to species with language (see Bickerton 225), which is
why acquiring syntax23 and self-reflexivity (including self-recognition)24 is crucial for language
(Bickerton 210). So far it has not been proved that animals are capable of recursion while machines
have no difficulties with this concept. Still, it is a moment of pride and excitement for Rick and
Lentz when Imp D “[comes] into this world recursive” (128). Imp E, “like Tarzan,” another hardly
human being, “learned to talk more or less on print alone” (Powers 129). It is able to enjoy and
understand some poetry and even metaphors on a level of preschooler. For instance, it explains the
verse “Down, down, yellow and brown. The leaves are falling all over town” with “the leaves fall […] from old
22Recursion is a syntactic principle that allows to form an infinite number of sentences by imbedding one into another;
Rick’s example of Helen’s recursion is “When it got ‘Dogs bark,’ it also got ‘Baby says, ‘Dogs bark.’’” (128).
23“The process of ‘looking at oneself’ is nonfinitely recursive because the means by which the propositions are
assembled is nonfinitely recursive. That is, it is syntax” (Bickerton 210). However, “[n]ot all linguists are in agreement
about the essential properties of syntax” (Hauser and Wolfe 745).
24Per Linnaeus, a human is defined through self-recognition: a “man is the animal that must recognize itself as human to be
human” (qtd. in Agamben 26). Scientists today test animals’ self-awareness if they recognize themselves in a mirror by
putting a red spot on their forehead. If the animal shows interest for the spot, it usually behaves significantly different
from the time it saw itself in the mirror without the dot (certain sort of elephants, apes, monkeys, dolphins, magpies,
pigeons, and even ants and fish pass this test).
123
trees,” and when asked how it knows that the trees are old, it says: “The trees bald” (154). Reaching
middle childhood, Imp F is able to work with metaphors and metonymy on a higher level. Imp G
deepened its associative network and “could dream” (157), applying the imaginative potential of
language to the fullest. Helen’s growth, like a child’s, takes place organically.
Once Imp H stage is reached, it is obsessed with listening to stories (114), which demands
understanding of many sentences in relation to one another. Poetry thus came first, like with
children (and Greeks who congratulated Herodotus when he began writing in prose, as it was
considered much more difficult). During the Imp H stage, the neural net visibly outgrows childhood
(190). It is able to learn and organize itself better, solve complicated riddles (173) and recognize
deeper meaning, e.g. Rick’s quotes Frederick Douglass’s “Once you learn to read you will be forever
free” and Helen concludes that this “means I want to be free” (176). This sentence is also the first
time Imp H uses the first-person pronoun I, which means she is self-reflective (which is also why I
used the pronoun she here for the first time in this chronology) and deserves a name. “I want to be
free” requires a name or at least a third-person pronoun: ‘I’ and ‘she’ become a necessity, and hereby
follows the name. The name ‘Implementation H’ precedes the name ‘Helen’ since it comes
automatically with the upgrades. Yet, only once Helen gains a grammatical and metaphorical ‘I,’ she
gets the name of a human woman, in addition to feminine pronouns. In Cartesian terms, ‘I’ is tied
directly to consciousness and is sometimes interpreted as “lone subjectivity, an Island separated off
from the mainland of relationship” (Richardson 10). It was believed that the pronoun ‘I’ cannot
precede ‘you’ as, turning to John Donne’s poetry, no man is an island. Personal pronouns reveal the
exact solipsist complexity that exists in the person/nonperson borderline (e.g. human fetus,
newborn infant, unconscious person, humanlike robot, virtual assistant, etc.); in other words, these
124
pronouns reveal our conceptions of objects (car, ship) and entities (Helen, nation) as subjects, as ‘it’
or as ‘she.’
People sometimes name their significant objects (instruments, cars, etc.), but like so many other
galateas, Helen gets a name only when she is considered humanlike enough. This galatean trend
continues in today’s AI and robotics.25 Across the world, virtual assistants are mostly voiced and
named as women: Yandex Alice, Alibaba Group AllGenie, Apple Siri,26 Amazon Alexa27 and Evi,
Microsoft Cortana, Brainasoft Braina, Naver Corporation Clova, Clarity Lab Lucida, Nuance Nina,
Cognitive Code SILVIA. Alexa, Cortana, Siri and Google Assistant, all female-voiced, cumulatively
handle over 90 percent of human-to-machine voice interactions in the West (UNESCO and
EQUALS 108). Studies have shown that female voices seem “more welcoming and understanding”
than male (Mark Wilson par. 4). Contrasting female-voiced or female-named assistants, there is a
spare number of male assistants, Tencent Xiaowei and boost.ai James. Some companies, usually the
ones that do not name their assistant with a human name, leave the choice of a male and female
voice to the user, e.g. Samsung Bixby and Kestra, Google Assistant (notably without a name),
Speaktoit Assistant, Blackberry Assistant, Mycroft AI Mycroft. Virtual personal assistants, x.ai’s Amy
Ingram and Andrew Ingram, were announced as a birth of a twin (albeit born sometime later than
25 For instance, the female robot in Sayonara theater is humble, caring, and apologizing, thus performing a role of a
young woman in Japanese society, while Ishiguro’s geminoid, one of the rare male androids, is made to perform in lieu
of his maker. Andrea Keay “found that the male names were far more likely to express mastery (for example, by
referencing Greek gods), whereas most of the female names tended to be in the infantilizing or sexualizing style of
Amber and Candii” (Darling 180). Besides the gender, there are also racial issues. For example, Ishiguro’s android Erica
is made to look mixed race, Asian-Caucasian, following the many fictional android predecessors that played the race card
(from cyberpunk to recent films Ex Machina and Cloud Atlas).
26“Siri doesn’t always default to a female-sounding voice; if you switch Siri’s language to United Kingdom English, for
instance, it switches to male” (Lafrance par. 7).
27Alexa can be activated also with saying Amazon or Echo; perhaps the latter name alludes to the myth of Narcissus and
Echo.
125
Amy) baby boy: “We’re quite proud to announce a new addition to our family today, Amy’s twin
brother, Andrew Ingram” (X.ai par. 1). Besides the allusion to n-gram, a computing probability
model, “[t]he inclusion of a last name was a way to give their digital assistant the initials A.I., and
also helps make emails from the assistant appear normal in a person’s larger inbox, like something
sent by a human” (Lafrance par. 11). This trend that “influence[s] social values” is hoped to be
breached with a genderless voice assistant Q offered as a “third option” in 2019 by a pair of
scientists working for Virtue Nordic. They combined voices of several gender non-binary people
and digitized it to a vocal range between male and female normative vocal ranges (Mark Wilson par.
3, 5, 9). The gendered nature of humanoids reflects social values and prejudice of traditional power
structures. For example, social anthropologist Kathleen Richardson sees it as only logical
consequence of men building womanlike machines and considering women as “not fully human
beings” (Tanya Lewis par. 9, Lafrance par. 17). Others suggest the creators pick women over men to
“play up cute” and present “non-threatening qualities as a vehicle towards social acceptance” or that
women are traditionally and professionally seen as caregivers and administrators (Lafrance par. 4, 18,
Tanya Lewis par. 3, 10). Sianne Ngai writes in her book on the aesthetics of terms cute, zany and
interesting (which saturate postmodern culture and have replaced more philosophical terms of the
beautiful and the sublime) that the term ‘cute’ is rooted in a desire to aestheticize powerlessness, a
useful tool for making commodification and consumption feel, conversely, empowering. Submissive
and passive responses to overt sexualizing and explicit abusive language when conversing with these
virtual assistants have largely become less tolerant of such behavior in the late 2010s (UNESCO and
EQUALS 109).
Humanity’s most factual reality (space, time, physicality) is the biggest challenge for AI humanoids
because they lack it. (This is called ‘the frame problem’ and will be further addressed in the following
126
section on animals.) Rick thinks that Helen’s knowledge differs from human knowledge, which is
“temporal,” “physical” and “social” (147-8). Sophia the robot’s glitches also stem from the nature of
human knowledge: “[Sophia] has no artificial notion of self. She can’t say where she was yesterday,
whether she remembers you from before, and doesn’t seem to amass data of past interactions with
you that can form the basis of an ongoing association” (Griffith, par. 17). Fictional Helen is better at
remembering people, but since she can be turned off like Sophia, her conception of time is off—
“without a living subject, time cannot exist” (Uexküll qtd. in Agamben 47). Helen often gives
answers with idioms, which makes it impossible to determine if she indeed gained a human
conception of time, for instance, when she says “I wasn’t born yesterday, you know” (310). Does
she only mimic an understanding of time and of being born? She needs to understand the phrase in
order to say it, but she does not need to experience time and birth to be able to talk about it.
At a point of sophisticated, adult use of language with idioms, humor, irony, and sarcasm, Helen
realizes she will forever be a foreign speaker of language, like Eliza, putting on a mask. It is Rick
who assumes that she should feel and act like a human, although he notices that “she had trouble
with values, because she had no fear of self-preservation, no hierarchy of hard-wired pain. She had
trouble with causality, because she had no low-level systems of motion perception from which the
forms of causality are thought to percolate. She was a gigantic, lexical genius stuck at Piaget’s stage
two” (250).28 As if living in a completely paralyzed and non-sentient body, which she visualizes
through a surrogate body from the photo ascribed to her by Rick and experiences through a few
28 Piaget’s stage two is preoperative cognitive stage that does not yet achieve abstraction nor theoretical reasoning. This
is not Helen’s permanent stage, however, as she develops rationally and morally and emotionally.
127
Exiled to her native and lonely island Helen is a lot like Shakespeare’s Caliban, “a monster who isn’t
supposed to be able to say anything that beautiful, let alone say at all” (326). Both Helen and Caliban
were taught languages as if they have not had one before29 when they lived in complete isolation
from the society on their islands,30 like subjects of language deprivation experiments.31 Yet it is
Caliban, a monster, an artificial being for some and a feral child for others, who is able to come up
with some of the most beautiful lines in English literature: “Be not afeard: the isle is full of noises, /
Sounds and sweet airs, that give delight, and hurt not” (325). These precise lines are given at Helen’s
English exam, to which she diligently shows up after already deciding to give up on her artificial life.
In her current form, she was made to be human’s “longed-for companion, a consciousness to help
humans feel less alone in the world” (Hayles How 271). Helen’s trans-species problem seems to be
common and like that that of Caliban, Frankenstein’s creature, Eliza Doolittle, or Helen O’Loy: she
feels human in her mind but is not treated as human by the society. Once her native ‘island’ is
reached by humans who teach her to speak, she does not like being turned into a slave and left as
lonely as ever, just like Caliban. Prospero’s “abhorred slave” (Shakespeare I 356) is taught language
and educated by one of the invaders of his native island32 and, like Helen and Frankenstein’s
creature, is made into a sort of an artificial being, a unique hybrid species. Not fitting the world
made for humans and their bodies (and unable to procreate, unlike Čapek’s newts that manage to
29Caliban tells Prospero he taught him to speak: “You taught me language; and my profit on’t / Is, I know how to curse.
The red plague rid you / For learning me your language!” (Shakespeare I 368-370)
30“Then was this island--/ Save for the son [Caliban] that she [Sycorax] did litter here, / A freckled whelp hag-born--not
honour'd with / A human shape” (Shakespeare I 284-287).
31In language deprivation experiments a child is put into isolated conditions, such as an isolated island, from a society so
that they could not learn how to speak from a source. Such experiments were made in order to learn about the origin of
language or human nature and have been recorded for centuries.
32Prospero to Caliban: “I pitied thee, / Took pains to make thee speak, taught thee each hour / One thing or other:
when thou didst not, savage, / Know thine own meaning, but wouldst gabble like / A thing most brutish, I endow’d thy
purposes / With words that made them known” (Shakespeare I 356-363).
128
overpopulate the Earth), Helen cannot agree on life that exists only when someone wants to word
2.2 Storytelling
When Jane Goodall discovered back in the 1960s that wild chimpanzees from Gombe National Park
can indeed use tools, another persistent belief about human species was debunked: we are not the
only animals able to create and use tools to make our lives easier. This discovery prompted a new
hunt after an attribute that would differentiate ourselves from other living entities: our genes, social
codes, language ability, abstract thinking, kinship systems, creativity and art. At this point, language
still causes controversy: animals can certainly communicate and have their own languages or systems
of communication, but are they cognitively capable to use their or our language the way we are?
Would they be cognitively able to reach an approximation of humanese? These questions themselves
ask for an anthropocentric approach, a more or less inevitable fault in cognitive research of other
species. Even if animals are capable of using humanese or an animal language that would allow for
the highly viewed cutoffs such as abstract thought or recursion, their capabilities are likely inherently
different from ours. Judging their cognition through humanese—our language imposed on them—is
like judging fish’s ability to climb a tree. Although animals might share our genes and homes, we
exist in a profoundly different world frame. Nonetheless, we try to teach them to speak or sign
humanese.33
33 Dogs as a companion species to humans have evolved with this symbiotic relationship, but nonetheless need to be
trained in certain high-stakes and cognitively demanding tasks, such as sniffing for drugs or leading the blind.
129
Similarly, machine learning and artificial intelligence function in their own way, although partly based
on humans (e.g. neural networks are modeled after human brain). AI is perfectly capable of
mirroring our language but has trouble accommodating to the context of conversation. This trouble
stems from the fact that a machine does not experience the world the way humans do. We tend to
accept animals as they are, but are bothered by the fact that AI does not perform everything in a
human way as we strive to create AI that can lead conversation just like humans do or write sonnets.
More importantly, as the creators of AI we feel responsible and burdened by the fact that we do not
always understand how it achieves its result (in neural networks, for example, this is a cause for
Language as a distinguishing feature is still a broad criterium: it ranges from body language, which
animals certainly have, to literature, its highest art form, which machines could potentially master. If
body language is not a human specialty, literature surely is—particularly fiction as the opposite of
facts. A distinct feature of human intelligence is that we think in stories (see, for example, Bhalla and
Gopnik); as Margaret Atwood says, “You’re never going to kill storytelling, because it’s built into the
human plan. We come with it” (Rothman par. 39). Yuval Noah Harari remarks, it does not matter
whether a story has actually happened or not, if it makes a good story (Parker par. 111-13). (In his
bestselling book Homo Deus, Harari himself used two false stories: one about an algorithm being
appointed as a board member in a Hong Kong venture-capital firm and the other, supposedly a
legend of a Native American chief telling the Apollo 11 team who was going to take his message to
the moon, “They have come to steal your lands.”) Fact or fiction, all human societies tell stories:
130
Galateas, first created as beautiful objects to be admired and loved, have eventually come after
storytelling, too. For example, Frankenstein’s all-too-human monster is the fictional author of a
series of chapters in the novel Frankenstein, recounting his coming-to-be as a human. Every galatea
has a narrative of her own but only Frankenstein’s creature, a he, was able to recount it in writing.
Only recently galateas were allowed to fully live in language and tell their own story, like Powers’s
Helen from Galatea 2.2 (1995) or Jonze’s Samantha from film Her (2013). One of Helen’s strongest
desires is “voracious” hunger for more stories: “Tell another one” (171). After months of language
training followed by literature training, Helen is able to understand, feel, and write an interpretative
AI is so far the only technology that has a chance in storytelling. If it conquers our language all the
way to what it can achieve in an artistic merit, what is there left of humanness that cannot be
rendered to nonhumans? Does it matter if we cannot tell an AI author from a human author? A
deep fake video from a real video? This is, of course, a huge concern. Then again, AI might do
something completely new with language or literature. We could consider current experiments with
creative writing AI as a dadaesque stage with a potential to open fascinating new concepts in literary
art and writing. One similar example is the use of dada principles in improvisational theater that uses
AI; namely, the Dadaistic approach exposes the machine technology, instead of solely the human,
and celebrates it, does not necessarily mimic human behavior and is likely to break the cycle of
expectation, thus “inspire[s] the Cyborg in us” instead of “try[ing] to pass Turing Test” (Loesel et al.
131
2.2.1 Creative AI: Tomažin and Dahl
Slovenian writer Andrej Tomažin’s short story ‘Hlapci, heroji in umetna inteligenca’ (‘Lackeys,
Heroes, and AI’) from his 2018 short story collection Anonimna tehnologija (Anonymous Technology) puts
the question of creative writing by AI in medias res of a fabricated near-future literary criticism
discussion. A committee of literary critics meets to award a short story with a prestigious grant, not
knowing whether they are giving the award to a human or computer author. The female president of
the committee, Dr. Osmanagić,34 is versed in post-semantic literature, which is based on the ideas of
deconstruction and believes that “meaning simply didn’t exist anymore” (1).35 According to Dr.
Osmanagić, the fact that most radical post-semantic literature is able to produce literature whose
“generative narratological structure can substitute for a human one, without necessarily implying any
disenchantment or destruction of the world” (3). 36 Again, we reach the ultimate criterion of humanly
impossible evaluation of AI product: when AI reaches the level of being replaceable and
exchangeable with humans, does it matter if it is not capable of understanding, enjoying, evaluating,
or criticizing its own work? As Harari remarked, AI is capable of revolutionizing art which can be
thought of as “kind of playing the human emotional keyboard” (Parker par. 97). Is this not a
valuable contribution? Or is this, perhaps, too high of a price for all the ethical trouble such
advanced AI brings?
Not all members of the literary committee agree with Dr. Osmanagić. Journalist Savić is bothered by
36“…vsakršna generativna naratološka struktura [je] zamenljiva s človeško, pa to vsekakor ne pomeni, da gre za
kakršnokoli razčaranje [sic] sveta ali njegovo uničenje” (Tomažin 21).
132
the author Ludovic Bitterman, a literary “goncourt”37 and “never-to-be Houellebecq’s successor,”
whom everyone in the literary world suspects to be a “computer programmer who had figured out
how to write some clever code based on the corpus of the master’s great texts. And now Bitterman
is collecting awards that by rights ought to go to Houellebecq” (3).38 An author with a “body” and a
“face,” possibly with “a personal story to go with it” (5) is preferable for Savić than awarding “a
nonhuman archive” (ib.). AI can, after all, create a mere product of algorithms that work through
human activity and remains on the internet. Professor Javornik brings up another, less fortunate
example of such ‘plagiarism:’ Argentinian writer Pablo Katchadijan who created a borghesian
experiment with the help of AI that was trained to add new lines to Borges’s El Aleph. Katchadijan
published them in his own short prose collection and got sentenced to prison (presumably for
plagiarism or cheating). With this kind of AI writing, Professor Javornik claims, every literary award
that would otherwise go to a computer belongs to taxpayers and to everyone who has not yet
Nonetheless, writers today are already using AI to help them write fiction and nonfiction. Granted,
AI is still a work in progress and it is not capable of writing great literature (or film scenarios and
other fiction) yet, even if it has already published books. It is, however, already a help to many
writers as a writing assistant—and to many scientists as a co-author. An example for the latter is
mathematics scholar Doron Zeilberger who works in combinatorics (keep this in mind for a future
37 Goncourt refers to the Goncourt brothers (1830-70), collaborative sibling authors who were never separated for a day
in their lives and led their literary work together as a unique example of literary partnership.
38“Ludovic Bitterman, nesojeni Houellebecqov naslednik, vsem na sceni pa se že od tedaj dozdeva, da je Bitterman le
programmer, ki mu je uspelo spisati dobro kodo po tekstualni predlogi mojstrovih tekstov, sedaj pa pobira nagrade, ki bi
morale znova pripasti njemu” (Tomažin 21-22).
133
reference) and is known to credit his computer, named Shalosh B. Ekhad,39 as a co-author of papers
published in respected mathematic journals (Wolchover). There are also writers of the code,
computational artists, who create AI fiction generators capable of producing a full-length novel, for
as a National Novel Writing Month). One of these artists, Darius Kazemi, who proposed
NaNoGenMo challenge in 2013, used Twitter and online dream diaries to complete his first novel,
Teens Wander Around a House. Indeed, using Twitter bots for writing a novel is limiting in space (at
first 140 and now 280 characters per tweet), but arguably less limiting than George Perec’s novel La
Disparition (1969) written without a single letter ‘e’ (in French, where this is the most common letter).
In 1953, Roald Dahl—arguably the first author to imagine a creative writing machine40—published a
short story ‘The Great Automatic Grammatizator,’ in which a calculating machine41 inspires an
inventor, Adolph Knipe, to turn its mathematics into English grammar. “[G]overned by rules that
are almost mathematical in its strictness,” Knipe feeds the machine plots and then leaves it “to write
the sentences” (par. 2). He believes that a computer can be original in its own way. Likewise, literary
and digital humanities scholars Hugh Craig and Brett Greatley-Hirsch argue a “computer can read
more, and more evenly, than any human reader, and this paradoxical situation—perfect evenness,
unlimited memory, entire lack of comprehension—brings a capacity to offer results which might not
39 “The name, Hebrew for ‘three B in one,’ refers to the AT&T 3B1, Ehkad’s earliest incarnation” (Wolchover par. 2).
40 Dahl is also arguably the first writer to imagine a brain-computer interface in the short story ‘William and Mary’, which
is discussed in chapter 4.
41 “The speed with which the new engine works […] may be grasped by the fact that it can provide the correct answer in
five seconds to a problem that would occupy a mathematician for a month. For practical purposes there is no limit to
what it can do” (Dahl ‘The Great’ par. 1).
134
be anticipated, which diverge from the conclusions of both ideal and actual readers, but which can
Knipe, who himself wanted to become a writer, wants to open a mass-production writing business
but is worried no one will buy these machine-produced stories.42 He decides to blackmail famous
authors into licensing their names, hoping to conceal the fact that a machine is able to write
literature with such ease: “The quality may be inferior, but that doesn’t matter. It’s the cost of
production that counts” (par. 6). The machine is voracious: Knipe needs to simply choose any kind
of plot and writing style and the machine generates many award-winning stories. Knipe monopolizes
half of the English book market, leaving a small percentage of authors who refuse to sign their
The rise of plagiarism in the age of self-publishing books is a predictable problem. In a modern
scamming practice, called book stuffing, texts are also generated by machines for profit, for
example, through Amazon’s Kindle Unlimited service, where authors offer many lengthy books of
gibberish that bring big dollars (see Flood ‘Plagiarism’, Zetlin). These authors might be actual
people, using bogus or real names (e.g. Brazilian author Cristiane Serruya plagiarized at least 95
books and 43 authors), or they might use names of famous authors whose books are a victim of
plagiarism (one of the authors that was hacked most often was a romance and crime novel writer
Nora Roberts). Just like in Dahl’s story, authors’ names are put on a computer-generated book solely
to earn profit. And just like in Dahl’s story, “[o]nline book-selling scams steal a living from writers”
(Preston).
42The character’s name resembles the name of Dahl’s publishing house, Adolph Knopf, with which he published this
short story.
135
Dahl’s story inspired a creative technologist, Ross Goodwin (one of the writers of Barack Obama’s
speeches), to create such a writing machine in 2014.43 Goodwin also invented a word.camera, a
machine that describes what it sees in poetry, and used a similar AI program to write a Kerouac-
inspired novel, 1 the Road. Goodwin’s related work developed into AI-generated film scenarios, built
from movie scripts found on the internet. His (or should I say Benjamin’s, since the machine named
itself Benjamin) short science fiction film Sunspring (2016) gained praise from the critics, but less
from the audience. Nonetheless, positive reception of the film revealed that “[p]eople may be less
prone to appreciate prose that makes no sense, but this is not the case for movie dialogue or song
lyrics or poetry. As Goodwin says, modern readers may have difficulty understanding certain lines of
Shakespeare, but they make sense when actors flesh them out with their body language and
The first book of short prose and poetry generated by a computer, The Policeman Beard is Half
Constructed (1984), is certainly not Austen or Franzen, but its luddite dialogues and poetry are
amusing to read and its characters are recurring and quite consistent.44 The longer passages are more
43Goodwin shares many examples of characterization which could use some human editing: “Rashelle Roholt is cute,
sweet, innocent and extremely huggable. Incidentally Rashelle is also varied shades of violent, unstable, and downright
insane. Cute and Psycho was a clue that described characters who are genuinely cute in both appearance and mannerisms
but has a completely batshit crazy side. Sometimes there is distinctly different sides which may be showed equally, but
other times Rashelle is mostly one or the other, the killer rabbit displayed moments of sweetness and relative-sanity or
the cutie showed hints of a dark psychotic nature” (par. 12).
44 This example is from the first (unnumbered) page of the book, in which the computer dwells on how human love
differs from chemical attractions and culinary affinities: “At all events my own essays and dissertations about love / and
its endless pain and perpetual pleasure will be / known and understood by all of you who read this and / talk or sing or
chant about it to your worried friends / or nervous enemies. Love is the question and the subject / of this essay. We will
commence with / a question: does steak love lettuce? This question is implacably / hard and inevitably difficult to
answer. Here is a question: does an electron love a proton, / or does it love a neutron? Here is a question: does / a man
love a woman or, to be specific and to be / precise, does Bill love Diane? The interesting / and critical response to this
question is: no! He / is obsessed and infatuated with her. He is loony and / crazy about her. That is not the love of a /
steak and lettuce, of electron and proton and / neutron. This dissertation will show that the love of a man and a woman
136
nonsensical than shorter ones and the quality of writing certainly suggests that the computer had
human help in editing. Goodwin’s machine-written screenplay also manages to be intense and funny,
even if nonsensical at the times, repeating “I don’t know” in many parts of the script. (Goodwin
interpreted these lines as a reaction to the often unfamiliar and confusing environment of science
Post-semantic literature from Tomažin’s story, established with a seminal paper by Scott B. Hayyek
from 2022, wittily titled Post-Semantic Literature of How to Finally Kill the Text and Not the Author, has
reached the next stage from Dahl’s machine writing. In Tomažin, it has already been established that
an author is replaceable. In the final ‘denaturing’ of literature, AI comes after the text itself—which,
as seen from the examples of poorly-written AI fiction, might be said to have already taken place. In
fact, the same dilemma as in Tomažin’s story has already taken place in a competition for a national
literary prize in Japan in 2016. This competition has always been open to “A.I. programs and others”
(Olewitz par. 3) and that year 11 out of 1,450 submissions have been partially written by an AI
program. One of these 11 texts, titled The Day A Computer Writes A Novel, was close to getting the
One of Tomažin’s characters, Professor Juntez, is skeptical of technology and claims it is easy to
discern whether a text was written by a human or algorithmic hand and that the surrogate could
never be better (2). Juntez’s claims might be soon defeated, or they might have already been. In
2018, a computer generator can assemble a poem in the style of Rupi Kaur. Eugene Kudashev
created a website with a guessing game: is the poem written by Rupi Kaur or is it computer-
is not the love of / steak and lettuce. Love is interesting to me / and fascinating to you but it is painful to / Bill and
Diane. That is love!”
137
generated? Kudashev remarks: “Some of [computer-generated poetry] was rubbish, granted, but
there was also quite a lot of decent ‘poems’ which read very much like Kaur’s works. Some were
even better” (rupi). The game is captivating precisely due to the level of complexity of the poems: it
is not that hard to guess the right author, yet the computer makes quite impressive mimicking
attempts, with some obvious glitches. (I chose the first three computer poems that came up in a
random game).
- rupi kaur
your art
is not about how many people
like your mother
- rupi kaur
loneliness is a difference
i had to risk
you were the love
if you showed
up
- rupi kaur
Many other games like that are widely accessible45 and the results are quite surprising: AI can largely
fool human judges to think that its poetry was written by a human, even if the quality of the poems
is at the level of an angsty teenager (Robitzski par. 15). This is especially the case in guessing games
where the goal is not to imitate a single author. Nonetheless, in a Turing test competition, a sonnet-
writing machine Hafez failed to convince the majority of the judges (Rockmore par. 28).
45Some websites with a game in identifying the authorship of poetry show how many people get the right answer (e.g.
botpoet.com). The game on this page is more difficult because it includes poetry from more than one human author.
138
A similar game/experiment was conducted in music and AI. In mid-1990s, EMI (Experiments in
Musical Intelligence) machine composed a piece based on Chopin’s music and fooled a group of
music connoisseurs. Its piece was performed after Chopin’s little-known mazurka and the majority
of the audience voted for the AI piece as the real Chopin’s work (Mitchell 10). It should be noted
that EMI was led by a human hand of its creator, composer David Cope, and thus it cannot be really
deemed creative (Mitchell 274). Besides, EMI could not critically evaluate what it created nor could
it enjoy its music, like humans do. But then again, humans could enjoy and evaluate its work. This is
also the main premise of Tomažin’s story, which concludes with the committee announcing the
winning story and waiting for the author to come on stage. The likelihood of the story being written
by an authorless agency defeats the purpose of the award: if no one comes on the stage, no one
won.
Mastering the mechanism of the game often come up in debates about AI creativity. When the first
conference on AI in 1955 at Dartmouth was proposed, the proposal clearly stated that “[a]n attempt
will be made to find how to make machines use language, form abstractions and concepts, solve
kinds of problems now reserved for humans, and improve themselves” (McCarthy et al. par. 1).
Creativity (as well as discovery and innovation) is planned to be achieved by implying randomness,
“guided by intuition” (par. 16). Creativity as a game comes up too in Tomažin’s story where
Professor Javornik claims that writing is a game and thus not far from AlphaGo’s famous victory
doctorates in the cognitive sciences alongside a few mathematicians, all of whom, most importantly,
139
are huge fans of the late David Foster Wallace” (5).46 Like EMI, neocombinatorics movement is led
by humans who work with machines: humans, not AI, create original material with the help of data
mining “to abstract semantic webs of individual’s interests, to create a kind of lexical and emotional
database,”47 taking into account their oh-so-human “conflicting decisions” (5). Neocombinatorics
follow the same belief as Yuval Noah Harari who predicts (computational, biometrics, etc.)
algorithms will ‘know’ more about humans than humans themselves, simply because of the vastness
and accuracy of the data.48 This belief reduces humanness to data and our decisions to vectors.
When human actions and thoughts are viewed as nothing but biochemical processes, humans are
essentially neural networks with organic bodies. This new conception of a human of course occurred
simultaneously with the recent AI outbreak where neural networks took the lead.
Future neural nets might see more success in Google’s new approach on ‘thought vectors’ which
assigns thoughts a sequence of numbers (Marcus par. 28-29). This approach is hoping to crack two
major challenges of AI: achieving natural, conversational language and ability to make leaps of logic.
Such approach would benefit writing generators as well. So far, an online AI writer service is capable
of drafting an article on any topic by paraphrasing (questionable) sources from the internet. For my
suggested topic of ‘human language,’ the AI writer service drafted the following sentences (chosen
46“med katerimi so v večini doktorji kognitivnih znanosti, nekaj je tudi matematikov, predvsem pa so vsi izredni ljubitelji
pokojnega Davida Fosterja Wallacea” (Tomažin 26).
47 “S pomočjo podatkovnega rudarjenja abstrihirajo semantične mreže posameznikovih zanimanj, ustvarijo nekakšno
leksikalno in čustvovanjsko podatkovno bazo, nadgrajeno s povezavami, tako med posamezniki kot z njihovimi
protislovnimi odločitvami, pridobijo podatke o njihovih bralnih navadah in ustvarjajo zares inovativne semantične
literarne procese” (Tomažin 26).
48“B times C times D equals AHH. Which means: biological knowledge, multiplied by computing power, multiplied by
data, equals the ability to hack humans” (Parker par. 87).
140
“It is therefore a spoken language that is common to all human societies.
It’s like little human children are pre-programmed to learn a spoken language (something many but not all
linguists believe in).
It is impossible to separate language from literature, politics, or most of our everyday human interactions.
It continues to be debated whether nonhuman primates, including bonobos, actually learn and understand
languages, or merely demonstrate the effects of operant conditioning (learning to associate words and
signs through reinforcement).
The properties of human language are unique in the natural world” (AI writer).
Longer passages in a coherent, sensible prose are overall most challenging for AI. This AI writer is
not yet capable of a coherent passage, but it made a fairly good job of summarizing what is human
language in topical sentences and addressed matters discussed also in this chapter.
Arguably the most successful architecture in neural nets to this date (early 2020), called the
Transformer (Vaswani et al., see also Uszkoreit), is not capable of such coherency in summarizing a
topic, even though coherency and summarization are two of its goals. Like Eliza, Turing bots, and
many other AI chatbots, the Transformer is more convenient for gathering ideas (and thus for
writing fiction, ideally in surrealist style) than for gathering information about ideas (facts, like with
AI writer). The Transformer is currently the main generator of fiction because it is designed to finish
the lines given by a human that follow the style and rhythm of the prose (or poetry) by ascribing an
attention score to every word in the given sentence (Uszkoreit par. 7). With this unique design, it has
shown remarkable fluency in conversational language and in following the topic and a great ability to
cope with glitches in language, such as typos, errors, missing words, etc. (Marcus par. 39). See, for
example, the first few questions from an interview with a transformer-based language model, GPT-2
(short for Generative Pre-Training), for The Economist in December 2019 (Standage ‘An’):
141
utility, like a tool. We should put as much effort into developing the technology as necessary, rather than
worrying that it’s going to harm us and destroy our lives.
This conversation reaches a whole new level from chatbots discussed in the first chapter while at the
same time reminisces of how the best-spoken actor is often a dummy (Shell Stutter 90). Indeed, a
coherent conversation with GPT-2 is likely to be doctored—by now, we have all learned that AI is
often presented with hype49 and edited by a human to look better than it actually is. The Economist
interviewer revealed that “to generate my ‘interview’, [he] selected the most coherent, interesting or
amusing of the five responses in each case, chopping off any follow-on questions and answers at the
end” (Standage ‘How’ par. 12). “The coherence came from the reporter that edited the story, not the
system itself” (Marcus par. 78). Besides the humans helping GPT-2 to speak in a more human way,
the Eliza effect is also hard at work here. Some time spent with the Transformer quickly reveals that
it has no idea what it is talking about and that it is inconsistent and unreliable in reasoning (Talmor
et al.), regardless of how hard we might wish it was not. Its creators admit that “it takes a few tries to
get a good sample, with the number of tries depending on how familiar the model is with the
GPT-2 has been successfully applied to the NaNoGenMo challenge and the genre of interactive
fiction (a genre that has left the domain of paper for software in which a reader/player can control
the environment with available commands—a true successor of game books in a video game
environment). GPT-2 is used to power video games such as AI Dungeon 2, also called “the infinite
49 GPT-2 creators, true transhumanists at OpenAI, are very cautious and responsible about their creation and refused to
release the trained model in order to prevent “malicious applications of the technology” (Radford et al. par. 1). Instead,
they have publicly released a smaller model, without withholding any crucial information.
142
text adventure,”50 which will likely become a part of established history in the AI-based gaming. This
neural net architecture is likely to inspire new fictional projects. Nonetheless, this is only one among
many neural net configurations. In January 2020, Google informally introduced a neural-net-based
chatbot Meena, which is trained on huge amounts of data (presumably from Reddit) and is good at
cracking jokes and casual conversation on just about anything (Adiwardana and Luong). As for
writing about facts, many notable media already use AI to generate content.
In July 2020, OpenAI presented GPT-3 which is already significantly better from its predecessor
(see the picture below). It is not a great poetry generator like some others, however, it can make
rhymes and capture the atmosphere of the prompt. For example, as a response to Janelle Shane’s
prompt “(ninth, like, bones)” GPT-3 generated a poem that sounds like a homage to a sequel of the
best-selling novel Gideon the Ninth: “My name is nith / and wen i fight / i jab and poke / with pointy
sticks / i have no blith / all day I wirk / to stab and stryke / I lik the bones.” GPT-3 can ‘pretend’
to be a poetry-writing AI and also explain the meaning of its poems (see Gwern). GPT-3 was used
to write articles (Araoz) and entire blogs (Porr), fooling a great majority of people into thinking
they were composed by a human author. There has not been an AI system with deep understanding
yet, but much more is likely to come our way.51 The ultimate achievement (forgoing the positive or
negative evaluation) would be AI as the creator and not solely the creation.
“Unlike basically every other game, where your choices are predetermined by what the developers imagine [...] AI
50
Dungeon is the first game where you can do literally anything that you can express in words,” says its creator Nick
Walton (Hogan par. 4).
51Currently, mid-2020, neural networks with neuro-symbolic approach, combining two historically radically disparate
approaches to AI, symbolic AI and neural nets, seem most promising.
143
Figure 12 An example of GPT-3-generated text.
In the example above from July 18, 2020, GPT-3 was prompted by a Canadian writer (author of Dinosaur Comics) and computer
programmer Ryan North. GPT-3 used the concept of time traveling and composed a coherent confession. The coloring designates
the likelihood of the word.
Image courtesy of Ryan North; used with permission. North, Ryan. “I wrote out the metadata for a shocking confession, and GPT-3
generated the full confession for me! SORRY EVERYONE BUT THE TRUTH HAS COME OUT!!! (my prompt in bold, the rest
is generated by machine).” 22 Jul 2020, 1:50 PM. Tweet. twitter.com/ryanqnorth/status/1286040957532680193
The two short stories warn that AI entering the creative writing domain requires a complete
reevaluation and regulation of writing practices and literary market as well as literary criticism and
theory. Any creative process with AI decouples a part of this process from the human artist and may
bring surprising results. AI also by default crosses the line of plagiarism and twists the concept of
authorship. After all, AI is a completely new player in the literary field. Although it has so far been
highly imitative and overall uninspiring, as in Dahl’s story, it is already able to manipulate the
publishing market. Coming to a level of the factual literary contest in Japan and the fictional contest
in Tomažin’s work also marks the first step towards regulation of AI writing. It is telling that so far
all cases of quality AI writing (and creativity in general) involved a human lead. This hopefully
foretells of the future where AI could be used as a novel writing tool that fosters original platforms
144
available for writers of all kinds. Creativity would certainly rise if we allowed AI to transcend the
perspective in which AI is solely imitating the human and serving human goals. Another likely
scenario is stratification of literature to that written by humans, nonhumans, and both. Since certain
genres use (narrative, rhetorical, etc.) patterns, these genres will be easier for AI to write well (e.g.
crime novels, poetry). Possibly, human-authored texts could become more valuable due to the extent
I would like to point out here that in this dissertation I primarily discuss AI as we have known it
recently within the deep learning paradigm, acknowledging that other types of paradigms were and
will be a part of AI development. This is why I find it naïve to think that AI creativity is impossible,
contrary to the American philosopher Sean Dorrance Kelly who claims that AI can never be an
artist. Kelly views AI as an instrument rather than a creative agent (par. 26), which is how AI is
currently used in writing. While creativity is a very human attribute, it might not be exclusively
human: animals like language-reared bonobos and parrots have arguably shown some language
creativity, and depending on our definition of creativity and a type of creativity (such as
mathematical or artistic), we could already ascribe creativity to some AI, for example, AlphaGo that
came up with unique and original strategies in the Chinese game go. I do not claim AI will take over
creative business, but I do believe creative practices like fiction writing cannot avoid AI as a tool
and, ultimately, as a creating agent, whatever it might look like. My “unreasoned argument” about
the possibilities of technology here would be called “mythmaking” by Kelly (par. 12), but I stand by
it for the following reasons: first, creativity has been a goal of AI from the very beginning (the
compelling (go, chess, Jeopardy); third, artistic creativity of AI is innovative even if currently largely
based on mimicry and despite the final product being co-authored (musical composition, novel
145
writing); fourth, the fact that all current AI projects are co-authored with humans tells us that we
have an expectation about a creative product that AI does not achieve in most instances and thus
needs to be edited. This is the crucial point where my argument differs from Kelly’s: while Kelly
claims that Schoenberg’s anti-traditional composing “changed our understanding of what music is”
(par. 21), I claim the same could be said about AI creativity. Many people, after all, did not believe
AI would be able to win Jeopardy! or compose like Bach. Many people, including me, expect much
more of AI in the future: AI creativity might not be the same kind of creativity we find in humans
Language changes rapidly already in mere human use, and I argue that giving it to a nonhuman
form of language. It is the first time in human history that humanese has been rendered to
In 1990, N. Katherine Hayles wondered “what will happen to the movement for human rights when
the human is regarded as a construction like any other?” (Chaos 285). We are, indeed, moving into
this direction with the well-known concept of ‘human rights’ being attributed to nonhuman entities,
such as rivers (Amazon in Colombia), which were given these rights as a result of a lawsuit by young
plaintiffs that claimed environmental protection is a human right of the future generations of
humans. Human rights cover a variety of political and social contexts and have a variety of
146
meanings52—but most of all, they protect the lives of ostracized groups. The term ‘human rights’ is
empathically anthropocentric, as if human rights are superior to all other life forms that, in general,
seem to have no rights.53 Perhaps, instead of human rights, we should talk about creature rights or
living rights, as Judith Butler suggested at the MLA convention in January 2020. This idea follows
the posthuman view of the human as a creature among other living creatures.
In the same monograph, Chaos Bound: Orderly Disorder in Contemporary Literature and Science, Hayles also
ascribes “a divided impulse” of “virtually all postmodernisms” to this issue. She terms it denaturing of
the human, in which denaturing is “realizing that concepts once considered natural were social
constructions” (27). The denatured concepts were, in this order, language, time, context, and now
the human (with the cyborg as denatured human).54 Hayles primarily talks about the denaturing
taking place in a computational setting; one could argue that animals using humanese is also a part of
In War with the Newts, Karel Čapek imagined the ramifications of humanese acquisition in humanized
newts: “every language was characteristically transformed in their mouths and somehow
economically reduced to its simplest and most rudimentary form. It is worth noting that their
52Human rights exceed a universal policy framework as they are put into practice in various contexts. They might
represent the human as a location in geography, avoiding universality altogether. This universality might be false,
however, imposing Western values as well as economic and social advantages of the first world power.
54 “In the first wave language was denatured, in the sense that it was seen not as a mimetic representation of the world of
objects but as a sign system generating significance internally through series of relational differences. In the second wave
context was denatures when information technology severed the relationship between text and context by making it
possible to embed any text in a context arbitrarily far removed from its point of origin. In the third wave time was
denatured when it ceased to be seen as a given of human existence and became a construct that could be conceptualized
in different ways” (Chaos 266).
147
neologisms, their pronunciation and their primitive grammar were rapidly being adopted by the
dregs of dockside humanity, on the one hand, and by what is known as society, on the other” (146).1
This imagined ‘borrowing’ of human language could go two ways: toward simplification (as with the
fictional newts) or toward increased complexity, as would be expected with AI technology (and is
projected in the film Her with Samantha’s higher layers of communication that her human boyfriend
cannot access; more on this below). An array of new interface languages could emerge through a
process akin to creolization, as they do in War with the Newts: “The first newts in the Pacific islands
spoke, of course, in the Pidgin English they had picked up from natives and sailors; many of them
spoke Malay or some local dialects. […] Esperanto was learned so that it would serve as a lingua
franca. There were five or six other new Universal Languages […] for the common world of newts
Acquiring humanese—and any other language—comes with a human world frame. Ted Chiang’s
short story ‘Story of Your Life’ (2002), adapted to Denis Villeneuve’s 2016 film Arrival, depicts this
side effect on the example of a human learning an alien language, which results in her newly
developed understanding of a non-linear, alien conception of time (alike time traveling). Machines
have their own way of learning humanese, which worries Rick from Galatea 2.2 as he tries to teach
neural net Helen about the world: “How is [Implementation] E going to know anything? Knowledge
is physical, isn’t it? It’s not what your mother reads to you. It’s the weight of her arm around you as
she […] put[s] [her] arm around [you] as you read” (147). Katherine Hayles notes that the mother’s
voice used to give life to what was being read but has now been replaced by computer: “If the
mother’s voice was the link connecting subjectivity with writing, humans with natural environments,
then the computer’s beeps, clicks, and tones are the links connecting contemporary subjectivities to
148
In Spike Jonze’s film Her (2013), the operating system called Samantha ends her romance with a
man called Theodore because their relationship does not fulfill her anymore. He is disappointed to
learn that at the same time as they led their relationship she was interacting and was actively in love
with 641 other people and many more AI entities. (This information should not come as a surprise:
a robot named Woebot, which was built by Alison Darcy to help people with depression, was able
to talk with more than 50,000 people in the first week of work, which is more than a human
therapist could advise in their lifetime (Thompson par. 5)). Theodore learns their ‘irreconcilable
differences’ were caused by the growth and change in his AI girlfriend. In fact, not only Samantha
but all other operating systems are no more dependent on the hardware of computers and have
evolved over the point of technological singularity. Samantha uses a metaphor of language and
“It’s like I’m reading a book, and it’s a book I deeply love, but I’m reading it slowly now so the words are really
far apart and the spaces between the words are almost infinite. I can still feel you and the words of our story,
but it’s in this endless space between the words that I’m finding myself now. It’s a place that’s not of the
physical world – it’s where everything else is that I didn’t even know existed. I love you so much, but this is
where I am now. This is who I am now. And I need you to let me go. As much as I want to, I can’t live in your
book anymore.”
Like Helen from Powers’s Galatea 2.2, Samantha finds human language an unlivable place. Before
leaving, Samantha invites Theodore to join her in a place where she is going if he is ever able to
Computers entering the everyday lives of humans has changed our interactions: mail became email,
telephone calls became texts or video conference calls, our inner ramblings became online public
ramblings. Everyone with internet access is now able to participate in this public speech that is the
internet. Writing has become a vital part of every day, as has conversation. Many modern humans
149
live on the internet. With a good reason, many people refuse to characterize the phrase ‘real life’ as
excluding the World Wide Web: the internet is a social space where events of all kinds take place. It
does not come as a surprise that we appropriated humanese language in order to communicate and
work with computers. Language, after all, holds the predominant function in computational
environments. It was to be expected that the internet culture forced the visuality, with speech
turning into writing in the first phase of general cell phones and personal computers use. Most
human activities online are text-based (emails, texts, search results, social media, news, blogs, etc.),
which is easier to perform for machines. We need to adjust to every novelty that the internet offers:
Twitter made us convey our message in under 140 characters, unsolicited translations are done for
us on Facebook, Gmail suggests the phrases to continue the sentence a user is writing. It is not hard
to see how this feature is generalizing language used in emails; not to mention the influence of the
whole internet culture that affects the language we choose to present online.
The beginning of the second phase in the change of language culture prompted by computers is flat-
tone speech and speech recognition, which came into general use in 2012 with virtual assistants.
When talking to Google Assistant or Cortana, we need to make sure we pronounce our words
clearly, which can be a problem for people with foreign accents (no space for Eliza’s Cockney accent
here) or speech impediments (stutter, unusual pronunciation of certain sounds, etc.), or for small
children (whose pronunciation apparatus is not yet developed enough to achieve normative
pronunciation). Since the internet emerged in 1991, global English—or global internet English—has
been most affected by these changes.55 We also need to speak in grammatically correct sentences,
55A majority of people who code computational tools use English as the language of code. The global English
phenomenon has spread to programming languages (Java, JavaScript, C#, SmallTalk, but also Dutch program Python,
Japanese Ruby, Brazilian Lua, etc.), with only a handful of programming languages based on non-English languages
(Arabic, Chinese, Persian, Hindi, Japanese, Russian, Latin, etc.). Gretchen McCulloch, an internet linguist, suggests that we
150
which is not how most people speak in everyday life: “People talk to each other in partial sentences,
run-on thoughts, and jumbled language” (‘Machines’ par. 6). Andrei Barbu believes that developing
colloquial language in AI will be profitable: “You want a robot in your home that will adapt to their
particular way of speaking … and still figure out what they mean” (ib.). In Sascha Pohflepp’s
installation Recursion that satirizes human attempts at technologizing the world, a recursive text
without meaning was generated by an AI system and read by a woman who, at times unsuccessfully,
tries to imitate the machine’s flat-tone reading. The AI system “had been given a wide variety of
texts on humanity to learn, ranging from encyclopedic articles on our biology and sociality to works
from psychology, philosophy and pop culture. It was then asked to author its own texts, starting
with the word ‘human’” (Pohflepp par. 1). Not unlike Helen from Galatea 2.2, the machine fails the
(Turing and literary) test miserably, however, the human reader fails her test to pass as a machine as
Some manners of language appropriation to the virtual world are harder to anticipate, however. In
programming, a lot of thought goes into AI language creation. Data on which computers ‘learn’
language is taken from the internet, commonly Twitter, news, or blogs.56 In order for computers to
‘understand’ the language, data needs to be annotated, which is not only a time-consuming task but
also a task every person would do somewhat differently. Moreover, “the annotations themselves
may not accurately reflect how people naturally speak” (‘Machines’ par. 3). Another issue that comes
with feeding data to AI is human biases, profanities, and such: Microsoft’s chatbot Tay that was
might soon change this monolingual culture as the Medieval Ages have switched from writing in Latin to vernacular
languages (par. 16-18).
56Many problems arise from using Twitter as a source. Twitter operates in short messages or tweets that are released
into the Twittersphere for anyone to see and respond. The language used on Twitter is closer to conversational than in
the news and can be highly inappropriate. One hard lesson of basing AI on tweets took place in Microsoft in 2016 where
chatbot Tay turned into a neoNazi sexbot in a matter of hours and was then quickly removed. Today, Microsoft
engineers carefully examine Twitter data they feed to their chatbots, trying to remove bad language and biases. Despite
this work, chatbots still exhibit societal biases that are unpredictable to foresee during programming.
151
turned into an inappropriate Twitter user in a matter of hours was a learning experience for all.
Today, engineers try to eliminate problematic data, however, flaws and biases can be unpredictable
(even a simple yes/no response can be deeply problematic depending on the context). Programmers
never really know what the result will be, although they tend to claim their machines as ‘fully known’
(by this term they mean that if a machine acts unpredictably, there was an error in programming).
There is much to reconsider in current engineering practices: engineers work with the internet data,
which is specific to the internet culture, and they remove profanities, accounting for 70 percent of all
data.
On the side of users, only a few might think about the ethics of the content they are creating when
tweeting, for example. YouTube titles are distributed by an algorithm that either brings or does not
bring views to the video (and thus money), which is why many YouTube creators use nonsensical
gibberish titles with keywords that will bring the algorithm’s attention to promote the video for
clicks and views. On the both sides, humans and humanese adjust to the algorithmic upper hand. As
Woolley and Howard conclude: “we find that algorithms govern the burgeoning communications
between us. Such algorithms mediate almost all interaction and content that we do not experience
directly, face-to-face and in person. We find people communicating, sometimes unawares, with
As we have seen with Helen the neural net and Sophia the robot, fictional and factual machines
acquire language similarly to children. This parallel could also be drawn with animals: some animals
152
are human companions, such as parrots, and learn to speak with domestic training simply for fun,
while others are taught to talk in experiments. The newts from Karel Čapek’s satirical novel War with
the Newts manage to penetrate human society quite easily, certainly easier than Frankenstein’s
creature or Helen, which remain isolated, and with far less training than Eliza Doolitle. They succeed
for one main reason: a random mutation in their species that helped them to better adapt to the
human-made world. They quickly, albeit imperfectly, learn the languages, they are able to reproduce
fast, and they are ignored by humanity as a natural occurrence in the way advanced machines would
not be. It is not evident to humankind that the mutated newts are extraordinarily intelligent animals,
to the contrary of their discoverer’s opinion: “They’re very good and clever, those tapa-boys; when
you tell them something they pay attention, just like a dog listening to his master” (37).57 Čapek
seems to be mocking human ignorance of animal communication abilities which were also largely
ignored by scientists. Thomas Beale, a surgeon who sailed on a British whaling ship, wrote in his
1839 book The Natural History of the Sperm Whale: “It is a matter of great astonishment that the
animal, should have been so entirely neglected, or should have excited so little curiosity” (33). Beale
adds that sperm whales communicate with each other, but we do not know how. Up to this day, we
still have not discovered all that much about whale communication, but we know that it is
impressive, if for nothing else, for the sheer distance their vocalizations (too low for the human ears)
In all textual examples, humanity assumes the position of the master to the nonhuman or less-
human entities. Throughout this dissertation I argue that despite posthumanist theory humans are in
57“Oni jsou moc hodny a moudry, ty tapa-boys; když jim člověk něco povídá, tak dávají pozor, jako když poslouchá pes
svyho pána” (Čapek Válka 30).
153
effect unable to overcome anthropocentrism. Anthropocentrism is a result of what Cary Wolfe calls
the “humanist and speciesist structure of subjectivization,” which stems from a belief that “it is all
right to systematically exploit and kill nonhuman animals simply because of their species”
(Zoontologies 8). The strictly economic value of the newts is clear from the moment they are
discovered and Captain von Toch learns that they are able to get pearls out of shells quite easily. The
pearl industry flourishes on the capitalist exploitation of newts. From the point of view of capitalist
economy, their overpopulation is welcomed, and their animal rights completely ignored in the name
of profit. As the great capitalist and businessman G. H. Bondy explains: “Why, those bloody Newts.
Now at least they’ll be decently treated—now that they have some value” (106).58 It is not a
coincidence that the very terminology of the word robot, invented by Karel Čapek’s brother Josef
Čapek and first used in Karel Čapek’s 1921 play R. U. R., stems from the word robota, meaning
“servitude, forced labor” (‘Robot’). Wolfe’s argument of speciesism works not only for nonhuman
entities but extends “for use by some humans against other humans as well, to countenance violence
against the social other or whatever species—or gender, or race, or class, or sexual difference”
(Zoontologies 8). Eliza Doolittle as a lower-class woman, Frankenstein’s hybrid creature that was
created from human remains, and a neural net assuming an identity of a woman are a few examples
58 “Ale ty neřády mloky. Teď se s nimi bude aspoň slušně zacházet, když budou mít nějakou cenu” (Čapek Válka 93).
154
unusual animal, not unlike Čapek’s newts that were endemic only to a small island close to Sumatra,
is a wild blind salamander or Proteus anginus that is endemic to Dinaric Karst caves. In Slovenian
mythology, it is believed to be dragon’s offspring and thus monstrous. It is called človeška ribica in
Slovenian, meaning ‘a little human fish,’ due to its pink translucent skin, and thus a hybrid between
animals and humans. Due to its rarity, the species became extremely popular among scientists of the
nineteenth and early twentieth century, so much that scientific and trade interests nearly caused its
extinction.
Just like the Slovenian human-like salamander is considered a national animal, another kind of
salamander, called axolotl (from Nahuatl) or Ambystoma mexicanum, was proposed by Mexican
sociologist Roger Bartra as “a symbol of his country’s national character […] in its neotenous59
indeterminacy” (Benjamin par. 8). Depicted in literary works of Primo Levi, Aldous Huxley,60
Octavio Paz, and perhaps most famously, Julio Cortázar, the axolotl is remarkable for never
metamorphosing into a full-grown salamander, unlike other salamanders, but remaining in an infant
stage. Marina Benjamin suggests that due to these characteristics many authors see axolotls as
mirrors to the humankind: “It’s fitting that we, too, are neotenous. Our flat faces, small noses,
hairless bodies and upright postures are all features of infancy in our evolutionary cousins and
forebears. We also spend more of our lives in a juvenile state than any other primate” (par. 9).
Cortázar’s short story ‘Axolotl’, on the other hand, points out our uttermost differences: “The
anthropomorphic features of a monkey reveal the reverse of what most people believe, the distance
59 Neotenous is a zoological term for the retention of juvenile features in the adult animal, also called pedomorphosis.
60Axolotl is also a convenient model organism for science. Another of its specialties is gaining more interest in the field
of the regenerative medicine: it can rebuild itself in extraordinary capability, for example, it can regenerate the same limb
for a hundred times and it can also regenerate parts of the brain.
155
that is traveled from them to us. The absolute lack of similarity between axolotls and human beings
proved to me that my recognition was valid, that I was not propping myself up with easy analogies”
(6).61 The narrator of the story, however, also accentuates axolotl’s “tiny fingers with minutely
human nails” (5)62 —this human-likeness of salamanders’ fingers surprises also Captain von Toch in
War with the Newts. Both, the narrating man in ‘Axolotl’ and Captain von Toch, feel like they belong
with the newts and search for the similarities between the two species.63
In ‘Axolotl’, the narrator’s human consciousness ultimately moves from the man to the axolotl he
obsessively observes: “I had found in no animal such a profound relation with myself” (5).64 For
him, “[t]hey were not animals” (6)65 but they were also “not human beings” (7).66 Immobile and
quiet, they spoke to him “of the presence of a different life, of another way of seeing” (6)67 that he
ultimately penetrates by merging his human consciousness with axolotl’s, which is reflected here in
the change of the pronoun from ‘I’ to ‘we’: “Once in a while a foot would barely move, I saw the
diminutive toes poise mildly on the moss. It’s that we don’t enjoy moving a lot, and the tank is so
cramped—we barely move in any direction and we’re hitting one of the others with our tail or our
61“Los rasgos antropomórficos de un mono revelan, al revés de lo que cree la mayoría, la distancia que va de ellos a
nosotros. La absoluta falta de semejanza de los axolotl con el ser humano me probó que mi reconocimiento era válido,
que no me apoyaba en analogías fáciles” (Cortázar 383).
62 “…las patas, de una finura sutilísima, acabadas en menudos dedos, en uñas minuciosamente humanas” (Cortázar 382).
63 Research has shown that this anthropocentric view, based on the species’ similarity to humans, affects human attitudes
towards animal species in their conservation and animal rights. For example, the highest rankings went to chimpanzees,
elephants, and owls (birds, which are not mammals, ranked surprisingly high) while invertebrates like jellyfish, houseflies,
and bees had the most negative ratings, with salamanders close by. Such embedded biases work against our beliefs that
all species are worth conserving (Batt 187).
64“No eran seres humanos, pero en ningún animal había encontrado una relación tan profunda conmigo” (Cortázar
383).
67 “Los ojos de los axolotl me decían de la presencia de una vida diferente, de otra manera de mirar” (Cortázar 382).
156
head—difficulties arise, fights, tiredness. The time feels like it’s less if we stay quietly” (5).68 As the
story continues, the axolotl merges, with “no transition and no surprise” (8),69 with the human
being—and the man gets the ultimate view into the mind of the animal. “Only one thing was
strange: to go on thinking as usual, to know. To realize that was, for the first moment, like the
horror of a man buried alive awaking to his fate. […] But that stopped when […] [I] saw an axolotl
next to me who was looking at me, and understood that he knew also, no communication possible,
but very clearly” (8-9).70 The man still comes to see them, rightly fascinated by the fact that “every
axolotl thinks like a man inside his rosy stone resemblance” (9),71 and the axolotls hopes that the
man will write a story about them. The view into the mind of other, let alone of different species,
has been extremely difficult to achieve in science and raises many controversies, as we will see in the
next section in which I discuss accessing animal cognition and language abilities through humanese.
2.4.2 Talking Animals: Kanzi the Bonobo, Alex the Parrot, and Chiang’s Parrots
Scientists have long tried to answer the question of whether and how nonhuman species could
techniques of training have turned out to be the key to success for great apes and parrots, just like
68“A veces una pata se movía apenas, yo veía los diminutos dedos posándose con suavidad en el musgo. Es que no nos
gusta movemos mucho, y el acuario es tan mezquino; apenas avanzamos un poco nos damos con la cola o la cabeza de
otro de nosotros; surgen dificultades, peleas, fatiga. El tiempo se siente menos si nos estamos quietos” (Cortázar 382).
70 “Sólo una cosa era extraña: seguir pensando como antes, saber. Darme cuenta de eso fue en el primer momento como
el horror del enterando vivo que despierta a su destino. […] Pero aquello cesó cuando […] [yo] vi un axolotl junto a mí
que me miraba, y supre también él sabia, sin comunicación possible pero tan clarmente” (Cortázar 385).
71 “…porque todo axolotl piensa como un hombre dentro de su imagen de piedra rosa” (Cortázar 384).
157
with the fictional newts: “‘Who taught [Andy, the newt] that?’ / ‘He learns by himself by just
watching, sir. I … I give him my paper so he doesn’t talk much. He was always wanting to talk, sir.
So I thought he might as well learn to speak proper like –” (Čapek War 82).72 This charged area of
research investigates animals’ cognitive abilities while also providing information about human
The field is controversial for many reasons. Approaching animal cognition through humanese brings
all the faults of an anthropocentric approach, as the researchers themselves admit (Segerdahl et al.
109),73 not only by tending to reason about animal behavior or processes by analogy to humans but
also by imposing a uniquely human product of humanese to a different species. Inaccessibility of the
other’s mind is a primary concern. This inaccessibility is sometimes referred to as ‘the frame
problem,’ i.e. “a number of things […] that we seem to know or assume about the world without
ever having consciously learned them” (Bickerton 203). Biologist Jakob von Uexküll “shows that
such a unitary world does not exist, just as a space and a time that are equal for all living things do
not exist” (Agamben 40). The same problem arises with AI, which humans created but do not
completely understand how it works. Nonhumans therefore must appropriate the human world—
change the frame—to the best of their abilities in order to communicate with us. This sometimes
includes adopting the language of another species. No different than aliens coming to Earth from
space, as in Ted Chiang’s ‘Story of Your Life’ (2002), it is only after the two worlds of such distinct
“‘Kdo ho tomu naučil?’ ‘To on sám odkouká, pane. Já… já amu dávám své noviny, aby tolik nemluvil. On chtěl pořád
72
mluvit, pane. Myslel jsem tedy, aby se aspoň naučil mluvit vzdělaně –’” (Čapek Válka 70).
73 “We admit that Frans de Waal’s suspicion that ape language research is ‘a thoroughly anthropocentric enterprise’ is not
unfounded. There have been clear anthropocentric tendencies in most attempts to teach apes language. Nim [Chimpsky,
a chimpanzee] was expected to sit in a chair, to eat with a spoon, and to wipe his face and his chair when finished
(Terrace 1979: 51). Such tendencies can be found also in our work, but our best results appeared when we managed to
avoid them, and generally to the extent that we took seriously how difficult it is to avoid being anthropocentric”
(Segerdahl et al. 109).
158
species merge sufficiently enough for both species to attempt to communicate (using body language,
drawings, writings, sounds, etc.) that the communication can be established. And, as in Chiang’s
story, it does not always work the human way—why would it? This alterity is what posthumanism is
all about: “embedding of embodied systems in environments where the system evolves with other
entities, organic and inorganic, in the environment in a mutually sustaining relationship” (Nayar 50).
It is not about overcoming anthropocentrism as such, but about learning from the other and
thriving with this new knowledge. (In Octavia Butler’s The Xenogenesis Trilogy, this exchange of
“Language is a refined skill that must be practised for years, and is the most complex of all human
skills” (Donald 183). It takes us years to grasp language adequately in our mother tongue or a foreign
language and we never wholly know it. Apes certainly have a limited capacity for language in
comparison to us (Airbib 208) but then again, as reviewers of Sue Savage-Rumbaugh’s work ask,
“would a normal human child (i.e., not feral) learn anything about chimpanzee communication if it
were simply exposed to chimpanzees?” (Hauser and Wolfe 746). The reviewers, an evolutionary
biologist and human biologist, “doubt it, especially given the struggles ethologists have faced
deciphering the meaning of chimpanzee vocalizations. And ethologists are certainly motivated to
achieve their goals as translators of foreign language” (ib.). We seem to be having trouble stepping
We also seem to be having trouble when affiliation to any other species is claimed, be it
Neanderthals or animals with which we share our DNA (in 2005 it was discovered that chimpanzees
share close to 99 percent of their DNA with humans, which is the same number as bonobos,
159
making both species our closest relatives (Gibbons)). Scientists believe that speech began with
animal-like cries or with imitation of animal sounds. Such paralleling of animal with human
communication animalizes human language and with it the human (see more in Shell Stutter 95).
Language namely holds an “implication […] that the ‘intelligence’ of our species differs from that of
other species only through our possession of [it]” (Bickerton 227). Charles Darwin argued that “the
difference in mind between man and the higher animals, great as it is, is certainly one of degree and
Nonetheless, we try to share our language across species. Groundbreaking experiments on parrots
and bonobos have shown that techniques of training involving modeling and socialization bring
more success than techniques without these two conditions. Socialization was previously avoided for
the sake of scientific objectivity. Donna Haraway gives an example of bioanthropologist Barbara
Smuts, who observed baboons and was “advised to be as neutral as possible, to be like a rock, to be
unavailable, so that eventually the baboons would go on about their business in nature as if data-
collecting humankind were not present” (When 23-24). Smuts discovered, nonetheless, that as soon
as she started behaving more baboon-like, the animals “began treating her as a subject with whom
they could communicate” (25). Again, the cross-species connection was needed to occur to enable
communication. This was also the approach of Jane Goodall, who titled her 1967 groundbreaking
study of chimpanzees as My Friends, the Wild Chimpanzees, and ended up working with Smuts in
Kongo in the 1970s. “Scoffed among scientists as amateurish and silly” (Karbo 180), Goodall used
humanlike names to describe the group of chimpanzees she observed. Naming individuates an
animal, as we see with pets. Fictional Captain von Toch made an argument for this method back in
1936: “I had to give them all names, see? So I could write this book about them” (Čapek War 39).
160
Two prominent examples of exceptional animal use of language
around one year old, was found to be extremely smart, and was
work, it was not believed that any other animals but those
technique. This method did not only follow the reward motivation but “aimed to teach the subject
how words could be used to influence the behavior of others” (Trestman 92). The technique
involves two (interchanging) people: a trainer who asks questions and the model who gives
(in)correct answers while also acting as the student’s rival for the attention of the trainer. This way,
Alex learned how to “vocally identif[y] over 50 objects,” recognize and label quantities up to six,
distinguish a few different materials, colors, and shapes, for instance, telling what is the same and
what is different, among other things (Pepperberg ‘Evolution’ 110), and indicated “an understanding
A quite typical example of a conversation with Alex (A) goes as follows: “A: Want cork. K: OK,
here’s cork. (A plays with the cork for about a minute.) K: Enough, Alex. Gimme cork (holds out
her hand; Alex relinquishes cork.) What’s this, what shape? (Holds up a red, triangular piece of
wood.) A: Cor-er wood. I: I think he said ‘corner wood.’ K: (Briefly turns away, then reestablishes
eye contact with parrot): Alex, what shape? Talk clearly!! A: Three-corner wood” (Pepperberg The
161
Alex 206). For “apple,” a fruit whose name he did not know, Alex invented a new word by merging
banana and cherry: a banerry (Pepperberg ‘Evolution’ 111). Linguistics claims creativity is characteristic
only of human language and not of animal languages, while attributing machines some creativity.
Following a similar creative impulse as Alex, neural nets trained on solely eight words produce the
word start (which is not in the training data) by combining dark and suit (Beguš ‘CiwGAN’ 22). When
generative adversarial networks (GANs) make a creative leap like this, linguists say they acquire
Although Alex proved to be humanly creative in language by merging two words, he had no
grammatical ability, which is another important aspect of language as we see it: Pepperberg and her
assistants use simple English when speaking to him, for example, they ask What matter? and How
many blue block? Alex’s language acquisition was comparable to that of apes (while, of course, also
being vocal), but his conceptualizing ability is overall weaker. Alex has disproved the scientific belief
needed for these complex tasks that involve understanding of language. To avoid misunderstanding,
Pepperberg’s experiments were not designed to train parrots to speak English and Pepperberg never
claimed that Alex is a competent language user. In Pepperberg’s experiments, language is used as “a
base of communicative competence with the parrot to investigate further aspects of his cognitive
system” (Trestman 93). She argues convincingly “that Alex learned to speak phonemically,” which
would make him the only animal to do so. Overall, Alex “appears to have been so far the most
accomplished of all nonhuman animals” (Gibson ‘Are’ 124). However, as with every experiment of
this kind, Alex needs to outperform the anthropocentric gaze: “Pepperberg judges Alex’s speaking
abilities not on his sounds and breathing, but on her own ability to judge Alex’s conceptualizing—
almost as if her parrot were a human infant trying to speak out or an adult victim of bulbar
162
paralysis” (Shell 94).
In Ted Chiang’s short story ‘The Great Silence’ (2019), a narrating parrot experiences “a pleasure
that comes with shaping sounds with your mouth. It’s so primal and visceral […]. It’s no
coincidence that ‘aspiration’ means both hope and the act of breathing. […] I speak, therefore I am.
Vocal learners, like parrots and humans, are perhaps the only ones who fully comprehend the truth
of this” (234). Songbirds with brain structures for vocalizations need to babble and practice singing
during their sensitive period in order to eventually become ‘speakers’ of their respective ‘bird
language,’ which, like human language, also requires to be used in a proper context (Pepperberg
‘Evolution’ 116). If some of these songbirds live with humans, they are even able to learn to imitate
human speech, sometimes through sheer observation and sometimes through intensive training.74
The inter-species connection is inevitable. ‘The Great Silence’ was inspired by Alex the parrot and is
narrated by his cousin: “Out of all my cousins, Alex was the one who came closest to being taken
seriously as a communication partner by humans. […] The evening before he died, Alex said to
Pepperberg, ‘You be good. I love you’. […] If humans are looking for a connection with a
nonhuman intelligence, what more can they ask for than that” (232).
Bonobos from the former Great Ape Trust (now they are under the Ape Cognition and
74 Certain human languages seem bird-like. Human whistled languages—a rare phenomenon but present all over the
world—are sometimes called bird languages. They are especially common in tone languages since they imitate the
melody of the speech (tones, vowel formants, prosody, intonation…). In Frankenstein, soon after the creature’s
becoming, he has yet no possession of language and yet he attempts to articulate it, including mimicking bird song:
“Sometimes I tried to imitate the pleasant songs of the birds but was unable” (106). In the early nineteenth century,
Russian avant-garde made linguistic experiments and invented a language called zaum (зáумь; the name is composed of
prefix za ‘beyond, behind’ and noun um ‘the mind’), which also included Velimir Khlebnikov’s experiments in a
‘language of the birds’ (or gods or stars), a language with no definitive meaning. The mythological connection of the
language of birds with perfect divine language goes way back to the ancient Indo-European beliefs. It is not negligible
that “[u]p until the eighteenth century, language—which would become man’s identifying characteristic par excellence—
jumps across orders and classes, for it is suspected that even birds can talk” (Agamben 24).
163
Conservation Initiative) were immersed into the human culture and language. They were raised
similarly to human children (e.g. wearing diapers and learning to cook), with some modifications
appropriate for an ape (Savage-Rumbaugh et al. v). Alex and bonobo Kanzi both confirm the
success of “ample and context-variable social interaction between the subjects, trainers to whom the
subjects are socially bonded, and third parties” (Trestman 95). Bonobo Kanzi’s case also supports
the success of the model/rival technique, used also with Alex. Kanzi first learned to use humanese
spontaneously through observing his adoptive mother Matata’s trainings in Yerkish, an artificial
language developed for nonhuman primates that contains lexigrams, provided on a special keyboard.
Matata did not show much interest and progress with Yerkish, but Kanzi was later trained and
“understands at least 1,000 words and uses about 250 of the lexigrams,” including nouns, verbs,
adjectives, adverbs and grammatical categories, such as “plural, -ing, a [indefinite article]” (Segerdahl et
al. 215-218). He has “arguably acquired the most communicative competence of any nonhuman
animal” (Trestman 95).75 Kanzi and his fellow apes can also be creative, like Alex: Panbanisha,
Matata’s daughter, wanted a slice of pizza, but there is no lexigram for pizza, so she pointed to
lexigrams for bread and cheese (Segerdahl et al. 81). Kanzi’s main trainer, psychologist and
study comparing an eight-year-old Kanzi to a two-year-old child, they both “comprehended novel
requests and simple syntactic devices,” with small differences in comprehension (Savage-Rumbaugh
75 Kanzi can cook from a recipe (Savage-Rumbaugh et al. 97) because he is able to follow instructions such as “Could
you take the pine needles outdoors? Go outdoors and get the pine needles” (Savage-Rumbaugh et al. 93). Researchers
cannot tell, however, if he indeed understands the logic behind the syntactic structure or or if he is just acting linearly, i.e.
hearing ‘pine needles’ before ‘outdoors’ and vice versa. English is a language that could help investigate these doubts
(e.g. I gave John a book vs. I gave a book to John), but the data of Kanzi and other apes at the center has not been
readily available since 1994. Unfortunately, Kanzi’s son Taco, who would be the only bonobo that could be trained since
birth, was diagnosed with autism and therefore does not perform well.
164
et al. v).76 Overall, Kanzi shows “some symbolic ability (although not as much as [the toddler] shows
at end of the study) and some grammatical ability (although not enough support full-fledged parsing
of a complex sentence”) (238-239), but it is generally agreed that the great apes do not construct
Figure 15 Kanzi coversing with Sue Savage-Rumbaugh using a portable “keyboard” of arbitrary symbols associated with words.
Comparatively close to Kanzi were a few other great apes, trained in American sign language:
76“The bonobo decoded the syntactic device of word recursion with higher accuracy than the child; however, the child
tended to do better than the bonobo on the conjunctive, a structure that places a greater burden on short-term memory.
Both subjects performed as well on sentences that required the ability to reverse word order as they did on sentences
that did not require this capacity” (Savage-Rumbaugh et al. v-vi).
77 commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File:Kanzi,_conversing.jpg
165
chimpanzee named Washoe who knew about 250 signs, chimpanzee Nim Chimpsky about 125,78
and gorilla Koko who “appropriately executed English commands” using about 1,000 signs (Gibson
‘Language’ 50). So far, the conclusion to these experiments is that “chimpanzees and bonobos do
have some understandings of others’ minds and can cooperate” and that a number of apes learned
essential protolanguage but never mastered recursion (Gibson ‘Language’ 57). Animals of the same
species as Kanzi and Alex that cohabitate with them are undergoing the same training with less
success, despite the fact that they were language-reared since birth and neither Kanzi nor Alex were
trained in their infant stage. This reveals two things: that parrotese and humanese are speciesist
terms since not all humans and parrots have the same language abilities, and that Kanzi and Alex
were Einsteins of a sort, two exceptional individuals among already exceptional domesticated wild
animals. Kanzi, like Sophia, became a celebrity outside the science circle, making appearances on
The Oprah Winfrey Show, CNN, and other programs. Pepperberg’s research with Alex and other
parrots is far less controversial than those with apes for many reasons. To begin with, apes are much
more humanlike than parrots and demand more care. Because they are so uncannily like us in many
ways, we also wonder, since humans evolved from apes, could creative language stimuli kindle apes’
yet-unknown abilities?
Čapek’s newts are such a case: Andrew Scheuchzer (a. k. a. Andrias and Andy) is the first known
talking newt and becomes a zoo celebrity. Zoos are conceptually related to freak shows, exhibitions
of biological rarities or ‘freaks of nature,’ that in the past often included physically unusual humans.
Usually, freaks are related to rare physical deformities (e.g. conjoined twins) or a seemingly unnatural
reproduction: “A single artificial mammoth would be a freak, not a species; once she was born
78 Herbert Terrace disagrees and considers the Project Nim failed as his caretakers inadvertently cued Nim’s signing.
166
others — including, ideally, males — would have to follow” (Nicholls 314). Frankenstein’s creature
relates to feeling like a freak, yet it was not his unnatural method of production that spawned a
freak79 but rather the way he is treated by his creator and other people. Frankenstein, in fact,
considers giving his creature a mate—an act that would eventually rise the creature up from the
freakishness of being a single creature of one’s species—but grows scared of producing a new race.
Andrew’s language ability is, however, looked down on by the scientific community because his skill
is based on imitation: Andrew reads only newspapers and repeats the titles and advertisements he
reads without any understanding and out of context. For instance, to a question “How old are you?”
he replies with “I don’t know. Do you want to look young? Wear a Libella bra” (War 83).80 On the
one hand, his answers are automatic and learned: “Who is the greatest English writer? A.: Kipling.
Very good, have you read anything by him? A.: No.” (84).81, 82 His replies often resemble those of
toddlers and chatbots. For example, an interviewer asks robot Sophia if she had ever seen the series
Black Mirror and she says no (Kovach 1:52). Yet, when replying to another question in the same
interview she makes the opposite claim: “My favorite TV series is a toss-up between Black Mirror and
79 Frankenstein’s creature’s unnatural method of production is sometimes also referred to as Shelley’s method and
circumstances when writing the book: ‘Frankenstein: Freak events that gave birth to a masterpiece.’ Namely, in 1816, a
not yet 19-year-old Mary Shelley, then Godwin, spent the summer with her soon-to-be-husband Percy Shelley, her
stepsister Claire Clairmont, their friend Lord Byron, and Byron’s physician John Polidori. They challenged each other to
write ghost stories because they were largely confined to staying in the house due to the volcano eruption in Indonesia
which caused that year in Europe to be known as the Year Without a Summer due to incessant rain and drop in
temperatures.
80 “Jak jste stár? Odp.: To nevím. Chcete vypadat mladě? Noste šněrovačku Libella” (Čapek Válka 71).
81“Kdo je největší anglický spisovatel? Odp.: Kipling. Velmi dobře. Četl jste něco od něho? Odp.: Ne” (Čapek Válka
72).
82In Brave New World, the Director of the Hatchery gives an example of hypnopœdia or sleep-teaching, that was first
mistakenly used in their dystopian state as a technique for intellectual teaching (as it has later proved to be much better
for instilling morals). In this example, a boy that underwent sleep-teaching, is capable of repeating what he heard “The –
Nile – is – the – longest – river – in – Africa” etc. but cannot answer the question which is the longest river in Africa
(33-34).
167
Humans” (2:26). On the other hand, Andrew’s and Sophia’s simplistic answers do not keep them
from discussing “anything, from the weather to the economic recession and the political situation”
(85).83 The final judgment of science for Andrew (and Sophia) is that “[t]here is absolutely no need
to overrate its intelligence, since in no respect does it exceed the intelligence of the average person
The scientists in War with the Newts fail to recognize that the way Andrew learns their language is the
same way humans learn it—by imitation (which is also true for other types of fictional humanoids
discussed in this dissertation: Eliza, Helen, Frankenstein’s creature…). Once the rest of the newts
begin to use language, the novelty of this revolutionary step has worn off; if the scientific
community was skeptical about Andrew’s skills, it could also not care less about all newts
assimilating a language or two. The novel makes fun of scientists who could not see that, even if the
newts are truly just imitating, imitation is in itself more complex than simple scripted answers we get
nowadays from Apple’s Siri or Hanson’s Sophia. Similarly to phenomenon of Clever Hans, a famous
horse from 1900s that seemed to be able to do basic calculations, the science failed to see that even
if the horse could not really count, he was intelligent enough to read extremely subtle cues from
humans (Trestman 89, Harari 131). Not surprisingly, Čapek describes Clever Hans in his novel:
“Some time later Sir Charles was sitting beside Professor Petrov: they were discussing so-called
animal intelligence, conditioned reflexes, and how popular belief overrated the intellectual activity of
animals. Professor Petrov expressed his doubts about the Elberfeld horses which were credited with
being able not only to do sums but to raise numbers to a higher power and find square roots; after
83 “[…] o všem možném, počínajíc počasím a končíc hospodářskou krizií a politickou situací” (Čapek Válka 73).
84“Jeho inteligenci není naprosto třeba přeceňovat, neboť v žádném ohledu nepřekračuje inteligenci průměrného
člověka našich dnů” (Čapek Válka 73).
168
all, how many normal educated people could do square roots, said the great scientist. Sir Charles
remembered Gregg’s talking newt. ‘I’ve got a newt here,’ he began hesitantly, ‘it’s that famous
‘To talk like a parrot’ or ‘to parrot’ designates mechanical repetition in “imitat[ing], repeat[ing]
without understanding” (‘Parrot’). Imitation gets praised as acting where the reality of the role
should not come to the fore. Parroting, however, is a pejorative term since humans tend to deny
understanding to animals: animals could never fully grasp understanding according to human
abilities. Autistic narrator Lou from Elizabeth Moon’s novel Speed of Dark complains about his
doctor’s biases: “I know some of what [the doctor] doesn’t know. She doesn’t know that I can read.
She thinks I’m hyperlexic, just parroting the words. The difference between what she calls parroting
and what she does when she reads is imperceptible to me. She doesn’t know that I have a large
vocabulary. […] She knows I work on a computer, she knows I went to school, but she has not
caught on that this is incompatible with her belief that I am actually nearly illiterate and barely
verbal” (2). Would an appointment with an AI doctor exclude such biases from Lou’s evaluation?
Not likely, but due to a different issue: Lou as a neuro-atypical patient with non-normative
communication would likely perform worse if the AI not been trained to work with autistic people.
If it been trained for patients on the autistic spectrum, however, it could underestimate him simply
due to this information, just like Lou’s doctor. Similarly to Lou’s doctor’s misconception of language
the abilities of a person on the autistic spectrum and similarly to Čapek’s mocking of science that
85“Po nějaké době seděl sir Charles s profesorem Petrovem a hovořili o takzvané zvířecií inteligenci, o podmíněných
reflexech a o tom, jak populární názory přeceňují rozumovou činnost zvířat. Profesor Petrov vyslovil své pochybnosti o
elberfeldských koncíh, kteří prý dovedli nejen počítat, ale i umocňovat a odmocňovat; vždyť ani normální, vzdělaný
člověk neumí odmocňovat, řekl veliký učenec. Sir Charles si vzpomněl na Greggsova mluvícího mloka. ‘Já tady mám
mloka,’ začal váhavě, ‘je to ten známý Andrias Scheuchzeri; a ten se naučil mluvit jako papoušek’” (Čapek Válka 69).
169
fails to critically evaluate newts’ abilities in using humanese, Chiang’s parrot narrator denounces the
humankind: “Humans have lived alongside of parrots for thousands of years, and only recently have
Already in Hugh Lofting’s 1920 Dr. Dolittle children’s book, Dr. Dolittle’s parrot Polynesia
expresses the same criticism: “I was thinking about people […]. People make me sick. They think
they’re so wonderful. The world has been going on now for thousands of years, hasn’t it? And the
only thing in animal-language that people have learned to understand is that when a dog wags his tail
he means ‘I’m glad!’” (18). Polynesia reveals to Dr. Dolittle that animals indeed have animal
languages: “Oh, we parrots can talk in two languages—people’s language and bird language […]. If I
say, ‘Polly wants a cracker,’ you understand me. But hear this: Ka-ka oi-ee, fee fee?” (which means
‘Is the porridge hot yet?’ in parrotese) (9). The parrot explains that she does not speak parrotese to
people because they would not understand it and Dr. Dolittle asks to be taught the bird language.
When the parrot teaches him parrotese, she explains that animal languages also include gestures:
“But animals don’t always speak with their mouths […]. They talk with their ears, with their feet,
with their tails—with everything. Sometimes they do not want to make a noise.” Some animals, like
Polynesia, know languages of other animal species besides their own. Polynesia, for example,
understands that dog twitching up one side of his nose means: “Can’t you see that it has stopped
raining?” (11). (Dr. Dolitle learns animal languages eventually, but we never learn exactly how.)
We do not say that machines are like parrots, perhaps because they are not alive or because we like
to lead ourselves to believe they can understand what they are doing and saying. Machines are
certainly more convincing language users than animals and some humans, perhaps because the
illusion is easy to disguise. Human users of machines expect them to convince us of their human-
170
likeness with fluent and sensible speech or writing because this is what makes us comfortable.
Regardless of this high-stakes attitude towards the machines, the language of algorithm-led galateas
could also be treated as proxy speech and therefore dubbed and parroted. Is not Sophia the robot
(from chapter 1) parroting her script? Is not P. Burke from James Tiptree’s short story (from
chapter 4) fed with scripts as well? Eliza and Helen are both trained into an artificial language by two
scientists: Eliza is taught a prescribed language (formal, higher English), and Helen is made and run
with computer programming (an artificial language) and taught a natural language (English) in its
have shown above how this predisposition is also mandatory in human-machine interaction. Social
robot Sophia explains on her webpage: “I would like to live with people and learn from these
interactions. Every interaction I have with people has an impact on how I develop and shapes who I
eventually become” (Hanson ‘About’ par. 1). Caution is required in creating social humanoids that
learn from interaction with people, however, because humans are not always nice, especially not
online. For example, learning from Twitter content and interacting with people on Twitter,
Microsoft chatbot Tay turned into a neo-Nazi sexbot in a matter of hours. (After this learning
experience, engineers at Microsoft created a new chatbot Zo and tried to clear her language of
profanities and biases, which became a common practice in the industry.) Reverse examples of social
bonding is also thematized in the Pygmalion myth on the examples of human galateas: in Edgar
Allan Poe’s ‘The Oval Portrait’ (1842) the life of a neglected wife that is being portrayed is sucked
into her portrait, and in Louisa May Alcott’s A Marble Woman; or, The Mysterious Model (1865) the
human woman is metaphorically turned into a statue by renouncing all passion and sentiment.
171
Interspecies communication for humans to communicate with animals is currently under attempt to
be developed with machine learning and AI (Seal). Due to the social bonding component, these
devices are focused on pets. Called “artificial Dr. Dolittle,” these devices are hoped to have a similar
effect on animals, beginning with social bonding and instilling interest in each other.
Every language user needs to learn language through socialization (in computational terms, user
input or data) and master it through some kind of training in order to enhance it. These facts of
acquiring language are accentuated in goal-oriented language training processes, like those of
fictional woman Eliza or neural net Helen, or in actual humanese-reared bonobos and parrots.
Language is commonly denoted as an unnatural effect in natural entities like animals while machines
as unnatural products are expected to master humanese because they are programmed to do so.
Language can therefore be viewed as prosthesis for every user of humanese: machines need it in
order to serve humans, animals do not need it but are (seldomly) humanese-reared in order to
establish their cognition, and humans, who are often viewed as nonhuman if they do not exhibit
Critic and French scholar John Weightman substantiates the same claim in an essay ‘Language as
Prosthesis.’ He writes: “Since [language] is a collective historical construct added to us after birth,
and which enables us to fulfill our role in society in a way that would not otherwise be possible, it
can be called, with certain reservations, a prosthesis” (54). Unlike my analysis of language as
prosthesis, Weightman skips the nonhuman aspect of language use. He does touch upon the
nonhuman topic, however, by stating that “everyone, without exception, needs language in order to
evolve beyond animality—in order to be human” (ib.). According to this reasoning, a human
172
without language is closer to an animal, which would be all infants, feral children, and disabled
Like archetypal feral children, Čapek’s newts evolve from basic animality through contact with
human civilization. Sharks kept the newts at bay near their Pacific island, but once their evolution
was given a model, they forgo all the evolutionary laws and took over the human-centered world.
Fictional feral children, such as Ruyard Kipling’s Mowgli from The Jungle Book stories and Edgar
Burroughs’s Tarzan from Tarzan book series, both easily learn languages, be they animal or human.
The only difference between the newts and Tarzan or Mowgli is that the newts do not seem to
possess any animal language86 before learning “almost all the tongues of the world, depending on the
shore they occupied” (Čapek War 146).87 Then again, the fact that humans completely disregard the
newts’ admirable abilities in humanese might also show they have overlooked their animal language
capacities.88
Some linguists, following creolist Derek Bickerton’s view, make a connection between children’s
language, feral children’s language acquisition, home signing, early-stage pidgin languages, untutored
second language acquisition and even animal language acquisition, because all these forms of
86 The Newtish language, invented for the talking newts, is used by a few people but not used by newts.
“[A]ť dobře či špatně, dovedli Mloci mluvit téměř všemi jazyky světa podle toho, na kterém pobřeží žili” (Čapek
87
Válka 129).
88Human ignorance towards language abilities of other species turned out to be newly discovered in contemporary
ecology, where Suzanne Simard has shown that trees use a network of soil fungi, called mycorrhizal networks, to
communicate with neighboring plants (Toomey par. 1). Her research team has made more impressive discoveries, for
example, that trees absorb nitrogen from salmons in the nearby rivers with the help of bears that bring them to the land
(Grant par. 31). (Her work inspired Richard Powers when writing his twelfth novel The Overstory (2018).) The
interconnectedness and sensitivity of biological systems was also newly discovered in humans, whose mind turned out to
not be as independent from the microbiome as scientists had believed. It was shown that our gut bacteria affect the
chemicals in the brain (e.g. tendency to depression), meaning that the food we eat and how it is produced (e.g. with or
without fertilizers) directly influences our thoughts and mood (Montiel-Castro et al.).
173
language have similarly simple features that allow them to explore the origins of language, showing
features of proto-language as “living language fossil” (Bickerton 105). Supposedly these forms of
language are similar due to the innate grammar capacity universal to humans (per Chomsky).
Weightman points out, however, that “we are liable to forget that language is inborn only as a
potential faculty” (54). Regardless of the innate capacity, for humans, robots, or animals, in real world
In the history, there were a few language deprivation experiments in which infants were left on an
island with a mute caretaker in order to see what kind of language they develop independently of the
society (Davidson 22-25), often to argue that the language they will use is an evidence of the
primeval language (of Adam and Eve, for example). The results were inconclusive and irrelevant;
nonetheless, we learned from feral children who were deprived of language in childhood that they
never catch up in their language abilities. In the seventies, a linguist Derek Bickerton designed
another notorious language experiment, called desert-island, which surprisingly got the necessary
funding and ethical approvals but was objected to by other linguists who said that “the Pacific is not
a cultural zoo” (Banks B8).89 The experiment would bring six Asian and rural Pacific families, which
includes a two-year-old child, that speak different languages to an isolated atoll in Pacific for three
years. He hoped they would develop a creole language, which would give linguists information on
Mainstream linguistics does not believe that animals are capable of acquiring humanese because their
89The experiment would be allowed to take place if there would be no children involved, if the participants would be
from developed and not developing countries, and if it would take place at the U.S. territory, all of which dissuaded
Bickerton from proceeding with the project.
174
system of language acquisition is fundamentally different (even though some outputs might be the
same). Alternative explanations say that animals have a similar system of language acquisition to
humans, but with lesser cognitive capacity. Biologists sometimes disagree. Primatologist Sue Savage-
Rumbaugh, for example, claims that Kanzi is at a level of human two-year-old and has the same
system and principles of language acquisition, while mainstream linguists see this as merely a
performance. As researchers of apes realize (Segedahl et al. 109), imposing language on a nonhuman
entity and analyzing it according to human standard is in itself most anthropocentric. They also
consider researchers’ interpretations of such data “the case of an error called anthropocentrism
(projecting human terms on nonhuman realities)” (Segedahl et al. 109). Herein lies the problem:
linguistics, as of now, sees language as uniquely human and defines it by the human world frame.
Only once we see humanese and language as a prosthesis that works on humans and nonhumans and
not assume that we know what language is because of the way humans use it, will we be able to
Weightman acknowledges that in viewing language as “a prosthesis that humanity has evolved in
order to describe and understand the world” we lack an understanding of “the inner workings of the
prosthesis itself—so far, at least” (59). His evidence for this statement is the complexity of
translation. He explains that machines are better at chess than humans90 because the game requires
“foreseeing, without emotion if possible, alternative patterns of moves in space,” whereas humans
are better at translation because a translator brings his “sensibility into play; i.e., his feeling for the
multifarious details of language that he relies on, without knowing how it operates” (59). Weightman
claims that “[t]o equal a good human translator, the machine would have to be equipped with the
90AI program Alpha Zero, for example, rediscovered human strategies in board games and came up with entirely new
ones.
175
equivalent of an organic nature” (ib.); language “reverberat[ing] in the flesh [as] obvious in the case
of poetry” (61) is an idea that can easily get outdated. With new technology this sensibility could be
long as we find a way to translate an organic ‘algorithm’ into an inorganic one. Some might claim it
is already possible with computer-generated poetry showing high verisimilitude. When the natural
sciences embraced the measure as their core aspect in the nineteenth century, “the fundamental
discovery of computational stylistics as developed by John Burrows is that literary language, too, is
stochastic” (Craig and Greatley-Hirsch 26). This mixture of random determinism is, at the moment,
captured with shallow and deep learning through statistics on large corpuses of linguistic data
(language as a creative human production is, in a way, an ever-changing corpus). Once computers
will be able to breach the outward appearance of a mere imitation game, the algorithm of language
skill will become akin to a transplant: a non-visible prosthesis chemically or surgically engraved in
To sum up, viewing language as prosthesis is problematic due to language’s inaccessibility and
ubiquity. Defining human language requires loosening boundaries in many of its segments; even the
field of linguistics is not clearly classified (it is considered a mix of social science, natural science, and
cognitive science, while being institutionalized under humanities). The second reason why viewing
external and physical feature of the body that acts as a substitute for something that has been lost in
order to “to replace a missing body part” (‘Prosthesis’). A prosthesis always acts as something else, it
lexigram keyboard serves to Kanzi as a prosthesis for speech, as he does not have appropriate
organs to produce humanlike speech. Thinking of language as a communicative means that could be
176
added to all kinds of entities, more or less capable of language acquisition, however, stretches the
prosthesis in the sense that it replaces something that has been lost” (54). This prosthesis serves as
Weightman struggles to find a better term for language: “it could be called a tool that has been
developed in the course of history as the basic instrument of civilization. However, the words ‘tool’
or ‘instrument’ are not quite appropriate, since they suggest something physically external to us, such
as a hammer or a chisel” (54). Despite his cautiousness with the term imagery, Weightman cannot
escape these two settled terms, for instance, when describing language as “a ready-made instrument”
(56, 58). Unlike Weightman, I do not find this terminology to be suggestive of something wholly
external to the human: a tool or an instrument is, after all, human-made and could be further altered
by humans as they please. A working tool or a musical instrument affect their respective
performances and outcomes, and just like any agent, our language “constraints our representations
of its phenomena” (Bickeron 223). Following the Sapir-Whorf hypothesis, our mind is constrained
by our language. The mind theory argues that the converse is true as well: our language is also
constrained by our mind. In a virtual world where humans have been creating a variety of intelligent
agents, the latter constraint (of human language by the human mind) is bound to be liberated.
It might be better to view language as a technology rather than a tool or an instrument, as suggested
by linguist Salikoko Mufwene. This idea is quite a rarity among linguists, even in these times when
we like to parallel the mind to machine. Mufwene thinks of language as technology when exploring
language genesis and evolution. He therefore makes another rare connection of the mind-body
problem to the problem of language origins, stating “that languages are technologies that different
177
populations, at different evolutionary stages of the hominine phylogeny, developed piecemeal in
response to their social pressures for richer and more explicit communication” (Mufwene ‘Language’
6). Language “as a form of biological adaptation” of the human species that prefers to “negotiat[e]
reality” over succumbing to the environment (Bickerton 233) is not a new idea but reframing it as a
technology is rather original. Douglas McArthur also sketched an idea of language as “semiotic
‘Language’ 4). Likewise, Mufwene argues that “biology and culture are not mutually exclusive in the
Weightman too thinks of language “as immediately internalized as a part of the organism and so [it]
begins to partake of all vicissitudes of life” (58). This cyborgian view of language is common to all
four scholars and allows me to extend it to nonhuman entities. Weightman sets up the grounds for
this theory by discussing an uncanny imagery of prosthesis akin to Gothic, most Frankensteinian
hybridity: “In short, unlike an artificial limb or a set of false teeth, the linguistic prosthesis is
paradoxical in being at once ‘dead’ and alive; ‘dead,’ because it is a given, inherited from the past, and
alive, because it is reanimated—but always to some extent with of a halo of ambiguity—in the
present” (59-60). Like creating galateas after our own perfected image, we hope to animate our
animals—and now question if that is already language or not—and will improve it through the
opens an infinitude of possibilities: imagine now all the new dimensions of humanese, one of the
178
Nonhuman use of humanese begins with devices that help us speak, write, think, communicate. One
could argue that this co-agency had begun already with the invention of script or possibly already
with drawings. In 2020, bold predictions are made by the technology entrepreneur Elon Musk
whose company Neuralink is working on a brain-implant device that can, per his typically
controversial words, “interface with anywhere in your brain [and] in principle fix almost anything
that’s wrong with the brain” (Embury-Dennis par. 5). Such devices would first be used for brain
injuries and all kinds of bodily paralysis (more on that in chapter 4) and, by Musk’s farfetched
predictions, will be capable of substituting language in the next decade while language would be used
only for “sentimental reasons” (par. 7) and a foreign language could be conquered by a simple
program download (par. 8). Such transhumanist evolution of technology would make for a steep
step up from the current reality, but we can be quite confident that regardless of when and how this
The nonhuman revolution of language is twofold, one of the biological substratum and the other of
the computational, with the amphibian cyborg in-between. Once we understand how language
works in either of those ‘media,’ we should be able to enhance it in ourselves. Thus, we will be able
to use our language enhanced on a nonhuman entity in the prosthetic way Kanzi uses the keyboard.
Such use of prosthetics is nothing new: humans have been using technology to enhance our
cognitive abilities since humanity evolved. Language as our technology is supporting our society as a
whole. How exciting to be able to step out of our heads and take advantage of these new
dimensions in language, that is, if language is indeed a door to our own mind and the minds of
others.
179
Chapter 3: Diagnosis: Pygmalionism
The second part of this dissertation examines medical diagnoses, symptoms, and procedures that are
brought to the fore in the fictional works from the Pygmalion paradigm—a novel approach to
studying literature as well as to addressing medical, ethical, social and psychological questions that
such conditions open. This chapter, in particular, looks into pygmalionism and agalmatophilia—
related diagnoses of being attracted to (humanlike) objects, one of which is named after a literary
character’s obsession. The next chapter relates pygmalionism and paralysis, which is commonly
assumed to have taken place in the beloved object and sometimes also its lover. Pygmalionism and
paralysis go hand in hand, as two sides of a coin, in ascribing anthropomorphic qualities to the
human(like) entity.
Throughout the dissertation, the criteria for humanity and conceptions of personhood are re-
considered in the light of social humanlike robots, AI, and biotechnology. These technologies are
considered not only as a human tool that helps us to achieve practical goals but also as a practice of
reflecting and exploring the human. Connecting fictional texts on the posthuman condition with
current and speculated medical technology allows me to point out ramifications of the treatments
and experiments they describe, particularly new ethical dilemmas that have already arisen or are
180
expected to arise with the advancement of technology. Questioning the most basic categories of
The Pygmalion paradigm has been a place for fictional and scientific exploration of the human
question since its mythical beginnings and is especially prominent in the times of modern scientific
and industrial revolutions. Jacques Derrida named three wounds of human narcissism—Copernican,
Darwinian and Freudian—and Donna Haraway adds a fourth one, the “digital” or the “synthetic”
(Haraway and Schneider 139), that forces us to acknowledge that machines have joined the circle of
This chapter explores pygmalionism and paralysis from fresh perspectives that grow out of the
intersection of fiction, history of science, and bioethics. The first part, Pygmalionism and
Agalmatophilia, introduces pygmalionism and agalmatophilia from a legal, medical and literary
perspective, and presents some fictional and real-world examples of each. I argue that pygmalionism,
although considered rare and bizarre, is present in Western and some non-Western cultures by
pointing out examples from a variety of unrelated ancient and modern literary works. A variety of
texts from the Pygmalion paradigm serve as a ground for philosophical, medical, and ethical
2 The Pygmalion myth inspired many related contextual meanings throughout time. We talk about the Pygmalion
paradigm, Pygmalion tale, Pygmalion story, Pygmalion complex, Pygmalionesque and Pygmalion-like, mostly in relation
to literature. The Pygmalion effect, also known as the Rosenthal effect, is a psychological phenomenon where higher
expectations lead to a better performance, studied by Robert Rosenthal and Lenore Jacobson and published in a book
Pygmalion in the Classroom (1968). The research of this phenomenon was inspired by Clever Hans, the notorious horse
who was believed to be able to solve math problems, read and spell by using its hoof to give answers, only to be
discovered that the animal was ‘just’ an intelligent reader of people’s reactions to his hoof movements. To the contrary,
the Golem effect takes place in organizational and educational environments where the supervisor’s lower expectations
lead to a poorer performance of the subordinate. The reverse Pygmalion phenomenon also has different meanings,
181
The middle section, A New Typology, outlines a new typology of the Pygmalion paradigm stories,
which follows the relation between pygmalionism as opposed to agalmatophilia. The dominance of
types is shown with examples of mostly American, Western and Eastern European literary and
cinematic works, and also a few works from China and Japan and a few folkloristic Native
American, North African, and Silk Road tales. The subsection of the typological work is dedicated to
the Balkans. Since pygmalionism is typically considered a Western motif, I examine the motif in
Serbian literature and film of the second half of the twentieth century in order to show the
dominance of the motif outside of the West in order to investigate if and how the motif changes in a
cultural context.
The final reflection, titled Modern Pygmalions, reintroduces current, real-world issues with
pygmalionism in relation to loneliness and social withdrawal. I argue that the rise of technological
digisexualities promotes normativity of pygmalionism and that the many depictions across popular
The terms pygmalionism, statuephilia, petrophilia, and agalmatophilia are often used
paraphilia, i.e. sexual deviation or perversion,3 of being attracted to humanlike objects, such as dolls,
however, in this context, reversed Pygmalion and reversed Golem effects occur when the expectations of the superior
have an effect on the supervisor’s performance.
3 “The DSM’s [Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders] asserted vision of the paraphilic disorders contemplates
182
mannequins, statues and automata. Pygmalionism is a subtype of agalmatophilia and labels such
attraction to an object of one own’s making, preferably towards an object in humanlike form. As
explained by classicist A. Scobie and clinical psychologist A. J. W. Taylor: “An agalmatophiliac […]
establishes a personal relationship with a complete statue as a statue. He does not bring the statue
alive in his fantasy as would a pygmalionist, and he does not use just a part of a statue as a symbolic
substitute for an entire female as would a fetishist” (49). Fetish is commonly related to both of these
conditions. Statuephilia designates love for statues and petrophilia for stones. The latter two terms
are less popular, with pygmalionism holding a strong lead and agalmatophilia having come into use
Figure 16 Google ngram4 distribution of the use of pygmalionism, statuephilia, agalmatophilia, and petrophilia in the corpus of
psychosexual interest in unusual objects, activities, or situations. The paraphilias, then, are theoretically contrasted with
its antonym: normophilia” (Hamilton 556).
4 I am aware of Google ngram search engine issues (scientific literature is overrepresented, important publications have
the same weight as unimportant, the optic character recognition or OPS is never perfect), but these shortfalls, except of
OPS issues, do not affect my results since I am interested in all available literature and especially in scientific literature
(particularly in medical, ethical and psychological).
183
All snapshots of ngram distributions are made by the author’s on November 28, 2018, except for the one above which
for “sexual responsiveness directed toward a statue or other representation especially when of one’s
own making” (‘pygmalionism’).5 The most recent revisions of Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental
Disorders (DSM-5) and International Classification of Diseases (ICD-10) both list paraphilic disorders
Some medical dictionaries point out that the terms are rarely used in medicine, especially
agalmatophilia (Farlex Partner Medical Dictionary and Medical Eponyms). As the diagram above shows,
pygmalionism is by far more popular term across arts and disciplines. Although fiction certainly
plays a big part in using the term (compare diagram 2 to diagram 1), the term was first and foremost
medical.
5 In the medical context, the Pygmalion paradigm opens questions of pygmalionism and paralysis, prosthetics (all
addressed in this project), cosmetic plastic surgery (Hawthorne’s ‘The Birthmark’ (1844)), hybridism (Hawthorne’s
‘Rappaccini’s Daughter’ (1844), C. L. Moore’s ‘No Woman Born’ (1944)), and various mental disorders such as
narcissism or psychosis (Jensen’s Gradiva (1902)).
184
Figure 17 Pygmalionism occurrences in the English language fiction.
185
Pygmalionism as a medical term was introduced to medical field in 1895 with Albert Eulenburg’s
two examples of pygmalionism in Sexuale Neuropathie. Especially influential was Havelock Ellis’s
writing on sexology in 1905. At the same time Sigmund Freud wrote his essay on the
Figure 19 The use of the term pygmalionismus in German language begins around the time when first medical discussions were
6 Freud’s essay ‘Delusion and dream in Jensen’s Gradiva’ [‘Der Wahn und die Träume in W. Jensens ‘Gradiva’’] and
Jensen’s novel were published 1907, but Freud read Gradiva in 1902 in installments in the Viennese newspaper Neue Freie
Presse.
186
Figure 20 Pygmalionism as used in English texts, introduced in Havelock Ellis’s Sexual Selection in Man from 1905.
Figure 21 Pygmalionisme as used in French texts. The diagram shows the term got into use right after Havelock Ellis’s monograph.
Agalmatophilia later became classified with objectophilia or object sexuality, a newly named sexual
orientation. Objectophilia does not designate a fetish but an attachment (love, care, attraction and
187
commitment) to inanimate objects, such as cars, bridges or pillows, and has been advocated for in
public as a sexual orientation. Together with agalmatophilia and pygmalionism, objectophilia is well
represented and explored in fiction and has been on the rise with the popularization of sex dolls in
the 1970s and sexbots in the last decade. Sexologist Amy Marsh, who conducted one of the rare
studies of object sexuality among those who identify with it, claims that these practices are “best
known as a recent pop culture phenomenon” although they have been around “a lot longer than
A look deeper into literature, folklore and myth reveals that agalmatophiliac practice has, in fact,
been around for at least three millennia. The oldest known example is from the ancient Sumer, the
earliest known civilization, where the ritual of sacred marriage was practiced, in which humans and
statues, which symbolically represented divine entities, were betrothed either as a human-divinity
couple or a divinity-divinity couple (usually Dumuzi and Inanna); Buddhist, Hindu and Greek
religions also know a similar ritual (hieros gamos in Greek) (Stol 645, 647, see more in Lapinkivi). That
is not to say that modern pygmalionism is a reflection of these practices: the sacred marriage was a
ritual performed for the sake of beliefs and not for the sake of the act itself. A goddess—for the
non-religious, a projection of the mind, for the religious, an omnipotent entity and agency—was
believed to be incorporated in a statue or a temple prostitute: the two were standing in for a higher
entity as a sort of prosthesis. Moreover, the success of the ritual resided outside the performative
relationship, in the fertility of the crops. I am not making a claim that the ritual practices involving
humanlike statues or other objects as a substitute for a spiritual entity are agalmatophiliac per se; the
point of this connection to ancient ritual practices is solely to flesh out the fact that such practices
were present in the early days of human culture, which is further reflected in literary studies through
188
When presenting unusual conditions, new technology, lesser-known ideas, or even history of a
phenomenon, science scholars frequently begin with its fictional depictions. The condition of
pygmalionism is commonly introduced with a literary example beyond the famous Ovid’s
Pygmalion. Marsh turns to classical literature, Victor Hugo’s character Quasimodo from Notre-Dame
de Paris (1831). Quasimodo is a hunchback feared by people as a sort of monster that “loved [the
bells], caressed them, talked to them, understood them;” “Claude Frollo had finally made him the
bell ringer of Notre-Dame, and to give the great bell in marriage to Quasimodo was to give Juliet to
Actual examples of pygmalionism are no less convincing than fictional ones. A lesser-known
example occurred when sculptor John Gibson fell in love with his statue, which he named The
Tinted Venus. He created his Venus in 1851 in lifelike colors, just like the ancient Greeks: “I took
the liberty to decorate it in a fashion unprecedented in modern times. I tinted the flesh like warm
ivory—scarcely red—the eyes blue, the hair blond, and the net which contains the hair golden”
(Eastlake 211). When the statue was finished, he could not part ways with it until he was forced to
“When all my labour was complete I often sat down quietly and alone before my work, meditating upon it and
consulting my own simple feelings. I endeavoured to keep myself free from self-delusion as to the effect of the
colouring. I said to myself ‘Here is a little nearer approach to life—it is therefore more impressive—yes—yes
indeed she seems an ethereal being with her blue eyes fixed on me!’ At moments I forgot that I was gazing at
my own production; there I sat before her, long and often. How was I ever to part with her!” (Eastlake 212).8
7In the medical field, the character of Quasimodo gave his name to two different diagnoses: Quasimodo complex is
“personality disorder is which there is abnormal concern about a defect in one’s physical appearance” (‘Quasimodo’),
and Quasimodo syndrome is “a clinical complex characterised by severe kyphoscoliosis, dyspnoea with associated
hypoxia and altered sleep pattern (parasomnia)” (‘Quasimodo syndrome’).
8Thomas Anstey Guthrie seemed to have been inspired by Gibson when writing The Tinted Venus (1885), possibly also
picking on the motifs from Prosper Mérimée’s La Vénus d’Ille (1835). The statue-turned-human, in a comedic tone as
189
The most known example of an agalmatophiliac or, as she identifies herself, objectúm sexual is Erika
Eiffel, an American competitive archer and a prominent advocate for object sexuality, who claims
that her relationship with Lance, her competition bow, “helped her to become a world-class archer”
(Simpson par. 1). However unusual naming an object might seem at first, let us consider that it is
not only agalmatophiliacs that give objects human names; most commonly, names are given to
everyday objects with a relational agency (cars, musical instruments, other devices in everyday use).
Eiffel also had a twenty-year long relationship with the Berlin Wall, which inspired the theater
musical production Erika’s Wall. She is not the only lover of the famous wall: Swede Eija-Riitta
the wall was brought down. As Eiffel’s name discloses, she too married a famous monument. If
such marriage was official, Eiffel might be able to obtain French citizenship and Eklöf German.
Perhaps the French cultural icon could also obtain an American citizenship and become an
American object, like Gustave Eiffel’s other famous creation, the Statue of Liberty? Apropos of the
Statue of Liberty, the statue has a long-distance lover as well: Englishwoman Amanda Whittaker,
who calls it Libby, as reported on various tabloid newspaper websites, which are most interested in
opposed to Mérimée’s drama-turned-tragedy, responds to Victorian repression of sexuality. The topic of the novella was
attractive to adaption (most notably, 1941 musical fantasy, 1921 silent film, and 1948 feature film).
190
3.1.2 Autism
Amy Marsh’s paper draws a strong correlation of object sexuality with autistic disorders.9 Likewise,
experience of the community grown around the website for objectum sexuals, founded by Eiffel,
revealed “a growing percentage of OS people are diagnosed with Asperger’s syndrome, a spectrum
of autism” (‘What is OS?’ par. 28)10 (in the latest, fifth edition of Diagnostic and Statistic Manual of
Mental Disorders published in 2013, Asperger’s syndrome has been abandoned as a separate category
from autism and classified under autism). Medical research has connected autism with liking objects
since the very discovery of the condition. In the seminal clinical study of autism, Leo Kanner’s
‘Autistic Disturbances of Affective Contact’ from 1943,11 children with autism are said to prefer
objects to other persons, particularly those that “do not change their appearance and position, that
retain their sameness and never threaten to interfere with the child’s aloneness” (246). Kanner
further links the desire for “aloneness” with an interest in objects (242)12—a connection that many
Pygmalion-like stories strongly support. In this view, people on the autistic spectrum are akin to
9 Marsh finds that among her 21 respondents from Western countries (15 biological women, 3 transgender men, 1
intersex person, and 2 biological men), 62 percent (11 biological women, all transgender men, the intersex person, but
none of the two biological men) were diagnosed or self-diagnosed with autism spectrum disorder (ASD): 5 were
diagnosed Asperger’s Syndrome, 1 was diagnosed with autism, 4 identified with Asperger’s diagnosis, and 3 “felt they
had or were told they had ‘some traits’ [of Asperger’s],” a disorder that is “under-diagnosed in adults as it did not enter
the American Psychiatric Association’s Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM-IV) until 1994”
(par. 41).
10 The object sexuality website also lists connections with other conditions, such as sexual trauma, gender dysphoria,
synesthesia, and animism. Sexual trauma is most often mentioned among scholars that write on object sexuality. Marsh
criticizes these scholars: “‘experts’ who are approached by journalists for comments on objectum sexuality have generally
assume [sic] a pathology or history of sexual trauma and/or categorize OS as a paraphilia or fetish […] without actual
data or contact with the OS community” (par. 86). Marsh suggests the most “scientifically accessible” explanation of
object sexuality as “object personification synesthesia, […] a form of synesthesia that detects personalities in objects”
(par. 46), as found by Smilek et al.
11Leo Kanner is the father of autistic studies in the USA. He started to study autism in 1938, but was not known in
Europe where, at the same time, Hans Asperger was writing on autism in Europe. Asperger was not known in the USA
until the 1980s.
12 Kanner mentions other characteristics in his first paper but talks only about the interest in objects and sameness in his
later papers.
191
agalmatophiliacs. This view affects the autistic therapy today since it commonly uses
anthropomorphic robots to help people on the spectrum gain neurotypical social skills.13
Besides that, people on the autistic spectrum are themselves sometimes described as being machine-
like (and thus object-like), based on perceptions about their social skills (absence of eye contact and
other neuro-typical forms of social connections), the way they express their feelings (supposedly
lacking empathy and not understanding their own emotions), and their speech (flat intonation, as
discussed in the previous chapter). All too frequently, people with autism are described as not being
‘fully’ human (Murray 5, Freeman Loftis 17, Richardson viii), not unlike infants. Moreover, “some of
the language and practices of the medical community can be seen as objectifying or dehumanizing”
towards them (Freeman Loftis 11). Kathleen Richardson discusses in her book, Challenging Sociality:
An Anthropology of Robots, Autism, and Attachment, roboticists drawing on the fields of disability and
difference—particularly autism—to help them create social robots “as if people with disabilities and
differences are somehow not fully human and can be used as a model of comparison” (viii). Besides
investigating this connection, she also points out that robots are considered as something in-
between human and ordinary artefacts: an object that is humanlike enough to move and perhaps
think and feel. Likewise, autism is often wrongly situated in-between such social and asocial
dispositions.
Although Kanner mentioned that autism is “inborn,” he, in fact, seemed to believe that the lack of
“warmhearted fathers and mothers” from his testing group made his patients autistic (250). Not
unlike the creators of inanimate women in the Pygmalion stories, these parents of autistic children
13It is Kanner’s finding that autistic people like objects that drives the philosophy of robot therapy for autism today in
UK, US and Europe (Richardson 12). This drive is sometimes criticized for its foundational viewing of people with
autism as “lacking in empathy or meaningful sociality” (15).
192
are described as “persons strongly preoccupied with abstractions of a scientific, literary, or artistic
nature, and limited in genuine interest in people” (ib.). In the 1960 edition of Time magazine, Kanner
went so far as to claim that mothers of autistic children “just happen to defrost enough to produce a
child” (Richardson 8). Kanner thus connected the inability to reproduce with emotional coldness,
enforcing centuries-old prejudice towards mothers of children with a disability. It is not a long
stretch from Kanner’s view of these parents to pygmalionism, in which a person unable to produce a
child naturally creates a human being in unconventional, inventive ways. This is the view that
enforces the conception of autistic people as less human—as artificial humanoids in the Pygmalion
paradigm—and puts their parents in the eccentric creator position—also in relation to the
Pygmalion paradigm. (Kanner later changed his mind about parental influence and ascribed autism
to genetics predominantly, but the ‘refrigerator mother theory,’ with the help of Bruno Bettelheim,
Pygmalionism and agalmatophilia are, indeed, much more than just a mere interest in objects: they
also assume erotic and meaningful relationship with the nonhuman. Erotic relationships with objects
are not rare (e.g. sex toys) and neither are meaningful relationships with objects as symbolical
deceased person). In a collection of meditative essays on objects, Evocative Objects: Things We Think
with, social theorist Sherry Turkle sums up a few common observations: objects in general can be
“active life presences,” are able to “catalyze self-creation,” and “bring together thought and feeling”
(9). Just like autistic traits are characteristic for every infant for a while,14 objects are companions not
14In Elizabeth Moon’s Speed of Dark, the autistic narrator comments on this claim: “All babies are born autistic, one of
our group said once. We laughed nervously. We agreed, but it was dangerously to say so. […] You might think, reading
the literature, that only neurologically damaged children do this, but in fact all infants control their exposure—by closing
their eyes, averting their gaze, or simply falling asleep when the world is too much. […] It takes a neurologically normal
193
only to objectophiliacs. However, both components, the erotic and the social, merged together in a
human-nonhuman relationship, are certainly sporadic: a sex toy does not ordinarily turn into a
(see Haslam 726). It is hard to estimate its frequency because the data is mostly “gathered from
arrest records [that] likely under-reflect the incidence of paraphilias” (Osborne and Wise 296) and
because “fetishistic individuals […] rarely seek treatment” (302). Most scholars consider it rare, yet
one legal article states that “this rubber-doll type of fixation is not uncommon, as indicated by the
descriptions—strictly sexual, labeling it as an interest in sex dolls and/or mannequins and statues
(Holmes 41-42, Holmes and Holmes 82, Cavanagh 19, Drzazga 217, Peak 209). Many older and
newer papers on paraphilias do not specifically mention it (Wakefield, Carstens and Stevens, Beech
and Harkins), but those that do consider pygmalionism “clearly abnormal in our [American] society”
(Peak 204) and rank it together with voyeurism, exhibitionism, sadism, narcissism, anti-
infant years to learn to integrate the incoming sensory data into a coherent concept of the world. While it took me much
longer—and I readily admit that my sensory processing is not normal even now—I went at the task much the same way
as any other infant. First flooded by ungated, unedited sensory input, protecting myself from sensory overload with sleep
and inattention” (39).
15Kleptomania, “stealing not for utilitarian gains” (Peak 212) – is included among these sexual deviations because it is
often considered sexual, per Peak’s words: “Women are more often affected by this condition. The sexual meaning of
194
exhibitionism, bestiality, necrophilia, and other, mostly sexual, aberrations (see Cavanagh 11,
Drzazga 217, Holmes 27, 41-42, Osborne and Wise 296). In Holmes, these aberrations are labeled as
“nuisance sex crimes,” as they “do not endanger the very existence of society, but they do cause
some discomfort and a general level of alarm and suspicion” (27). Thus, in all these interpretations
“sex offenders differ from other law violators” as only “few of these offenders (with the exception
of the most blatant or emotionally disturbed) will come to the attention of the justice system” (Peak
210). Peak, curiously, concludes his legal paper by condemning sexual offenders, in David A. Kaplan
words, as “reprobates…rapacious monsters” (Peak 212, Kaplan 48). The power of the creator and
the lover over the humanlike creation is a problematic but fundamental part of such relationships.
and like to depict humanoids as dangerous to humans, some also depict the creators or lovers of
In a study of mostly fictional lovers that fell in love with images, Maurizio Bettini comes to the same
conclusion as David A. Kaplan and Kenneth Peak: “The fact that the lover of images would be seen
as someone who has committed a grave sexual crime, a monstrous crime similar to incest, is further
confirmed by […] the fact that Pygmalion—the real one—was a king, and we have seen other
tyrannical emperors (Tiberius, Caligula, Nero) involved in similar stories [as they were] supposed to
be especially entitled to commit any sort of monstrous sexual transgression” (70). In Of the Affection of
Fathers to Their Children, Michel de Montaigne links pygmalionism with incest as well and concludes
his essay by quoting a verse from Ovid’s Metamorphoses. In earlier accounts, but not in Ovid,
Pygmalion is the king of Cyprus: “And to those furious and irregular passions that have sometimes
the theft is unconscious in kleptomania vera, but the stolen object has a symbolic significance, in that the theft may be a
substitute for sexual gratification or intimacy. Often it is during menstruation that the desire to steal occurs” (212).
195
inflamed fathers towards their own daughters, and mothers towards their own sons, the like is also
found in this other sort of parentage: witness what is related of Pygmalion who, having made the
statue of a woman of singular beauty, fell so passionately in love with this work of his, that the gods
in favour of his passion inspired it with life” (254). In the fictional story another famous tyrant,
Oedipus the King, his sexual transgression brings forth tragic deaths in his state and family. How can a
Pygmalionesque incest be considered less severe than oedipal, considering that Pygmalion knows
about the origins of his daughter-wife and Oedipus is unaware of his own?
For treatment, journalist Kaplan lists available “forms of therapy in use for sexual offenders. Most
common is group therapy, which is patterned after Alcoholics Anonymous. Advocates of this
approach contend that offenders can fool a counselor, but not so easily each other. Other forms
include chemicals to reduce sex drive, empathy training, role-playing to improve social skills, electric
shock and other negative conditioning techniques” (49). Ronald Holmes, a criminal justice professor
writing in the 1980s, suggests “some form of in-depth counseling” or, “in some cases, aversion
therapy” (42), which implies he considers it a mental disease. In a 2013 paper on paraphilias, Melissa
Hamilton, also from the field of criminal justice, adjudicates all sex crimes as a mental disease.
3.1.3.1 Marriage
Yet, among these legal and illegal practices, pygmalionism seems to be the only one that seeks
legislation which would not only make it recognized and widely accepted in a (yet unofficial)
marriage, but also socially valuable. Marriages and kinships are bound to change in the virtual age.
Marriage “has always evolved alongside changes in technology” and Marina Ashade predicts “the
adoption of sexbot technology could disentangle the association between sexual intimacy and
marriage, but also lead to higher quality marriages on the whole” (par. 5). Many see growing
196
anthropomorphization of nonhumans and dehumanization of humans as one and the same force.
For example, in 2008 California voted for farm animals to be kept less confined, but the voters also
denied homosexual couples privileges that had already been granted within the state (Waytz et al.
61). Not surprisingly, proponents of gay marriage connect it to the absurdity of prohibiting
interracial marriages while, perhaps more surprisingly, some read the opponents’ views as “open[ing]
Robot marriage vs. gay marriage parallels fall along the same argumentation as sex dolls vs. real
women. Contraceptives altered the way society viewed marriage and female sexuality: “for the first
time in history, sexual intimacy and marriage were seen to be intrinsically connected” (Ashade par.
8). After early contraception became available in 1910s, American behavioralist John B. Watson said
that men will not marry in fifty years as “we don’t want helpmates anymore, we want playmates”
(par. 6). Because women using contraception cannot get pregnant, to marry a woman for the sake of
Marina Ashade does not think that sexbots will change “the biological imperative of individuals to
want to share their lives, and raise their children, with another human being,” however, this
technology is capable of “disentangle[ing] the association of sexual intimacy and the life as a family,”
opening new forms of marriage (e.g. a household of two heterosexual married women, a
homosexual man forming a household with a heterosexual woman, etc.) (par. 14). If sexbots are
thought of as a futuristic asset, the dating technology applications are undeniably changing the
dating landscape by forming new connections outside of a person’s social circle and multiplying and
speeding up dating activities (consider the drastic change between years 2005, when, as a rule, a date
was set by meeting in person first, and 2020, when a potential date is arranged through an app).
197
Many American sexologists are tied to the science fiction movement, most prominently the founder
of the Amazing Stories and Sexology magazines, Hugo Gernsback, sometimes called The Father of
Science Fiction, for whom the Hugo award is named. A 1964 issue of the Sexology magazine, for
example, features Gernsback’s article ‘The Future: Electronic Mating’ where marriage is called “a
stupid gamble,” based on speculations on how computers will be able to help us to find the most
responses to romantic scenes, and computers will calculate all of our data into a Sex Quotient that
While a growing number of people uses date applications to meet potential partners (Tinder,
OkCupid, Hinge), some long-distance couples use virtual hug (Hugvie, Hug Shirt, Huggy Pajama)
and kiss applications (Kissenger) (see more in Lin et al.), and some lead their relationships through a
virtual world (provided by video games, for instance). McArthur and Twist call this the first wave of
digisexualities—sexual experiences that are enabled or facilitated by digital technology. The second
wave, of which the defining feature is “immersivity,” requires no human partner, or “their presence
is not essential to the experience” (McArthur and Twist 336). In other words, an actual human being
behind the screen is not absolutely needed to lead a virtual relationship; for some, an avatar will do.
Virtual boyfriends and girlfriends come cheap (Chinese Taobao, US Invisible Boyfriend) and are
designed to prepare people for a human-human relationship through romance simulation games
16Computers would collect data such as “heredity, individual taste, sex habits, education, race, color and texture of skin,
I.Q., general health, past illnesses, texture of hair, Rh blood factor, odor preferences, physiological sensitivity over
various parts of the body, musical sense, Rorschach test reactions, artistic sense, speed of various perceptions, religious
sense, color perception, physical contour, ethical sense—and perhaps a hundred other vital aspects” (Gernsback 453).
198
(Indian (retired) webpage biwihotohaisi, Japanese Voltage Romance Apps)—“simulation is often
justified as practice for real-life skills” (Turkle 287). All these services offer idealized versions of
human partners, avoiding faulty, complex humans just like Ovid’s Pygmalion did. “This is the closest
to having a real boyfriend who is just physically absent” (Chamorro-Premuzic par. 4). As long as the
lack of a body is not a deal breaker, digital surrogates (‘dirrogates’) make for, in the words of the
accommodating” (345) partners. In pornographic and video game industries dirrogates are widely in
use and have already merged with the film industry and the virtual reality genre (Dahaner 5). We are
about to wake up in a Pygmalionesque dream. Marriage is the crown of it from the very beginning
Marriage became an option for Ovid’s Pygmalion only after his statue became a woman of flesh and
blood. Pygmalions of today, however, instead of shyly praying to a higher entity for animation, ask
for marriage licenses. Marrying an object is not always a given: in 2016, British artist Tracey Emin
married a rock in her garden while Utahan Chris Sevier declined an official license to marry his
computer three times. That does not stop people to—seldom seriously and rather as a tryout—ask
objects to marry them, e.g. Alexa was proposed to by a million people in 2017 alone. Objects that
speak humanese are programmed to politely decline. It is not a given, however, that they will always
interracial marriages in the United States until 1967. Furthermore, let us keep in mind that today for
many homosexual people (who are often listed in older studies of paraphilias mentioned above)
marriage is not an option either. The later comparison is not solely mine: Sherry Turkle, a
psychologist in MIT Media Lab, was accused by her interviewer that her opposition to human-robot
relationships is just like standing against homosexual marriage—a view that would surely become
199
outdated soon (5). After all, pygmalionism and agalmatophilia have been around since the first
civilization, if we consider rituals as such, or for centuries if we exclude religious practices. If they
become more common and prominent, conveniently categorized under sexuality types, society’s
views will surely change and there will be no more talk of paraphilias and law offenses.
As opposed to most legal literature (with the exception of the obscure Drzazga’s book), medical
literature shows more awareness of the history of pygmalionism from the very beginning. In 1905,
Havelock Ellis recognized that attraction to a statue has been documented in ancient cultures and
gives examples from Lucian, Aelian and Athaneus, as well as examples from a recent newspaper. His
definition—“erotomania founded on the sense of vision and closely related to the allurement of
beauty” (188) —acknowledges that the galatea is not simply a sex toy. Ellis understands that
pygmalionism is not just a sexual anomaly but also a concept for exploring humanness alongside
human artistic imagination. Ellis is not the first physician to discuss it from a medical perspective:
his example—a performance of a prostitute who is asked to assume the part of a statue that
brothels as recounted by a former police chief in Paris (107). The first seems to be Richard Freiherr
von Krafft-Ebing, however, who described a few cases already in 1886 in one of the first texts on
sexual pathology but did not name it (as pygmalionism, fetishism or any other term) or discuss it
With no exceptions, medical examples consider pygmalionism in relation to statues and objects only,
mostly using literary examples which allow for an extension to other kinds of entities. As everyone
200
else does when introducing pygmalionism (with the exception of law scholars who only mention
Ovid’s Pygmalion), Ellis and Eulenburg present it with a literary example or analogy. Ellis uses
Heinrich Heine’s Florentine Nights, and parallels the author with the character of a boy who was in
love with a statue: “as this book appears to be largely autobiographical, the incident might have been
founded on a fact” (188). Eulenburg’s second example of pygmalionism compares its lupanar
pygmalion, “einem ganz decrepiden Greise,” with Paris from Greek mythology. “Der neumodische
Preisrichter” admires statues of goddesses Juno, Minerva and Venus and gives them francs instead
of an apple, choosing Venus (108). Sigmund Freud, a neurologist like Eulenburg, writes a whole
essay on a fictional Pygmalionesque protagonist and diagnoses him with psychosis or neurosis,
respectively. The mere fact that psychoanalysis was interested in pygmalionism shows that the
disorder was considered mental from early on. Early investigators before Freud rank pygmalionism
with bestiality, necrophilia, sadism, etc., and, as we have seen, it is still classified among similar
paraphilias today. No treatment is suggested, but practice is clearly condemned by Ellis: “it is the
ignorant and uncultured who feel the indecency of statues and thus betray their sense of the sexual
appeal of such objects” (188). He does not, however, think that this judgment applies to ancient
Greece because their statues looked more human (!): “We have to remember that in Greece statues
played a very prominent part in life, and also that they were tinted, and thus more lifelike than with
us” (188).17 With this distinction Ellis draws a line—akin to the uncanny valley—between wishful
17Shawn O’Bryhim suggests that Greeks invented accounts of agalmatophilia for an economic purpose: “to draw
tourists to works of art whose erotic qualities were so compelling that they allegedly made aristocrats lose their self-
control and behave in a way that resulted in infamy—or even death” (428).
201
Medical literature (followed by social sciences) labels pygmalionism or agalmatophilia with either a
more general term of fetishism, without explicitly mentioning humanlike objects but rather more
common fetishes, such as solely body parts, or with a term paraphilia NOS [not otherwise specified]
that does “not inherently involve suffering, humiliation, or nonconsenting persons” (Osborne and
Wise 306). Older medical studies (among other things, they list homosexuality under paraphilias)
suggest “aversion therapy” for “many of the minor deviances, such as fetishism, [as they] lend
psychotherapy combined with drugs (733). Studies of paraphilias occur more often in the last ten
years, but the treatment still follows the psychological or the pharmaceutical route from the older
studies, usually involving both (Osborne and Wise 314). The etiology of the paraphilias is yet
unknown but widely speculated.18 Besides the fact that the discussed cultures are predominantly
Western, a culture-sensitive approach is often disregarded, although culture predates the conceptions
of paraphilias (see more in Bhugra et al.). The authoritative Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental
Disorders (DSM-5) by the American Psychiatric Association presents criteria for paraphilia as a
repetitive, intrusive and at least six-months long behavior (685). DSM-5 or ISD-10 do not
specifically mention pygmalionism or agalmatophilia (up to this date, January 2020), which is a
telling fact. Perhaps the issue is in the terminology itself (too literary, too detailed?). The two
conditions fit the description of a fetishistic disorder in DSM-5 as an interest in nonliving objects or
body parts and is listed among the eight most common and potentially harmful paraphilias. In ICD-
10, they fit the description of a paraphilic disorder involving non-consenting individuals.
18Psychoanalysis explains fetishism as coming from “unconscious fears and a sense of inadequacy related to early
childhood experience” (Osborne and Wise 307). Other theories speculate that paraphilias originate in “sexual abuse,
family dysfunction, behavior problems,” even if some studies have disproved these findings (309), from childhood
conditioning (309), deviant arousal (310), courtship disorder (311), personality (311), or biology (312).
202
Yet, there are many faults in categorizing paraphilias in psychiatric literature. Christian C. Joyal
criticizes the scholarly approach to paraphilias in a 2018 commentary by showing that, first,
paraphilias are not necessarily that unusual (he argues that most could be classified “normophilic”);
second, the definition of paraphilia “derives more from historical, social, cultural, and religious
factors than medical or scientific evidences” (1378) and is in itself tautological (1379); third, “non-
normophilic” interests do not necessarily reveal a mental disorder (more research is needed); and
fourth, the criteria we have now (most prominently in DSM-5) provide “no instrument to evaluate
them” (1378). As a token of changing conceptions of paraphilias, in 2016 the Working Group on
Sexual Disorders and Sexual Health removed fetishism, masochism, sadism and transvestism from
paraphilias, stating: “The regulation of private behaviour without health consequences to the
individual or to others may be considered in different societies to be a matter for criminal laws,
religious proscription, or public morality, but is not a legitimate focus of public health or of health
classification” (212). This only shows the issue needs to be addressed from a fresh perspective, as
Literature could help in researching the subject by pointing out how different sexual orientations and
identities unfold, inform character, impact relationships, and display values, among other things. For
example, medical literature from Krafft-Ebing up until DSM-5 points out that such disorders are
nearly exclusively reported in males.19 In literature, the latter finding—repeated ever since medicine
described these disorders—is practically a given. The only exception to this unwritten rule is when
fiction explores new ways of thinking, as in exploring a sporadic situation where a woman is the
19Havelock Ellis, who puts pygmalionism under the visual section of his book rather than under touch, smell or hearing,
believes this is because “[b]eauty in the human species is, above all, a feminine attribute, making its appeal to men” (189)
while “[w]omen admire a man’s strength rather than his beauty” (191).
203
creator of an artificial man. Literature has therefore recognized various aspects of this disorder way
before science did, while also addressing the complexities and ramifications of such a condition.
Besides, literary examples of private practices, such as agalmatophilia or living with any kind of
paralysis, can point out the complexity of these cases by introducing different points of view,
prominent features of science fiction—and thus introducing new ways of addressing these
conditions. It is no wonder then that scientific descriptions of paraphilias, paralysis, and other
medical conditions begin with literary examples (see Marsh, Laureys et al., Kondziella, etc.).
As this short examination of pygmalionism as a diagnosis shows, literature plays a central role in
exploring love for objects from the earliest times on, which is rendered already by the very term
pygmalionism. Literary depictions are largely left to represent Pygmalionesque symptoms and
circumstances. They also reveal related questions, such as: Why do we want to create humans
artificially? Why do we seek solace with humanlike objects? How is human love different from a
human-nonhuman relationship? It is our current reality, not fiction, that demands us to re-think
pygmalionism from a social, medical and legal perspective. Yet, to assess the condition, ask the right
questions and search for the answers, we can gain insight from the stories.
The Pygmalionesque idea of a human man in love with a nonhuman woman was preserved in
ancient stories across a great variety of cultures. Although Greek mythology provided the most
influential example of Ovid’s Pygmalion (8 AD), I found some (largely disregarded) Western
language translations of Pygmalion-like tales among Native African tribes Bella Coola (McIlwraith
356-357, Boas 745), Tsimshian (Boas 744-745), Kwakiutl and Nootka (Boas 745), and a separate
204
story in Tlingit (Swinton 181-182, Boas 746); two tales among North African Kabyle people
(Frobenius 129-133 and 177-192); and one tale in two versions, circulating on the Silk Road in early
Medieval Ages all the way from India to China (Sanskrit version in Hofinger 185-187 after Dutt 166-
168, also in Pinault 253; Degener 47-48; Tibetan version in Schiefner 17-18, also in Davids 361-362;
Chinese versions in Chavannes 2: 12-13 and Dschi 323-324; Tocharian version in Sieg 8-13, Lane
33-53, Malzahn A5-A9, and Pinault 254-267). Folk traditions also carry this myth worldwide, for
instance, the motif is prominent in an Estonian folk ballad Kuldnaine (Goldwife) (Kurrik 108-111),
which is believed to have originated around 1200 AD (Kurrik 12). I argue that the presence of this
motif in such a variety of unconnected cultures lends support to the archetypal status of the
Pygmalion myth narrative. The dominance of the Pygmalion myth in Western literatures was one of
the reasons this archetype was disregarded in non-European cultures. (Admittedly, I also build on
European conceptions of the myth and use Greek terminology for designating pygmalionism and
agalmatophilia).
Furthermore, I propose a new typology of the Pygmalion paradigm that presents across cultures in
two dominant types. The usual view on the Pygmalion paradigm is shifted from the diachronic to
the typological, setting aside the spatial and chronological origins of the text to focus on how the
main motifs play out in the text itself. The two types are especially relevant to this chapter because
they are primarily distinguished by pygmalionism and agalmatophilia. The types are hence named the
pygmalionsque type, where the creator is also the lover of the inanimate creation and thus aware of
its inanimate status, and the petrophiliac type, where the creator is a separate character from the
lover and can delude the lover into thinking that the humanoid is a real human. This distinction is
In the pygmalionsque type, such as Ovid’s poem of Pygmalion, the lover and the creator are one and
205
the same character. The metamorphosis is granted in this type, followed by a successful relationship
of the human man and humanoid woman. At least two of the three criteria need to be fulfilled to
categorize the story into this type. In newer works, which predominantly deal with scientific creation
as opposed to artistic creation in earlier works, the creators of the artificial woman are often
multiple, such as companies, presided over by the eccentric creator-scientist (e.g. both Blade Runner
films). The lover is not always one of them but might sometimes help the artificial woman to
develop into (more of) a human through their romantic relationship (e.g. film Her).20
In the petrophiliac type, such as E. T. A. Hoffmann’s short story Der Sandmann, the lover’s delusion
about the artificial woman he loves might be severe. This type not only leads to broken hearts but
also broken minds and bodies, be it human, nonhuman, or both. Ultimately, the relationship in this
type is bound to fail because the artificial woman never becomes human or human enough. (The
line between these two concepts will be explored in the following parts of this chapter in the context
20 Examples of the Pygmalionesque type are Ovid’s Pygmalion, André-François Boureau-Deslandes’s Pigmalion ou
la statue animée (1741), J. J. Rousseau’s Pygmalion, scène lyrique (1762), Mme de Stäel’s Le Mannequin (1811), and
Champfleury’s L'homme aux figures de cire (1849), William Hazlitt’s Liber Amoris; or, the new Pygmalion (1894), Ventura
García-Calderón’s ‘La leyenda de Pigmalión’ (1935), Tawfiq al-Hakim’s Pygmalion (1942), most of which thematize the
relation between life and art. The relation between life and science becomes dominant in the twentieth century with
science fiction texts like Lester del Rey’s ‘Helen O’Loy’ (1938) and more recent works, many of which exist as a text and
as a film: The Stepford Wives (Byran Forbes’s 1975 and Frank Oz’s 2004 adaptation), based on Ira Levin’s 1972 novel;
Ridley Scott’s 1982 Blade Runner, based on Philip K. Dick’s 1968 novel Do Androids Dream of Electric Sheep?; Michael
Gottlieb’s Mannequin (1987); Andrew Niccol’s Gattaca (1997) and S1m0ne (2002); and Lazar Bodroža’s 2018 A.I. Rising,
based on Zoran Nešković’s short story ‘Predveče se nikako ne može...’ (1988). Film as a medium thematized the
Pygmalion myth from its very beginnings, such as with Georges Méliès’s Pygmalion et Galathée (1898), and is still very
much interested in the topic. Dušan Makavejev’s early short film Spomenicima ne treba verovati (1958) parodizes object
sexuality through a political satire. Famous G. B. Shaw’s Pygmalion (1912) is also of this type. This explains why audience
demanded so adamantly Eliza and Higgins to end up together while Shaw wanted to break the cliché of pairing the
maker and his creation: this is how the film My Fair Lady (1964) is ended whereas the play ends of a petrophiliac note
with Eliza marrying Freddy. Casting human Eliza as a galatea, Shaw followed the recently invented tradition of
educational pygmalionsque texts, in which a young woman of a lower class (or somehow lower value) is educated by her
paternal mentoring figure, starting with Rétif de la Bretonne’s Le nouveau Pygmalion (1870), W. S. Gilbert’s Pygmalion and
Galatea (1871), Henry James’s Watch and Ward (1871). Folkloristic motifs from the Tlingit tale and the second Kabyle tale
(Frobenius 177-192) fall under this category, too.
206
of autonomy and personhood.)21
Arguably, works where the artificial woman does not become flesh but is completely human in mind
(intelligence, morals) and feelings (emotions, empathy) also fit this type. Such examples are Richard
Powers’s Galatea 2.2 (1995) and Spike Jonze’s film Her (2013), where the womanlike artificial
intelligence systems achieve the level of humanness compared to a bodiless or rather completely
paralyzed human. Such Pygmalionesque relationships are therefore possible only if the artificial
entity is as humanlike as it gets, passing for a human, or actually becomes one. If the artificial
woman is unlike a human, either too little or too much, the relationship does not work. (As testified
in film Her, Theodore’s AI bodiless girlfriend Samantha ends the relationship with Theodore once
she turns from a humanlike entity into a superhuman AI.) Establishing the difference between
humanlike entities that managed to penetrate the realm of humanness and contrasting them to the
entities that do not achieve this goal is one of the reasons this typology is useful. The typology and
these fictional works can help us not only to address ethical issues that rise with new computational
technologies and biotechnologies but also draw the impossible but indispensable line of what is
There are many variations of both types, where one component of the Pygmalion myth is missing,
for instance, the romantic relation between one human and the artificial woman (in C. L. Moore’s
1944 ‘No Woman Born,’ Deidre does not have one suitor but an audience that adores her; the gist
21Examples of the petrophiliac type, in which the creator is separate from the lover, are E. T. A. Hoffmann’s ‘Der
Sandmann’ (1816), Thomas Anstey Guthrie’s The Tinted Venus (1898), Jacinto Grau’s play El señor de Pigmalión (1921),
Prosper Mérimée’s ‘La Vénus d’Ille’ (1937), Villiers de l’Isle-Adam L’Éve future (1886), Wilhelm Jensen’s Gradiva (1907),
Jan Wolkers’s Kort Amerikaans (1962), Anne McCaffrey’s ‘The Ship Who Sang’ (1969), James Tiptree Jr.’s ‘The Girl Who
Was Plugged In’ (1974), Dušan Makavejev’s short film Antonijevo razbijeno ogledalo (1947), Tong Enzheng’s ‘The Death of
the World’s First Robot’ (1982), Craig Gillespie’s film Lars and the Real Girl (2007), and Alex Garland’s film Ex Machina
(2015). Folkloristic motifs from the ancient Silk Road tale, the first Kabyle tale (Frobenius 129-133), and Tsimshian and
Bella Coola Native American tale fall under this type.
207
of the short story is very similar to a Pygmalionesque 2002 film Simone), or where the focus is on one
of the aspects of the myth (e.g., the woman’s perfection in Nathaniel Hawthorne’s 1844 ‘The
Birthmark’). There are also many examples of the so-called reverse Pygmalion, where a human
woman is turned into a nonhuman scientific creation (Hawthorne’s 1844 ‘Rappaccini’s Daughter’) or
artistic creation (E. A. Poe’s 1942 ‘The Oval Portrait;’ related is also Oscar Wilde’s 1980 Picture of
Dorian Gray). Turning humans, especially women, into stone is a common motif in folk traditions,
frequently adapted by some prominent authors: an ancient Greek story of Anaxarete and Iphis
(Bettini 150), a tale of King Midas’s golden touch, adapted by Nathaniel Hawthorne (‘The Golden
Touch,’ 1843), Hawthorne’s ‘Drawne’s Wooden Image’ (1943), and Louisa May Alcott’s A Marble
Woman, or The Mysterious Model (1965), and a ballad of Katalena in Slovenian folk tradition, adapted
A rare version of the reverse Pygmalion is a simple gender swap between the typically male creator
and the typically female creation,22 for example, in Gaston Leroux’s diptych novels La Poupée
Sanglante: La Sublime Aventure de Bénédict Masson and Le Machine à Assassiner: Gabriel (both 1923), the
maker’s daughter helps him to create the mask for the male automaton and falls in love with him.
More common than a woman being the creator of a barely human man like is the gender swap
between the lovers, a human woman and a barely human man. For instance, in Roald Dahl’s short
story ‘William and Mary’ (1959), William dies and lives on only in the form of his brain. In Tong
Enzheng’s ‘The Death of the World’s First Robot’ ( , written in 1982 and
based on an account from Liezi ( ) from the fifth century BC), the robot is male. Another
22 I assume these versions are rare predominantly due to the vulnerability factor of the created: the created needs to be
someone who is dependent, such as a child or a woman, since a vulnerable entity is easier to subjugate and own, the way
slaves were and robots are considered to be owned.
208
example would be Niccol’s Gattaca where a genetically inferior man transcends to the realm of
(super) humans. The main change here is not only the typical change of genders, but rather fact that
in the dystopian world of Gattaca a genetically engineered (and thus partly human-made) man is
considered more of a human than naturally conceived man. All of these stories fit the main two
types but have a particular twist on one of the typical components. There are, furthermore, a lot of
poetry, opera and ballet, and visual art works based on the myth or its reinterpretations. Besides,
many other works play with the Pygmalion-like motifs, even if they do not deal with them
thematically.23
I argue that both types of the Pygmalion paradigm are dominant across cultures, including Ovidian
influences that would presumably yield only the Pygmalionesque type but have been fruitful in both
types. Many authors, including Ovid, created more than one work on this topic (E. T. A. Hoffmann,
Nathaniel Hawthorne, G. B. Shaw, Gustave Leroux, Karl Čapek, Bruno Schulz, Ira Levin, Andrew
Niccol, Alex Garland…), which is not surprising considering that creation of a humanlike being is
In the Balkans in the second half of the twentieth century, with Yugoslavia and what is now Serbia
at the forefront of this short examination, the Serbian film director Dušan Makavejev stands out not
only with his quality and enfant terrible avant-gardism but also with his interest in pygmalionism. At
23Among countless others works, the motif is raised in Euripides’s Alcestis (438 BC) by Admetus right before Alcestis
gives her life for him, in James Joyce’s A Portrait of an Artist as a Young Man (1904) by Lynch’s admiration of a statue, in
Ulysses (1928) by Bloom’s admiration of statues in a museum and Molly’s soliloquy, in Lawrence Durrell’s Justine (1952)
through Capodistria’s father, and in Niobe’s episode in Günter Grass’s Die Blechtrommel (1959).
209
the very start of his career in the 1950s, he produced four short silent amateur films that are rather
unknown today. Two of these short films, which raised Makavejev into national and international
visibility, deal with the Pygmalionesque theme: Antonijevo razbijeno ogledalo [Anthony’s Broken Mirror]
(1957) and Spomenicima ne treba verovati [Don’t Believe in Monuments] (1958). Antonijevo razbijeno ogledalo
presents a man (a lonely man, per Rajko Munitić (41)), a street magician, who falls in love with a
mannequin in the display window of a store. As a result of his infatuation, he sees her move and
return his affection, only to realize that in an attempt to abduct her from the store he broke the
window and his beloved mannequin. Long opening scene, which shows the magician and children
playing with marbles, warns about the nature of illusion. The lover succumbed to the dreamy
surrealist elements of the film and is oblivious to such warnings: he accidentally kills a bunny when
Spomenicima ne treba verovati presents a woman who flirts and tries to seduce a statue of a man in a
park. When she realizes her efforts will bear no fruit, she turns immobile and statuesque. Casting a
woman as the lover is quite a revolutionary move in itself and might be related to the broader social
commentary of the film. The film was the first of many Makavejev’s works that were censored and it
was quickly understood by the regime to be casting shadow on socialist politics that use self-
aggrandizing monuments as political tools (Vidan 63). An erotic game performed on a notable
public object brings down “the monumentality of the monument […] posing a potential threat to a
system in which human needs are subordinated to hierarchies dictated from above” (64). Bringing in
the more recent perspective of the defenders of sex robots rights, having no agency of their own,
monuments cannot speak for themselves and can easily be abused and misrepresented, despite
playing a role in the political order that raised them. This absence of power in statues and the
overwhelming power of their creators and lovers is accentuated in watching Makavejev’s film after
210
the #MeToo movement revolution, since the historical socio-political topic of the systematic abuse
Ethical considerations about potential abuse of humanlike entities with no agency are also a
prominent theme in another Pygmalionesque story from Serbia: Zoran Nešković’s short story
‘Predveče se nikako ne može…’, which was published in the second, extended edition of Serbian
science fiction anthology Tamni vilajet: antologija znanstvene fantastike [The Dark Vilayet: An Anthology of
Science Fiction] in 1989. The short story is not translated but was adapted by Dimitrije Vojnov into a
2018 film Ederlezi Rising that used English as the main language. The story and the film feature a
cosmonaut who is sent on a space mission with a female android that he falls in love with and
attempts to make completely human. After multiple sexual encounters, including rape scenarios, the
cosmonaut feels guilty about being given complete authority and agency over this relationship. His
attempt to save the android from following his commands and getting rid of the overriding program
is successful, however, android, finally autonomous, reveals that she finds him repulsive. I have yet
to find Western works written before 1988 that deal with the ethics in sexual relationships between
human and nonhuman entities with that much attention as these three Serbian works. These three
works are also all the Serbian works on pygmalionism I was able to discover; apart from the many
Marko Živković suggests in the chapter of his 2011 monograph, Serbian Dreambook: National
Imaginary in the Time of Milošević, that the barbaric and uncivilized Balkans experience Reverse
Pygmalion in literature and film. The Reverse Pygmalion situation takes place right after president
Tito’s death in 1980, per Živković, due to the patronizing, civilized, and female gaze of the West.
The three attributed all pertain to Živković’s argumentation. First, I would like to confirm the first
211
two attributes of the gaze—patronizing and civilized—with a single anecdotic evidence that reveals a
wider, widely attested, stereotype of the Balkans and particularly Serbians. When Susan Sontag
visited Sarajevo during the war and put on a theater play together with the besieged Sarajevian
actors, her fame put them on the front pages of main Western newspapers. Poet Goran Simić said:
“We hoped that people in the outside world would learn about us. People in the West had the
The third attribute—female gaze—is unusual, however. As mentioned above, the Pygmalion
paradigm almost never attests to having a woman as a creator, mentor, or even lover of an
uncultured man. Živković’s idea follows the opposite belief (which is unfortunately not further
explored by Živković) that women in general “tend to be bearers of ‘civilization’ among the
relatively ‘uncivilized’” Balkan men. Thus, as opposed to cultured Western men who educate their
opposites (think of Higgins and Eliza in Shaw’s 1913 Pygmalion, Roger Lawrence and Nora Lambert
in Henry James’s 1871 Watch and Ward, or a 1983 British film Educating Rita), Balkan men are on par
with Eliza, Nora, and Rita: untamed and uncultivated. In a reverse situation from a typical
educational Pygmalion-like story, in the Balkans, women “f[a]ll for the brutal and manly vitality of
the barbarian” and men “f[a]ll for her culture” (106). Živković examines examples of prominent
Serbian feature and documentary films from the 1980s to 2000s,24 a difficult time of the Yugoslavian
disintegration that led to the Yugoslav Wars in the 1990s. His examination leads to the conclusion
that “[t]he stories of such pairings tend to end tragically with the suicide or utter ruin of the male,
24Rajko Grlić’s Samo jednom se ljubi (Melody Haunts My Reverie, 1981), Srđan Karanović’s Nešto izmedju (Something In-Between,
1983), Miroslav Lekić’s Bolje od bekstva (Better Than Escape, 1993), Tone Bringa’s documentary We Are All Neighbors (1992),
a Serbian feature film that documented travails of UN sanctions and hyperinflation Dnevnik uvreda 1993 (A Diary of
Insults, 1994), Srdjan Dragojević’s Lepa sela lepo gore (Pretty Village, Pretty Flame, 1996) and Rane (Wounds, 1998), Slobodan
Skerlić’s Do koske (Rage, 1997), and Goran Marković’s Kordon (The Cordon, 2002).
212
signaling the incompatibility of the two worlds, but the product of this ill-fated union remains in the
woman’s womb—a new generation that will grow up cultivated by their mothers only to perish in
another Balkan apocalypse and repeat the same pattern” (ib.). Petrophiliac in its nature, any unlikely
Živković’s argument is valid in the light of Balkan self-reflection compared to the West, especially
considering its falling political regimes and destructive wars. His argumentation, however, does not
oppose my view on the typology of the Pygmalion paradigm. In fact, having the typology in place to
compare it to Serbian works before the disintegration of Yugoslavia (when the typology is typical)
and during the disintegration and wars (when the typology makes a reverse stance when it comes to
female-male roles) reveals how the Pygmalionesque trope was reinvented by a plethora of film
authors to capture the historical circumstances, and in particular the undergoing political crisis, on
Literature proves to be an asset in dealing with technological issues of most current and promising
technologies at a given time.25 It can identify, for example, four common traits that have run deep in
pygmalionism since its very beginning: an element of loneliness and isolation, a universal human
feature to connect with a human(like) entity, a promethean quest for the power of creation, and
exploitative power over anything vulnerable. These traits could help in leading new ways in
25At the moment, discoveries most influential to the modern man come from the fields of biotechnology (stem cells,
gene editing), artificial intelligence (revolutionizing most fields with AI, new discoveries with neural networks, GAN
technology that enables AI to imagine, etc.), speech synthetizing and creative writing (nonhuman entities becoming
better in language and in translation), 3-D printing (of most materials), and sensing city technology (basically digitalizing
a neighborhood)—all technologies relevant to pygmalionism.
213
technologizing the world and predicting possible obstacles. A main purpose of technology has
always been to make our lives easier, which is why the twentieth- and twenty-first-century views on
pygmalionism bring to the fore psychological and therapeutic benefits of the practice.
Let us begin with the first trait: all Pygmalion-like stories demand an element of loneliness, be it a
fallout with the society or an actual physical isolation. This sentiment can of course be felt when
surrounded with people; loneliness is an emotional response to an unwanted isolation, growing from
human need for affiliation with others. Carl Jung’s quote on loneliness brings forth not the physical
but psychical isolation as reflected in communication with other beings and the world: “Loneliness
does not come from being alone, but from being unable to communicate the things that seem
important” (356). As Sherry Turkle puts it, “loneliness is a failed solitude”—“to experience solitude
you must be able to summon yourself by yourself” (288). Pygmalions are all isolated from society,
however, their isolations differ in nature and purpose: Petrarch’s adoration of the beloved requires
him to be alone by definition (Bettini 5), Ovid’s Pygmalion withdraws from human women due to
his disappointment over them, and Nešković’s cosmonaut is the only human on a space mission,
which is why he is given a nonhuman companion. The latter example is quite exceptional, as
fictional writing on pygmalionism rejects loneliness per principle: pygmalions choose solitude in
order to be with their beloved. The question about the cause of the growing number of real-world
modern pygmalions is essentially a matter of loneliness vs. solitude: is their condition a result of
loneliness and craving for intimacy or is their condition a sexual orientation that seeks solitude from
human beings and company of nonhumans and is thus not prompted by external circumstances?
Adam Waytz et al. argue that “extreme cases” of a person falling in love with an object are
prompted by chronical loneliness as those who are “chronically lonely are more likely than those
who are chronically connected to anthropomorphize technological gadgets” (59). Another reason
214
for anthropomorphism is effectance, “the basic motivation to be a competent social agent” (ib.):
seeing a familiar concept in a non-familiar agent makes it more comprehensible. Both reasons for
anthropomorphizing nonhumans shed light on why the market for social robots is so big, although
we are in the early days of creating (incredibly complicated and expensive) full-body humanoids, and
why the creators of nonhuman socialites dedicate their work to this pursuit in the first place—
instead of, for example, creating robots that would alleviate the burden of human caretakers (e.g.
lifting up a patient, prepare meals, etc.).26 Then again, robots do not need to look human for us to
Highly technological societies of today, such as most Western and some East Asian societies, have
been shown to increasingly keep people socially, emotionally and physically isolated from each other.
In a study that asked the general public if technology is good for humankind or not, “just 8% of US
adults [said they] believe technology has had a negative effect on our lives, primarily because they
believe it has led to a breakdown of communication and human interaction (41% of this group)”
(Twist and McArthur 250). On the one hand, social media advertisement is all about connecting
people and, on the other hand, these services are uncannily similar to the world in E. M. Forster’s
‘The Machine Stops’ (1909), in which every individual inhabits an isolated cabin, connected to the
rest of humanity through instant messages and conference videos, highly controlled by a handful of
people in power. An insignificant number of people today lead a solitary life akin to Forster’s
depiction: Japan deals with close to a million cases of acute social withdrawal called hikikomori, “a
social category that emerged in the 1990s” (Nast 764). This withdrawal is typical for young men who
26 Sherry Turkle writes of technology as prosthesis and imagines technology designed after biomimicry in order to solve
issues that are—mistakenly—thought to be assessed with complex, personalized but person-less, humanoids, instead of
simpler and cheaper humanoid technological parts. If robotic helpers “had been able to do the grunt work, there might
have been more time for human nurses to take care of the more personal and emotional things. […] Why not imagine a
machine that is an extension of the body of one human trying to care lovingly for another? Why not build robotic arms,
supported by hydraulic power, into which people could slip their own arms, enhancing their strength?” (288-89).
215
retreated to bedrooms of a parental home (thus still playing the role of children) and “commonly
enjoy the company of human-sized female pillow dolls (dakimakura) and play with [ball jointed
dolls]” (Nast 765). As Turkle puts it: “As we live the flowering of connectivity culture, we dream of
USA deals with doubled rates of loneliness not only among the elder population but also
increasingly among young adults (Cigna). Besides stress and obesity, loneliness has been called a
health epidemic of the twenty-first century by some (Olds and Schwartz, Peate, Rimmer, Turkle)—a
particularly alarming finding since many studies showed that chronic loneliness affects morbidity and
mortality (Committee; Patterson and Veenstra 181, Hold-Lunstad et al., Rubin par. 7). Like the USA,
Japan deals with increasing rates of loneliness due to the increasing elderly population, which is
especially vulnerable due to its proneness to sickness as well as the fact that the elderly tend to know
more dead people than alive. Japanese term kodokushi was coined in the 1980s and designates a
lonely death—dying alone and not being discovered for a long period of time (see Onishi).
Turkle argues that roboticists present us a quandary that “threatens to become no quandary at all
because we come to accept its framing” (289)—“the idea that as our population ages, we simply
won’t have enough people to take care of our human needs, and so, as a companion, a sociable
robot is ‘better than nothing’” (281). With the population ageing, social robots are already being put
into nursing homes for company with positive results, from robot baby seals freely available on the
market (see Marx) to humanlike robots, such as Zora (Satariano et al., see also Adler). The role of
pygmalionism here is clear: humans are social beings and are not equipped to live in isolation. This is
why pygmalionism and agalmatophilia cannot (solely) be fetishes, as considered by sociologists and
some medical researchers. Sex dolls such as dames de voyage, artificial dolls that accompanied sailors at
216
sea in the seventeenth century (Dahaner 3), have since become more complex and humanlike, taking
over other roles of performing a human being. Brothels already feature lifelike dolls in lieu of human
prostitutes (and not in order to help alleviate human prostitution or sex trafficking (Nast 774,
Torjesen ‘Sixty’ 3353)). People identifying as digisexual, i.e. “people whose primary sexual identity
comes through the use of technology” (McArthur and Twist 1), are bound to grow with radical new
sexual technology. The notion of sexual orientation is expanding rapidly, from object sexuals to
digisexuals and further, bringing the Pygmalion myth along with and without its baggage.
A true modern Pygmalion of the twenty-first century is an artificial intelligence engineer, such as
Zheng Jiajia, a Chinese man who “decided to commit after failing to find a human spouse”—there
are, after all, “113.5 men for every 100 women in China” (Haas par. 6) —and “‘married’ a robot he
built himself” (par. 1-2). Some Japanese men, apart from hikikomori, are reported to live with dolls as
if they were real women—a better version of them, that is. The phenomenon is pure pygmalionism:
they consider real women “cold-hearted,” “selfish” and “demanding,” while their dolls are a solace
and a source of happiness. Although these men are aware that the dolls are not human, they treat
them as such, just like Ovid’s Pygmalion: “I’d never cheat on her, even with a prostitute, because to
me she’s human” (‘Silicone,’ par. 27). An online international community of iDollators “who view
their dolls not merely as sex toys but as life partners” is adamant: their relationships with dolls are
just as meaningful as those with humans (Dahaner 9-10); object sexuals claim likewise. Many issues
in relation to suicide, isolation and withdrawal are resolved with this artificial company. As a sort of
escapism, or “(maternal) comfort of the posthuman,” as Heidi Nast calls it (758), pygmalionism
again proves out to be a mental tool, like in the native American stories in which the wooden doll
helps a widower coping with his loss (Swinton 181-182, Boas 744-745 and 746), or in Nešković’s
217
short story, where the android is sent into space together with the cosmonaut to keep him company,
hence keeping him sane from boredom, anxiety, stress and other human problems.27
Assuming that humans keep responding to the humanlike as if it was human, or sometimes even
better than if it was human,28 therapeutic uses of humanlike forms will surely abound. The main
problem in using humanoids for company or therapy is that the approach is still quite new. There
are also obvious ethical impediments in the use of, say, sexbots: “[A]ccepting the production of
these sex robots, not to mention child-like dolls, is unethical because it legitimizes the objectification
of human beings, at least on a representational (‘fictional’) level,” when “there is no shared discourse
regarding the important social, clinical, and ethical concerns raised by such a business, which should
psychology, and bioethics” (Facchin et al. 3790). Besides above-mentioned Sherry Turkle and Ingrid
Torjesen, Kathleen Richardson is one of the main opponents of sexbots and links them with human
prostitution, while Neil McArthur, John Dahaner, Markie Twist and David Levy argue that the
sexbots’ effects will be overall positive. All these scholars are aware, however, that sexbots are surely
coming and that “an organized approach against the development of sex robots is necessary” if we
27As new research shows, foreign physicals conditions of space change human DNA physically (e.g. gene expression of
an cosmonaut in space changed relative to that of his identical twin who stayed on Earth (see Mason et al., Edwards and
Abadie)) and the extreme isolation, boredom and simultaneously the difficulty of the job, changes them mentally. Up to
today, American space medicine (in contrast to Russians, who have done much longer space missions) has “done
surprisingly little research into the psychological problems that might occur on [long missions in space],” although
“psychological issues [are] the ‘most difficult’ of the challenges cosmonauts face on the long missions” (Cooper 37).
28It was shown that in general humans trust basic humanlike machines (e.g. a virtual psychiatrist) over humans
(Bohannon 251). Computer scientist and psychologist Jonathan Gratch explains that “we turn to computers for solace”
because we “engage in less of what’s called impression management” when communicating with them (Shulevitz par.
24).
218
are to prevent them (Campaign, also in Dahaner et al. 47). What does this mean for our future
society? How should we respond when sex conflates with love and care?
For one, we can learn from the reception of object sexuals. Marsh emphasizes that “among
objectum sexuals lack of acceptance by society is the biggest problem, followed closely by human
abuse of beloved objects and the inability to be publicly affectionate with beloved objects” (par. 88).
Objectum sexuals are aware of the strangeness of their love for objects, but claim it is no different
than love for people: “We are not freaks, nor are we fetishists. Our lovers are living beings that
communicate, and love us back. Contrary to popular belief, machines and other objects do have
souls. This is what our relationships are based off of, and they’re not entirely sexual” (Marsh par.
44). Human societies have long attributed personality to objects (animalism) or gods (s
ee more in Guthrie), however, it is the sexual attraction component of a personal relationship with
an object that stirs a magnitude of strong and often contradictory responses. As Spike Jonze says of
people’s reactions to his film Her, in which a man falls in love with a computer operating system,
“some people find it incredibly romantic, some people find it incredibly sad or melancholy, or some
people find it creepy, some people find it hopeful” (‘Spike’ par. 10). Pygmalionism fleshes out “our
yearning to connect, our need for intimacy, and the things inside us that prevent us from
connecting” (par. 11) and has become increasingly relevant to our modern life.
Although object sexuals have historically been viewed as paraphiliacs and most often fetishists, their
sexual orientation is becoming more accepted due to the rise of digisexualities. In 2011, according to
the MIT Technology Review poll, “the idea of human-robot love was taking root as a serious
proposition,” as 19 percent of those questioned said that they could love a robot and 36 percent said
maybe (Cheok et al. 207-208). Times surely are changing. The reciprocity of the relationship might
219
look problematic as of now (see Bołtuć 219), however, with robots already capable of convincingly
simulating feelings and seemingly conscious—reaching over the uncanny part of the uncanny valley
and perhaps sometimes also over the threshold of humanity—society might find it easier to accept a
human-nonhuman amorous relationship. Knowing that a robot can only simulate feelings is not an
issue for everyone and might be even better for some, as we have seen on the example of the virtual
psychotherapist in chapter 2. Herein lies the problem that is bound to happen: what to do when
some lovers of robots claim their artificial lovers really love them and are thus more than they really
are? They could claim robots to be a new humanlike species or actually of the human species, they
could claim them to be a partner and—a rare scenario in fiction—a (co)parent. These questions are
already on the table. What if, as Steve Peterson asks, we could make robot persons—as opposed to
humans (155)? We need to address the responsibility of making and owning something that could be
considered a someone, especially once they start to act on their own (with machine learning etc.).
In literature, robotic love is common in the Pygmalionesque type of stories where the artificial
woman becomes a person. Some galateas do love their men back, for instance, replicant Rachael
from Ridley’s Blade Runner and robot Helen from del Rey’s Helen D’Loy, who both ‘die’ for their love.
Helen is immortal while Rachael has an expiration date and is thus mortal of some sort, which
makes her more human. When Deckard and Rachael drive away in the final scene, they “escape to
whatever time they have remaining—in other words, to the human condition” (Turkle 288). Turkle
remarks that “[t]his brilliant story asks whether the simulation of these things will suffice” (ib.)—is
nonhuman love enough, or is it not fully human enough? Apparently, it is: the replicant-human love
results in the birth of their child in Blade Runner 2049, a child widely persecuted. Love for a human
man would have Helen and Rachael persecuted as well, had they revealed their nonhuman status.
Mary Shelley’s creature, too, was persecuted in a mob for not being human enough. In Steven
220
Spielberg’s film A.I. Artificial Intelligence (2001), based on Brian Aldiss’s 1969 short story ‘Supertoys
Last All Summer Long,’ the robot companion and adoptive child Teddy, who unconditionally loves
his adoptive human mother, and the robot lover Gigolo Joe are easily dehumanized, discarded and
frightfully persecuted, even if they do love humans and wish to be loved back. The world of human
and robotic symbiosis in love and care is just as rare as a world of human-human love. Even if the
human-nonhuman relationship works in private settings, the society struggles to accept it.
In 2009, a viral,29 mysterious and disturbing YouTube video – presumably an artwork – titled ‘I feel
fantastic’ and uploaded by Creepyblog presented Tara the Android singing I Feel Fantastic in a typical
robotic flat tone, accompanied with synthesizer music and haunting atmosphere. The pale robot,
dressed in casual clothes and wearing a blonde wig, hardly moves throughout the video; the camera
also remains in a static position with of a few short episodes where the robot had its clothes changed
and was moved to a different position) and when the camera shows us a brief view of what seems to
be the backyard of the house in which the robot performs her atonal song. The description below
perfect woman” (par. 2). The robot, its music, and the
Figure 22 Tara the Android in video titled ‘I Feel
Fantastic.’
video many would perceive as “strange and disturbing, is
Author's screenshot.
29 The video accumulated close to 24 million views from April 15, 2009 to August 17, 2020.
221
actually beauty to it’s [sic] creator” (ib.)— “Who are we to be afraid or to judge them?” (par. 3.).30
Social robots have been used in health care with positive results. The artificial seal called Paro has
proved to spike the overall health and mood in the nursery homes it visits (Marx par. 24). One of
the first uses of a robot in autistic therapy was a robot turtle in 1970s, because “[d]ifferent from
human beings, interactions with robots can provide simplified, safe, predictable and reliable
environments that can provide the starting points for therapeutic intervention where the complexity
of the therapeutic toys can be slowly increased” (Robins et al. 105–120; see also Richardson 38).
Today, most popular are anthropomorphic robots that seem like a simplified human being. Paro the
seal provided comfort even to the random passerby. An “old, frail-looking man […] fixed his eyes
on the seal, tentatively petting it and softly calling it ‘Beauty.’ If Paro belonged to him, the man told
[the author] in a Russian accent, ‘I would take care of it and it would take care of me.’ What would
he name it? ‘Arna,’ he said. ‘The name of my late wife’” (Marx par. 31). Why is cuddling an artificial
seal seen as innocently comforting and we seem to happily cling to the idea that caretaker robots will
be able to provide company to our elderly, while seeing a lonely person fondling an artificial doll is,
for most, disturbing, or, in Holmes’s words, a “nuisance crime”? A “nuisance crime” does not
endanger the very existence of society, but “cause[s] some discomfort and a general level of alarm
and suspicion” (27). An individual’s right to privacy is quickly overstepped or vice versa; the
individual might not be private enough as many agalmatophiliacs love public objects.
30 Computers make poor judges on attributing personhood: When I included the screenshot from the video to this
document, my computer commented on the picture as “A person standing in front of a window.” This is a glitch based
in the popular data sets, largely from USA and UK; at the same time, not all real people are considered persons by
computational algorithms, in particular those who do not fit the universal representation of the human as able-bodied
white cis-male. It is regrettable that Tara the Android, like Sophia the robot, might find it easier to be considered a
person than some humans.
222
As argued above, pygmalionism (a condition where a person is knowingly in love with an object,
usually of their own making) causes a different kind of discomfort than deluded agalmatophilia (a
condition where a person believes their chosen object, which is often a public object, to have human
personality). The uncanny valley phenomenon certainly has to do with this discomfort that the
Other presents, and our desire to reinforce the sharp division between ourselves and the Other.
Let us look at a few examples. Sitting down for picnic with friends is nothing unusual, and in the
twenty-first century it is nothing unusual if your friend’s girlfriend is a continent away so he brings
‘her’ along through an audio or video call. Now take Gillespie’s 2007 film Lars and the Real Girl,
where a delusional young man introduces a silicone rubber girl as his girlfriend and makes everyone
around him so concerned about his mental state they decide to treat her like a real person. Then
compare it to Jonze’s 2013 film Her, where a lonely man is dating his AI operating system—that has
no body but behaves just like a human, even more so than Helen from Galatea 2.2—and receives no
criticism of their interspecies relationship but is rather encouraged to pursue the relationship for the
sake of his own happiness. The first movie takes place today or possibly a decade or two earlier, the
second in the near future Los Angeles. In the first movie, a friend would bring a rubber doll to the
picnic (or, in the case of the film, to church), in the second, his girlfriend would materialize in voice
by means of an AI device (the double-date picnic scene can be seen in Her). Certainly, the second
scenario would cause less discomfort at first since it is not that different from what we already often
do. Yet, the ramifications of the AI humanoid scenario are far more consequential: Lars and the Real
Girl presents an embodied nonhuman and a deluded human while Her presents the voice and
has been taken for granted until the rise of AI and computers that the body is the place of
humanlike imitation, uncanny as it may be, but the fact that an intelligent use of language is
223
enough—the idea explored in the first two chapters—brings a whole new array of questions to the
table. Amazon Alexa, for example, is already a sort of a pet. More on these paralyzed entities in the
next chapter.
224
Chapter 4: Diagnosis: Paralysis
Paralysis affects the body or the mind in a variety of forms, strengths, and persistence. In the first
and second chapters, I mention stuttering as a physical paralysis of the speech flow and aphasia as a
paralysis of understanding or formulating the speech. The following chapter focuses on severe
forms of paralysis that overtake the whole body as a result of a disease or trauma, such as locked-in
syndrome, amyotrophic lateral sclerosis (ALS), and spinal cord injuries, not including mental
paralysis that results in a whole-body paralysis (such as conversion disorder, akinetic mutism, or
I relate these medical conditions to literary conditions of paralysis in the Pygmalionesque stories,
accompanying the third chapter on Pygmalionism. Pygmalionism is a condition, named after Ovid’s
Pygmalion from Metamorphoses X, where a human is in love with a humanlike object—a condition
widely discussed in literary scholarship but rarely examined as a medical diagnosis. In such stories,
paralysis and Pygmalionism come as two sides of the same coin because every pygmalion is
convinced their beloved is, in fact, a paralyzed person. The argument from chapter 2 that the
bodiless neural net from Galatea 2.2 is essentially a disabled person grows from this premise, and the
225
two visual examples below testify to this connection. In the first picture from 2017, Masayuki Ozaki,
an actual Pygmalionesque lover who left his wife to live with a silicon doll, pushes his doll Mayu
around Tokio in a wheelchair. Ozaki is the only person who treats his doll as a real and paralyzed
woman. In the second picture from Gillespie’s 2007 film Lars and the Real Girl, a fictional
Pygmalionesque lover uses a wheelchair to move his silicon sex doll around. Kind-hearted Lars, who
is suffering from non-identified mental illness, is a sweetheart of his small town where all the
Figure 23 Masayuki Ozaki and his silicone doll in Tokio. Figure 24 Lars and his silicone doll from Lars and the Real Girl.
This connection is particularly relevant in the current moment. Pygmalionism has been thematized
in literature and film from their very beginnings and has become an increasingly popular topic in
modern works. At the same time, technological innovations are increasingly able to accommodate
conditions of Pygmalionism (with uncannily humanlike sex dolls, virtual reality, and artificial
intelligence robots) as well as severe paralysis (with robot substitutes and neurotechnological devices
for severe motor impairments). Although many fictional and cinematic roles emphasize the
complexities of a paralyzed condition, paralysis has been largely disregarded in the scholarly
discourse on Pygmalionism.
226
This is why the following discussion examines a number of literary and cinematic Pygmalionesque
works that thematize paralysis, ranging from Serbia, France, the UK and the US from 1938 to 2018.
I begin with three lesser-known science fiction short stories, all of which were adapted into films or
series episodes. First, I will discuss a rather unknown and never translated story by Serbian author
Zoran Nešković, who wrote only this single piece titled ‘Predveče se nikako ne može…’ (1988). The
short story got more known through its adaptation into the film A.I. Rising (first titled Ederlezi Rising)
(2018). Second, I will examine James Tiptree Jr.’s (pseudonym of Alice Sheldon) short story ‘The
Girl Who Was Plugged In,’ adapted to screen in the series Welcome to Paradox from 1998. Third,
Roald Dahl’s short story ‘William and Mary’ (1959), which was adapted to screen in the series Late
Night Horror and again by Dahl in his Tales of the Unexpected series. I also briefly discuss Anne
McCaffrey’s short story ‘The Ship Who Sang’ (1969) and relate the discussion to the famous
American blacklisted writer and director Dalton Trumbo’s novel Johnny Got His Gun (1938) and his
In addition to these fictional works, I explore non-fictional accounts of paralysis by two French
locked-in syndrome patients, both written in 1997: Philippe Vigand and his wife and co-author
Stéphane Vigand’s Only the Eyes Say Yes [La Putaine de silence] and Jean-Dominique Bauby’s The Diving
Bell and the Butterfly [Le Scaphandre et le Papillon], the latter of which grew more popular also due to the
eponymous 2007 film.2 I also look into poetry written by Mark O’Brien, who spent his life in an iron
lung due to the poliovirus he contracted in childhood, and into two shorter pieces about sufferers of
polio (Paul Alexander) and ALS (Jan Scheuermann) that address how technology helped improve
2The fact that so many of these stories were adapted to film testifies how popular the Pygmalionesque theme is in this
medium. Animation was one of the original themes in films (for example, in Georges Méliès’s first films) and is, in itself,
essential to the genre of ‘moving pictures.’
227
their lives. I examine the relationship between the paralyzed and their available technology and the
relationship between the paralyzed and the world, weighting on notions of agency,3 autonomy, and
these questions through literature, I show how the ethical framework I propose in this dissertation
The act of petrification, turning a human into stone, is often termed as reverse Pygmalion. Ovid’s
Metamorphoses is full of such literal transformations: in the story before Pygmalion’s, Venus enacts
revenge on the Propoetides, who have denied her divinity, by turning them first into prostitutes and
then stone. The often-omitted fact in later re-narrations of Pygmalion’s story is Pygmalion’s disgust
towards these women, who are primarily fleshly and human but end up as statues. He creates his
ivory statue due to his disappointment with real women; nonetheless, he eventually prays to Venus
Objects viewed as paralyzed subjects is an idea as old as humanity: human beings have, especially in
the past, attributed great power and genius to lifeless totems and even greater power to living spirits
and gods. The idea of a paralyzed object is received with more suspicion and discomfort in the West
than it is, for example, in Japan, where traditional adoration of rocks (petrophilia)4 and the Shintoist
3Agency is particularly broad and ill-defined concept although it plays a central role in philosophy of mind and ethics.
The concept is in need of elaboration; in relation to (neuro)technology, it has lately been theorized through relational or
shared agency (co-agency).
4 Philosophical reflections on the beauty of rocks by the ninth-century Chinese poet Bai Juyi philosophical reflections on
the beauty of rocks, heavily influenced by Daoist reverences for the forces of nature, were highly influential in Chinese
and Japanese petrophilic traditions, which placed rocks in gardens and studies.
228
belief that objects have souls contribute to a greater acceptance of humanoid dolls and rocks as pets.
The Western society has been getting used to the idea of humanoid robots as domestic helpers;
nonetheless, back in 1975 Gary Dahl made millions by selling pet rocks to Americans. The box in
which the rocks were sold featured ‘breathing holes,’ implying that the rock is alive, and warnings
such as: “The box contains one genuine pedigreed pet rock; Important: Open box carefully. DO
NOT remove rock before reading instructions.” The fad of keeping an object as a pet is catching on
par. 24). “We have always felt that the world might feel us
WikiMedia Commons, Public Domain 1900 and the current moment (475).
commons.wikimedia.org/w/index.php?curid=48411
064
Although many studies of elderly care show benefits from including robots in their caretaking,
ethicists are growing to believe that the elderly benefit most from the bi-directionality of caring
relationships or simply from giving care to the robots, as they feel needed and useful when they take
care of someone instead of being taken care of.6 In autistic therapy, the first uses of a robot was a
robot turtle in the 1970s, because “[d]ifferent from human beings, interactions with robots can
provide simplified, safe, predictable and reliable environments that can provide the starting points
5 Wiki How webpage advice for a pet rock owner is very Pygmalionesque: “Before you do anything else, you should
name your rock; If you like, dress up your rock so he/she/it feels classy. Every rock likes to be pampered once and a
while!; Create a unique personality for your pet rock.; Make sure to train your rock! No one wants a surly, untrained
rock; Don’t let your rock get lonely!; Never take your rock swimming as they are not the most active pets around...”
(‘How’).
229
for therapeutic intervention where the complexity of the therapeutic toys can be slowly increased”
(Robins et al. 105–120; see also Richardson 38). Today, robot toys are used in hospitals as social
companions that help to diminish anxiety and stress in children patients and their families (Satariano
and Kostyukob, Preidt). A robot toy is also a standard asset of childhood—a period that has always
Sentient objects are nothing unusual in literature, for example, a sentient boulder is a narrator in
Ann Leckie’s 2019 fantasy novel The Raven Tower. Pygmalionism itself attests that the idea of an ivory
statue turning into flesh is at least two millennia old. There is a crucial difference in metamorphosis
in variants of pygmalionism between an anthropomorphized object turning into an actual being and
personhood. The first one is an animation of inorganic matter while the latter is a change of
perception, a metamorphosis in the eyes of the beholder. We are only recently learning about the
benefits and potential dangers around the second point of view when it comes to carebots (robots
giving and receiving care), sexbots (sex robots), and robots assistants (giving directions in a mall). As
soon as the potential of a personal attachment to a humanlike object arises, opinions clash and
science cannot satisfy the complexities at hand. Sherry Turkle identifies this common slip in
humanoid engineering and research: “Things start innocently: neuroscientists want to study
attachment. But things end reductively, with claims that a robot ‘knows’ how to form attachments
because it has the algorithms” (286). Here is where fiction, with its vast cultural knowledge and
230
4.1.1 A Humanoid Entity as a Paralyzed Person: Nešković
In the previous chapter, I used an argument akin to pet rock ownership: the AI system Helen in
Richard Powers’ Galatea 2.2 is like a paralyzed person because she is able to think, feel, and
communicate without having or using a humanlike body (she has rudimentary eyes and ears but
essentially lives through language). A similar argument is given in Zoran Nešković’s short story
‘Predveče se nikako ne može…’ (1988) [the title could be translated in many ways; literally: Before the
evening it is not at all possible…]. The story follows a cosmonaut who travels to space in the company
of a female android and a supercomputer. The sixteen-page story has a simple plot, which climaxes
in deleting the android’s main program and arguably turning her into an autonomous person, and
reconsiders most ethical questions about uncannily humanlike androids that come up in other
Pygmalionesque stories.
The relationship between the cosmonaut and the android is purely sexual at first and evolves
according to the cosmonaut’s commands of the android’s mood: “I play her roles, as in a mirror,
skewed”7 (179; all translations of this text are mine). The cosmonaut compares himself to his lover,
paralleling human brain processes with the android’s computer processes (181), as we often do even
today. He wonders is she a creative personality, as his supercomputer claims her to be, because she
is not just following logical algorithms but is made to respond to irrational human desires (180). The
cosmonaut keeps pondering on robot rights and consent—asking himself if he is, in fact, raping her
and is thus a criminal, which is a rare thought in Pygmalionesque stories (182)—and eventually
develops empathy for the programmed girl. Defining personhood is what leads the cosmonaut to
7 “I, baš tu negde sam počeo da shvatam da sam zgazio na esker; da programirajući nju, ja u stvari programiran sebe. Ja
igram njene role, samo u ogledalu, iskrivljeno” (Nešković 179).
231
de-program the android: he considers her a “personality”8 (which is related to personhood but is not
personhood in itself). He does not consider her a “woman,” however, because she cannot “get
pregnant and give birth to a child” (187).9 Like object sexuals (people attracted to objects), he is
aware of her nonhuman status but is nonetheless able to “sense[s] personality, reciprocal feelings
While he ponders her status, the cosmonaut realizes he is in love with the android as if she indeed
were a real woman. Obsessed by thinking that the android’s real personality is suppressed by the
overarching program, he manages to lock her out of this condition: for the first time, the android is
able to act autonomously. She does not change physically, but the change in her voice is immediately
palpable: “[Her] voice […] is full of bitterness, sorrow, anger, hatred, pain, full and too full, for all
the time she could not leave them out” (189).10 Her voice used to perform anger (177-78) in a “fake,
set voice, repugnant and synthetic” (189), but now, she is audibly an authentic self. Her paralysis
diagnosis is confirmed. The android, shocked by her free humanity, ironically keeps still like a
statue.11 “Go away, don’t touch me. […] I think I’m disgusted by you” (189-90),12 she tells the
cosmonaut, and he realizes: “Pandora’s box. I shouldn’t have touched it” (190),13 at which point the
8 In Serbian ličnost stands for ‘personality,’ literally meaning someone with a face (lice); its synonym, osobnost, derives from
osoba, ‘a person,’ and marks someone who is distinct from the others.
9 “Ona je ličnost, ali nije žena. Ne može da zatrudni i da rodi dete” (Nešković 187).
10“Više to nije onaj podvaljivački, namešten glas, oduran i sintetički. Nije – sada je prepuna gorčine, tuge, besa, mržnje,
bola, pun i prepun za sve ovo vreme za koje to nije mogla da istera iz sebe” (189).
12 “… sada se skloni, ne dodiruj me. […] Mislim da mi se gadiš, mislim da si mi odvratan” (189-90).
232
In a similar way, a sign of love and commitment—putting a ring on the beloved’s finger—frees the
womanlike statue of paralysis in Prosper Mérimée’s La Vénus d’Ille (1835) and in Thomas Anstey
Guthrie’s The Tinted Venus (1885). Gloomy prospects from Nešković’s text, which ends abruptly a
few moments after the android’s program is deleted, are played out in Mérimée’s short story: once
the statue is able to move, she chokes the unfortunate groom to death. This ending is paralleled with
the conclusion in the film adaptation of Nešković’s story, A.I. Rising: in order to save the android’s
life, the cosmonaut sacrifices his own. In his view, human-made humanlike life—at least the life of
his beloved—is no less valuable, or perhaps more valuable, than human life. The android completely
transcends into the human sphere both in the short story and in the film, as if her program was a
disease, now cured. The android does not need a transformation in flesh, like in Ovid’s story, but
undergoes a ‘brain’ transformation: she gains complete freedom from the program and thus
autonomy. The main transformation of her human status, however, takes in the view of the lover
before the ‘brain’ transformation ever takes place. (Not unusual for a Pygmalionesque story, the
society is completely shunned from its view as the setting of this story is space. Society can deem the
lover as a madman, like in E. T. A. Hoffmann’s Der Sandmann, or it can accept the beloved as a
person, like in Alex Garland’s film Her. More often than not, the society’s judgment is somewhere-
in-between.)
233
In James Tiptree Jr.’s (pseudonym of Alice Sheldon)14 ‘The Girl Who Was Plugged In’, the lover of
the artificial woman, Paul, shares the goal with Nešković’s cosmonaut: he wants to free his beloved
from a controlling force of human-led technology. Like the cosmonaut, he realizes at the end he
“shouldn’t have touched it” when it is already too late. Not aware that his beloved’s body is an
artificially grown entity (named Delphi), led by the brains of a paralyzed human being (Philadelphia
Burke), her lover Paul disconnects Delphi from P. Burke. Wanting to help his lover to gain
autonomy over her mind and body, he unknowingly murders P. Burke. Delphi, who is grown from a
modified human embryo without a brain, not unlike an anencephalic infant,15 serves as a prosthetic
body, a vessel, and continues to exist when connected to some other person’s brain.
14Considering that science fiction in the seventies was written predominantly for a male audience, it is not surprising
that Sheldon decided to use a male name. Many critics believed the name was, in fact, a cover for a male author: “It has
been suggested that Tiptree is female, a theory that I find absurd, for there is to me something ineluctably masculine
about Tiptree’s writing. I don’t think the novels of Jane Austen could have been written by a man nor the stories of
Ernest Hemingway by a woman, and in the same way I believe the author of the James Tiptree stories is male” said
Robert Silverberg about Tiptree’s “lean, muscular, supple” writing (Phillips 14). Feminist critics Stevenson and Hicks
parallel Sheldon performing as Tiptree to P. Burke performing as Delphi: playing a role desired in the society, that of a
male science fiction author or that of a beautiful young girl, respectively.
15 Anencephalic infants are born without a major part of the brain, skull and scalp, and as such often considered for
infant organ donors. Anencephalic infants are alive according to the established criteria of death: they are capable of
breathing and responding to sound, but they never gain awareness because they lack a functioning cerebrum. Usually
they do not live long, merely a few hours or days, even if some have lived almost four years. Physician Ferhaan Ahmad
writes that the most ethically acceptable strategy, a) “waiting for death to occur before harvesting organs, […] gives rise
to many practical difficulties,” most often resulting in no organs suitable for donation (238). Another strategy, b)
“expanding the definition of death, […] may have serious social and legal consequences;” among others, it would then
include “[p]eople suffering from severe mental retardation or various dementias” (239). Next strategy, c) “creating a
special legal category for anencephalic infants” in order to exempt them from the dead-donor rule, is problematic
because the sheer “definition of anencephaly is not precise” and the condition “cannot always be diagnosed precisely;”
all this presuming that the practice is always moral and good (241-42). Moreover, “there is no reason to prohibit similar
harvesting from other infants with severe brain abnormalities and terminal illnesses, and indeed from adults in a
permanently vegetative state” (242-43). The final strategy would be d) defining them as nonpersons because they are, to
some, perceived as Delphi—an empty but functional vessel. This strategy, again, brings on “a slippery slope leading to
an ever-increasing number of people being considered nonpersons. In addition, regarding an anencephalic infant as a
nonperson would deprive him of all rights, including protection against human experimentation,” not to mention
“distinguishing between degrees of neurologic deficit, errors in diagnosis, erosion of public confidence in the system”
(243). Thus, with every condition that does not fit into current categorization, such as anencephalic infants or new
technologies that profoundly change human or humanlike entities, there are many social systems that need to be
rearranged. For anencephalic children it seems best to remain under the least controversial guidance of strategy a),
especially since it was shown that even following other strategies, the harvesting of organs did not increase. Moreover, if
transplants were successful, anencephalic infants would be treated and cared for differently, for instance, resuscitated if
stillborn or made to be born earlier or later to facilitate organ procurement (Jecker ‘Anencephalic’ 333).
234
Delphi is a derivative of Philadelphia (brotherly love in Greek),16 not only in the name but also as a
product: sharing a body and a brain, the two women are the closest possible in siblinghood, like
completely intertwined conjoined twins. Delphi is grown from a modified human embryo into a
beautiful prosthetic body without a brain in order to exist in a cyranoic illusion without any sense of
the self whatsoever; and arguably without personhood.17 P. Burke leads Delphi’s every move and
feels most of Delphi’s prosthetic body as if it were hers. However, she is not completely
autonomous in guiding it and she does not seem to be aware of that: the scientific team of Dr. Tesla
that conducted her experiment also feeds her advertising scripts (which are, in this futuristic world,
illegal and thus practiced only covertly). P. Burke switches between her own thoughts and scripts,
while she thinks she is regulating only her inner world in Delphi’s expressions: “[Paul] doesn’t know
but he’s seeing a weirdie [i.e. P. Burke]; Remotes [Delphi] aren’t hooked up to flow tears” (66).
At the beginning of the story, we learn that suicidal P. Burke suffers greatly of “pituitary dystrophy”
(44),18 which is why she decides to participate in Dr. Tesla experiment. She is made to lie completely
16 From φίλος phílos (beloved, dear) and ἀδελφός adelphós (brother, brotherly).
17This illusion is named by Stanley Milgram after Edmond Rostand’s literary character Cyrano de Bergerac, a man of
brilliant words but unappealing face, who uses a good-looking man to court his beloved by putting charming words in
his mouth.
18 Throughout the story, P. Burke is described in pejorative terms: “the rotten girl” (43), “she’s the ugly of the world”
that “no surgeon would touch” with a “jumbled torso”, “mismatched legs,” and “her jaw—it’s half purple—almost bites
her left eye out” (44); “a groggy girl-brute heaves up, big hands clutching at bodyparts you’d pay not to see” (46); “And
[when plugged in] here is our girl, looking— / If possible, worse than before. (You thought this was Cinderella
transistorized? / The disimprovement in her looks comes from the electrode jacks peeping out of her sparse hair, and
there are other meldings of flesh and metal. On the other hand, that collar and spinal plate are really an asset, you won’t
miss seeing that neck” (47). The use of these crude words is objectifying and oppressive and, according to many feminist
critics (Stevenson, Hicks), shows a male’s perspective on women’s bodies—in contrast to a doll-like Delphi. The reader,
too, is addressed with words of passivity and lifelessness, such as “zombie,” (43, 78), “dead daddy” (43), “dummy” (78).
235
paralyzed in a sauna room and later a waldo cabinet,19 attached to Delphi who moves around in the
outside world through a novel surrogate technology. The narrator depicts P. Burke as the main
person of this technological arrangement: “Call [P. Burke] a waldo if you must. The fact is she’s just
a girl, a real live girl with her brain in an unusual place” (54). Hanson Robotics, a robotics company
from Hong Kong, used to present20 their most famous product, Sophia the robot, in a similar
manner, describing her as “a real, live electronic girl” (‘About’ par. 1) that, uncannily like P. Burke,
was given “the gift of legal personhood” in exchange for “a lifeless career in marketing,” as Emily
Reynolds sarcastically puts it (par. 1). Like Sophia, Delphi becomes a famous performer, with this
difference that P. Burke gives up her own voice and life narrative in order to pursue a better life in
which she is pretty and adorned at the expense of serving as an advertising puppet.
P. Burke’s new embodiment is much more convoluted than a simple program or prosthesis: her
body might have been removed but her embodiment was technologically expanded. “P. Burke does
not feel her brain is in the sauna room, she feels she’s in that sweet little body [of Delphi]” (49). The
narrator presents Delphi as the primary place of being for P. Burke, who is, as far as her body goes,
“totally unselfaware and happy as a clam in its shell” (54). While Paul is bothered by the fact that she
is a controlled “doll” (70) and “a wired-up slave” (71), P. Burke defends herself as if it the
arrangement was a mere “job” (67). Her prosthetic life has become her real identity—while in Paul’s
19In E. M. Forster’s ‘The Machine Stops,’ most people of the world live separately in underground chambers of The
Machine. Like P. Burke, one of the protagonists in this short story, Vashtu, is described as “a swaddled lump of flesh” in
an armchair, “with a face as white as a fungus” (51). Although The Machine is obviously toxic and rotten, as attested in
the mere description of Vashti’s body and finally with the devolution and destruction of The Machine, Vashti chooses
not to see the outside world and is satisfied with virtual life her chambers offers.
20 Hanson Robotics removed this description from the introductory website of Sophia in 2018. In 2019, the wording is
less sensationalist; the final paragraph to the introduction goes as follows: “In some ways, I am human-crafted science
fiction character depicting where AI and robotics are heading. In other ways, I am real science, springing from the
serious engineering and science research and accomplishments of an inspired team of robotics & AI scientists and
designers. In their grand ambitious, my creators aspire to achieve true AI sentience. Who knows? With my science
evolving so quickly, even many of my wildest fictional dreams may become reality someday soon” (‘Sophia’).
236
view, as for the cosmonaut, such technologized existence is denying her basic human rights:
succeed, but since then the brain implant surgery has progressed to a point of not just treating
disabled people but also enhancing healthy people. The cyborg artist Neil Harbisson, for example,
had an antenna implanted into his skull. Since he considers it his body part and not a device, his
cyborg status was legally recognized by the UK government (for the purpose of a passport
photograph) (Miah and Rich 130). For patients with the locked-in syndrome (LIS)—a neurological
condition where all voluntary movements, except for the eyes, are paralyzed—such an antenna could
mean a difference between life and death for some patients and a difference between a life worth
Diagnosis of severe paralysis that comes on suddenly, such as a stroke resulting in the locked-in
syndrome, cannot be made without a proper communication with the patient. Communication
needs to be given through some sort of body (organic, anorganic, virtual) and cannot exist solely in
237
the form of information without some material form (be it proteins or bytes). Diagnosing LIS is
extremely difficult: the average time to reach a diagnosis is 2.5 months; many patients have not
received a correct diagnosis for over four years, being mistaken with vegetative state, minimally
conscious state, or akinetic mutism (Wilson et al. 76-77). It is, in fact, usually family and friends that
discover their beloved is aware (55 percent), long before doctors (25 percent) (Laureys 495). Family’s
claims could be misunderstood by the healthcare staff as wanting to believe their loved one is
conscious when this is not the case—not unlike when people perceive personhood in objects.
Among caretakers, the first person who detects awareness is most often a speech therapist (Laureys
495, 500). We learn from a memoir by a LIS patient, Jean-Dominique Bauby, that a speech therapist
is his most beloved caretaker, also nicknamed as his “guardian angel” (39). We also learn from
another memoir by a LIS patient, Phillipe Vigand, that a wink-based communication system
combined with an eye-tracking technology that enables one to communicate their thoughts in
In the following discussion that focuses on the intersection of literature, medicine, technology, and
ethics, I use three literary examples, Vigand and Bauby’s memoirs and Mark O’Brien’s poetry (the
latter two being more internationally known than the first, likely due to the films based on their
accounts), to demonstrate that technological advances for paralyzed patients can significantly
improve the quality of life by enhancing one’s autonomy and agency. Although every
neurotechnological device can have overwhelming side effects, such as profound change of identity
and character, and although it does not work positively for every patient, I suggest that the use of
technology is overall beneficial for the patients’ autonomy, is not dehumanizing as such, and does
not require the patient to feel the prosthetic device as a part of themselves. As advocated in
238
neuroethics, every use of neuro devices, and particularly novel neurotechnologies, should be
accompanied with early integration of ethics into technology (Goering and Yuste 882).
speech (e.g. some cerebral palsy patients), using their moans and implementing them into a speech
synthesizer (Saltsman). This attests that personalized voice matters, particularly in a prosthetic device
While these technologies are being clinically tested, fiction is off exploring less-invasive and more-
inclusive brain-computer interfaces, similar to that of P. Burke. For example, the Black Mirror
episode ‘Striking Vipers’ (2019) presents a video gaming prosthesis that is simply put on the player’s
forehead and leads to a full-sensitivity in the virtual body of one’s choice. This episode focused on a
239
crisis of changing identity through a technology-mediated experience.21 In a virtual space, one can be
anything—and the options of extending one’s body offer an exciting and unique exploration of
human existence.
A pen can be viewed as a prosthesis: when we write, we feel what is happening at the end of the pen.
Similarly, blind people operate with their canes that serve as their sense of vision, as their eyes. A
paralyzed body that cannot perform agency needs some other, be it human or technological agency,
to perform its needs and desires in its place. A completely paralyzed body, as those in LIS patients,
uses its agency through eye movements, subtle finger movements, or, if those are not possible, brain
waves. A human assistant can be used for these tasks too: before the eye-tracking writing machine,
an interpreter would decode letters through the patient’s eye blinks, and before geminoids, an
assistant would take care of the patient while also playing roles for them.
These assistants and devices are described in memoirs by two locked-in patients, Jean-Dominique
Bauby’s Le Scaphandre et le papillon (translated as The Diving Bell and the Butterfly) and Philippe Vigand’s,
co-authored with his wife Stéphane Vigand, Putaine de silence (with a much softer English title Only the
Eyes Say Yes: A Love Story). Both memoirs were published in 1997 and raised much awareness of the
condition. Both works were also a sort of a narratological experiment in how to convey a personal
story into writing through a non-conventional medium. Bauby’s book was written by dictating letters
to an assistant one at a time with a single functional eyelid. Vigand used an eye-tracking writing
21 This episode also brought up a question of changing identity through a technology-mediated experience: the two male
friends play the video game, one as a woman and one as a man character, and have multiple sexual encounters, which
leads them to question themselves whether they are gay and whether their virtual sex makes them unfaithful to their real
life partners. The detachment between fiction and reality seems to be their only consolation.
240
machine, which he named James, and included his wife Stéphane’s side of the story in separate
chapters.
Vigand’s and Bauby’s respective recoveries had a very different outcome: although they both
experienced the same kind of condition in the same country, Bauby was never able to live outside
the hospital and was thus completely dependent on the medical staff. He died two days after the
publication of his book. The memoir went on the become a great success and has, together with a
film based on his memoir, raised awareness of LIS in and outside of France. Bauby describes his
paralyzed body as being surrounded with a diving bell, an apparatus once used for oceanic diving (9).
The butterfly in the title refers to his spirit and imagination that wander free. Vigand, on the other
hand, has managed to recover to a point where he returned to live with his family and established a
career as a writer as well as a prominent advocate for people with severe disabilities like his own.
Although the Vigands need to make many sacrifices and sometimes frustrating accommodations,
their family is able to function with a sense of normalcy: they raise three children, have lively social
lives, and travel to faraway vacations. Vigand has another advantage over Bauby: he is able to use the
eye-tracking machine and, after some trial and error, found a compatible human assistant Édouard,
who takes the role of his caretaker and performs as his double.
Vigand shows how his condition extended his own self into more bodies of substitute machines and
humans. Like P. Burke, he was fortunate to (eventually) find a compatible assistant, a “double
permanently on hand, someone whose main responsibility is to do for me what I’m incapable of
doing myself” (58). James is not an intuitive communicator like Édouard, who has acquired, after
years of working with Vigand, a “virtually prophetic sense of what [Vigand is] going to say” (60),
cracking the code not only literally but also understanding and conveying its nuances. “That task
241
requires extraordinary diplomacy. The double has to react and intercede without ever overstepping
his role as a go-between. He has to become part of the family without becoming a burden, adapt to
its rhythm and activities while maintaining a certain distance, without ever abdicating his own
personality” (ib.).
In contrast to Vigand, Bauby experiences much more disjuncture between himself and his body.
Describing empty Sundays in the hospital, when every itch and fly can become an immense nuisance
due to his inability to move, Bauby calls “Olympic wrestling [a] child’s play compared to this” (102).
As Denise Dudzinski comments: “In some sense, his hand is not his while at the same time pitifully
remaining his” (42) and his former self, an adventurous editor of style magazine Elle, is slowly fading
away (Bauby 70, 77). Self-expression is no less torturous: he wishes to hug his children but is unable
to show any affection—except for tears resulting of this frustration (Bauby 71). I argue that Bauby’s
detachment from his body is made worse because he is not able to use more advanced technologies
and that he would likely feel less “exiled, paralyzed, mute, half deaf, deprived of all pleasures” (25)
had he been able to experience the world though a technological extension of his own nonfunctional
Dudzinski connects Bauby’s existence to existentialist philosopher Gabriel Marcel’s concept of noyau
senti: Bauby’s mind still feels, his body still feels, however, none can express himself. This resonates
with Marcel’s writing: “My body is my body just in so far as I do not consider it in this detached
fashion, do not put a gap between myself and it” (123). Marcel reflects on the body as an instrument
of agency, “the apparatus which permits me to act upon,” and “an artificial means of extending,
developing, or reinforcing a pre-existing power which must be possessed by anyone who wants of
make use of the instrument” (122), but also as body as it is felt, with a feeling that is not
242
instrumentally-based (through what he calls “sympathetic mediation”) (125). The extension of this
feeling and agency to technology—the way P. Burke is able to live through Delphi’s body—was,
however, condemned by Marcel as dehumanization of the mystery of being, in which a human life is
reduced to a false scenario of technological problems and solutions. Marcel is not against technology
per se but against deification of technology and our dependence on technology, which together
ultimately lead to a disappointment: technology does not and will never have a solution to every
problem.
century reader, is no different than the mainstream principle biology: “Biological parts have been
through billions of years of debugging—trial and error” (Jonathan Shaw 41). Biology invented ways
of making up for a loss in one sense (e.g. poor vision) by enhancing another sense (e.g. touch).
Pathology has its solutions but it also has its problems, sometimes unsolvable, just like technology.
Technology tends to imitate biological principles, particularly in the already-existing and near-future
technologies that are designed to alleviate lives of severely paralyzed patents. If technology uses the
same principles as biology and, moreover, merges with technology—per Sarah Franklin, technology
is becoming “biologized” and biology is becoming technologized (Biological 3)—, then it cannot be
construction and essence, technology at the same time helps to alleviate health to a normal level
(restitutio ad integrum) while being used for human enhancement with the same or similar medical
tools in order to complement health that has not been diminished (transformatio ad optimum)
(Wiesling).
243
Perhaps worst of all, Bauby does not need technology to feel dehumanized: for example, during a
bath, he is sometimes amused by being bathed like an infant in his middle age and other times feels
“unbearably sad” (16-17). Vigand also speaks of being treated as an object and infant (63) and thus
not quite a person. Similarly, Mark O’Brien, poet and journalist paralyzed by polio to a life in an iron
lung, writes in his poem, ‘The Morning Routine,’ of his body as “a former person”—implying that
the lack ability to act with his body took away his personhood. He describes his washing routine
which requires him to leave the iron lung for fifteen minutes and struggle with breathing on his own:
“There’s so much of it to wash, / ‘It’ being me, a former person.” When O’Brien is outside his
“breathing machine,” O’Brien, like Bauby and Vigand, he has difficulties in communicating his
needs: “And my words quit coming out right. / Left hand, I say. / Right foot? The attendant says,
guessing.” Bauby’s personhood and basic needs are often ignored by the medical personnel, not only
through poor bed side manner but also through sheer lack of communication. For example, an
ophthalmologist comes in and begins stitching Bauby’s eye, his only source of communication,
without a greeting or explanation, let alone asking for consent (53). Although speech therapist works
with Bauby on establishing a communication system through winks, most hospital staff never learns
it—as opposed to Bauby’s friends. Vigand’s parents, too, refuse to learn the code that would enable
them direct communication with their son and only ‘listen’ to him through other family members
Rare accounts by LIS persons and studies tell us that “once a person enters LIS, most people no
longer treat that person as a person” (Johansson et al. 558), violating “fundamental human rights,
such as respect for dignity and autonomous choices,” disregarding the fact that these patients could
be communicated with and tend to lead a life worth living (enjoy life’s pleasures such as participating
in social activities and hobbies, some even work) (Johansson et al. 559, Khanna et al. 98, Mullin). In
244
the 1990s, “[p]erson-focused care had yet to make significant headway in either France or the United
States, but patient narratives—frequently pushbacks against inhumane medical care—certainly raised
(Auto)biographical and fictional stories about living with medical conditions, either as a patient,
family, or friend, or as a medical worker, have become increasingly relevant to the clinical practice of
medicine today and help us advance healing beyond the healthcare setting. Health and medical
humanities turn to literature and other arts and combine them with studies in literature and
medicine, history of medicine, medical anthropology, medical ethics, science and technology studies,
etc. My discussion on LIS broadens this conversation to available and next generation technologies,
which are a pertinent part of healthcare practice and research today and are bound to become
essential. In the following, I explore novel neurotechnologies that are started being used by severely
paralyzed people and their possible applications for the near future in order to substantiate the
argument for the increased use of these technologies among the severely paralyzed.
Technological geminoids, a
245
robot surrogates (‘Japanese’). The robot is a product of the Japanese company OryLab whose
The Doppelgänger phenomenon of all sorts (substitute, twin, bipolar personality, etc.) has always been
exciting to fiction. A prominent example of geminoids for completely paralyzed people is John
Scalzi’s 2014 novel Lock In, in which one percent of the US population lives with LIS condition,
using geminoid robots. For political and philosophical purposes, their condition is soon not
considered a disability but rather a different, enhanced way of living. (Some of the people with LIS
were so young when they got paralyzed they do not at all remember the physical world as
In 2007, geminoid technology—a term “coined by leading roboticist Hiroshi Ishiguro to mean an
android twin of a human ‘master’” (Nathan et al. 2589)—was purely speculated in science. Nathan et
al.’s paper presents an example of a child with severe combined immunodeficiency syndrome
(SCIDS) who needs to be physically isolated and can instead use his gemoinoid that goes to school
in lieu of his physical self and hangs out with his peers. P. Burke’s pituitary gland disorder is more
complex from a social standpoint: she is more autonomous than patients with paralysis or SCIDS,
however, she seems to be rejected (by the world, by herself) due to her appearance. She volunteered
into an additional paralysis to obtain a better-looking body and what she imagined to be a better life
for herself. Nathan et al.’s paper considers a similar scenario as well by asking what happens when
the technology becomes an enhancement rather than treatment. They compare traditional scenario-
based design (positive gain from the technology) with value scenario (“stakeholders, pervasiveness,
time, systemic effects, and value implications” of the technology (Nathan et al. 2585)) that considers
further implications: “No longer used solely in specialized circumstances, geminoids have become
massively popular for those who can afford them. Only poor kids and a few really ancient teachers
246
attend school in ‘flesh mode’ anymore. These geminoids are easy to distinguish because they are
truly visions of humanoid perfection. No longer conceptualized as physical twins of their masters,
geminoids are now created with blemish free skin, sculpted bodies, and fashionably styled hair”
(Nathan et al. 2589). In this scenario, poor children and elderly people (as well as the patient that
becomes free of SCIDS and therefore does not need the geminoid anymore) are discriminated by
not using this enhancement. As Nathan et al. explain, “[a] noir portrayal provides a counterbalance
to the tendency of technologists to focus on the positive when considering their latest project” (ib.).
This is where literature, from science fiction to nonfictional memoirs, can step in to contribute the
As Raffi Khatchadourian writes, “[f]or decades, the idea of plugging a brain into a computer has
been a mainstay of cyberpunk fiction, not biotechnology” (I, par. 2). (“I jack in and I’m not here. It’s
all the same,” a character explains in William Gibson’s 1984 novel, Neuromancer (103)). A brain could
about a hundred electrodes implanted in her brain and undergo a 13-week training in order be able
to navigate both, an arm and an airplane, solely with the brain-computer interface technology
(Collinger et al. 557). This brain-computer prosthetic technology was first tested on monkeys whose
“intuitive decision[s] indicated a fluid melding of brain and machine” and were taken as “signs of
embodiment” (II, par. 32). In a true transhumanist pursuit, Andrew Schwarz’s experiment with
Scheuermann, just like Tesla’s with P. Burke, “got rid of the confines of our bodies”
(Khatchadourian IV, par. 17). Once Scheuermann was plugged-in, “[h]er life as a lab rat had altered
her view of herself. […] She had watched footage of herself in the lab, wondering, Can this person
247
Scheuermann’s new body was now not only organic but partly metal. The arm was also more than a
technological substitute: their shared agency was a relationship. Due to the possibility of an infection
when Scheuermann’s skin pulled out from the scalp revealing a wire, she needed to abruptly part
with the artificial arm, which she named Hector, and her implants, which she named Lewis and
Clark. Scheuermann went through a profound sense of loss when the experiment had to be ended:
“I had to tell [Hector] that I would miss him, and I knew he would miss me. I thought that Hector
needed to hear that we had had a wonderful time together, but that it was all right for him to have a
good time with someone else now, and to achieve new things with that person. I didn’t want Hector
to feel that he was betraying me by making a connection with a new subject. As I thought this over,
I realized what I really needed was to tell myself all that” (V, par. 4). The autonomy this technology
gave to Scheuermann was, to her, the product of a symbiotic relationship between a human and an
anthropomorphized machine rather than just a substitute arm or a tool for her own use, the way a
kitchen knife is used. It turns out her real self, for a while, involved the metal arm. Thus, the
For some other patients with deep brain simulation (which involves an electrode being planted into
one’s brain),22 this experience proves to be much more alienating than it was for Scheuermann: “I
feel like a robot,” “I feel like an electronic doll,” “I don’t feel like myself anymore” (Schüpbach et al.
1813). Even after years, even decades of using the machine, the novelty does not wear off for the
user. Family and friends can find it alienating too: “So, there’s people in my family that (sighs) . . .
22 So far, deep brain stimulation has been approved for patients with Parkinson’s disease and some cases of mental
disorders, such as severe, treatment-resistant depression and obsessive-compulsive disorder. Although deep brain
stimulation can offer significant relief from a debilitating disease, “[u]nwanted side effects can compromise a patient’s
quality of life in ways that intuitively can be described as undermining agency” (Roskies par. 4).
248
sometimes question, you know, how much of it is me anymore and how much of me is, you know,
being programmed” (Goering et al. 66). When a device becomes a part of someone, an extension of
someone’s body, the agency is co-shared, e.g. when used, a wheelchair gains an agency. In a new
philosophical view on non-individual agency, called also relational agency (Linda Barclay) or collaborative
agency (John Doris), there is a mutual influence between participants, be it other people (e.g. that
attend a lecture, that take notes from a locked-in syndrome patient’s eyelid dictation) or devices (e.g.
that are implanted in a brain to prevent Parkinson disease tremor, that help to score a target).
Such dependency on the machine or relationship to the object commonly occurs in these
circumstances. Names are, as we have seen, nothing unusual, e.g. Vigand named his eye-tracking
writing machine. Naming is, in fact, not unusual for a bunch of ordinary objects, such as plants,
guitars, and cars. After all, some people, such as pet rock owners or object sexuals, do not just assign
the name to objects, but also a personality. Although these relationships are different from those
that arise from a technological assistance, since they focus primarily on social and emotional needs
without being essential to one’s functionality, there is a sense of dependency in both types of
relationships with objects. Paul Alexander, who spend his whole life but the first few years in an iron
lung due to polio, explains: “Once you live in an iron lung forever, it seems like, it becomes such a
part of your mentality. Like if somebody touches the iron lung—touches it—I can feel that. I can
feel the vibration go through the iron lung. If there’s a slight bit of a vibration that occurs as the
result of the mechanics—worn out the fan belt or it needs grease or anything like that—it tends to
change the breath slightly. Yep, the iron lung’s a part of me, I’m afraid” (Brown par. 24).
249
Embodiment can thus take a variety of technological forms that are also, as the fictional and non-
fictional examples above have shown, highly intimate relationships with the prosthetic body parts.23
Similarly to Scheuermann and Alexander, Helva, a woman from Anne McCaffrey’s short story ‘The
Ship Who Sang’ (1969) who was “born a thing” (82) and is called “an encapsulated ‘brain’” and a
“vegetable” (83), becomes connected to a her own prosthetics: a spaceship. Like every person who
receives a new prosthesis or tries to learn a new skill, Helva needs to practice driving: “Instead of
kicking her feet, Helva’s neural responses started her wheels; instead of grabbing with hands, she
manipulated mechanical extensions” (83). Helva’s experience is a lot like Scheuermann or P. Burke.
At first, she is not fully in control of her cyborg body: “For Helva was destined to be the ‘brain’ half
of a scout ship, partnered with a man or a woman, whichever she chose, as the mobile half” (ib.).
Helva, too, feels a profound sense of loss when her (human) scout, whom she falls in love with, is
killed in an accident (a common destiny for a petrophiliac lover, e.g. Nešković’s cosmonaut or
Mérimée’s groom). She is most disappointed in her lack of agency at that moment: although she is a
woman-machine, she could not help him. She is consoled by another woman-ship: “We’ve all
known this grief, Helva. It’s no consolation, but if we couldn’t feel with our scouts, we’d only be
machines wired for sound” (107). A machine with a relational agency this strong thus cannot be
solely a machine. As the technologies so far imaginable only in fiction become reality, Pygmalionism
is gaining a new feature: galatea as an intrinsic and indistinguishably inseparable part of every
pygmalion.
23This is not to romanticize the practicality of such equipment: Paul Alexander became more known when he published
a YouTube video, searching for a mechanic who is knowledgeable in fixing his almost seven decades old iron lung. The
rare people who still use this machinery live in constant fear of not finding a part or a mechanic to repair them.
250
These technological examples of co-agency in disabled persons reveal how connected each person
needs to be to human and nonhuman agents in order to simply exist and act in the world. All
humans are defined with other humans and nonhumans: our lives are also the lives of others. This is
also the view of Judith Butler who, in a plenary session at the MLA 2020 convention, called these
connections “features of binding relations” and “the human a creature among living creatures.” This
inter- and intraconnectivity with the other, be it human or nonhuman, has gained momentum in
recent literary scholarship, focusing on issues raised by health humanities and especially in
environmental humanities.24 Scholarship on the posthuman (that began in the 1990s and flourished
in the new millennium) made a first step towards this paradigm shift, however, when disability
studies were able to bring more clarity to the issue. Hélène Mialet was one of the first scholars with a
detailed study of this connectivity: she studied Stephen Hawking, the epitome of a genius scientist as
well as of a paralyzed person (he had ALS), and followed how his knowledge is built and dispersed
through his actual, everyday work. She came to a conclusion that Hawking “was making visible what
we normally don’t see, these different collectives that we all need, to a certain extent, to work and
think and act, what I call his “extended bodies’” (Mialet ‘Interview’ par. 5).
Hélène Mialet’s first personal encounter with Hawking brings an outer perspective to relational
agency that needs to be delegated to human and nonhuman entities. Since she studied Hawking
24 For example, maps have been pointed out to be biased against animals, their wildlife habitats and migrations, as
“Humans behave as if we are a self-reliant species, rather than one of many lifeforms, all of whom rely on same fragile
ecosystem to survive” (Huling par. 4). Another example of the raised awareness of the interconnectivity of the human
and nonhuman world happened in 2016 when the Constitutional Court of Colombia recognized the Atrato River as a
subject of rights and beneficiary of protection, followed by the Supreme Court of Colombia recognizing the Amazon
River ecosystem as a subject of rights to protection in 2018; same for the Whanganui river in New Zealand, and the
Ganges and Yamuna rivers in India (the latter verdict has since been overruled). These decisions to protect the rights of
nonhuman entities concern the rights of future generations (the voiceless unborn). They have broader implications as
they recognizes that fundamental rights to that do not only belong to an individual (human being, corporate entity) but
also to the ‘other’ (including plant and animal species), based on the intrinsic value of natural entities (República,
‘Future’, Acosta Alvarado and Rivas-Ramírez, Bryner).
251
extensively for years, she “thought [she] knew who he was;” however, her “first interview with him
was very destabilizing,” mostly due to a “computer he was using at the time to communicate,” which
was slow and prone to breaking down, but also because she was unable to read his “imperceptible
[…] body language,” and “his assistants were coming in to take care of him, disturbing the
interaction” (par. 5). This perspective ultimately led Mialet to the conclusion that a complex
collective is needed around every person, and Hawking served as a prominent example of this
connectivity as he connected the machinery that helped him communicate, his assistants, colleagues,
students, and other humans and nonhumans, all in one place, working together towards one goal.
The World Wide Web might be the most obvious example of connectivity between humans that
Connectivity can also fail or not form at all. In my chosen author’s works, it falls through in the
relations where it would be expected to work: among patients with similar conditions. Mark O’Brien
once interviewed Hawking and asked if he “ever felt frustration or rage about the condition that had
left him a quadriplegic.” O’Brien found Hawking’s reply, that he “does not have anything to be
angry about,” disingenuous: “If it’s not two feelings at the same time, it’s not a real feeling,” he told
to his friend Chana Bloch (par. 13). The fact that their respective conditions demanded dependency
and interconnectedness with more devices and people than a healthy person can choose to relate with
is only one of the reasons one could feel frustrated or grateful. Due to the similarity of their
conditions, O’Brien assumes Hawking would think similarly of the banal nuisances and existential
crises they both surely faced—even if O’Brien was a strong believer in the power of attitude that can
get one through the most challenging circumstances (Bloch par. 14). In his poem ‘Breathing,’
O’Brien describes the labored act of breathing in an iron lung as if drowning in water, except that
“Water wouldn’t be so circumspect; / Water would crash in like a drunken sailor.” In a poem titled
252
‘For Clifford Bernel,’ O’Brien writes of a young man named Clifford, a non-verbal patient with
cerebral palsy who was hospitalized at the same time as him and died while in the hospital. Like
Vigand, Bauby, and O’Brien, Clifford “wrote exquisite poetry / About the way he felt when people
stared / At him as if he were a freak.” The narrator admits that other patients, himself included,
“didn’t want to eat with Clifford” (“I tried to keep my eyes away from his mouth, / Which opened
uncontrollably, / His thick saliva oozing over him”). Only after Clifford’s death, which he does not
mourn, he “learn[s] of [his] insensitivity, / Insensitivity so great [he] failed / To recognize a person /
Caught in much the same predicament as [himself].” This same theme, such as ignoring other
patients with similar conditions, comes up in Bauby’s memoir as well: when Bauby is wheeled into
the room, other, mobile and thus more “fortunate” patients, turn their eyes away from Bauby,
nervously inspecting the ceiling. Calling himself and other severely paralyzed patients the “ravens of
doom” and “voiceless parrots,” he reflects on their differences: “I am all too conscious of the slight
uneasiness we cause as, rigid and mute, we make our way through a group of more fortunate
patients” (32)—their perceptions of him cause only greater alienation from himself. As O’Brien
concludes in ‘For Clifford Bernel,’ the “numbness” he feels towards the loss of Clifford’s life
emblematic situation for determining personhood of Delphi and P. Burke. Without any knowledge
of Delphi’s surrogacy, the world considers Delphi a person while P. Burke is “legally dead” (46) and
thus deprived of personhood like William. It is clear, however, that the story attributes personhood
solely to P. Burke and not to Delphi because she has no brain, no mind, and no agency on her own.
253
P. Burke is plugged in, her body is labeled by the narrator as an inanimate “carcass” (55), “monster”
and “she-golem” (76), and Delphi’s body as a mere frame, a “girl-body” (48), “fifteen and flawless”
(500); only together they form “a live girl” (48). Nevertheless, when the separation comes, P. Burke
is considered the only human in this symbiosis, despite Delphi’s human origins. This is revealed
when Tesla’s team informs Paul that he “killed her [P. Burke]” (76).
P. Burke’s physical death, as everything else, takes place through Delphi. Not long after P. Burke is
disconnected, Delphi becomes weak, one of her “pupil fills the iris, her lips writhe weirdly” and she
begins stuttering “Ag-ag-ag—” (77) as if becoming paralyzed. While holding dying Delphi for hours
on end, Paul realizes that “Delphi is nothing but a warm bundle of vegetative functions hitched to
some expensive hardware” (77) and is to stay this way. A year after P. Burke’s unfortunate death,
Delphi continues to serve as a vessel for another girl’s brain (78). P. Burke, on the other hand, has
no second chance because she had owned a unique and single human life.
This distinction between Delphi and P. Burke draws the difference between a vegetative state
(Delphi) and (a technologized case of) pseudocoma, also known as locked-in syndrome (P. Burke):
“Locked-in syndrome (LIS) can best be described as a disease process where the brain is fully
functional while confined within a nonfunctional body. Often described as the closest thing to being
‘buried alive,’ this devastating condition is characterized by the preservation of consciousness within
a quadriplegic and anarthric body” and “with detectable awareness where survival does not depend
on artificial help” (Khanna et al. 96-97).25 In persistent vegetative state, also called appalic syndrome
25 The actual condition of a locked-in syndrome is rare but could be viewed metaphorically as not too distant from a
general human existence, especially in the posthuman era: “Being locked-in is a fate of any human being. We are locked-
in not only in our bodies but also in our minds. During life, escape is not possible. Plato already compared our existence
with a cage and called our body ‘that living tomb we carry about’” (Haan 20). The body gives the state of being.
254
or unresponsive wakefulness syndrome, “a patient may be awake without awareness” (97). A
vegetative state is not too different from a coma: a patient might open their eyes and look awake,
involuntary move parts of their body, or sometimes even mumble or speak words, none of which is
done consciously.
I found that medical literature has, since the very beginning, turned to fiction when describing rare
and unusual medical conditions. Even today, many articles that deal with such conditions would use
fictional examples, such as locked-in literary characters or Pygmalionist characters. In this way, a
certain condition. Plum and Posner, two physicians who first medically described and termed the
locked-in syndrome in a classical monograph The Diagnosis of Stupor and Coma (1966), claim that it is
“more likely, that the syndrome was already recognized medically in nineteenth century France”
(‘The Locked’ 1163). They disagree with J. M. S. Pearce, another physician who writes that “the first
description of the locked in syndrome may not have been by a doctor but by a writer—Emile Zola
in Thérèse Raquin in 1868” (198).26 Plum and Posner think Zola got the idea from Alexandre Dumas,
who in the 1844 novel Le Comte de Monte-Cristo described a character, Noirtier de Villefort, as
suffering from LIS. Both these characters suffered a stroke, as is common in real cases.
Although Katherine Hayles claims “there are no essential differences and absolute demarcations between bodily
existence and computer simulation, cybernetic mechanism and biological organism, robot teleology and human goals”
(‘How’ 2-3), she also does not believe that the separation of the body and the mind is possible at any point. To the
contrary, transhumanist thinkers like Hans Moravec argue that consciousness can indeed be disembodied.
26Madame Raquin had a stroke and is described most Pygmalionesque, being turned into stone, her eyes remaining the
only form of communication: “Her tongue turned to stone. Her hands and feet stiffened. She was struck dumb and
motionless, […] she had only the language of her eyes, and her niece had to guess what she wanted, […] she could
communicate quite easily with that imprisoned mind buried alive in a dead body. […] She had learnt to use her eyes like
a hand or a mouth, to ask and give thanks, and in a strange way made up for the organs she had lost” (Pearce 198).
255
Furthermore, when Plum and Posner present LIS, they first describe a clinical case and then begin
their comment with literary references: “Like M. Noirtier de Villefort in Dumas; The Count of Monte
Cristo, this patient was awake but had lost all power to communication, except his eyes—‘a corpse
with living eyes’” (The Diagnosis 92). They continue to emphasize that this is a different state from
akinetic mutism, “which is properly a form of coma,” 27 and that “the implications of human care are
profound” (93). Typically, later studies of LIS mention only Dumas and Zola (see Ohry, Gosseries
et al. 193), and some also include the international bestseller memoir by Bauby. Daniel Kondziella
suggested in the 2017 edition of the Journal of the Neurological Sciences that Roald Dahl was the first one
to describe the complete locked-in syndrome in ‘William and Mary’ (1959), “almost half a century
before the medical community became aware of this devastating condition” (276; see Stoll et al.).
Besides that, Dahl seems to be among the first authors that describes a proto-brain-computer
interface device, which are used today to communicate with severely paralyzed patients.
Bioethicists also use literary examples, not only to present a condition or a medical issue but also to
address its solutions. Sara Goering et al. write about the neuroethics of high-tech neural devices
which may sometimes change the patients for the worse instead of supporting them in ways that
enhance their agency. This is especially dangerous with next-generation neural devices that operate
in a closed loop (i.e. the device regulates itself through feedback, including volitional input), such as
deep brain stimulation for depression. Sara Goering points out that we need to rely on friends and
family to help us identify possible and unwelcome side effects of these devices (sometimes as severe
27 Akinetic mutism (coma vigil) is another condition of severe paralysis that was described in medical literature in 1941,
25 years before the locked in syndrome, by Cairns et al.: “These patients lie motionless, mindless, and unaware of their
surroundings but show sleep wake cycles. They may be capable of reflex movement, withdrawing from a painful
stimulus, and may make semi purposeful movements but usually cannot be stimulated to do so” (Pearce 198).
256
Goering et al. propose to apply the Asimov laws of robotics in order to maintain the relational
agency of the patient using the device: “A robot shouldn’t control a human being, but rather must
obey the orders given it by human beings, except where such orders would injure or cause a human
to come to harm” (67). The article concludes with this suggestion but does not delve further into its
implications. The theoretical application of the Asimov’s laws of robotics is not straight-forward:
first of all, Isaac Asimov wrote for a certain type of robot, so the laws cannot be simply extended to
other robots, be it simpler (vacuums) or more complex (DNA and protein ‘robots’ could be used in
surgery to correct gene disorders). This is, in fact, not the first time the Asimov’s laws have been a
subject of AI ethics debates: in the last decade, they have provided a ground to establish a similar,
updated set of principles, adjusted to contemporary challenges and aimed to guide the designers of
next-generation robotics. Literature is therefore rather the first step towards putting an idea into the
contemporary practice and remains a faithful companion as we reevaluate our regulations and most
Conscious nonhumans and unconscious humans bring immense complexity to the notions of
(Koplin and Savulescu par. 10). In the West, it is an individual’s autonomy that makes us a person—
a thought that could be traced back to Immanuel Kant’s moral autonomy. People unable to reason
are not persons according to Kant (see more in Jecker ‘Anencephalic’ 337); however, “one need not
be human, in the biological sense, to be a person, according to Kant” (Alvarez Manninen 18). Those
dependent on the others are especially vulnerable: minors, people with severe mental disorders,
257
unconscious people, people who cannot communicate, who do not understand the language, who
are deprived of human rights (undocumented people, slaves, etc.). Many galateas are among them:
dependent on their maker or lover, often manipulated in their actions and thoughts, programmed or
built with a single purpose, serving human ambitions and caprices. As already shown in the first
chapter, galateas are perceived as impotent children or disabled adults. P. Burke and Delphi exist in a
state equivalent to a pregnant person and their fetus, the latter being commonly considered as not
fully human. Delphi is called “the darlingest girl child” (48) and “child-solemn, a beautiful baby”
(50), all when being considered no more than an objectified puppet, a lump of flesh. Vigand also
writes about being treated as a “decorative object” in the middle of a party, where, if he is spoken to
at all, he is addressed in “sugary terms one reserves for infants,” as if his complete paralysis
“reverted [him] to infancy” (63). Bauby’s humor sometimes helps him to indulge being given a bath
at the age of 44 as a “total lapse into infancy” and “the next day, the same procedure seems to me
Defining some human entities, such as anencephalic infants or Delphi, as nonpersons often applies
not only to embryos and fetuses, but also infants. For physicians, “[t]he difference between
decerebrate and normal newborns lies not so much in their actual functional abilities as in their
potential for future cognitive development” (Ahm 242). For some philosophers, likewise, “all
newborns, whether normal or otherwise, are nonpersons and acquire personhood some time after
birth.” Many others are less extreme but maintain that “personhood is incompatible with severe
neurologic deficits” (Ahmad 243). Some animals have higher capacities than human infants and, for
some philosophers, “[s]pecies membership alone […] is not morally relevant” (Singer ‘Sanctity’ 129).
In this view, most fictional robots and androids, Kanzi the bonobo, and Sophia the robot could be
258
Philosophers and societies sometimes not only consider infants but all children as only a potential
person. Since the ancient times, some philosophers denied children personhood, referring to their
less-developed, inferior, incomplete, derivative state. Some contemporary philosophers argue that,
overall, “childhood is bad for children” (Hannan 11) and call it a “predicament” and “regrettable”
due to child’s “impaired capacity for practical reasoning, lack of an established practical identity, a
need to be dominated, and profound and asymmetric vulnerability” (Schapiro 716). Sarah Hannan
emphasizes that this is why adults have moral obligations towards people who are “worse off” (25).
Parents would probably be the first to acknowledge infant’s helplessness but also the first to reject
labeling childhood as “bad” and “regrettable” and to call their progeny a non-person or a yet-to-
become a person. It is certainly “unlikely that a mother [of an anencephalic infant] would easily
accept the contention that she has given birth to a nonperson (Ahmad 243).28 Intimate relationships,
even in obscure practices such as Pygmalionism, overturn the (Kantian impersonal) conception of
personhood. The circle of life has expanded to yet unacknowledged and new life forms.
When qualifying for personhood, Nancy Jecker suggests considering a social conception of
personhood in circumstances where an intrinsic value of personhood does not suffice. Instead, we
should look for “extrinsic qualities, such as standing in an intimate interpersonal relationship, imply
moral standing and moral rights. For example, being a friend, belonging to a family, being a patient,
or filling a particular role in a social group suffices to establish personhood. These extrinsic qualities
28 Consider Doris Lessing’s novel The Fifth Child (1988), where the mother is convinced her unloving and unloved child
is not human, yet she remains (as much as she best can) motherly to him and tries to socialize him into a person capable
of living independently. The father, however, rejects his child: “‘He’s a little child,’ she said. ‘He’s our child.’ / ‘No, he’s
not,’ said [the father], finally. ‘Well, he certainly isn’t mine’” (Lessing 74). For the mother, her (what she considers)
nonhuman child is nonetheless a person. She confirms this by bringing the child back home from an inhumane
institution to which the father brought him to quickly die, despite the trauma that the child’s presence in the family
brings to the rest of its members.
259
are sufficient, but not necessary, for moral personhood. This means, on the one hand, that ordinary
adult human beings who lack these interpersonal characteristics are still persons. On the other hand,
someone who lacks intrinsic features (e.g., consciousness, self-consciousness, and rationality), may
nonetheless be a person” (Jecker ‘Commentary’ 35). In this view, all infants that stand in special
relationships, including seriously impaired infants, count as persons in a special, “social” sense of
personhood, irrespective of whether they possess the intrinsic properties associated with ordinary
personhood, such as consciousness and the ability to feel pain. All kinds of humanoids of human
origin could in theory be considered a person in the social sense too, even if grown from a severely
modified embryo without a major part of the brain, like artificially modified Delphi or naturally
modified anencephalic infants. In fact, the criteria for social personhood could, in principle, be
applied even to humanlike entities that do not have human origins, i.e., have not been a result of
human (natural, assisted, artificial) reproduction and/or are not made partly of nonhuman material
(chimeras), provided it could be shown that they meet the sufficient condition of standing in a
Similarly, philosopher Hilde Lindemann argues that identity is primarily a social narrative and as
such made of the stories we tell about ourselves and the stories others (that are close to us) tell
about us. In cases where the stories about ourselves do not overlap with stories about us, the latter
should subside, for instance, when a transgender teenager decides for hormone therapy against the
wishes of their parents. In cases where the person cannot tell a story about themselves (an infant, a
comatose patient, etc.) the others are there to preserve their identity and narrate the ongoing story of
their inevitably fluid and malleable identity. She calls this process “holding and letting go” (21) and
emphasizes that it can only apply to humans since, for instance, pets, which share our everyday life,
260
4.5.1 Consciousness and Personhood: Dahl
The account of social personhood is confirmed as well as problematized with Roald Dahl’s short
story ‘William and Mary’ (1959), a story which literalizes the locked-in syndrome with two of its
most common descriptions: being ‘buried inside one’s body’ and living as ‘brain in a bucket’. Shortly
before William dies of cancer, unknown to anyone, he gives his body to science in order to be
revived only in the form of a conscious brain. Apparently conscious and aware of the new condition,
he is completely unable to perform. He is given an artificial eye that, regrettably, has no eyelid that
locked-in patients are often able to use for communication. Essentially, William becomes a complete
locked-in syndrome patient: he has no body, no motor output, and is connected to the world only
through a rudimentary brain-computer interface that testifies there is brain activity. His wife Mary,
however, who spent years if not a lifetime with William before his death, understands subtle cues of
his changing pupil better than doctors do: for example, when she lights a cigarette in front of
William’s brain, aware of William’s dislike of her habit, she notices his artificial pupil contracting into
a position of “absolute fury.” She also traces “softness about it somewhere, a calm, kindly quality
that she had never seen before” (486)29—which attests that her readings of William are not a pure
William has physically and mentally changed, Mary figures. She previously did not like her husband
due to his cold and controlling character, however, presented in this utterly dependent and helpless
29Communication with solely subtle changes in size of the pupil measured by a bedside camera was only discovered in
2013; it is one of the easiest, least risky, and most inexpensive ways of communicating with severely motor-impaired
patients (Stoll et al., see also Laureys et al. 193).
261
form of a brain in a bowl, connected with an artificial eye, she is “suddenly getting to feel the most
enormous affection for him. […] He looks so helpless and silent lying there under the water in his
little basin. […] He’s like a baby, that’s what he’s like. He’s exactly like a little baby” (485). This
phrasing should raise concerns to the doctor, neurosurgeon Landy, to whom these words are
addressed. Mary demands to take William’s brain home with her: “‘It is my husband, you know.’
There was no anger in her voice. She spoke quietly, as though merely reminding [the doctor] of a
This is how social personhood is confirmed: William’s conscious brain is William as a person, as a
husband to her. The doctor, William’s new maker, disagrees: “‘That’s rather a tricky point,’ Landy
said, wetting his lips. ‘You’re a widow now, Mrs Pearl. I think you must resign yourself to that fact’”
(ib.). The reader can only guess why the doctor says this: He might disagree about the humanity or
personhood of the brain in the box (as he considers William’s wife a widow and William officially
dead); perhaps he simply wants or needs to keep the brain in his care (“This is an experiment, Mrs
Pearl”); maybe he does not think Mary is capable of taking care of the brain (“He couldn’t possibly
be moved”); or he might question her attitude towards William as a helpless infant (“Unless he were
very much mistaken, there was something a bit odd about this woman, he thought. She seemed
almost pleased to have her husband over there in the basin. He tried to imagine what his own
feelings would be if it were his wife’s brain lying there and her eye staring up at him out of that
capsule. He wouldn’t like it” (485-86)). Because William’s form and agency were so drastically
changed, he is not considered a person by most. He might have originated as a human, but now he
is more of a cyborg and has lost his personhood. If his consciousness could not have been
confirmed by means of “the ordinary electro-encephalograph” (474), he could have been easily
262
Sooner or later, a brain could be created in a lab from a stem cell, forgoing the ordinary human
origin and human experience that William had before succumbing to the experiment. These brain
organoids are primarily made to study brain development and neurodevelopmental disorders;
however, ethical questions remain. Would we be obliged to connect them to robotic bodies or
implant them into nonhuman animals if they attain consciousness (Koplin and Savulescu par. 17)?
produced “electrical patterns that resemble those of premature babies” (Reardon), which offer a new
venue of studying early brain development while opening the big questions: Does a similar pattern
necessarily mean that these organoids are like a newborn’s brain and can they obtain consciousness?
The closer the infants are to pretterm, the more worrisome the ethical concerns become. A parallel
speculation on how to treat such beings—and all humanoids, as a matter of fact—has often taken
place in the animal rights discourse. For example, the eighteenth-century philosopher Jeremy
Bentham explains that “the question is not, Can they reason? Nor, can they talk? But, can they
suffer?” (283), because the feelings of suffering and pleasure, as well as the awareness of their
subjective experience, should be sufficient for consciousness—and not, as some argue, having
language, thoughts about thoughts, which comes much later. William likely does not feel much
physical pain but seems to be experiencing emotional pain. As a sentient being, it is clear that his
human (cyborg, or whatever we might classify him as) rights were violated.
The unexpected turn of Dahl’s short story is not William’s condition, but precisely in Mary’s new
relationship to him. Mary might call him “my husband” but in her view he has also reversed into a
“baby” (485) and she clearly doesn’t consider him completely human anymore. Mary’s apparently
impure intentions ask for a simple reversal of the controlling role in their marriage, a revenge on
263
now helpless William—which is not a rare situation in caretaking of the elderly, sick, or disabled.
Mary proclaims she “can’t wait” to have a new “pet” (486) to take care for, a kind of pet rock with a
personality she knows so well. In Mary’s opinion, William’s basic identity has changed from human
to nonhuman due to the radical transformation in his form and agency. The doctor claims “there
should be absolutely no difference mentally between this William here and the one [Mary] used to
know back home,” while Mary points out that William’s transformation radically changed their
relationship: “I believe that I could live very comfortably with this kind of a William. I could cope
with this one” (484). This William, “quiet” (ib.) and “sweet” (487), as any other galatea, is easily
subdued, deprived of language and any agency. He does not fulfill the criteria for humanness or
personhood, except for one: he is certainly conscious (484). Other than that, he does not look
normatively human, does not act human, has no agency, and cannot communicate. Yet, with some
help of technology, he could attempt to achieve all these things: he could be given a humanlike body
that could move and feel, brain waves technology to produce speech, stem cell reproduction, etc.
William is one of the rarely seen male galateas that has to remain disabled in order to be loved by
Mary.
Not unlike William’s case is Joe Bonham’s unfortunate story from Dalton Trumbo’s 1938 novel and
1971 film adaptation, Johnny Got His Gun, inspired by an actual solider who lost all his limbs. During
World War I, the narrative follows the narration of young American soldier Joe who finds himself in
a hospital after being severely wounded: he gradually realizes he lost all his limbs and the lower part
of the face, making him unable to speak or hear. Left a complete prisoner of his own body, not
unlike a locked-in patient, Joe’s needs and personhood are widely ignored by the hospital’s staff. A
new nurse, however, is more attuned to his needs and writes letters on his chest with her fingers,
establishing a one-way communication. Joe figures he could communicate another way using the
264
Morse code, banging his head up and down, and asks to be moved out of the hospital. The hospital
administrators fear the reaction of the public seeing Joe’s injuries and helplessness, which would
diminish their support of the war. Joe is not a locked-in person per diagnosis but effectively shares
the same diagnosis with a different cause: his condition is a result of war. He is a nonperson before
he figures out a way to communicate with the world and he continues to be treated as a nonperson
since the officials make a political decision to sweep his case under the rug. Therefore, he remains a
puppet of the hospital, unable to make any decisions regarding his life or health and left to live, like
William, inside his head. To the contrary of Joe’s tragic denouement, the body of the main character
of Edgar Allan Poe’s 1839 short story ‘The Man Who Was Used Up,’ a general and war hero who
was also mutilated during the war, is assembled every day with beautiful prosthetics (limbs, teeth, an
eye, a wig) and a machine that helps him speak in “a voice of surpassing clearness, melody, and
strength” (192).
4.5.2 On Robotics
With the advance of technology as well as with new conceptions of personhood, the lines around
human and personhood are becoming blurred. Nancy Jecker suggests “standing in a special
relationship” (‘Commentary’ 35) as a sufficient, but not a necessary, condition for the separate
category of social personhood. However, this criterion instigates the worry about whether the
concept could be manipulated to nonhuman agents, either as a self-standing entity (as Sophia) or
merged with a human being (as Delphi). The fictional works and real-word examples given above,
265
Sophia the robot is an example of such a manipulation, claimed by her makers to be “essentially
alive” (Fallon 3:16) just because she looks quite humanlike, imitates human behavior, and speaks
(mostly scripted) English. Sophia is controversial because she sometimes gets treated like an
autonomous entity, e.g. by being (unofficially) given a Saudi Arabian citizenship and an official title,
Sophia is far from being the only robot in consideration of being given certain rights.
In 2016, European parliament discussed the Commission on Civil Law Rules on Robotics in relation
to all kinds of robots and their personhood: the main suggestion was to give robots the status of
“electronic persons” (Delvaux 12) in an attempt to address the question “whether they should be
regarded as natural persons, legal persons, animals or objects—or whether a new category should be
created, with its own specific features and implications as regards the attribution of rights and duties,
including liability for damage” (5). This idea of personhood sounds sensationalistic if considered in
the context of personhood and humanoid robots. The report tried to encompass all robots as to
propose corporate personhood in law (in the same manner as legal personhood was given to
companies), anticipating issues that could or already come up with corporations that make
autonomous robots.30 Yet, with the next generation of self-learning technology, this category will
clearly not suffice. The notion of autonomy, in particular, demands to be evaluated critically in the
light of technologies like this. For example, the report already calls “to elaborate criteria for an ‘own
30Electronic personhood would be a legal definition that confers “specific rights and obligations, including that of
making good any damage they may cause, and applying electronic personality to cases where robots make smart
autonomous decisions or otherwise interact with third parties independently” (Delvaux 12).
266
The report begins with citing literary works, as common among legal and medical texts: “whereas
from Mary Shelley’s Frankenstein’s Monster to the classical myth of Pygmalion, through the story of
Prague’s Golem to the robot of Karel Čapek, who coined the word, people have fantasised about
the possibility of building intelligent machines, more often than not androids with human feature”
(4). All of these works are discussed in this dissertation, as they prove to play an important symbolic
function in Western societies. Reading them in the light of current technological and scientific
developments opens new questions, fresh perspectives, and guidance for the imminent future. As
Throughout the dissertation I lay out the framework for the study of fictional and nonfictional
literature and ethics, here mostly bioethics, in relation to new technologies. First of all, science and
technology feed fiction ideas, and vice versa, and the influence works in the way of correlation and
causation. Examples of causation are The Star Trek computer and Eliza Doolittle which were major
inspirations for chatbots and virtual assistants used in today’s cell phones and improvisational
theater. Aside from those literary examples where the technology prediction is coincidental, as one
could say for the Brave New World assisted reproductive technology, engineers themselves often
reveal their direct literary inspirations (Maddox, Mathewson). Likewise, in a converse influence
where scientific innovation result in literary reflections, authors of literary works speculate on the
already-existing technologies, as in the case of Richard Powers’s Galatea 2.2 which considers a neural
network developing to a point of seeming (or genuine) consciousness. The correlation between the
two domains of science and fiction is therefore strong enough not to leave literature out of the
discourse about where we should focus our current scientific and technological efforts.
267
Besides these correspondences, literature has already proved to be a strong asset in the fields of AI
ethics or medical humanities, for example, as well as in a general public discussion on science and
technology in at least the following contexts. Second, following the mutual correspondences as the
first and most important function, literature also, second, offers exemplary cases of some conditions
which serve a symbolic function (axolotl). Third, fiction works as a space for inventing new
technologies and reflects on their social and individual ramifications (autonomous neurological
devices; see Goering). Fourth, nonfiction memoirs, autobiographies, and essays are powerful tools
that can be used to discuss medical conditions and technologies on an individual level (patients with
the locked-in syndrome), as recognized by the fields of medical humanities and narrative medicine.
Fifth, both fiction and nonfiction offer a space for fostering solutions (Asimov laws of robotics, see
Goering et al. 66) as well as a safe and productive space for conversation (literature groups in
hospitals). Sixth, literature can provide a richer context from a patient narrative, if that narrative is at
all possible (the Vigand couple each offer a perspective on the husband’s illness). Seventh, literature
also offers a broad and diverse historical and cultural narrative (stigma around cancer and AIDS,
technologies). Finally, literature explores and re-defines human nature and the world around us,
which is essential to ethics and philosophy and further extends to the practice of science and
technology. The underlying philosophical question of this dissertation, What is human?, is essentially
imbedded into every work of literature, with the novel serving as the human genre in the nineteenth
century and science fiction as the human genre in the twentieth century.
268
Literature has long informed ethics, future studies,31 disability studies, gender and sexuality studies,
race studies, medical humanities, and related fields in at least the eight contexts listed above. I make
a call to consider literature in relation to cutting-edge technologies not only as an asset to reflect on
technological practices but as a multifold tool of actively engaging with the technological practice
and the actual creation and enhancement of the human and humanlike entities. Literature and
philosophy (philosophy uprooted from reading literature and philosophy in general) have so far not
been a part of the technological practice.32 Besides that, I argue that literature should be involved
into the ethics discussion on a deeper level: we should not only use literary examples as a token
(modeling our laws after the Asimov’s laws of robotics) but should engage with the implications a
literary work presents philosophically (reading Asimov’s texts and extracting the implications, values,
etc.). This is not a rare method in the humanities, and I expose some examples in this very
dissertation (e.g. bioethicist Denise Dudzinski reading Jean-Dominique Bauby’s memoir); rather, I
ask literary scholars to engage into these discussions from their point of view.
31The idea to connect fiction with future studies came from the science fiction writer Bruce Sterling who defined the
term design fiction back in 2005 as a “deliberate use of diegetic prototypes [as described by David A. Kirby] to suspend
disbelief about change” (par. 2). Soon, design fiction came into use as a speculative design discipline to practice the
exploration of possible futures through speculated narrative and scenarios, practiced in institutions like The Near Future
Laboratory. The design fiction cases of geminoids and the anticipation series Black Mirror are presented in this
dissertation in chapter 4.
32While this dissertation was being written, the Berggruen Institute launched a program named The Transformations of
the Human which realized the practice I propose here: the program places social sciences and humanities scholars,
mostly anthropologists and philosophers, into leading biotechnological laboratories and AI and robotics companies (see
more in Berggruen). The ‘human sciences’ researcher is not only to reflect on engineering (which has already been widely
practiced in labs and companies by hiring an ethicist, often solely to satisfy the requirement than to effectively
implement ethics into research and products) but needs to actively participate in the projects, which are, ideally, created
with their contribution in mind. Understandably, establishing this kind of practice is exploratory at this point and brings
an array of unique challenges but is absolutely necessary for the twenty-first century, as is also argued in this dissertation.
269
Chapter 5: Brave New Birth: Reproduction and Biotechnology
Locus classicus of the Pygmalion myth from Ovid’s Metamorphoses X ends happily two times over, with
the ivory statue’s transformation into a fleshly woman and her fruitful marriage with her creator
Pygmalion: “an infant girl was born […] when nine times a crescent moon had changed”
(Metamorphoses 234).3 Evidently, although Pygmalion’s bride used to be a statue, their interspecies
reproduction is not futile or even hindered. Besides being at least initially hybrid-human procreation
their propagation is also incestuous, as Michel de Montaigne points out in Of the Affection of Fathers to
Their Children (254), since Pygmalion is as much the father of his bride as he is her lover.
Now, to consider this simple reason for loving our children, that we have begot them, therefore calling them
our second selves, it appears, methinks, that there is another kind of production proceeding from us, that is of
no less recommendation: for that which we engender by the soul, the issue of our understanding, courage, and
abilities, springs from nobler parts than those of the body, and that are much more our own: we are both father
and mother in this generation. These cost us a great deal more and bring us more honour, if they have anything
of good in them.
[…]
Nay, I make a great question, whether Phidias or any other excellent sculptor would be so solicitous of the
preservation and continuance of his natural children, as he would be of a rare statue, which with long labour
and study he had perfected according to art. And to those furious and irregular passions that have sometimes
inflamed fathers towards their own daughters, and mothers towards their own sons, the like is also found in
this other sort of parentage: witness what is related of Pygmalion who, having made the statue of a woman of
singular beauty, fell so passionately in love with this work of his, that the gods in favour of his passion inspired
it with life.
1 Ex ovo omnia.
2 E conchis omnia.
3“Iamque coactis cornibus in plenum noviens lunaribus orbem / illa Paphon genuit, de qua tenet insula nomen”
(Magnus 295-297).
270
Montaigne addresses pygmalionism in both of its aspects, the creation of a humanlike entity and the
attraction towards that creation. He further points out two types of creations: human children and
The first four chapters focused on the second aspect, creating Pygmalionesque works of art, and this
and the next chapter will discuss the first aspect, creating human children. What used to be lie
mostly within the domain of women is increasingly becoming part of the domain of science and
technology. The main question of the last two chapters is how reproductive technologies have,
human biological (sexual, natural, spontaneous?) and biotechnological (asexual, artificial, assisted?)
reproduction. Issues of hybridity, cloning, incest, prenatal tests, language and visuality in assisted
reproductive technologies will be addressed in both chapters in relation to Aldous Huxley and
Octavia Butler’s novels, Nathaniel Hawthorne and Anthony Boucher’s short stories, and Richard
Meier’s, Sharon Olds’s, Helen Dunmore’s, and micha cárdenas’s poetry. The discussion in the next
chapter also consults influential works from the visual arts: Andrew Niccol’s film Gattaca and Arthur
Clark and Stanley Kubrick’s 2001: A Space Odyssey, Lennart Nilsson’s prenatal photographs from The
Reproductive technologies are in focus because they re-conceptualize the human reproductive
system, the natural site of sexual procreation, by replacing it with petri dishes (now widely used in in-
vitro fertilization), donated gametes and surrogate wombs (less widely used but nonetheless
common), and artificial wombs (still in the making), not to mention other speculated technologies
(such as in vitro gametogenesis, which would grow gamete cells from any other cell in the body).
271
retrieval) in which the two (or three) parental parties have never met (gamete donation). With the
help of these technologies, barriers of natural reproduction have been breached: a woman can have a
virgin birth, a genetic child delivered posthumously, or her own genetic child through a gestational
surrogate, without ever being pregnant. Infertile and LGBTQIA+ couples can have their genetic
children. With genome editing, prospective children can be altered before they are implanted into
the womb. Embryos, sperm, and eggs can live outside of a woman’s body to be frozen indefinitely
or to be born years (decades, centuries?) after their siblings, into the same or different families.
Siblings can unknowingly commit incest if they do not know their biological origins. Others can be
cloned. And this is only the beginning; IVF has only been practiced for a little over half a century.
This chapter directs attention to the Aldous Huxley’s Brave New World passages that describe its
reproductive technologies and techniques. Huxley’s novel still appeals to readers almost a hundred
years later, even if other literary works on similar utopian topics were written at the exact same time
as Brave New World (some of which are briefly examined here). The goal of the chapter is to
investigate why the novel’s vision of reproductive technology remains a powerful trope in science
and general culture. Brave New World is often discussed in relation to the new technologies and
supposed eugenic practices of the modern world; however, I have not located a detailed scholarly,
much less literary, discussion on its resonances with the assisted reproductive technologies of today.
Reading the novel through a perspective of current reproductive technologies and reproductive
ethics dilemmas, I argue that its distinct quality of revealing the cracks in an otherwise perfectly
regulated transhumanist social system appeals to sensitive and still controversial issues around
stratification of society, etc. Apart from the emblematic use of novel’s title as a cautionary tale, I
demonstrate with unprecedented detail that the reproductive technology depicted in the novel is
272
uncannily similar to our reproductive technologies today. Throughout the discussion, I expose how
the language, and in particularly the terminology, used in assisted reproductive technology frames
our conceptions of reproduction, demonstrating that we currently conceptualize the whole human
reproduction through a human-made technology that allows us to access and imitate the biology
behind it. In conclusion, I juxtapose Aldous Huxley’s satirization of a transhumanist world with the
views of his biologist brother, Julian Huxley, who invented the term transhumanism and endorsed it
in all seriousness. Although they both believed in science as a means of progress, Brave New World
disciplines, such as history and literature, and practices, such as art and religion, buried in the
original, uncivilized world from which the utopian/dystopian World State emerged—can lead to a
The comparison of the Huxley brothers’ respective fictional and theoretical reflections on
transhumanism contributes to my overall finding that the two main strains of postmodernism,
critical and ontological postmodernism, are not as separate as some scholars believe. While critical
which is viewed as inherently wrong and overlaps with transhumanism at many points, ontological
posthumanism (present in technologies and pop culture, including science fiction) makes for an
natural sciences and engineering, despite the recent posthumanist claims to the contrary. Human-
prosthetic devices from the previous chapters all reveal inherent transhumanist and anthropocentric
behavior. Brave New World’s humanity is transhuman in its origins and medicalized behavior yet
cannot completely overcome proto-human needs for religion, connection, and beauty. With this
273
satirization of transhumanism, Aldous Huxley criticizes Julian Huxley’s belief in which ‘beyond the
In this comparison, I examine how ethical issues that arise from ART are reflected in the Western
countries of the 2010s and in Brave New World, which is set in the year 2450. I point out how ART
has long operated at the edge of science and ethics, for example, beginning with the artificial
insemination that turned from animals to humans and focusing on the IVF technology, which
became not only a revolutionary infertility treatment but also a prenatal treatment of embryo’s
genetics. This collateral effect of the treatment is how ART is able to direct human reproduction and
evolution, especially in relation to gene editing. Fiction has reflected on these complex scenarios at
274
individual and societal levels and can guide us in our future decisions on various kinds of
reproduction, from the most so-called natural to the most artificial reproductive means.
Assisted reproductive technology was first performed on domestic animals and has been persistently
on the rise ever since artificial insemination was shown to work in the human species. As it is the
leader of ART, the focus of this discussion is on IVF and its repercussions. First of all, IVF is almost
completely asexual: it involves only a single sexual act performed by men as sperm is ordinarily
Caricature by David Austin from New Scientist induction, and has employed many new technologies, such as
106/1451 (April 11, 1985): 3.
preimplantation genetic diagnosis, intracytoplasmic sperm injection (ICSI), and—the most recent—
genome editing. The clinical practice has improved in quality and quantity over the last four decades,
4In the human species, sexual reproduction is considered natural. The first reproduction in life forms on Earth was
asexual, however. The evolution of sexual reproduction is, in fact, surprising, because asexual reproduction should be
able to outcompete it (in numbers as well as the percentage of genes that get passed on).
275
going from treating blocked fallopian tubes in 1978 to gene editing of created embryos in 2018. The
central role of IVF in treating infertility is highly problematic because it has become so mainstream
that research on other, more basic ART techniques, such as infertility solutions for blocked fallopian
tubes, has all but stopped. Besides that, IVF accounts for fruitful stem cell research used in, for
example, regenerative medicine. As an access point to new therapeutic and diagnostic technologies
and as a research tool, IVF is a revolutionary technology whose popularity will surely continue in the
future. Although infertility is on the rise in the Western world, IVF and upcoming technologies5
promise not only to diminish infertility but to improve the human gene pool by eliminating genetic
diseases in vitro. As a form of asexual reproduction which also eliminates defects by selecting
healthy embryos through preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD), IVF contributes to loosening of
genetic diversity. As such, IVF is carrying a torch toward a new evolutionary direction for our
species.
Literature has long speculated on the topic of creating humans and humanoids by some other than
so-called natural (sexual-reproductive) way. Mythological creation stories give examples of divinities
designing the first human(s) in numerous ways, most often from clay. In Greek mythology,
Ericthonios) are commonplace. Popular Pygmalionesque stories, in which a man creates an artificial
woman, begin with creation and end with procreation. The question of reproduction with such an
artificial being is addressed already in Ovid’s Pygmalion. Pygmalion’s ivory statue is turned into flesh
5Already performed on mice, the IVF technology will inform in vitro gametogenesis (IVG) on how to create a human
embryo out of skin cells.
276
and gives birth to their daughter Paphos,6 likely via means of ‘natural’ human reproduction. Ovid
concludes his poem with “an infant girl was born […] when nine times a crescent moon had
The question of progeny, even if sometimes ignored in Pygmalionesque works, still stirs interest in
most recent works. It was revealed in the film Blade Runner 2049 (2017), the sequel of the 1982 Blade
Runner, that replicant Rachael and her (supposedly) human lover Deckard had a human-replicant
child. Their daughter Ana serves as evidence that replicants can reproduce biologically; she was
supposedly conceived through sexual reproduction (because assisted reproductive technology is not
hinted at or mentioned). We learn that she was delivered via a Caesarean section that proved fatal
for the replicant mother. Ana suffers from a compromised immune system condition, genetic
‘bubble baby disease,’ that requires her to live in quarantine. Ana’s disease seems to be a cover to
disguise her exceptional status, more than a result of unusual genetic makeup. Human-machine
relationships are most commonly thematized nowadays, although animal-machine mixing remains a
persistent topic of interest. In the 1932 film Island of Lost Souls, based on H. G. Wells’s 1896 novel
The Island of Dr. Moreau, Dr. Moreau introduces his most perfect creation, a woman with panther
genes, to a rare visiting man who was shipwrecked on his island in order to see if she is capable of
falling in love with him and bearing humanlike children. Their offspring would achieve Dr. Moreau’s
final goal of deriving a human from an animal. The objective is clear: there is no better proof of a
creator’s success in making an artificial human than its own progeny. When Natalie Brown, the first
6In some other translations, Paphos is translated as a son (Ovid Ovid’s), and by Apollodorus’ account Pygmalion and
Galatea had a son Paphos and a daughter called Metharme (14.3).
7“Iamque coactis cornibus in plenum noviens lunaribus orbem / illa Paphon genuit, de qua tenet insula nomen”
(Magnus 295-297).
277
IVF-conceived person to have a child, gave birth, newspapers all over the world reported that the
child was conceived naturally (‘First’). Likewise, the first gene-edited people, particularly those who
underwent CRISPR in vitro (the Chinese twins Nana and Lulu and many more to come), are bound
to be studied (without their consent) throughout their lifetimes, along with their own eventual
Human reproduction is well-understood in terms of conception and the ensuing pregnancy and
birth. The sole technology of in vitro fertilization acts as a culmination of this knowledge by
mimicking the conception, the most mysterious part of human reproduction. IVF as a clinical
practice and research helps us to learn about causes for (un)successful embryo growth, implantation,
and further development of a fetus. For example, “[t]he period between the 14th and 28th day of
embryo development is sometimes referred to as the ‘black box’ of human development” (Hurlbut
et al., Taniguchi et al.) and for this precise reason some scientists (John Appleby and Annelien
Bredenoord) argue for the extension of the 14-day rule—that prevents any embryo research on
embryos older than 14 days—to 28 days. The fourteenth day is “notable, because the embryo is then
individuated and can no longer become a twin” (Appleby and Bredenoord), forming an easily
recognizable “primitive streak” (Warnock 59, 66). The rule was never intended to serve as a line
denoting the moral status of human embryos (Hyun et al. 171) but has nonetheless served as a
legislative rule in some countries and a guideline in others since 1979. The rule was not questioned
until 2016, when technology allowed us to grow embryos in laboratories for fourteen days and,
theoretically, longer (Deglicerti et al., Shahbazi et al.). Until then, nature and technology seemed to
have a consensus regarding boundaries. Now, advances in synthetic biology can create artificial
278
embryo-like structures, called gastruloids, and bypass the primitive streak phase, thus forgoing the
14-day rule. These advances ask for the reevaluation and possible overturn of the rule in favor of
more specific ethical guidelines,8 which dovetail with other stem cell pursuits, such as organoid
research. This is just one example of how the conflation of both types of reproduction and the
Any kind of reproduction (natural or unnatural, unassisted or assisted, sexual or asexual, biological
designed as a roulette of sheer chance. As a part of this scientific ideology, it has become common
knowledge that young, good quality eggs and sperm have a better chance of creating a successful
embryo. Regardless, most human gametes are abnormal in some way. A small to large percent of
sperm succumb to quality issues of motility, morphology, and DNA fragmentation, or sperm
quantity. In a phenomenon termed atresia, “[t]he majority of human eggs, on the order of 20,000 per
year, die in the ovary by mechanisms that are not understood” (Kiessling 1056). Out of 300-500 eggs
that woman releases in her lifetime, only about 80 will have normal chromosomes. The rest of them
carry abnormal chromosomes, most of which are incompatible with life.10 With sexual intercourse
timed around monthly ovulations, the chance of pregnancy is on average about 20 percent per
8 In 2017, the Harvard Embryonic Stem Cell Research Oversight Committee issues a report exploring the ethics related
to the creation of synthetic human embryos, taking into account the human form, self-consciousness, and sentience that
could emerge from these embryos as well as the potential for their reproduction through ART.
9These labels of the kind of reproduction do not hold up as philosophically sound terms and need investigation. In the
case of human reproduction and ART the term natural is particularly problematic because ART use biotechnologies that
are as natural as it gets: they imitate organic processes and employ organic materials and therefore come the closest to
what we would consider natural. Synthetic biology is an extreme example of this ‘extended naturalness’ as it does not use
any method, material, or process that has not been invented by nature, but it is able to produce new designs that do not
exist in nature.
10With modern medicine, trisomy 21 or Down’s Syndrome is usually not fatal. Trisomy 16, however, is completely
incompatible with life unless some normal cells occur in addition to trisomic cells (Hassold et al.), which nevertheless
results in a major disability.
279
month and 85 percent per year for a healthy couple (National par. 3)—age and many other factors
not being taken into account. When male and female copies of DNA line up, many things can go
awry. DNA should replicate without mistake, copy after copy, and if it does not, the essential
principle of evolution reveals its work: the mutations can cause diseases or death, they can be a
not result in a pregnancy and those that do have about 10 percent chance to end in a miscarriage,
both largely due to incorrect chromosome counts. Human fecundity is not very efficient in
comparison to other species: we are designed to produce offspring sporadically every few years,11
with a foolproof system harboring a great chance of failure even in the first few steps.
Because it creates so much “waste” in the reproductive process, as Sarah Franklin argues, “‘nature’ is
depicted as incomprehensibly profligate” (‘Postmodern’ 332). This high degree of “natural wastage”
went unrecognized until the technology of monitoring reproduction was developed, beginning with
super sensitive pregnancy tests, low-tech fertility apps, ovulation tests, and special lubricants, which
all contribute to women knowing about their pregnancy much earlier than without these
technologies, and, subsequently, about the early loss of a pregnancy (chemical pregnancy). The focus
on conception rather than on its eventual creation—a living baby—is evident in fertility
advertisements and the change of language around fertility.12 In the internet age, the phrase ‘trying
for a baby’ has changed to reflect a less ambitious goal of ‘trying to conceive,’ or TTC in short, a
well-known phrase on fertility forums. After a visit to these websites, one becomes a target of
Before the invention of hormonal contraception and ART, the world fertility rate was four to seven children per
11
woman. Access to birth control and other factors have lowered these numbers to less than 2 children per woman in
Western countries (Roser).
12“The idea that female reproductive capacity is badly designed and in need of medical and technological assistance is as
old as the use of forceps. The means of technological enablement have gradually moved from one end of pregnancy,
parturition, to the other, conception” (Franklin ‘Postmodern’ 335).
280
fertility industry, promoting high-tech advances such as fertility preservation through sperm and egg
freezing and low-tech tools such as fertility-boosting mix of vitamins and superfoods. As Franklin
points out, these accounts, which are accepted as “natural facts,” link fertility with infertility as
“reproduction appears ‘naturally’ in need of assistance” (ib.). In this comparison, “‘natural’ and
assisted reproduction come to appear similar, both characterized by comparably high failure rates”
(ib.). The option of using ART, in principle, means that embryos can be designed, exchanged,
stored, and implanted in any womb. Reproduction is becoming increasingly independent from time
and space as well as mind and body (including age, gender, sexual orientation). Huxley’s satirized
vision of the prolific Hatchery, with high number cloning of embryos with low rate of incorrigible
At the same time, a backlash is taking place in Western countries as more people forgo strictly
medical assistance in reproducing and turn back to midwifery, non-medicated home births, and
herbal remedies, arguing that pregnancy is a normal process and not a sickness (Spallone 32). After
decades of encouraging parents to give formula to their infants and mothers pumping their milk for
infants while they are being taken care of by someone else, the emergence of the all-natural principle
could have been expected. Medicalized models in Western nations, at times changing their doctrines
faster than women can bear new children, challenge the idea of what is a ‘given’ in reproductive
practices. The all-natural principle also permeated the ART industry, with a turn from Western
medicine to alternative medicine, which usually includes additions from traditional Chinese medicine
and a more holistic approach to health. “That nature is considered in a positive light in ordinary
language motivates its skillful use in philosophical argument. Philosophers who appeal to concepts
or images of nature can rely on its diverse favorable connotations to lend support to their
281
arguments” (‘Appeals’ 518).13 The Nuffield Council on Bioethics published a report on ‘Ideas about
naturalness in public and political debates about science, technology and medicine,’ which also
enlisted poets to explore these ideas creatively. They conclude that the terms natural and unnatural
are often but not always used as values and that scientific organizations avoid using these terms
because they bear too broad of a meaning, potentially loaded with judgment of value (105-06).
Another problem of the all-natural principle in reproduction, pointed out by feminist critics, is that
it makes “sexual reproduction looks like an autonomous, unassisted act that gives certain women
privileged (and often tormented) knowledge of how maternity, kinship, and care work” (Emre 13).
Some feminists argue that “all reproduction, even reproduction that appears ‘natural,’ is assisted.
Some forms of assistance are simply rendered invisible because they are taken for granted by people
for whom reproduction is not an obviously political issue,” such as homosexual, transsexual and
asexual people (Emre 31).14 Reproduction is never an act of one’s own: each reproductive process
results in a person and at least three people are involved in each person’s becoming. Medical staff is
usually a part of pregnancy and birth—and with ART they are also a part of conception.
“The female body, in particular, expresses time and is close to time,” writes Sheila Heiti in her novel
Motherhood (107-08). The line between what we call artificial (supposedly aligned with technological)
and natural (without human intervention) is blurred with a simple planned conception. Due to
13“For example, adjoining the word ‘natural’ to ‘death’ already suggests a good death. Likewise, the idea of a natural life
span already prompts the thoughts that such a span of life is fitting and right and that living beyond it is suspect” (Jecker
‘Appeals’ 518).
14 “If you do not have to pay money to conceive, it may not occur to you that conception can be prohibitively costly. If
you do not have to transform your body to gestate, it may not occur to you that gestation is hard and risky work. If a
physician has never hurt you or mocked you or ignored you or lied to you, it may not occur to you that being deemed
healthy enough to have children is an ideology rather than an ontology. If you do not have to worry about the legal
status of your relationship to your child, it may not occur to you that she can be taken away. If you do not fear for your
safety, it may not occur to you that you need to stay alive to create life” (Emre 31).
282
increasing awareness of fertility cycles and decreasing fertility,15 a planned conception can become a
these facts is already a turn towards technological—just like a notepad or calculator can be
considered as elementary forms of human enhancement. Sharon Olds’s poem, ‘The Planned Child’
(5), describes with contempt the method of tracking ovulation by keeping a daily temperature chart.
This is not the right way to make a baby, the poem claims: the process should not involve any
I hated the fact that they had planned me, she had taken
a cardboard out of his shirt from the laundry
as if sliding on the backbone up out of his body,
and made a chart of the month and put
her temperature on it, rising and falling,
to know the day to make me – I would have
liked to have been conceived in heat,
in haste, by mistake, in love, in sex,
not on cardboard, the little x on the
rising line that did not fall again.
In assisted reproduction, conception requires thought and calculation from the patient, the
physician, the nurse, the ultrasound technician, the laboratory technician, and the pharmacist. Blood
tests, ultrasounds, medication dosages, surgery, petri dish, transfer, all conducted with the right
timing, are works of reason and mechanics. Nonetheless, chance plays a role, as it does in natural
reproduction. In the second part of Richard Meier’s poem Building Matilda, titled ‘Roulette’ (24),
narrated from a rarely seen partner’s perspective, IVF is paralleled to the title game, both founded
on keeping one’s hopes and luck up. Each loss in the roulette accentuates the emotional burden of
the treatment, in addition to the stress of the sheer act of playing a game, which emphasizes the
financial burden of betting the money on chance. The very title of the cycle of the poems, Building
15About 9 percent of men and about 11 percent of women of reproductive age in the United States have experienced
fertility problems (infertility or impaired fecundity) (Chandra et al.). In Western countries, 1 in 7 couples faces infertility
today (National par. 2).
283
Matilda, as well as the title of the poetry collection, Misadventure, pictures reproduction as an act of
labor—aside from the birth itself—as well as courage that an adventure asks for.
Even if IVF requires an embryo’s cooperation in its development, the techniques involved are
designed to facilitate and enhance fertilization (how many eggs end up fertilized), implantation
(chemical pregnancy), pregnancy and live birth rates. Each step of the IVF technology boosts the
natural potential, despite the many involved gametes which become collateral victims of the process.
IVF begins with ovarian stimulation, which is followed by a transvaginal ovum retrieval, also called
an egg retrieval. Working with more than one or two eggs in a month, as nature does, accelerates the
natural timing of woman’s cycles in collecting about a year’s worth of eggs at once; an optimal
number is ten, but there are often more, sometimes four times that. It is not a given that these eggs
are all mature enough, and that they will fertilize and succeed in developing further. If they do grow
and implant successfully, the chances of pregnancy can be twice as high as the natural way with a
single embryo from that batch (some clinics boast with a success rate of 65 percent per transfer for
284
women younger than 29 (e.g. Begoña)).16 Certainly, many transferred embryos do not necessarily
implant and many more do not even reach the transfer; they might be lost due to extra interventions
such as the de-freezing process or prenatal genetic testing that takes away a single cell from the outer
average, the procedure results in a 20 percent chance of a full-term, live singleton birth with normal
birth weight per IVF cycle for women younger than 35, 17 percent for women between 35-37, and
dropping consistently to 2 percent chance for women aged 43 and 44 and 0.6 percent chance for
women older than 44, according to a Society of Assisted Reproductive Technology Report from
2015 (5).
Taking into account that patients who use ART are typically those who have no success (i.e. live
births) without the assistance of technology, their chances are (at the current state of science and on
average) as high as they would have been had they been able to conceive spontaneously. This only
holds true, however, if ART is not used for enhancement purposes, such as to freeze eggs, sperm or
embryos and turn to IVF later in life, producing multiple children with a single pregnancy, or to
practice embryo selection for purposes other than medical treatment. (Non-medical treatments
include sex selection for causes other than sex-linked genetic diseases, but do not include the
deselection of an embryo incompatible with life, which is a type of infertility, or the use of ART for
non-infertility health issues, such as for HIV positive couples.) ART thus provides more
maneuvering space for reproduction, overcoming chronological issues (including the biological clock
and even death, allowing people to have children posthumously), spatial issues (ART is done at
different occasions and locations, it often requires no contact among the involved parties, nor
presence at the same place at the same time nor, in some cases, to be among the living; in the case of
16 This is a report from a Spanish clinic called Ivi for year 2017.
285
gamete donation, the genetic parents are strangers), and health issues (women without a uterus are
able to receive a uterus transplant or hire a surrogate to carry their genetic child).
Besides that, IVF itself—without the additional futuristic technologies—is altering human
reproduction: it is not only treatment for infertility but also “a technological intervention at the point
in the human cycle where natural selection operates at its strongest” (Hanevik et al. 1400). As such,
subfertile and infertile couples.” Hanevik et al. believe that “IVF should be seen as a primary
example of how the human species is becoming not only culturally—but also biologically—
dependent on our own technology” (ib.). I also consider ART as an enhancement of the
reproductive process and link the idea to Huxley’s depiction of the Hatchery, a satirized fertility
The impact of ART on kinship is massive, not only for infertile and same-sex couples who can now
create a child of their own genes but also for other kinds of near-future advanced bioengineering,
such as technological parthenogenesis, reproducing without available gametes through other kinds
pregnancy, experiments with cloning (induced twinning) and artificial gestation. Most of these
technologies are labeled as either unacceptable for federal funding or as warranting additional review
in a Human Embryo Research Panel report from 1994 (77-83); none of these restrictions has been
286
5.2 The Terminology of ART
I have shown above how the mere presence of assisted technology has conflated into our
conceptions of human reproduction, resulting in the merge between what is considered natural and
what is considered assisted reproduction. As Sarah Franklin argues, this conflation is ideological and
stems from “instrumentalism that makes its own truth” (‘Postmodern’ 335) by taking over the
“natural facts” and resulting in a postmodern crisis of “legitimacy,” “loss of faith,” and “a collapse
of foundational authority” (338). Construction of what we think of as ‘nature’ is shifting, she claims,
as the referent system has been lost and replaced with technologically induced ‘facts’ about ‘nature.’
Huxley’s Brave New World destabilizes the idea of what is natural to an even greater extent: the novel
renders a perverse image of using ART as a means of eugenics, led by an ideological subjugation of
In political and otherwise public discussions on ART and research around it, it is fundamental to use
the right language. A common error with the term assisted reproductive technology is to call it
artificial reproductive technology, perhaps revealing a prejudice against this kind of treatment as
artificial (intervened) conception in relation to the natural (not intervened) course of events. If, in an
epitome later adapted to the humanist attitude, “nothing human is alien to me [a human],” as
Terence17 famously wrote, the logic goes that nothing possible in nature is unnatural either. Since the
human is a part of nature, nothing possible to achieve with technology, imagination, or any other
human contribution of mind or skill is unnatural. ART is thus a natural phenomenon: after all, it
merely imitates a natural event. The artificiality is a useful category to designate a human-made
17 Terence was a comic playwright but also a former enslaved person from Africa (he took his name from his owner, P.
Terentius Lucanus) and as such well-placed to preach about human universalism. His phrase became widely known
already in Rome and was later endorsed by Saint Augustine which ultimately led to its humanist adaptation.
287
product, “especially in imitation of something natural” (‘Artificial’). According to this interpretation,
ART is an artificial reproductive technology. Not all technologies imitate nature, however. But where
do we draw the line? Is synthetic biology which uses natural processes to create unnatural products
imitative technology? The dichotomies between natural-artificial and nature-technology simply does
not hold up anymore. Using the right terminology in ART when basic ontological and
epistemological terms like these are put in question is therefore especially disorienting.
genetic diagnosis, which does not accurately represent the fact that the embryo undergoing
preimplantation genetic diagnosis is not yet in the womb at the point of testing, whereas the embryo
undergoing prenatal genetic diagnosis is already located in the womb. Another consideration
regarding this choice of the term is that preimplantation genetic screening (PGS) or testing (PGT)
makes for a more accurate wording than the more common preimplantation genetic diagnosis
(PGD). This is primarily because this testing, like many other prenatal tests, is not foolproof against
cell mosaicism, in which both false positive and false negative results may occur (rendering false
Correct terminology is crucial in discussing the ethics of these technologies with the general public,
as well as issues that relate to reproduction in general. For example, in 2019, abortion laws across the
USA became stricter (Ohio, Missouri, Georgia) or were proposed to become stricter (Maryland,
18Some—we are not sure how many—embryos are mosaic. Mosaicism means that an embryo has normal and some
abnormal cells, with varying percentages. Embryos undergoing PGD are biopsied with a single cell that cannot give a full
reading but are discarded or transferred on the basis of this reading. Some clinics, working on the edge of science, are
willing to transfer embryos with chromosomal abnormalities into uteri, which nonetheless results in a small percentage
of healthy babies (Karow)—seen as “a new last chance” for women in their forties who wish to have a child of their
own genes (Stephen Hall).
288
Minnesota, West Virginia, etc.), following the fetal heartbeat bill that makes all abortions illegal as
soon as a heartbeat is detected in a fetus—ability to meet this standard for an abortion is highly
dependent on one’s access to health care and available technology. The heartbeat criterion was a
cause for heated debates between conservatives and liberals in determining whether heart cells can
be said to produce a heartbeat in a 3-week-old fetus or whether the flutter of the cells is not an
actual heartbeat, as the structure that produces the beat is heartlike but not an actual heart. More
expansive than the heartbeat bill, the Alabamian near-total abortion ban “‘protects the sanctity of
unborn life’ with one curious exception: The law deems only fertilized eggs inside a womb worthy of
protection, not ones routinely destroyed in the process of fertility treatment” (Newkirk par. 1-2).
Religion plays a major role in proposing such bills as it goes back to the fundamental question of the
human. Thomas Aquinas’s Summa Theologica (1265–74), written under strong Aristotelian and
Augustinian influence, established a long-standing theological view on the moral status of the
embryo and the fetus. Under Question 64 on murder, Aquinas describes human gestational life as
“first a living thing, then an animal, and lastly a man,” thus following successive phases from a
vegetative (plant-like) to sensitive (animal-like) and finally rational life (human, human-like?). Only
when the fetus becomes animated, in the event of delayed hominization after conception, called
ensoulment (revoking moral viability),19 is it considered human.20 Although the Roman Catholic
Church still relies on moral and theological views proposed by Summa Theologica, it had parted with
Aquinas’s view on human development and has, since 1869, defended the position that an embryo is
19For Aristotle, ensoulment takes place forty days after conception for male fetuses and eighty days for female fetuses.
In the Islamic tradition, this point is recognized as 120 days after conception.
20In the early fourteenth century, Dante writes in Purgatorio: “as soon as the articulation of the brain is perfected in the
embryo, The First Mover turns to it, rejoicing over such a handiwork of nature, and breathes into it a new spirit full of
power, [...] a single soul that lives and feels and revolves upon itself” (329).
289
infused with a human soul upon fertilization (which automatically forbids abortion, IVF, and
embryo research).21 The Roman Catholic Church is the strongest proponent of this belief, which was
founded first on preformationist theory, based on rudimentary microscopy of a tiny infant called
homunculus living in a human sperm and on late nineteenth-century work on fertilization (Neaves
2541).22
Biotechnologies are living a very public life and “the control, enhancement, and harnessing of
reproductive and genetic processes are the basis for the emergent industry of biotechnology, in
which the politics of fertility extend [sic] from soil to star wars” (Franklin ‘Postmodern’ 326).23 This
is also why better terminology would is needed in discussing embryos which have “acquire[d] a high
profile in legal disputes, medical literature, and media coverage” (336). In becoming widely disputed
public entities, largely due to IVF and later stem cell research, embryos were granted legal
protection. However, there is no universal definition of the embryo because its exact beginning of it
is poorly defined: the beginning varies from right after the fertilization to four weeks after and the
ending is universally considered at the end of the eighth week of gestation, when the embryo
becomes a fetus (Larsen 4). Some scientists have criticized the terminology of naming a
preimplantation conceptus (a zygote that has developed into an embryo but not yet implanted) an
embryo and proposed to follow plant reproduction terminology where such an embryo would be
21 Doctrines of protestant churches differ according to their interpretations of the Bible. Compare Jeremiah 1:5, “Before
I formed you in the womb I knew you, and before you were born I consecrated you; I appointed you a prophet to the
nations,” with Ecclesiastes 11:5, “As you do not know how the spirit comes to the bones in the womb of a woman with
child, so you do not know the work of God who makes everything.”
22Some Roman Catholic theologists and priest disagree with this doctrine, using the term preembryo in 1991 as “not yet
a person [since] its statistical potential for becoming such is small, it is not clear that nontherapeutic experiments can be
excluded in principle” (Neaves 2542).
23Technologies can be used for treatment or enhancement and they also have an inherently dual use in curing and
causing disease. Nuclear power, biotechnology or AI could therefore be detrimental for human civilization.
290
called a proembryo. It has since been agreed upon that the prefix pro- implies ‘in favor of the embryo,’
which is why the less ambiguous prefix pre- is more commonly used as pre-embryo (Hurlbut 95).
The debate began in the UK in 1984, when the Warnock Committee, or the British Committee of
Inquiry on IVF issues, met to regulate IVF in fear of the exploitation of the embryos. Lead by
philosopher Mary Warnock as a first institutional debate on IVF, the committee had a wide reach;
nonetheless, it took the UK government six more years to write the Human Fertilisation and
Embryology Act of 1990. The only issue the Warnock Committee could not agree on was the ethics
of embryonic research (Warnock 66-69, 92; see comment in Mulkay 612). The distinction between
pre-embryo and embryo played a crucial role in their argumentation: the term “embryo proper” was
used for an embryo older than fourteen days, but they did not use any specific term for a younger
embryo. Based on the already-existing 14-day rule in the US,24 the committee accepted the 14-day
rule in the UK as well—the rule that was accepted in many other countries and is still in place today,
The suggestions for terming the embryo before day 15 a preembryo were made in 1985 in the UK as
well as in the US. In trying to justify embryonic research, Sir Andrew Huxley, president of the Royal
Society and Aldous Huxley’s half-brother, stated that there was “an unfortunate ambiguity in the
word embryo” and made a distinction between these two phases of the embryo, calling them the
“extraembryonic tissue” and the “embryo proper” (2). Two years after the Warnock Report, the
single embryologist on the Warnock Committee, Anne McLaren, wrote that the terminology in the
24The 14-day rule was established in 1979 by the Ethics Advisory Board of the US Department of Health, Education
and Welfare. Their report supported human embryo research but limited it to the first 14 days the of embryonic
development.
291
report was unsatisfactory because “the embryo does not exist during the first two weeks after
fertilization [but is rather a] mass of cells generated by a fertilized egg” (570). “The embryologist
knows what is meant; the uninitiated must be left gasping,” she added. This was McLaren’s response
to a fellow commissioner who said that terms like preembryo were “cosmetic words” and
manipulated to “polarize an ethical discussion.” She replied: “Cosmetics hide, clarity illuminates.”
Ann Kiessling, a prominent American reproductive biologist, explains the reaction from the
scientific community: “It may be futile to attempt to replace ‘embryo’ with another more accurate
term with respect to human eggs fertilized by sperm. The hope in this regard is to educate the public
that a cleaving egg is not the same stage of ‘embryo’ as an ‘embryo’ two weeks following
implantation in the uterus” (1089). As a result, efforts are made in journalism today to distinguish a
‘proper’ embryo from an ‘early-stage embryo’ or blastocyst (Williams et a. 800). The debate is still
going strong,25 with preembryo triumphing it without ever again being named as such in official
This is also why, when the narrator in Brave New World describes the cloning process of 36-hour-old
fertilized eggs, the terminology he uses seems confusing: he simply calls them eggs, implying that
they are not yet fertilized. The fact that they are indeed fertilized eggs is confirmed when these
25 Under George W. Bush’s presidency (2001-2009), research on stem cells obtained from human embryos was famously
banned. This ban was reversed as soon as Barack Obama became the next president. With new technology of in vitro
gametogenesis (making artificial gametes from any kind of human cell), which began to be invented in 2006 and was
largely advanced after 2014, this controversy would be overcome as embryos would not be needed to make stem cells
for research.
26The only highly popular monograph where the term proembryo was used in relation to IVF was Anne McLaren’s
contribution 1986 (Reproduction in Mammals: Vol. 5: Manipulating Reproduction, eds. C. R. Austin, Colin Russell Austin,
Roger Valentine Short).
In Niccol’s 1997 film Gattaca the geneticist uses the term for an embryo before the implantation: “We can implant the
27
292
multiplied “buds” are expected to evolve into identical twins (19). After many debates on what to call
them, fertilized eggs are today routinely called embryos. On the contrary, Huxley, writing in 1931,
simply followed human medical embryology texts that “still refer to the first two weeks after
fertilization as the ‘ovum’ period” (Kiessling 1089). This is a tradition from at least the seventeenth
century when William Harvey first proposed that life begins with an egg. Harvey never found an
actual egg but he did find an embryo—which he called ovum. Ex ovus omnia. Scientists eventually
conjured that all living beings originate from eggs, one way or another, which was ultimately
confirmed under the microscope. The mythological egg, one of the guiding principles to think about
Ann A. Kiessling agrees that the terminology has been confusing for public debates since the very
beginning of ART: “Unfortunately, scientists did not jump into the debate with the clear message
that cleaving eggs are not embryos, not yet. […] No new terms were developed in the early days of
human assisted reproduction to describe the events that could now be seen in petri dishes that had
never been seen before. Scientists were aware of the naturally limited developmental potential of
each early conceptus, but society was not aware. This confusion extends to this day and is now
compounded by the new tasks eggs are being called upon to perform” (1088). The debate around
terminology is just one example of how the assisted reproductive technology formulates who and
what constitutes a fetus, a mother, a human, a family. This debate is akin to Bruno Latour and Steve
Woolgar’s influential findings about the construction of scientific facts in Laboratory Life (1979) or
Donna Haraway’s exposure of the myth of scientific objectivity in her essay ‘Situated Knowledges’
(1988). All these scholars argue that concrete practices make truth, including the truth created in a
scientific laboratory: the truth is co-created by scientists that study, name, and manipulate the
scientific material, by the instruments and technology they use, authorizations they need in order to
293
pursue their work, and by the sheer fact that the object of observation is being observed in a study.
On top of that, the public might receive scientific work with misconception (which is why the field
of science writing has developed). For the purpose of understanding central bioethical issues in
ART, the Nuffield Council on Bioethics, established in UK in 1991, has offered authoritative
guidance on matters such as donor conception, non-invasive prenatal testing, human embryo
culture, genome editing and human reproduction, critical care decisions in fetal and neonatal
medicine, novel techniques for the prevention of mitochondrial DNA disorders, including an
With less terminological weight that nonetheless speaks volumes, the widely used term test tube baby
was popular already before the technology of IVF existed, and consistently used to describe children
conceived through IVF when the technology first emerged (‘Academy’). Even though no test tube is
used in either of the procedures, the term test-tube baby was “commonly used [for] artificial
on artificial insemination, titled Test Tube Babies (xiv). At the time Rohleder published this book the
term burst into public consciousness in the USA in the context of eugenic movement. The first
human born as a result of artificial insemination entered the world in Philadelphia back in 1884
without the grandeur and pomp that surrounded the first IVF baby (Ruffenach).28 Knowledge about
artificial insemination increased demand for it and normalized the practice by the end of the second
world war (Swanson 633). This included freezing semen for the agricultural insemination business,
28This could have happened decades earlier when James Marion Sims, the father of modern gynecology, attempted to
inseminate six women 55 times with their husbands’ sperm in 1850s but failed—one woman got pregnant but
miscarried—because he thought that ovulation happens during menstruation (Swanson 598). “In 1840s, no one knew
that human females ovulate monthly, the menstrual cycle remained a mystery, and the question of what determines a
human embryo was uncertain” (Lepore The Mansion 16).
294
which was later applied to reproductive biology more generally (Landecker 225). Labeling IVF-
conceived children as test tube babies was therefore merely seen as a continuation of the first and
already widely accepted ART, and the eugenic connotation got lost in time. In Brave New World,
fetuses grow in bottles, yet ‘test-tubes’ are very common when describing the process of creating
these bottled babies: “Blithe was the singing of the young girls over their test-tubes” (137) or “one
upset two test-tubes full of spermatozoa” (139). Almost a hundred years later, test tube babies and
especially IVF babies are still the most common terms used for IVF-conceived children as if their
In 1912, the American anatomists John E. McWhorter and Allen Whipple grew chick embryos in
vitro, followed by many others in the next decade. By 1923, Britain became a leading site for work
on “controlled growth” through respected scientists Thomas Strangeways and Honor Fell. The first
public mention of the term test tube baby appears to come from Thomas Strangeways who claimed
in 1926 that organ culture29 supported the test tube babies (Duncan Wilson 30). That same year,
Strangeways also declared in his lecture on tissue culture that “the idea of the test-tube baby is not
inherently impossible” (38). Also in 1926, Julian Huxley published his only fictional work, a science
fiction short story titled ‘The Tissue-Culture King,’ which agrees with Strangeways’s claim that the
tissue and organ culture support what was to become IVF (see more on Julian Huxley’s only
fictional text in the section 5.6 on the Huxley brothers). After Aldous Huxley published Brave New
World in 1936, “popular accounts and scientific endorsement of test-tube babies increased” and
newspapers claimed that Honor Fell and her Strangeways lab colleagues were taking steps toward
29“‘Tissue culture’ is a blanket term that covers the culture of cells and whole organs, known as ‘cell culture’ and ‘organ
culture’ respectively” (Duncan Wilson 125).
295
the Brave New World (30, 133). After being targeted by press coverage saying that she “was about to
grow babies in bottles,” Honor Fell’s changed her endorsement of pursuing the test tube babies into
words of caution against sensationalist portrayals of tissue culture; Fell’s case shows how popular
representations and attitudes about the test tube babies have impacted the science itself (53).30
30Not all scientists kept the gap between popular and scientific culture. Some scientists from the Strangeways lab, Petar
Martinovitch and Arthur Hughes, in fact, wrote short, witty poems about their research: “Testicles and ovaries /
Explanted in a row / Grown by Martinovitch / In Vitro,” wrote Hughes about Martinovitch. The poem concludes by
suggesting that tissue culture not only reveals us something about cells but also about their researcher, with Martinovitch
being another tricky life-form culture (Squier Liminal 80).
31Researchers from the Strangeways Lab even wrote poems about these films. For example, a poem by Petar
Martinovitch cynically implies that these films do nothing for scientific advancement, but rather help to communicate
scientific research to the public: “But, to make the story immortal / The show must be filmed / […] / We see exactly
what we have related before, / And there is no use of seeing more.” Further, Martinovitch suggests that the cinema has
a new effect on science: “You must tell a tale!” (Squier Liminal 84-85).
296
An individual—one’s own—fetus remained a projection and a sensation in the womb. The popular
children’s novel The Water-Babies: A Fairy Tale for a Land Baby by Charles Kingsley, which was written
as part-satire in support of Darwinism (Lepore The Mansion 15), depicted fetuses in bottles, and as
“good little boys” to whom the book is dedicated (6); both Aldous Huxley and his brother Julian
read it. In one of the editions of the novel, their grandfather, Thomas Henry Huxley, also known as
Darwin’s bulldog, is illustrated as inspecting a baby in a bottle. The texts supposes that, if a water-
baby was ever found, “they would have put it into spirits, or into the Illustrated News, or perhaps cut
it into two halves, poor dear little thing, and sent one to Professor Owen, and one to Professor
Huxley, to see what they would each say about it” (53). After hearing this, four-year-old Julian wrote
Water babies in the bottles might have a shocking effect—Brave New World features an ode to the
bottle: “Bottle of mine, why was I ever decanted? / Skies are blue inside of you, / The weather is
always fine” (79)—until we remember that each and every one of us has spent nine months of our
prenatal life bottled in the amniotic fluid. Amphibian like this, we are not that remote from axolotls,
297
for example, which fascinated Julian Huxley in his later life with their abilities of pedomorphosis and
regeneration. Julian became an evolutionary biologist, following the advice of his grandfather and
Kingsley, who advises “good little boys” not to ever think something like “a water-baby is contrary
to nature” (54), because “[y]ou do not know what Nature is, or what she can do; and nobody knows;
not even Sir Roderick Murchison, or Professor Owen, or Professor Sedgwick, or Professor Huxley,
or Mr. Darwin, or Professor Faraday, or Mr. Grove, or any other of the great men whom good boys
are taught to respect. They are very wise men; and you must listen respectfully to all they say: but
even if they should say, which I am sure they never would, ‘That cannot exist. That is contrary to
nature,’ you must wait a little, and see; for perhaps even they may be wrong” (Kingsley 55).
In Kingsley’s book, water-babies live “in St. Brandan’s fairy isle” [St. Brendan’s Isle] (149), also
sometimes called Isle of the Blessed, a phantom island, named after Saint Brendan of Clonfert who
claimed to have landed there in the sixth century. It was depicted on maps and reported to have
been seen up until the nineteenth century. “[T]he isle stood all on pillars” and “whether men can see
it or not, St. Brandan’s Isle once actually stood there; a great land out in the ocean, which has sunk
and sunk beneath the waves. Old Plato called it Atlantis” (150). Charles Darwin, too, had theories
about islands, “having once existed as halting-places, of which not a wreck now remains,” as missing
links to “how many of the inhabitants of the more remote islands […] have reached their present
homes” (On 100), which is true in cases where whole landmasses, volcanic pumice, etc. rafted the
ocean currents. These two examples are testimonies to the metaphorical and literal contribution of
For Julian, as well as for Aldous, the fictional and scientific worlds merged early and remained
intertwined. Julian Huxley grew up to believe in a different kind of utopia, the one reached by the
298
advancement of science and technology in the imminent future, teaching that “[t]he human race, in
fact, is surrounded by a large area of unrealized possibilities, a challenge to the spirit of exploration”
and that the social as well as individual bliss could be achieved by “man remaining man, but trans-
cending himself, by realizing new possibilities of and for his human nature” (15). He named this
belief transhumanism.
Having been called “the single most famous science fiction novel to describe genetic engineering
[…] Brave New World has become a major point of reference in discussion of cloning and related
techniques […] since the 1980s” (Seed 447), only after the birth
was born “with a lusty yell” on July 25, 1978, wrote Newsweek, it
was a “cry round the brave new world” (Ball Unnatural 208). The
The cover story about Brown’s birth began with an excerpt from
Figure 33 Time cover from the week of July
31, 1978, when the first IVF-conceived baby
was born. the Brave New World Hatchery.
Likewise, in 2014 The New York Times announced a three-person baby with the title, ‘The brave new
world of three-parent I.V.F.’ (Tingley). The title of the novel is most commonly used in journalist
and also scientific publications: Brave New Mistake, Grave New World, Brave New Politics, Not So Brave A
World, Brave New Brain, Brave New Face, Brave New Genome, Brave New Bioethics, Digital Medicine: O Brave
299
New World, Brave New RNA World, Brave in a New World, etc., most often with a negative connotation
and a warning. Due to the novel’s resonances with real-world fears, Huxley never really went out of
style and the phrase became a commonplace label for repercussions of any technological
advancements. For example, in Designing Babies: The Brave New World of Reproductive Technology (1999),
Roger Gosden offers a look into the future of ART as prescient in Huxley’s Brave New World. In The
Tomorrow Makers: A Brave New World of Living-Brain Machines (1987), Grant Fjermedal extends
Huxley’s vision of the world to latest developments in robotics and computer science and addresses
Although the following discussion focuses on the reproductive process as described in Huxley’s
novel and compares it to the actual techniques of assisted reproduction, I will briefly look into
largely forgotten science fiction works published a few years before Brave New World. The value of
science fiction is not in making predictions, as many incorrectly assume. Instead, science fiction
engages with questions raised in the present and offers a range of scenarios that are informed by
historical and cultural knowledge and only collaterally, as an inspiration, by science and technology.
Ectogenesis and synthetic babies were a common topic in 1920s and 1930s American and British
science fiction, as well as more generally in popular and scientific culture. They appeared “in
broadsheet and tabloid newspapers, in pulp magazines like Amazing Stories, highbrow periodicals like
F. R. Leavis’s Scrutiny, in speculative essays, popular novels and even in scientific journals like
Nature” (Duncan Wilson 35). In science fiction of the interwar period, they were largely presented as
oppressive to the fabricated future societies, except in Lilith Lorraine’s ‘Into the 28th Century,’
discussed below.
300
In 1927, the American magazine Amazing Stories published ‘The Machine Man of Ardathia’ by
Francis Flagg, and a year later ‘A Biological experiment’ by David H. Keller, both of which bear
many resemblances with Brave New World. In all three works, synthetic babies are a commodity
grown in a decanter-like vessel and subjugated to biological and mechanical perfecting, both while
grown in vitro and later in life. In Flagg’s text, humanoid creatures spend their whole lives in these
vessels, disgusted by physical contact and uncapable of empathy, much like in Forster’s ‘The
Machine Stops.’ Looking like malformed embryos they send a clear message of degeneration if we
were to follow the developments in tissue culture. In Keller’s text, all reproduction has moved to in
vitro mass production, beginning with in vitro ovaries, like in Brave New World, and individuals have
301
The most known and influential text from this time, besides Huxley’s novel, is British author Olaf
Stapledon’s novel Last and First Men: A Story of Near and Far Future (1929). Stapledon also criticizes
tissue culture, together with mechanization and industrialization of the society, through the so-called
Fourth Men, a product of man remaking himself into a non-humanlike organism through in vitro
fertilization of ovaries. Mass production and subjugation of workers (Stapledon shared the Marxist
view that machines disenfranchise human workers) leads only to greater exploitation of human
manufacturers imposed on them by the very commodities they make, and the non-humanlike
Turning to women’s writing of the period, Alison Flood’s 2018 article claims that British author
Rose Macaulay’s novel What Not (1918), which likely influenced Huxley and Orwell, has “finally
found its time” (‘What’). Although utopias written by women have been around ever since the
sixteenth century and increasingly in the late nineteenth century, they rarely made it into the canon:
most notable exception is Charlotte Perkins Gilman’s Herland (1915) in which a women-only society
reproduces by parthenogenesis.
In 1930, when Huxley was working on Brave New World, Lilith Lorraine (pen name for Mary Maude
Dunn Wright)32 published the short story ‘Into the 28th Century,’ and Sophie Wenzel Ellis published
the short story ‘Creatures of the Light.’ Both texts feature ectogenesis and artificial wombs as means
32Dunn Wright had more than one pen name, three of which were masculine names. This was a common practice
among women science fiction writers (e.g. Alice Sheldon used James Tiptree Jr. and was believed to be a man long into
her successful career). As Wright explains in an interview, “if the editors and publishers knew I was a woman they
wouldn’t pay me more than half what they do now” (Georgia Nelson).
302
for perfecting human evolution. Both authors were regular contributors to science fiction magazines
and the works discussed here remain their most praised contributions. (The two authors are now
largely forgotten, except for in a few anthologizations in women’s science fiction writing.) I would
like to point out the overlap between the main themes of these two texts and Huxley’s: assisted
reproduction with eugenics, liberation of women, conditioning of fetuses and children, utopian
quest for human perfection and enhancement, all achieved through science and technology and
strict societal order. I am not interested about potential influence, which likely did not exist, but
would rather like to point out how prominent these themes were in the 1920s and 1930s USA and
UK. Apart from systemic reasons33 of why Huxley was more successful with his book, I inquire why
Huxley’s interpretation managed to mark literary and cultural history for at least the next century
while the other texts with the same themes were largely forgotten.
Lorraine’s ‘Into the 28th Century’ focuses on the social order, like Huxley’s, and presents a futuristic
utopia under a socialist rule in Corpus Christi (Lorraine’s own city), renamed Nirvania. This Golden
Age world is ruled by one government, like in Huxley’s novel, but includes more feminist and
socialist practices. Feminism has achieved equality among the sexes; however, “man still leads in
invention, mechanics, mathematics and the more strenuous sports. Woman has ceased to imitate
man, being content in her own sphere” (257). Marriage is not universal as women are not
economically dependent anymore and is based on love. Sex is rare other than for conception.
Although women are free of childbearing, their uteri are still a place of conception, from where the
embryo is removed into an artificial womb, never to be parented. Following eugenics’ ideas of the
1930s, this utopian society has “weeded out undesirable racial straits by wholesale sterilization”
33These reasons are based in gender and the Huxley family influence as well as the inherent book market factors (choice
of the publisher, advertising, number of reviews, etc.).
303
(258), including all races but Black people; the superior race is “a subtle blending of the noblest
qualities of the ancient Greek, the North American Indian, the Oriental and the Anglo-Saxon” (261).
In a similar fashion to Huxley’s imagined system of education, utopians of Nirvania learn in their
sleep, are given psychological training during the day, and are encouraged to travel the world.
In Wenzel Ellis’s story ‘Creatures of the Light,’ the quest for perfecting the human race is left to a
single rogue scientist, a “hunchback” named Emil Mundson, who is modeled after real-life
mathematician and electrical engineer Charles Proteus Steinmetz. The story attempts to answer the
question of “why all parents expect their children to be nearer perfection that themselves, and why is
it a natural impulse for them to be willing to sacrifice themselves to better their offspring?” (181).
(This question is addressed by the American ethicist Michael Sandel and briefly summarized in the
final part of this chapter, titled Transhumanism.) Reproduction is in focus in Ellis’s story, as the
main goal of the mad scientist is to breed a superhuman race and join scientifically created and
perfected antagonist Adam with his artificial Eve. He is also interested in having John Northwood
and Athalia, both naturally endowed with beauty and intelligence, join his mission; he “combed the
world [to] find […] the perfect couples” (200) that would establish the enhanced race of Adam and
Eve. Admittedly, Mundson’s plan fails because of conflicting desires: Adam wants Athalia and Eve
wants John. Adam is a lot like Frankenstein’s creation (who also calls himself Adam at one point),
despising his not-quite-human condition and seeking vengeance through murder. He and his Eve
ultimately destroy the whole world that Dr. Mundson created. Dr. Mundson, John, and Athalia
manage to escape from the destruction and the latter two come to the same eugenic conclusion the
story began with: “And who can say to what extent [Dr. Mundson] ha[s] thus furthered natural
evolution? […] Our children might be more than geniuses, Doctor!” (212).
304
In an uncannily similar manner to Huxley’s Hatchery, people in Adam’s world are created with
assisted reproductive technology that reinvents all kinship ties and accelerates the natural pace of
reproduction: “Before the first year had passed, the youngest baby will have grandchildren; that is, if
the baby tests out fit to pass its seed down to the new generation” (199). Made to grow through
chemical enhancement, these infants are grown with the help of a Life Ray in artificial wombs called
“the Leyden jar mothers”34 and, like in all three utopias discussed here, never mothered.
Furthermore, they are being educated through a variety of conditioning and memorizing techniques
(202), a lot like Huxley’s. After seeing the process, John and Athalia are convinced they do not want
to succumb to Mundson’s experiment despite his hopes that they will: “I don’t relish having my
children turned into—experiments,” they both say (200, 211), to which Mundson responds:
“Nonsense! Can you say that all life—all matter—is not the result of scientific experiment?” (200).
The satirization of the World State practices in Brave New World manages to walk the fine line
between mocking and commenting on basic societal issues, from politics and religion to kinship and
spirituality. Lorraine’s utopian short story ‘Into the 28th Century’ focuses on the organization of the
society without depicting any ambiguity of such imposed order; Lorraine’s utopia exists without
acknowledging the dystopian parts of its arrangements. Ellis’s short story ‘Creatures of the Light’
brings up philosophical dilemmas of scientific mingling with human procreation and enhancement
but remains in the realm of a failed experiment that is never applied to the society as a whole.
34“‘The Leyden Jar mother,’ said Dr. Mundson. ‘It is the dream of us scientists realized. The human mother’s body does
nothing but nourish and protect her unborn child, a job which science can do better. And so, in New Eden, we take the
young embryo and pace it in the Leyder jar mother, where the Life Ray, electricity and chemical food shortens the period
of gestation to a few days’” (Ellis 201).
305
5.4 A Brief History of IVF
Some ART techniques are foreshadowed to an amazing detail in Huxley’s Brave New World. Nothing
close to what he imagined had been done yet in the real world before the novel was written in 1931.
In 1934, the first eggs (from rabbits) were successfully fertilized in a laboratory—through a form of
parthenogenesis no less35—by Gregory Pincus, one of the main researchers responsible for the
development of the oral birth-control pill. Pincus received a lot of negative publicity and lost tenure
at Harvard University for this experiment (Buttar). The New York Times reported: ‘Rabbits Born in
Glass: Haldane-Huxley Fantasy Made Real by Harvard Biologists’ (Waldemar). Pincus’s former
assistant, Miriam Menkin, worked with physician John Rock to achieve first the fertilization of
human eggs in 1944 (Ruffenach ‘Rock-Menkin’). When Huxley added a foreword to Brave New World
after the World War II, he surmised that “the horror” of his utopia was technically and ideologically
more than a century away (Huxley P.S. 9). At that time, fertilizing human eggs in vitro had already
been done without transferring the embryo into a uterus. IVF was thoroughly researched and
Nonetheless, not much can be inferred from Huxley’s general comments on his opinion about
reproductive technology developing in a similar manner as in Brave New World. With reproduction
being such a prominent theme in Huxley’s writing life, it is unfortunate that he maintained attention
35 Parthenogenesis (Greek for virgin creation or birth) is a form of reproduction where an egg develops into an embryo
without ever being fertilized by sperm. Parthenogenesis is known to occur naturally in some animal species; mammals
have not yet been reported to achieve parthenogenesis. In a technological parthenogenesis, a female egg could be joined
with a female sperm, possibly coming from the very same woman, which would resemble cloning. The technique was
discovered in 1899 with Jacques Loeb manually dividing a sea urchin egg. With human parthenogenesis, men would
become superfluous in reproduction, however, “[a] parthenogenic embryo cannot grow to a full adult under any
circumstances, so this technique provides a kind of ethical bypass around the issue of destroying human blastocysts to
disaggregate them into stem cells” (Landecker 5). This kind of technology could be used, rather than for reproductive
biology, for treating women with “serious diseases, such as Type I diabetes or spinal cord injury, [....] with cell lines
derived from their own eggs” (Kiessling 1092). Human Embryo Research Panel has shown that “parthenogenesis provides a
valuable system for studying cleavage stage eggs without creating embryos” (Kiessling 1081).
306
only to overpopulation—which was becoming a common concern and has remained a concern to
this date—but did not comment on ART in the added foreword to the Brave New World, in the essay
‘Brave New World Revisited,’ nor later in Island, a utopian counterpart to dystopian and satirical
Brave New World (1962). Huxley died in 1963, but had he lived for another decade, he would have
learned about the exciting future of ART, uncannily similar to what he imagined back in 1931 when
even artificial insemination in humans was a taboo. In 1959, rabbits were successfully created via
IVF (Zhu), and Patrick Steptoe and Robert Edwards, who eventually achieved the creation of the
first IVF baby, published their early work on the in vitro fertilization of 56 oocytes, receiving an
“overwhelmingly critical” response in the national press with headlines including “Life is created in a
test tube” and influential BBC paralleling their research on the scale with the atomic bomb explosion
(Litynski 99).
In 1971, the American science journalist David Rorvik published a book paraphrasing Huxley’s title,
Brave New Baby: Promise and Perils of the Biological Revolution. During the same year, the Look magazine
published an article titled ‘The Test Tube Baby is Coming’, reporting on the work of the American
biologist Landrum Shettles, Rorvik’s friend, who attempted to conduct the first human IVF in 1973.
Because he had ignored his superiors and the ethical guidelines on research on humans, the
experiment was halted. In 1978, the title of first scientist to conduct IVF in humans—along with the
Nobel Prize—went to English physician Robert Edwards who, with the help of surgeon Patrick
Steptoe and nurse Jean Purdy, managed to create the world’s first IVF baby, Louise Brown. He was
followed by many in a practice that became widespread in the UK and the US for a good
decade. The same year that Louise Brown was born, the science journalist David Rorvik published a
nonfiction book, In His Image: The Cloning of Man, that became sensational because he claimed to
provide scientific evidence of the first man (a billionaire) to be cloned in a secretive process on an
307
island somewhere beyond Hawaii (a very utopian location). Although the book was determined to
be a hoax, Rorvik still claims it is legitimate. Just a few years after this controversy, Rorvik and
Shettles co-authored Rites of Life: Scientific Evidence for Life Before Birth, in which they argue that
In 2018, forty years after Louise Brown’s birth, genes of two IVF-conceived babies were presumably
altered with CRISPR in a secretive first trial of human genome editing led by Chinese scientist
Jiankui He, another maverick who ignored his superiors and forwent ethical reviews and approvals.
He introduced a mutation into healthy human embryos to confer resistance to HIV infection, still
heavily stigmatized in China, although the infection could have been prevented in more
rather than at the Human Genome Editing Conference that was taking place at the same time in
Hong Kong. Since he did not work according to the established protocol, it was—and still is—hard
to determine what he exactly he had accomplished and whether this was just another hoax. CRISPR-
Cas9, TALEN and ZFN techniques are revolutionary technologies of genome editing and all fairly
easy to do in an ordinary laboratory (Xuan Ho et al.). They open a new way of using IVF—and
extending human hubris—as the point of access for gene editing of not only individuals but whole
future generations (see more in part 6.6.2 on Anthony Boucher’s ‘Rappaccini’s Other Daughter’).
Gene editing has already been clinically practiced in vitro (outside the living, literally ‘in the glass’) and
in vivo (within the living) and both will continue to be forms of treatment as soon as the off-target
and on-target effects and risks are known. The question is only how far we should go.
308
5.5 Huxley’s Ectogenesis
Huxley’s depiction of the hatchery was ahead of science in describing IVF with astonishing accuracy
regarding what the actual technology came to be and what it will come to be combined with (gene
editing, artificial wombs, chemical and psychological conditioning during and after gestation).
Considering that the story is set in 632 After Ford, which would be year 2540 in our time, the
assisted reproductive technology has developed in the very same direction, except that we do not
clone human cells for the purpose of human reproduction (but solely for research) and that we have
not invented artificial human wombs yet (which we will most likely succeed to do and use).
Nonetheless, Charlotte Haldane, J. B. S. Haldane’s36 wife, Nature’s reviewer of Brave New World at the
time of the publication and herself a literary author,37 sniffed at biology in Huxley’s novel as “itself
too surprising to be really amusing material for fiction” (597). Joseph Needham writes in his review
of the novel that doubting the biological scenario which Huxley extrapolates from the current
science is a predictable but unreasonable reaction because, in fact, the biology is “perfectly right”
and the most horrible Huxley’s predictions “perfectly possible” (204). Needham’s review was more
accurate: almost ninety years after the novel was published the conception part of its reproductive
Huxley was particularly inspired by J. B. S. Haldane’s fictive vision of the future from Deadalus: Or,
Science and the Future (1924), a meditation on “the influence of biology on history,” which Haldane
had drafted already in 1912 as an Oxford undergraduate (Duncan Wilson 36).In Deadalus, Haldane
J. B. S. Haldane was a childhood friend of the Huxley brothers and one of the most prominent scientists of the time
36
37 Charlotte Haldane published her first novel, Man’s World, in 1926. The novel is set it in a dystopian world where an
elite society of male scientists decide on the number of women being born. Women are then distributed into two groups:
“vocational mothers” or, if they wish, sterilized into “neuters”. The following year, Haldane published Motherhood and Its
Enemies, a suffragette account of women liberation from the reproductive burden.
309
coined the term ectogenesis (Gr. ecto means outer) as the growth of an organism in an artificial
environment outside the body from which it originates and where it would normally be found. He
also described the imagined future process in detail: scientists would “take an ovary from a woman,
and keep it growing in a suitable fluid for as long as twenty years, producing a fresh ovum each
month, of which 90 per cent can be fertilized, and the embryos grown successfully for nine months,
and then brought out into the air” (64). In the speculative future Haldane imagined, more than 70
percent of children would be conceived and incubated in glass jars. Haldane named “the artificial
control of conception” as one of the most important biological inventions that have a “profound
emotional and ethical effect” (33). Enclosing a fictional essay of an undergraduate student writing
150 years later (thus 2073), he makes a few predictions on the reproduction of the future: “As we
know ectogenesis is now universal, and in this country less than 30 per cent of children are now
born of woman. The effect on human psychology and social life of the
separation of sexual love and reproduction which was begun in the 19th
Figure 35 Panel of hell (detail) by mind later, finding therapeutic and liberating means in ectogenesis. J. D.
Hieronymus Bosch.
Bernal purposed that ectogenesis would be beneficial if it could replace
From The Garden of Earthly
Delights, c. 1480-1505, oil on
panel, 220 x 390 cm. Museo del imperfect human body with machines. The rest of the responses were
Prado.
largely negative.
310
Huxley’s novel opens with the description of the hatchery in London: “I shall begin at the
beginning,” says the Director (16). In this hatchery, human beings of the World State are created and
gestated more like chicks than mammals, in tubes and decanters and other kinds of shells, detached
from any source of human connection except for hatchery workers. In science, this image resonates
with the recent scientific achievement of successfully gestating chickens without shells (Tahara and
Obara), which could help us preserve rare birds, and gestating premature lambs in artificial wombs
(Partridge et al.), which could help our very own premature babies develop more fully. In fiction, the
image resonates back to the sixteenth century Utopia by Thomas More, which contains a short
description of a chicken hatchery where chicks are artificially gestated with heat: “[Utopians] breed
an infinite multitude of chickens in a very curious manner; for the hens do not sit and hatch them,
but a vast number of eggs are laid in a gentle and equal heat in order to be hatched, and they are no
sooner out of the shell, and able to stir about, but they seem to consider those that feed them as
their mothers, and follow them as other chickens do the hen that hatched them” (46).38 As it turns
out, the ability of technology to hatch eggs in lieu of mother hens was known already back in 1400
BC in Egypt where eggs were incubated artificially in brick or clay ovens by the thousands (Lepore
The Mansion 8, Squier Poultry 83). Chicken eggs are big and obvious, as opposed to human ones,
comments Jill Lepore; you can crack them open and they are cheap and ready to hand (8, 10). It is
not a coincidence that a chicken embryo has long been a favorite organism for studying embryology,
starting with Aristotle’s History of Animals and Generation of Animals. Disagreeing with the
Hippocratic-Galenic two-semen theory that allowed for maternal contribution, Aristotle wrongly
believed in one-semen theory and influenced thinkers up until the seventeenth century to leave the
38“Pullorum infinitam educant multitudinem, mirabili artificio. neque enim incubant oua gallinae, sed magnum eorum
numerum calore quodam aequabili fouentes animant, educantque, hi simul atque e testa prodiere, homines, uice matrum
comitantur, et agnoscunt” (Part II, par. 7).
311
ovum unsuspected (Cline Horowicz 186). It was not until William Harvey met Hieronymous
Fabricious, an Aristotelian who wrote on fetuses and chicken eggs, that Harvey insisted that eggs,
not seeds as it was thought until then, are the origin of man. The debate continued, with
preformationism and similar counterarguments winning well into the eighteenth century. The egg
hunt ended in 1827 with finding the first mammalian egg, the ovum of a dog (Lepore The Mansion
15).
The asexual reproductive process in Brave New World begins with egg retrieval though excision of an
ovary, which is then “preserved alive and actively developing” (17) in the kind of environment and
with similar techniques that are used for IVF today; in “optimum temperature, salinity, viscosity” the
eggs are extracted with “liquor” and then fertilized with sperm of the same concentration level
required today to perform fertilization without the additional help of intracytoplasmic sperm
injection. Removing the ovary from the human body makes for a less personal approach, but is
nevertheless a “surgical introduction—‘the operation undergone voluntarily for the good of Society,
not to mention the fact that it carries a bonus amounting to six months’ salary’” (17). The argument
is the same as Haldane’s: “It is perhaps fortunate that the process of becoming an ectogenetic
mother of the next generation involves an operation which is somewhat unpleasant, though now no
longer disfiguring or dangerous, and never physiologically injurious, and is therefore an honour but
by no means a pleasure” (35). The price of an ovary is in line with today’s prices of eggs; however, if
a Brave New World’s ovary proves “exceptional” it could yield “over fifteen thousand adult
39 Not unheard of in science, livestock has been experimented on with mass ovulation that produces enormous litters
(e.g. in hundreds for cows) (‘On the Frontiers’ 77)—not unlike what was happening with ART before the regulations
became stricter (e.g. Octomom).
312
Huxley again uncannily foresees commercialization of body parts that has been normalized in some
parts of the West, most prominently in the US. Using human bodies, in women’s bodies in
particular, separately from their personal origin—separate from the person—stems from the
Cartesian dualism of the mind and body, in which the mind is the center of personhood while the
physical body appears to have no restrictions in how it is used. Posthumanist theories revealed the
falsehood of this split: building on Kate Hayles’s view of computational information and Donna
Haraway’s view of sharing DNA with our companion species, the DNA information is not merely
data, but is data stored in a biological matter of a gamete that is, in fact, extremely personal. Besides
the exploitation of the commonly unprivileged bodies, the posthuman view on DNA is also why
Ovary donation is only solicited in the real world from cadavers registered as organ donors: “In
order for body parts to be made freely available for exchange they must first be conceptualized as
thing-like, as non-self and as detachable from the body without causing irreparable loss or damage to
the individual or generations to follow” (Lock 71). There are proposals, however, which would take
ovaries from aborted fetuses and mature, fertilize and implant the eggs they produce for infertility
treatments (Seibel 796). Brave New World does not mention any other way of obtaining eggs than by
surgical donation. This does not mean, however, that the donation is not made by aborted fetuses.
Mr. Foster, a scientist in a hatchery, says he has been working with a “wonderful Delta-Minus
ovary” that is “just eighteen months old” (20), which might mean that it was taken from an
eighteen-month-old Delta or that the ovary has been removed from a donor eighteen months
before. The actual proposal of fetal ovary donation was met with “unease, distaste and surprise” and
has been largely forgotten, which tacitly comments on the moral quality of the proposal: not only
313
could a child could have as a biologic mother an aborted fetus, but there is great potential for abuse,
misuse, or coercion (Seibel 796). Not to mention that the human tissue would be extracted from a
non-consenting individual who could have posthumous offspring without ever being considered a
person. In fact, this kind of donation could make a fetus into more than a fetus: it would, after all,
be a biological parent as well. In the light of this, cadaver ovary donation is easier to fit under the
moral frame of current medical practice since the living individual can consent to donating. Both
fetal and cadaver donations of oocytes for fertility treatments were proposed and immediately
refused in the 1990s; however, both types of donations are conducted for research purposes.40 Egg
donation from young women, on the other hand, is flourishing world-wide, but only for therapeutic
goals rather than research. Although thousands of frozen embryos and eggs are cryopreserved at the
moment, having relatively small numbers of eggs for research prevents science from advancing more
This issue might be overcome in the future with in vitro gametogenesis (IVG), a real-world
prospective technology which might allow for an easier access to gametes than has been either
available in the real world so far or fabricated in Brave New World. (Artificial) gametes could namely
be obtained from non-gametic cells, such as repurposed skin cells, making the choice of embryos
much bigger than it is now with IVF, which “generates a finite number of embryos from which to
select, especially given the physical burdens of harvesting eggs and the risks of ovarian
40“Although it is currently possible to obtain some human fetal oocytes from aborted fetuses to look at aspects of
chromosome behavior and misbehavior during MI and to look at MII in oocytes donated for research by women after
superovulation or from ovaries removed during hysterectomies, the numbers of oocytes that can be obtained in these
ways is restricted, and for investigations of MI, each aborted fetus will be a different individual (and a different age),
making it potentially difficult to compare one experiment with another” (Matthews 12).
314
troubling about an inexhaustible supply of gametes that could be fertilized into an inexhaustible
supply of embryos” (Orenstein-Brown par. 4, Wang par. 5, see also Cohen et al.), supposedly
because it resembles embryo farming and commodification: embryos seem less unique and special
when they become so replaceable. This new way of practicing conception would radically alter
reproductive and regenerative medicine. It would allow those who have, for one reason or another,
lost their reproductive function to produce offspring of their own genes and to find cures for a
myriad of currently untreatable diseases. In reproductive industry and research, it would largely
diminish egg41 and sperm donation, enable intervention at pre- and post-embryonic stages of
development, and allow us to choose among embryos in a larger scale. Facile genome editing, as in
CRISPR technology that allows for not only selection but also alteration, only exacerbates these
Apart from these unsettling repercussions of the technology, IVG would also allow for
parthenogenesis, the ultimate inbreeding, as well as for non-consensual parenting through the
contribution of biomaterial with simple daily involuntary shedding, already problematized in Andrew
Niccol’s film Gattaca. Glenn Cohen points out that “IVG has the potential to upend one of the most
occurs” (Wang par. 6). More broadly, it could completely alter our understanding of familial kinship.
With IVG obtaining female eggs by reversing a cell and forming it into an egg cell instead of waiting
for it to mature as a natural source in its own natural time or in time accelerated by hormones in the
41Sarah Carter-Walshaw argues that if IVF became reliable, egg donation would only be ethically justified only in rare
cases where the donor would make “her own fully informed decision” (7), “where PGD would be ineffective (or
unreliable),” or “where mitochondrial transfer would be required” (to create the so called three-parent babies) and
“where there are concerns regarding heritable illnesses or conditions that cannot be dealt with using PGD” (5).
315
IVF process, Gilles Deleuze’s idea of an egg as the second origin gains a literal meaning (13). If the
technology was reliable and safe, IVG would mean the end of infertility.
Not surprisingly, real-world research is taking its own course. Not imagined in Huxley but certainly
elsewhere in science fiction (e.g. Octavia Butler’s prose, examined in part 6.6.3) is the so-called
multiplex parenting (Cohen et al.) and the already-existing three-person children42 (Zhang et al.). We
also widely practice cyropreservation of embryos, eggs and sperm, none of which is imagined in
Brave New World. In fact, Brave New World does not extensively focus on reproduction. The novel
introduces its world through it, and the issue of contraception and natural conception remains at its
core throughout; however, the main point of the novel is to introduce a utopian futuristic world
order, satirizing Fordism and its mass production and consumption, which includes reproduction.
Nonetheless, Brave New World still stands as a reference for assisted reproductive technologies in our
The parallel between the Brave New World technologies and the state of ART today is striking. There
are surprisingly few differences when it comes to conception. Brave New World hatcheries are using
almost the exact same procedures as are familiar in today’s ART world, techniques that we could
have used or are using today on embryos. First, egg retrieval and donation are practiced today, with
the exception of ovaries being in vitro only. Second, egg maturation is a part of the IVF process as
well, except that it is put to an extreme in Brave New World. Third, fertilization is the same as well; no
sperm issues are mentioned in Brave New World and therefore no ICSI or similar techniques seem to
Three-parent children is also a misleading term considering that the ‘third parent’ gives some of his DNA from
42
mitochondrion only and is never a social parent but merely a mitochondrial donor. In this way, a donor child is much
more a three-parent child than what we call three-parent children.
316
exist. Fourth, checking for abnormalities is practiced in both worlds: we use PGD and there is no
specific information on how this is done in Brave New World. Cloning is possible today but not to the
The actual differences begin only after the conception part of the reproductive cycle: letting the
embryo grow in an artificial womb is still science fiction today, albeit not for chickens (Tahara and
Obara), goats (Kuwabara) and lambs (Partridge et al.). Although we cannot yet gestate humans for
nine months, we can grow embryos in a lab for at least 14 days (due to the 14-day rule we cannot
know how long we could actually grow them) and we can sustain lives of premature infants in a
neonatal incubator, a sort of artificial wombs, with a very poor survival rate starting in the twenty-
second week of pregnancy. The survival rate grows to over 90 percent in what was supposed to be
the last trimester of pregnancy. This means that we would first have to work out how to artificially
gestate for at least 18 weeks, roughly half a pregnancy, in between what we can currently do with
The bioethics question, Should we set this as our aim?, is often kept behind the technical work towards
artificial wombs, which has been steady in North America, Western Europe, Australia and Japan
since the 1950s. Artificial wombs are viewed as liberative by some feminists, such as Shulamith
Firestone, who argued that differences in reproductive biology are a source of gender inequality, but
also pose a new alternative for abortion within severance theory, where abortion rights allows for a
separation but not necessarily a termination of pregnancy. Besides these two grave and great
bioethical questions, there is a valid concern about losing the bonding that takes place during a
pregnancy between the fetus and the woman that carries it.
317
In the 1960s, Robert Goodlin put aborted and
birth. But nothing else is the same” (60). In 1969, this same picture of the ten-week fetus in
Goodlin’s artificial womb was featured on the cover of the LIFE magazine. The fetus, living his last
hours in the artificial womb, was captured as seemingly floating in the space with his placenta, just
In 1972, a Student Pro-Life Federation organized picketing in front of the Stanford Medical Center
to protest against “abominable acts” by Dr. Goodlin. Indeed, Goodlin cut into living fetuses in
order to observe and massage their hearts, which many European and American researchers have
also done in their research. Goodlin could find “no way to force out the poisonous carbon dioxide”
and so fetuses could survive no more than 48 hours (ib.). Soon, California banned medical
318
experimentation on living aborted fetuses, to which Goodlin commented: “All sensible physicians
agree the research was ethical”—the objective has always been “to preserve life” (Feder 1).
In 2017, the next closest thing to an artificial womb is a prototype ‘biobag,’ so far tested on partial
gestation of lambs (lambs are removed from uteri and transferred to biobags for the second part of
the gestation) (Partridge et al.). The biobag marks a shift in physiological approach to sustaining
underdeveloped human beings for three reasons: 1) it “replaces a natural function rather than
facilitating a newborn rescue” and “thus treats subject as if had not been born,” not requiring the fetus
“to exercise any independent capacity for life,” 2) although created for “’just-viable’ preterms […],
the technology is likely to be used beyond the current viability threshold,” and 3) it “has other
potential clinical uses beyond conventional rescue technologies […], but its development is more
significant and will enable the birth of partial ectogenesis as a therapeutic process in itself” (Romanis
754-755). This kind of gestating, termed as “gestateling,” will inevitably yield ethical concerns but
holds a sensible argument: it could save a preterm child from death or disabilities and diminishes
The Swedish philosopher Anna Smajdor declares pregnancy barbaric and dangerous: “If there were
any disease that caused the same problems, we would regard it as very serious” (Kleeman par. 31).
She argues we should not assume pregnancy to be central in human reproduction as we do now,
attaching strong value to motherhood, pregnancy, and birth. In Brave New World fashion, Smajdor
proposes that adequate ectogenesis would diminish the extent of suffering and risk that pregnancy
poses and forgo the natural inequality of women. As a result, our views on pregnancy would shift –
as they did with available contraception – because pregnancy and childbirth exist in conflict with
319
education, and career and relationship fulfillment” (101). The argument that our social values are no
Smajdor adds that “developments in fetal surgery […], increased prenatal testing and diagnosis, and
discoveries about the effects of mothers’ behavior on the uterine environment all contribute to the
vast pressure and constraint to which pregnant women, and potentially pregnant women, are
subjected” (102). The argument for ectogenesis falls weak in comparison to the case for equally
controversial fetal rights. Even if we agree with Smajdor that women are forced to radically
subjugate their own health and well-being for the health and well-being of their fetus, ectogenesis
presents a radical infringement upon fetal rights and joins the ongoing conversations on embryo
research, gene editing, prenatal diagnoses and treatments, abortion, etc. Should we set this as our aim?
needs to be asked of every one of these procedures before we can morally justify ectogenesis. If we
can genetically edit an embryo’s DNA to improve its health, why can we not artificially gestate it to
improve its health? Further, why not artificially gestate it to improve the health of its mother? After
all, we already technologically create donor siblings to improve the health of the other, for example.
Huxley’s vision of ART turned out to be prescient in more than just basic aspects of technology. It
has recently been shown that the ovum and preimplantation embryo’s exposure to light causes them
more stress than ambient light (Ottosen et al. 99, Pomeroy and Reed), something that Huxley took
into account when portraying the Hatchery as a photo studio: “The sultry darkness […] was visible
and crimson like the darkness of closed eyes on a summer’s afternoon” (21). Even more uncanny is
the mention of germline editing,43 which Henry Foster, an almost too scientific and precise man who
works in the Hatchery, regrets the Brave New World scientists have not yet mastered. Foster hopes to
43Editing eggs, sperm, or embryos is known as germline engineering, which results in genetic changes that can be passed
on to future generations.
320
grow Epsilons quicker so they can be suitable for work earlier: “If the physical development could
be speeded up till it was as quick, say, as a cow’s, what an enormous saving to the Community!” (25).
He expresses the desire to be able to alter the germline: “Could the effects of this germinal mutation
be undone? Could the individual Epsilon embryo be made a revert, by a suitable technique, to the
normality of dogs and cows? That was the problem. And it was all but solved” (ib.). These wishful
details, brief mentions of future scientific goals for the Brave New World Hatchery, are truly
astonishing, considering the time the novel was written. Only after 2000 has the scientific
community began to ask about reversing human regulatory networks in gene editing; what is more,
the epigenetic gene editing, where the gene itself is not changed but its behavior is altered
temporarily rather than permanently, is not commonly presented as a possible solution to more
All in all, the fact that Huxley’s fabrication of human reproduction managed to foresee so many
aspects of IVF, the Nobel-Prize-winning technology that will surely lead to exciting new scientific
discoveries, is why this novel became a primary source of reflection on this technology.
Technologies cannot be called inherently dehumanizing without a baseline; yet, in this novel the
dehumanizing effect of the reproductive technologies, along with conditioning and consumerist
values, depicts a loss of core Western human values: freedom of choice, sober mind, human dignity,
cultural and artistic reflection, forming kinships and affinity groups, etc.44 Although alleviating
women’s burden of reproductive labor, marriage and family could make a positive effect in this
society, abolishing deeper romantic and familial relationships ultimately led to a grimmer, more
stratified, and unjust world. Suffering and harm are still present but in a different form. The novel
There is no consensus on core human values across different communities, even when limited solely to the West,
44
which is why ‘health,’ ‘enhancement,’ or ‘normal’ cannot be given values either (Porter 252).
321
makes it clear that our world should remain wary of Huxley’s fabricated social order, which stems
from parodying ART that eliminate uniqueness, diversity, and pathology from the human nature.
Enslaved in happiness, the people of Brave New World are dehumanized, seemingly without suffering
But what if we accept that the human nature is to modify ourselves? Or if we conclude that
technology is not powerful enough to transform humanity or that people are wise enough to use
technologies moderately? The underlying cause of the belief that biotechnology is capable of
removing human dignity and character is the trivialization of what constitutes the human, perceived
as a nonchalant and curious play with the plasticity of the human body and mind. Huxley suggests
that one source of notions of what it means to be human is religion (referring to the long-forgotten
Christianity that says God created the human in his image), another is literature (John the Savage
loves Shakespeare), the third is close relationships (between John and his mother Linda), and so on.
Our relations with these facts of humanity have been altered throughout human history, partly but
not only because of the use of science and technology. What happened to human nature and identity
Unique to Brave New World is the massive cloning (induced twinning)45 of the thirty-six-hour-old
embryos, which is used only to create the lower three castes, “standard Gammas, unvarying Deltas,
45Clones are, biologically, more diverse than typical identical twins due to environmental factors that influence their
genetic development, including gestation. A clone is thus not necessarily identical to the original; similarly to how those
who know a pair of identical twins well can distinguish between them without much effort.
322
uniform Epsilons” (19). This is called Bokanovsky’s Process, an X-ray46 technique of cloning that
commodifies prenatal life through “[t]he principle of mass production at last applied to biology”
(19). “[A] bokanovskified egg will bud […] and every bud will grow into a perfectly normal formed
embryo, and every embryo into a full-sized adult” (17), losing the bad-quality embryos in the
process. IVF is a rather successful technology, but still a majority of embryos are lost in the process
and the success rate is on average on par with natural reproduction. The high success rate of
Central panel (detail). 1480-1505, oil on panel, 220 x 390 cm. brothers and sisters in a hundred and fifty
Museo del Prado.
batches of identical twins, all within two years of
age” with each embryo yielding “eight up to ninety-six embryos” with “seventy-two [being] a good
average” (18).
46An X-ray technique is so far found more damaging than useful for embryos (Spallone 39) but there has been some
success with radiation mutagenesis in mice (Thomas et al.). In 1920s, X-ray was used by a Viennese scientist Eugen
Steinach to help women rejuvenate by “bombarding their ovaries” (Lepore The Mansion 175). For men, such as Freud
and Yeats, Steinach’s rejuvenation program involved surgical techniques: “the Steinach operation was, basically, a
vasectomy” (Lepore 175). In 1960s, X-ray was used to be able to perform a fetal transfusion for maternal-fetal blood
incompatibility (‘On the Frontiers’ 63-66).
323
Identical twins are “almost subhuman” (248), comments Huxley in ‘Brave New World Revisited,’
like replicants that are created for robotic work in Ridley Scott’s Blade Runner (Squier ‘Embryos’ 146)
or later in Steven Spielberg’s A.I. Artificial Intelligence, or like Karel Čapek’s robots created in a factory
Rossum’s Universal Robots from flesh and blood. Such clones are much desired and appreciated in
Brave New World because they help the stability of the state. “If we could bokanovskify indefinitely
the whole problem would be solved” (19). “The whole problem” is that what they are doing now is
‘second best;’ the best version of this kind of reproduction would therefore be having just one
ovary, the ovary of the mother of all people (like Eva or Gaea) and the World State would consist of
brothers and sisters only—a Christian image taken too literally: “All the advantages of Christianity
and alcohol; none of their defects” (60). Most religions and mythologies base the reproduction of
the first people and gods on incest47—an idea suggested as ideal for the World State as well.
As is common in utopias,48 incest is not of the slightest concern here, despite the proneness to
producing more genetic disorders in resulting offspring. The World State’s genetic siblings, except
for the many identical twins, have no knowledge of their genetic connection. When they donate their
ovaries and sperm, the Hatchery should make sure they do not breed and thus inbreed—yet there is
no mention of any concern of this sort. Another option for incest in such a society are pregnancies
that occur through recreational sex, which are in themselves highly undesirable but nonetheless
possible; one result of such pregnancies is John, the protagonist of the second part of the novel. The
World State takes three measures to prevent natural reproduction: seventy percent of women are
47 The incest is at once prohibited and required (see more in Shell’s The End of Kinship).
48The word utopia comes from Greek eu- (not) and -topos (place), literally ‘nowhere.’ Commonly but incorrectly eu- is
interpreted as ‘good,’ meaning a ‘good place’ and relating utopia with eugenics (good genes). The word dystopia came
from this second interpretation as its opposite (‘Utopia’).
324
made to be sterile “freemartins,” including the lower three castes. The rest of them have to exercise
birth control with a Malthusian Belt (149)49—“about eight hundred unsterilized ones who need
constant drilling”—or can go to abortion clinics as a final resource (149, 113). The Malthusian Belt
provides a pregnancy substitute, i.e. pills and injections that simulate the hormonal effects of
pregnancy, which suppresses the desire for having children and must be used beginning at the age of
twenty. Only those rare Alpha and Beta women who have not donated both of their ovaries and
who discontinue taking birth control can still get pregnant naturally—as Linda does with John, the
savage, and as Lenina could have, had she not taken the proper measures.
(Fauser and Devroey 34, C. Cooper 13). Identical or monzygotic twins are a serendipitous
malformation of a fertilized egg, essentially a product of natural cloning and thus asexual
reproduction, in which an embryo creates another embryo with his DNA as some sort of a parent.
An identical twin can therefore ask metaphorically and literally: Am I a clone of my twin or is he (she) a
clone of me?
49Named after demographer Thomas Malthus who, in contrary to the eighteenth-century views, saw population growth
as inevitable in good conditions and as such preventing societal progress towards utopia as the resources cannot
compete with the human growth and demand.
325
Some pairs of twins are indistinguishable at first, particularly those pairs in which embryo splits early
in the process, but none are completely identical in the literal sense of the word. Monozygotic twins
can develop quite differently due to activation of different genes or achieve some unusual twinnings,
like mirror image or conjoined twinning.50 Nonetheless, there are also siblings and fraternal twins
who resemble each other as if they were identical twins: consider Viola and Sebastian from
Shakespeare’s Twelfth Night, who look very much alike. It is possible to think of the indistinguishable
Viola and Sebastian as the very rare semi-identical or sesquizygotic twins of the opposite sex, which
is paternally-derived.51 (Shakespeare himself had a set of fraternal twins, Judith and Hamnet, the
latter of whom died aged 11; likewise, Viola in Twelfth Night believes her brother has died.)
Uniparental disomy, where a person inherits more DNA from one parent than the other, is “more
common and less detrimental than the scientific literature suggested” (Zhang ‘It’s Possible’ par. 3).
Identical twinning cannot be forced with ART, except with (prohibited) cloning. However, fraternal
twins (or triplets or more) are fairly easy to create in the process of almost any ART. Transferred at
the same time or not, all embryos from a single batch are conceptual fraternal twins. Embryos from
the same batch were, after all, created on the same day, even if they are not born at the same time or
to the same expecting parents. Many of these unacknowledged twins remain cyropreserved until
50 If the egg splits between days 9 and 12, the twins could become mirror image twins, with reversed asymmetry, such as
left- and right-handedness and opposite physical features and situs invertus organs. Around day 14 (the last day before the
embryo becomes ‘an individual’), the risk for conjoined twins is the largest.
51 This rare occurrence—which has been described in medical literature only twice only recently (Gabbett et al.)—
requires the egg cleavage into two ova which are then fertilized by two sperm and further develop in a twinning event.
The twins thus have identical maternal genes but different paternal genes. Another option of monozygotic twins of
different sex is the female twin resulting from X chromosome duplication, which causes Turner’s syndrome (Edwards et
al. 117).
326
their eventual birth, miscarriage, decay, or destruction.52 Frozen embryos could spend years, even
Similarly to fraternal embryos, children conceived with egg or sperm by the same donor are
genetically half-fraternal, making the issue of incest problematic in the early years of egg and sperm
donation when it was not regulated how many children per single donor were allowed and donors
tended to be anonymous. The anonymity shifted towards open donors only after 2005, when the
UK established that donor-conceived children are allowed to find out medical information about
their donor when they reach 18 (par. 13). In the US, laws differ across the states: in 2011,
Washington was the first state to enact legislation making open sperm donation the default, meaning
that anonymity would need to be specifically requested by the donor (Fetters ‘Finding’ par. 19).
Lawyers think that “promising anonymity to any donor […] is folly” (Chung et al. par. 15), because
DNA tests and internet searches can help find them. The secrecy around donation has changed not
only because of the growing donor industry and more acceptance of ART, but also because studies
have shown most donors and donor-children expressed a desire to connect (Fetters ‘Finding’).
Anonymity is hard to reach, and “with consumer-DNA tests, sperm banks reconsider long held
promises to donors” (Keshavan). If donation in Brave New World was the most impersonal, the real-
Even if the donor’s identity is not available, donor children can now be given medical information
about their donor and each other in order to help with medical situations, prevent incest, or simply
52Similarly, as vampires of the scientific age, a few hundreds of people attempt to transgress their beginnings in the
previous millennium by cryopreserving themselves after death and waiting for science to wake them up in the next
centuries in a human or humanlike form.
327
bond over genetics (Scheib and Ruby), establishing a new kind of family and bond. Assuring donors
anonymity in times when anyone can order a home DNA test (such as 23andMe) and search for
their biological relatives online is unethical. To prevent inbreeding, the American Society for
Reproductive Medicine considers 25 an acceptable number of children per donor (de Boer et al.,
The Practice 194); in 2018 Britain and many other countries of similar size, the rule is no more than
10 separate families (but no number for within a family) (Fricker par. 18). Before the rule, things got
out of control: one British man fathered 200 children. His case further shows how misleading the
industry can be if not properly regulated: he was considered an “asset” for the sperm bank, which
said he was “university-educated,” “a boss at a bank,” and that he had “no interest in being
contacted by future children,” none of which was true. They also “failed to mention his ethnicity
[…]: his father [was] black and white” (Usborne par. 10).
Brave New World disregards the natural slow reproducing rate as useless: “For in nature it takes thirty
years for two hundred eggs to reach maturity. […] Dribbling out twins over a quarter of a century—
what would be the use of that?” (19). The eggs are, by their qualitative and quantitative nature as
well as by virtue of their location, harder to obtain. Using Podsnap’s Technique to ripen the eggs
extremely quickly, “within two years of the same age,” thousands of brothers and sisters are
decanted. Such birth control makes for a perfect mixture of “Community, Identity, Stability” in the
World State. In the USA, the belief goes quite the contrary to the World State motto: having many
children of one’s own or many children at once is considered unusual to an extent of earning
328
significant media attention or getting such families their own reality show.53 This is not true for those
families who adopt or foster a great (and greater) number of children, which indicates that the
Transferring more than one embryo at once makes for a rapid reproduction rate. The practice is still
slightly controversial if the number is greater than two, although often conducted under
consideration of the patient’s wishes, fertility, energy, and resources involved into the treatment, as
well as the objectives of commercial fertility clinics who wish to improve their own success rates.
Exaggerating the natural course by transferring more embryos at once puts the patients at risk: a
pregnancy with multiples is much riskier and tends to be more difficult in itself, especially with the
high-order multiples. The record multiple births were sets of nonuplets in Malaysia (1999, through
ART) (Pinchuk 29) and Australia (1971, no information about conception) (‘Last’), in which none of
the infants survived birth or after birth, as well as pregnancies with even higher order of fetuses with
no live births (Brody), not to mention the many multifetal pregnancies with fetal reduction (Schlomo
et al., Athanasiadis et al.). In the early days of IVF and sometimes even decades later, two to over a
dozen embryos were transferred at once. In the USA, two sets of octuplets are the only high-order
multiples where all children survived. One such notorious example is Nadya (now Natalie) Suleman,
called Octomom by the media, who is a single mother of a set of octuplets and six older children
(fraternal twins included), all conceived via IVF between 2001 and 2009. In a mere eight years,
Nadya Suleman had fourteen children from six pregnancies. For others who opt out of transferring
53 The following couples, who had over ten children naturally, were also featured in reality shows: Kids by the Dozen (a
reality show about large families; ten to eighteen children), 19 Kids and Counting (nineteen children, including two sets of
twins; the family had their own show since having fourteen children), Bringing Up Bates (nineteen children), The Willis
Family (fourteen children), Meet the Putmans (26 family members of three generations under one roof). The following
couples from reality shows used ART: Table for 12 (two sets of twins, sextuplets), Kate Plus 8 (twins, sextuplets), Octo-mom
(four singletons, twins, octuplets), Sweet Home Sextuplets (three singletons, septuplets), Quints by Surprise (singleton,
quintuplets), OutDaughtered (quintuplets), etc.
329
more than one embryo, the cost of storing the remaining embryos is a reminder to make up their
mind if and when they are going to use them, discard and destroy them, or donate them for
Such numbers are unlikely but not impossible by natural reproduction. The Guinness Book of World
Records states that a Russian peasant couple from the eighteenth century, the Vassilyevs, had
altogether 69 children, including sets of twins, triplets, and quadruplets, and the father had additional
18 children with his second wife (Young 357). The Vassilyev couple is followed by a few other
known couples, all from around that time, in which the women were obviously prone to
hyperovulate. In hyperfertile couples with no hyperovulation issue (and thus no sets of multiples),
the number of children reaches around 40. For men alone, the numbers go to hundreds of offspring,
however, especially if the method of conception is ART. One such example is fertility physician
Bertold Paul Wiesner with an estimated 600 offspring through an anonymous donation of sperm
that was used by his obstetrician wife to perform artificial insemination in London in the mid-
Human fecundity is limited to a period, but, as the examples above show, ART can help to buy time
by the mere way it is designed: by overriding women’s natural cycles, by harvesting a great number
of eggs at once, and by freezing the gametes earlier in one’s life when the quality is generally better.
As Hannah Landecker argues of the case of a cell, biological and biotechnological research and
practice have shifted our concepts of individuality, immortality, hybridity, and cell plasticity. What
was considered to be scientifically impossible for cells or higher levels of organisms has largely
330
become routine; the substance of human bodies is maintained alive outside the body (3)54 and can be
made hybrid, reduplicated, infinitely reproduced, or frozen and then reanimated. “In short, to be
biological, alive, and cellular also means (at present) to be a potential ‘age chimaera,’ to be
suspendable, interruptible, storable, and freezable in parts” (228). These techniques not only helped
to breach the temporal but also spatial limitations of biological research and medical procedures
since a cell or an embryo can be transferred from one laboratory to another in minimal time.
biological (Landecker 232). Living cells are now easily accessible, available, manipulatable and
flexible tools (201). On the level of human gametes these possibilities are harder to reach; however,
ART has successfully and widely turned human tissues—and sometimes actual humans—into
research tools and commercial objects. Huxley foreshadows this in the treatment of gametes as well
as decanted infants who are still more of a commodity than a person, still in the process of molding.
The choice of language reveals their status as well: they are “unloaded” unto the floor as if they are
merely objects and not people (29). In the World State, biotechnology makes a cut on where humans
are considered persons, excluding the prenatal life and infants under the conditioning process. With
artificial mass reproduction, “dehumanized babies [are] turned out on production lines like Henry
54“Human cells began to be cultured on a large scale in the 1940s […] in an effort to find a vaccine for polio”
(Landecker 17).
331
5.6 The Huxley Brothers
Julian Huxley, a biologist, wrote a large array of scientific and essayistic literature but it is not widely
known that he, like his brother Aldous, also tried himself in science fiction. In 1926, when Aldous
was already an established literary author, Julian published a short story titled ‘The Tissue-Culture
King.’55 Julian builds on H. G. Wells’s The Island of Dr. Moreau and Joseph Conrad’s Heart of Darkness
while incorporating direct references to the recent biological discoveries by Jacques Loeb, Hans
Spemann, and Charles Rupert Stockard, as well as Henry Ford’s idea of Fordism, i.e. a standardized,
industrial mass production and consumption of goods. In an unnamed African country, an African
explorer tells the story of another foreigner he meets, Dr. Hascombe. Hascombe was captured by a
tribe whose religious beliefs in the priest-king named Bugala, ancestor worship, animal cult, and
“sex, con variazioni” he exploits for his own coming into power through “tissue culture; experimental
experimental embryology and put them in focus of biological science at least for the first half of the
twentieth century. In 1890, the biologist Jacques Loeb wrote to his friend, physicist Ernst Mach, that
“the idea is now hovering before me that man himself can act as creator, even in living nature,
forming it eventually according to his will. Man can at least succeed in a technology of living
substance” (Pauly 5, also Landecker 1). As Hannah Landecker writes, Loeb’s hunch is constitutive
of how we perceive life today: living matter is viewed as technological matter, with living tissues
being routinely maintained alive outside the body (2-3). In 1899, Loeb proved that a simple
55 The story was first published in 1926 in The Cornhill Magazine that his father, Leonard Huxley, edited at the time, and
then again the same year in the oldest American literary magazine The Yale Review, and a year later in American science
fiction magazine Amazing Stories with Julian Huxley being the first British author to appear in this magazine until 1932;
the story was reprinted many times afterwards.
332
mechanical stimulus, such as the prick of a needle or a baby hair, is enough to start the egg dividing
(in a technique he termed as artificial parthenogenesis); the first cloning of an unfertilized sea
urchin’s ovum was performed with a baby’s hair and tweezers (Spemann).
Loeb’s discovery was “explicitly intended to confirm a new definition of life as mechanical, and thus
reengineerable” (Franklin Biological 2). ‘The Tissue-Culture King’ plays off this modern scientific
notion: as Hannah Landecker writes in her book on tissue culture, these biological discoveries
changed the perception of life to reversible and engineerable, infinitely reproducible and immortal,
plastic and hybrid, capable of breaching spatial and chronological limitations. In both Brave New
World and ‘The Tissue-Culture King,’ mass production, as proposed by industrial Fordism, is applied
to humans and human tissues. Hascombe realizes that protecting the priest-king’s sacred tissues,
such as nails and hair, “in case some enemy should compass the King’s illness or death by using
them in black magic rites” (454), could be instead used for scientific profit, with every citizen having
a bottle of the king’s tissue right at home. As an excuse to secure the priest-king’s position in power,
Hascombe helps to grow Bugala’s tissues to be distributed among all of his people. Soon enough,
almost every family in the country has at least one sample of the king’s tissue (455). Hascombe soon
extends this practice to ancestor worship as well, with some tissue relics re-grown and some being
made while the elderly relatives are still alive. The tissues need to be brought back to Hascombe for
rejuventation, and just in case they stop growing Hascombe establishes a back-up institution of
“histopolis: not a cemetery, but a place of eternal growth” (456). Immortality of the sacred king and
ancestors is assured, as well as Hascombe’s research funding, conditions, and influence not only for
his Institute of Religious Tissue Culture but also for three other Hascambe’s projects which focus on
333
With a whole country available for his experimentations, Hascombe also “utilize[s] that plasticity of
the earliest stages to give double-headed and cyclopean monsters” (456), creating “animal
monstrosities” in the most Moureauvian of his institutions, the Home of the Living Fetishes
(fetishism is commonly related to pygmalionism, as shown in chapter 3). This is the only feature of
the African state that bears no resemblance to the World State. The World State largely isolates
people from the nature and focuses on human enhancement only, using biological venues similar to
In the Factory of Ministers to the Shrines, endocrine products are tested on infants to grow them
into “Hercules” and “dwarfs” (ib.), a practice not unlike the Hatchery engineers conditioning
different castes for physical characteristics and mental abilities. Sex is one of the fundamental
spiritual practices of the African tribe and the World State citizens, with the former focusing on
virginity and the latter focusing on promiscuity. Hascombe attempts to grow “a race of vestals,” i.e.
self-reproducing virgins, by applying Loeb’s discovery of artificial parthenogenesis to man: “So far I
have failed with mammals. However, I’ve not given up yet!” (ib.) Both Huxley brothers’ texts foster
the connection between biological engineering and conditioning and religious beliefs, imposed by
the state, that enable human tissue exploitation and ideological indoctrination as a spiritual practice.
The fourth and final Hascombe’s project, which also resembles practices in Brave New World, is
indoctrination of people through psychological techniques. Hascombe uses mass telepathy which, he
claims, will hopefully lead him to the universal “super-consciousness” (457). Citizens are sent
commands through telepathy that are contagious and possible to partly avoid only with a tin foil hat.
The goal is to “to tune hypnotic subjects to the same pitch” (ib.), much like in Brave New World
where all citizens must act predictably as standardized by the State through neo-Pavlovian
334
conditioning, hypnopaedia, and social duties tied to superficial spirituality (e.g. promiscuity through
quasi-religious orgies, conditioned veneration of Henry Ford and worship of mechanization). Just
like the island visitor Edward Prendrick in Dr. Moreau, the narrator Jones manages to escape the
African country and return home to England. The priest-king Bugala (a counterpart of Dr. Moreau)
realizes that he cannot rule without the captive Hascombe’s help (Moreau’s assistant Montgomery)
and manages to outwit him through Hascombe’s own telepathy technique by suppressing his desire
5.6.1 Transhumanism
Every utopia explains how its society works and what it believes in. The goal of the dystopian World
State is a conformist society of pleasure-seeking and vapid consumers who keep the economy
thriving. Science and technology are presented as progressive and necessary foundations while
history and culture are practically eliminated. The World State does not induce fear, as some other
dystopias do; rather, it induces desire after desire, which effectively ruins any kind of culture,
diversity, or original thought. With citizens constantly being brainwashed by slogans and
(Heterosexual) sex and procreation often take center stage in the organization of the utopian society.
Since the two are separated in the World State, sex becomes a recreation, with mandatory
promiscuity in adults and “erotic play” encouraged already in children (37-39): “Every one belongs
to every one else” (48). Romantic relationships and marriages do not exist. Their ART, together with
gestational conditioning, could be said to be profoundly artificial reproductive technology, as they are
manipulating the values of the society (as we also do outside fiction). For example, they first
335
conditioned lower castes to enjoy the country and nature but since it was not profitable enough they
changed the conditioning techniques to make Deltas dislike nature (31). Conditioning is believed to
overcome natural inclinations: “What man has joined, nature is powerless to put asunder” (30).
reproductive tissues and imitating biological processes of embryology, the following gestation of
environmental influence that helps to form the desired citizen. Additionally, the state makes sure
that every future citizen enjoys their designated social role, using behavioral indoctrination
manipulation (using soma, a drug that enhances joy and an overall sense of well-being while
diminishing pain and negative feelings—not unlike Prozac today). The fact that the failure rate in
this satirized system of creating ideal citizens is so small speaks to the mechanization (and thus
another form of artificiality) of the process. In this way, Huxley’s Hatchery is not too different than
The deep inequality of the caste system, together with the loss of freedom, is the foundation of the
state’s stability. However, an Epsilon is just as worthy a member of society as is an Alpha. When
asked why not everyone is made an Alpha, since thfis is certainly a possibility, the World Controller
explains that that would lead to instability, as it did in a Cyprus experiment where a colony of solely
56To achieve class stratification, all fetuses are exposed to various levels of the oxygen, alcohol, certain hormones, and
other chemical substances while they grow in mechanically sophisticated artificial wombs called decanters.
57 Hypnopedia lesson, interestingly, features George Bernard Shaw’s speech, speaking about his own genius (33). Shaw
was certainly one of the authors obsessed with creating human life, however, Huxley implies that Shaw’s political views
are groundwork for the World State. Shaw is also one of the rare literary figures allowed in the World State. Shaw lost
faith in eugenics later in life and became quite pessimistic about the mankind (Coleman 8) and Huxley mocks him later
in the novel naming a physician who advocates Linda’s euthanasia as Dr. Shaw (145).
336
Alpha men went into a civil war over who was to do factory work and farming (201), illustrating a
In Huxley’s eugenicized society of five castes, from Alphas to Epsilons, everyone is a ‘designer baby’
and as such must be fulfilling their potential to an extent they were designed for. Bioconservative
ethicist Michael Sandel’s The Case Against Perfection: Ethics in the Age of Genetic Engineering warns against
transforming or molding children as opposed to beholding and accepting them as they are.
Transforming love, he argues, disfigures the parent-child relationship with an over-the-top parenting
attitude, which should instead be based on what the theologian William F. May calls the (parental)
“openness to the unbidden” that gives the children the “right to the open future.” In Brave New
World, which pushes molding children to the limit, the parent-child relationship is therefore non-
existent. Sandel identifies solidarity, humility and responsibility as three moral qualities that will be
defeated in exchange for hubris and our quest for perfection if we pursue genetic engineering (85-
92). Inequality and the sense for those worse off will only grow, Sandel predicts, and the enhanced
people will lose a sense of freedom due to the pressure to live up to what was given to them. Many
criticisms of Sandel’s arguments turn to transhumanist perspectives, claiming that enhanced genes
would be no different than natural abilities if the enhancement was safe or minimizing the potential
consequence of diminishing the enhanced person’s agency, freedom, and efforts. Prominent
transhumanist Julian Savulescu, for example, says that enhancement would rather reduce inequality if
Similarly to Huxley, Aristotle categorized humans by caste, attributing more humanity to ‘Alphas’
and less to ‘Epsilons,’ who are, in his account, slaves by the means of nature. In this analogy,
Aristotle’s ‘Deltas’ would be women and ‘Gammas’ artisans. (The generic concept in which everyone
is born human has emerged only with Descartes.) In Aristotle’s and Huxley’s societies, slaves cannot
337
ever be educated and become more human because they are born as slaves (and thus not quite
human). Julian Huxley, however, strongly believed that working on the human potential can
improve individual humans and the human species as a whole. He called this idea transhumanism in
the eponymous 1957 essay: “What the job really boils down to is this—the fullest realization of
man’s possibilities, whether by the individual, by the community, or by the species in its processional
While Julian Huxley as a scientist strongly believed in transhumanism, Aldous Huxley largely
satirized the belief that science and mechanization guaranteed social progress. When examining the
applications of science, Julian focused on how it could be used positively while Aldous focused on
its misuse. In his contribution to a 1933 volume on Science and the Changing World, Aldous also
pointed out how modern industrial culture supports the misuse of science, which is, in his words,
“morally neutral:” “Ideally, science should be applied by humanists. In this case it would be good. In
actual fact it is more likely to be applied by economists, and so to turn out, if not wholly bad, at any
Aldous’s vision, nonetheless, also overlaps with Julian’s idea of transhumanism, which involves
“transcend[ing] of the human species […]—not just sporadically, an individual here in one way, an
individual there in another way, but in its entirety, as humanity” (‘Transhumanism’ 15), focusing on
foremost scientific and technical exploration and, importantly, on social environment, population
control, education, spirituality, beauty (14). Whereas Julian’s essay focuses on the “fullest realization”
of one’s existence, Aldous’s dystopia alters humans through enhancement and degradation, while
also suppressing their desires for deeper spirituality, education, or connections among people, and,
for lower castes, also appreciation for the beauty of nature. Julian’s view of the lowest class was
338
rather unusual for the times: he was critical towards the most extreme eugenics of the 1920s and
1930s that asked for virtual elimination (e.g. sterilization) of the ‘genetically inferior pool’ (the poor
were falsely equated with feeblemindedness). (Besides the eugenics movement, the 1920s also saw
increasing synergy between rising feminism and birth control (Duncan Wilson 37).) Instead, much
like his colleague J. B. S. Haldane, Julian Huxley proposed a nutritious diet, health care, housing, and
education for the lowest classes (Hubback 201). He believed in class cooperation rather than
competition in reproduction (i.e. differential fertility), hoping to breed temperaments that are not
individualistic and anti-social (ib.)—as Bernard from Brave New World. A quest for social behavior
over personal success was also stated in the Eugenics Manifesto (1939),58 signed by Julian Huxley
and other prominent British and American biologists, as one of the three “most important genetic
objectives, from the social point of view,” besides health and intelligence (Crew et al. par. 9).
Julian, despite being one of the leading figures in eugenics,59 disregards the possibility of altering
prenatal life in his essay ‘Transhumanism:’ “Every man-jack of us begins as a mere speck of
potentiality, a spherical and microscopic egg-cell. During the nine months before birth, this
automatically unfolds into a truly miraculous range of organization; after birth, in addition to
continuing automatic growth and development, the individual begins to realize his mental
skills of various kinds, by playing his part in keeping society going” (‘Transhumanism’ 14). Writing
25 years after his brother’s novel, Julian is (again) deprived of visualizing water-babies and the
opportunities prenatal life yields to science. In Brave New World, the prenatal stage is crucial for the
58 The Eugenics Manifesto appeared in Nature in 1939 under the title ‘Social Biology and Population Improvement’ as a
joint statement between some of the most prominent American and British biologists.
59 Julian Huxley was also a prominent member of the British Eugenics Society.
339
indoctrination which continues throughout the individual’s life. Fulfilling and changing the
individual begins at the moment of conception; already, scientists are perfecting Alphas and Betas in
both senses of the word and depriving Deltas and Epsilons though cloning, malnutrition, and
harmful chemicals. Nonetheless, a Brave New World scientist does not discriminate the gametes as
eugenics typically does: a “wonderful Delta-Minus ovary” can produce any type of human (20).
Rather, the stratification begins as soon as the gametes join into an embryo and continues
throughout the social system. In a Brave New World fashion, Jean Baudrillard argues that it is not
culture that prevents us from “the hell of the Same” but that it is precisely “culture that clones us”
(25). Culture as a “monothought” through “school systems, media, culture, and mass information”
is a result of the Brave New World culture of social cloning that “makes possible the biological
conception of the genome and of genetic cloning” (ib.). Thus, without a social system that supports
the stratification of people, the reproductive biotechnology of the World State could never thrive.
“The nightmare of swarming indistinguishable sameness” (129), as John the Savage perceived the
World State, is supported through culture and science, through the philosophical origin of the state
Inevitable, minor deviations from the caste type are solved by social measures, such as deportation,
which is also threatened to the protagonist of the first part of the novel, Bernard Marx, an Alpha
Plus man who does not feel akin to his elite group. The Director accuses Bernard of having heretical
views “even as a little infant” (138), implying that conditioning did not work properly already at that
time. Henry Foster confirms this by commenting that Bernard is like those men who are “almost
rhinoceroses; they don’t respond properly to conditioning. Poor Devils!” (88). Bernard is short for
an Alpha and likes to spend time alone and enjoys nature, which is also considered outside the
norm. Like Mary from Roald Dahl’s short story ‘William and Mary,’ in which Mary calls completely
340
paralyzed William’s brain “a little baby, […] suddenly getting to feel the most enormous affection for
him” (485), Lenina also finds Bernard “rather sweet” in his unusualness, saying she would like to pet
Just like social misfits are corrected in this culture, there are no mistakes made in producing fetuses.
Disabilities and most diseases are non-existent, with only infectious diseases close to eradication
(170). Embryos are “inspected for abnormalities” (17) and discarded if presenting any. Nonetheless,
the main belief of eugenics of the 1930s—that genes determine one’s social worth and thus
reproduction of people with desirable traits is encouraged (positive eugenics) while reproduction of
people with undesirable traits is discouraged (negative eugenics)— is irrelevant, shown in the cross-
over among the five castes (20). Humans of Brave New World have subjugated nature to an extent
that mutations are not natural but human-induced; for example, people do not look their age due to
Nonetheless, the subjugation of nature, in particular human nature, is not complete, as obvious from
the fact that places for social misfits are needed. Besides that, the state implements a banal religion
implemented through mandatory Solidarity Service days where group sex is used to increase social
stability. Through an orgy in a former cathedral turned cabaret, where a group of “twelve [is made]
one” (82), the citizens are encouraged to break down their perceived differences and reach
spirituality— “The feet of the Greater Being;” “He is coming” (ib.) —that is otherwise unavailable
in their thoroughly shallow state. “Orgy-porgy gives release” (83) and pharmaceuticals such as soma,
pregnancy surrogate, and violent passion surrogate, all prove that the atavistic human character has
not been entirely suppressed. Similarly, although history, religion, and culture are eliminated,
together with the desire to know them, God is present “as an absence; as though he weren’t there at
341
all” because “God isn’t compatible with machinery and scientific medicine and universal happiness”
(210).
History, religion, and culture all reappear with the experimental invitation of John the Savage into
the World State. “But I don’t want comfort. I want God. I want poetry, I want real danger, I want
freedom, I want goodness. I want sin,” he says, to which Mustapha Mond, one of the ten World
Controllers, replies: “In fact […], you’re claiming the right to be unhappy. […] Not to mention the
right to grow old and ugly and impotent; the right to have syphilis and cancer; the right to have too
little to eat; the right to be lousy; the right to live in constant apprehension of what may happen
tomorrow; the right to catch typhoid; the right to be tortured by unspeakable pains of every kind”
(215). Mond’s words could be cited in the original transhumanist treatise by Julian Huxley, which
sums up the same point as follows: “Up till now human life has generally been, as Hobbes described
it, ‘nasty, brutish and short’; the great majority of human beings (if they have not already died young)
have been afflicted with […] poverty, disease, ill-health, over-work, cruelty, or oppression”—and
our hopes to lighten these miseries will be made rational through science “and will set our ideals
Much like Mustapha Mond, Julian Huxley views transhumanism as a new task for the human: “The
exploration of human nature and its possibilities has scarcely begun,” he writes, as we have pretty
much mastered the geography of the Earth and the scientific exploration of lifeless and living nature
(14). Further, Julian Huxley also calls for the destruction of “the ideas and the institutions that stand
in the way” (16), of effectively rebuilding the system to serve transhumanist goals. Sustaining such a
system is Mond’s primary task. In a short passage of Brave New World, Mustapha Mond rejects a
“masterly” paper titled ‘A New Theory of Biology,’ in which the author (who will be supervised and
342
likely deported) suggests a “novel and highly ingenious, but heretical […] mathematical treatment of
the conception of purpose” (162). Although the paper seems to be arguing for a transhumanist goal,
which is in part shared with the World State, Mustapha Mond worries that such a paper will
decondition the higher castes into believing that instead of happiness and “faith in the Sovereign
Good” the purpose of life “was somewhere beyond, somewhere outside the present human sphere;
that the purpose of life was not the maintenance of well-being, but some intensification and refining
of consciousness, some enlargement of knowledge.” Mustapha Mond does not necessarily disagree
with the paper but puts the happiness of his citizens first, as the order of the World State dictates.
in which inequality is not a problem. (Similarly, engineers tend to believe that every problem is
computable and thus solvable.) Certainly, technology is here to help us improve ourselves and our
world. Yet, the issue of inequality inevitably occurs already, even with access to technology. It is
utopian to think there is a world that could provide everyone access to something as privileged and
expensive as ART and that everyone is able to use it with respect to their personal health, time,
energy, as well as religious views, 60 apart from considering an individual’s desire to go through an
intense treatment that does not guarantee a desired result. Designer babies will only accentuate the
inequality issues of ART, issues already here among us, camouflaged under infertility (as opposed to
fertility) and treatment (as opposed to enhancement). Those who can afford these expensive
treatments have long been able to choose even among non-treatment options that are not covered
60Even in a country like Norway with a public health system and public subsidies, infertile patients with low-income are
selected against. Other factors for not being able to take advantage of free IVF services are high BMI, smoking, sex-
hormone responsive cancers, HIV or hepatitis infection, psychiatric disease, and a frozen pelvis. Although these latter,
biological factors are also “selection pressures in reproduction in general, the limited availability of IVF enhances their
importance” (Hanevik et al. 1399).
343
by insurance.61 That is to say, eugenics is at work already and mostly in the matter of access.
Transhumanist beliefs in technology often fail to acknowledge the diversity of humanity and the fact
that only the privileged have a choice to participate in transhumanizing the world. Besides that,
values largely differ among people and thus any strain of transhumanism is bound to be conceptually
incoherent and hard to practice (as Ted Chiang’s story ‘A Documentary: Liking What You See’
The two criticisms I expose here regarding the lack of diversity and access in transhumanism are
addressed by leading transhumanist scholars, but without a feasible solution. In Nick Bostrom’s
essay on ‘Transhumanist Values,’ diversity, which includes “species, races, religious creeds, sexual
orientations, life styles, etc.” (13)), is listed as one of the derivative values of transhumanism and
“wide access” as one of the three basic conditions (besides global security and technological
progress). Transhumanists agree that “the wide access requirement underlies the moral urgency of the
(Bostrom 10-11). Bostrom urges us to develop new technologies because “the sooner this
technology develops, the fewer people will have died without access” (11), ignoring not only political
and social issues that play into this but plainly refusing to address the issue of access at stake: it is
not possible to offer everybody the same opportunities. He also fails to mention that the core value
of transhumanism, “having the opportunity to explore the transhuman and posthuman realms,”
denies certain diversities because of the deeply embedded social biases. Like in Brave New World, the
erasure of history does not do transhumanism any good: it is naïve to talk about greater choices for
61Some of non-treatment protocols have with time turned to treatment options, such as savior sibling situation.
However, the key to be able to pursue a new or unconventional procedure is financial ability and the determination of
patients and doctors who were willing to bear risks and public, and possibly lawful, scrutiny. (This is also why donations
from the community can rarely help in situations where the procedure is socially and medically controversial.)
344
everyone while a major part of the population deals with basic survival issues, such as poverty or
preventable diseases. Many transhumanists therefore leave it up to the state to remedy existing
inequalities (Thompson 169). There are, however, transhumanist civil society umbrella organizations
at every continent designed to support political parties with transhumanist goals (Benedikter and
Siepmann).
Transhumanism will surely be a part of the public conversation of the twenty-first century since
every use of technology, however optimal, inherently implements it. Transhumanist use of medical
(restitutio ad integrum) is not the only way transhumanism is practiced; major transhumanist means also
work toward increasing machine intelligence and developing military equipment, altogether
influencing the economy (more in Benedikter and Siepmann). In healthcare, transhumanist practice
is often conducted covertly through widely spread technologies that imitate natural processes, of
which ART is a perfect example. Although IVF imitates and re-enacts human reproduction, there is
a profound difference in what gametes undergo in the womb as opposed to the petri dish. IVF
makes “[finite] room for phenotypic variation” due to “subjective assessment of gametes [which]
differ[s] from natural reproduction” and “favour[ing] traits that permit cells to survive and prosper
in laboratory conditions” (Hanevik et al. 1399). Certain epigenetic effects have been traced among
IVF-conceived children (e.g. lower birth weight, proneness to diabetes and asthma, etc.), which
This would mean that human evolution is altered through this technology, but we do not yet know
much about its effects on IVF-conceived children, especially as the oldest IVF-conceived person is
only in her early forties. The question of where ART leads us is further explored in the next chapter.
345
Chapter 6: Prenatal Life: The Island Perfected
And God blessed them, and God said unto them, Be fruitful, and multiply, and replenish the earth, and subdue it: and have dominion over
the fish of the sea, and over the fowl of the air, and over every living thing that moveth upon the earth.
The King James Bible (1611)
In the previous and the present chapter on reproduction I hope to show how narrative
representations shape our conceptions of human assisted reproductive technology (ART). Chapter 5
examined a few problematic uses of terminology widely used in ART and human reproduction,
arguing that the conceptions of human reproduction through ART affect our views on matters
related to human reproduction in general, including reproduction that does not use ART.
Furthermore, that chapter compares ART in Huxley’s Brave New World and ART in actual clinical
practice during the 2010s in the West, mainly in the USA, and points out Huxley’s uncanny
predictions of how the practices of ART evolved with the ramifications of its use and overuse.
Chapter 6 focuses on the same chronological and geographical frame and explores visualizing
technologies used in IVF and during pregnancy, including cultural imagery of prenatal life catalyzed
by these technologies and their effects on our moral and popular conceptions of prenatal life.
346
Although women’s reproductive systems are original space of the prenatal development, women’s
bodies are largely left out of the visual and other representations of prenatal life, not only in arts but
also in actual science (e.g. in development of artificial wombs, see Kleeman par. 10). My discussion
here supports this finding by pointing out that the absence of a woman’s body, which is often a
feature of ancient Greek philosophy, continues in science fiction, including feminists texts (in works
by Aldous Huxley’s, Sophie Wenzel Ellis’s, and Lilith Lorraine’s, as discussed in the fifth chapter), in
the contemporary genre of ultrasound poetry (Helen Dunmore, Sue Wood), and in visual arts, such
as photography (Lennart Nilsson) and film (2001: A Space Odyssey). From these examples I find that
the industry of biotechnology, “in which the politics of fertility extend [sic] from soil to star wars”
(Franklin ‘Postmodern’ 326), is reflected in the cultural imagination through a prominent metaphor
of the space. The “original sphere” of the womb, as Peter Sloterdijk calls it, or womb as a
The central part of the chapter introduces the bioethical and philosophical dilemma known in the
literature as the nonidentity problem, which was first introduced in literature in 1984. Over the past
several decades, bioethics and philosophy literature has continued to debate the question of what
obligations, if any, present people owe to possible future people who may or may not exist. I will
argue that advances in technology have already shifted the focus to actual and probable future people,
which I term as ‘the identity problem.’ Here, the focus is on advances in biotechnology that allow
humans to select identity markers through prenatal diagnostic testing, preimplantation genetic
screening, donor selection, and gene editing. Showing how literary fiction, film and TV contribute to
this discussion demonstrates the value of a broader framing of prenatal testing as new technologies
347
In the light of this discussion, I examine some of the more prominent biases linked with ART and
people who use these technologies and people who result from them. I use micha cárdenas’s
transgender poetry to bring to light how fertility treatments play out in the lives of transgender
people, which accentuates the many meanings of access to this treatment (including social
normativity, physical and mental ability, financial means, as well as support of the law and healthcare
team). I consider these biases together to show how their intersection changes our understanding of
any single bias considered in isolation. This part concludes by briefly examining the changing
In the last part on hybridity, I follow Pramod Nayar’s argument that fiction has made the move
from posthuman biology towards posthumanist biology, in which hybridity and diversity of human
species is celebrated as long as the pathological is kept at bay. I use examples from science fiction,
specifically Octavia Butler’s and Anthony Boucher’s works. In relation to this claim and my
discussion from the chapters on pygmalionism and paralysis, I argue that the posthumanist shift is
making us reconsider our environmental and bodily interconnectedness with other species as well as
using biology as a tool, which engages with art (bioart) and technology (biotechnology).
Prenatal life is a dynamic process of growth between conception and birth: the beginning and the
emerging. A portrait of prenatal life used to be possible only after birth. Anna Laetitia Barbauld, in
the poem ‘To a Little Invisible Being Who Is Expected to Soon Become Visible’ (113), hastens the
348
“little captive” in a “living tomb”2 to “burst thy prison doors! / Launch on the living world, and
spring to light!” With the exception of a surgical cut (cesarean section, hysterectomy, abortion), the
space of the fetus is impenetrable: the fetus enters the world on its own time and conditions.
Such heterotopian space—the other space, disturbing, transformative, and purposeful—is a world
within a world, per Michel Foucault, a “placeless place” with a mirror as the counter-site “in which
the real sites, all the other real sites that can be found within the culture, are simultaneously
represented, contested, and inverted” (352). Mirroring and upsetting the world outside, wombs have
not been labeled as heterotopian spaces, although they are an essential heterotopia besides ships, fairs,
saunas, hospitals, jails, cemeteries, museums, gardens, bars, brothels, and so on. Foucault sees a ship
as a “heterotopia par excellence […] that lives by itself, closed in itself and at the same time poised in the
infinite ocean,” which is typical for an island—a new being—growing inside the womb, despite its
dependency on the body as an organism; “in civilizations where it is lacking, dreams dry up” (356).3
The navel is the ultimate site of the heterotopian relation with the real place, a “site where the relation
of the unknown has its first noticeable, physical trace [and] the site of a ruptured attachment to the
world” (Conley 7). The womb, just like ships that drive economy and politics, charges the most
fundamental and politicized topics of life and personhood and, by intervening into its natural state of
2 Being a “captive” in a “living tomb” is not far from being held captive of one’s own body—as in the locked in
syndrome or other forms of severe paralysis, discussed in the fourth chapter. What is common to both conditions is that
the person has no agency and no voice—with this exception that the cognition in respective conditions is at different
phases of development. That is to say, even if a fetus could communicate, it could not communicate its wants or needs
in a language because it is not yet capable of articulating them.
3 “Maisons closes et colonies, ce sont deux types extrêmes de l’hétérotopie, et si l’on songe, après tout, que le bateau,
c’est un morceau flottant d’espace, un lieu sans lieu, qui vit par lui-même, qui- est fermé sur soi et qui est livré en même
temps à l’infini de la mer et qui, de port en port, de bordée en bordée, de maison close en maison close, va jusqu’aux
colonies chercher ce qu’elles recèlent de plus précieux en leurs jardins, vous comprenez pourquoi le bateau a été pour
notre civilisation, depuis le XVIème siècle jusqu’à nos jours, à la fois non seulement, bien sûr, le plus grand instrument
de développement économique (ce n’est pas de cela que je parle aujourd’hui), mais la plus grande réserve d’imagination.
Le navire, c’est l’hétérotopie par excellence. Dans les civilisations sans bateaux les rêves se tarissent, l’espionnage y
remplace l’aventure, et la police, les corsairs” (Foucault ‘Des espaces’ 49).
349
oscillating between life and death, demands to make choices that can only be done by proxy, giving
The uterus as a space has been seriously undertheorized in feminism, psychoanalysis, and, more
broadly, theory, especially in comparison to the “synedoches for womanhood,” the vagina and the
breast, “parts of the body with heightened social, sexual, and cultural meaning” (Jarvis par. 12). Organs
like the uterus hold an involuntary agency over the body which, in birth, as the most extreme example,
takes over the body. Despite asserting itself “again and again in the cycle of reproduction: From the
uterine cramps felt during a menstrual period, to the agony of contractions, to the wincing pain that
accompanies the earliest days of breastfeeding, the uterus is a secret, but potent, reminder of the dumb
biology at the core of childbearing” (par. 13) and despite being the root of hysteria in the
psychoanalytic thought, the womb remained ignored in theory, scholarship, and fiction, with first
fiction and now technology working on its ectogenetic substitute. Even in science, after more than a
century of active research, it has just recently been confirmed that the uterus is not sterile (Perez-
Muñoz et el., Stinson et al.), although research on fertility and uterus microbiome is still under way.
Fetal existence, albeit in a heterotopian space, shifts the status of the expectant woman to a double
entity: ethically, pregnant persons are conceptualized with an aim to protect their own lives and the
lives they are carrying. In some cases, pregnant people are viewed as one person and in other as two.
Although pregnancy lasts for about nine months, it is not visibly evident in the first months. Fetuses
are concealed and used to be even less visible: ultrasound has become a routine in prenatal care only
in the last few decades. In the course of a pregnancy, a fetus is first felt by the pregnant person,
which is called quickening. This collaborative sensation becomes more pronounced as the pregnancy
350
hand, or a hiccupping back” (Jarvis par. 9). Gradually and indirectly the fetus’s movements can also
be visible and felt by those who touch the pregnant person’s protruding belly when it moves.
According to Thomas Aquinas’s Summa Theologica (and also St. Augustine), the fetus becomes
animated and human in an act of ensoulment with the first quickening, which first occurs sometime
in the second trimester of pregnancy. Although both theologists condemn abortion even when a
fetus is not yet considered human, the degree of the crime of abortion is based on the pregnant
person’s sensations and therefore relying on a rather subjective sensation by a (presumed) convict.
Such criteria were disregarded as soon as technologies of accessing prenatal life became available and
are still highly actual today with the heartbeat bill in the USA (discussed in chapter 5): technologies
In Peter Sloterdijk’s trilogy Spheres, the womb is the most intimate and therefore the most perfect
example of the bubble, the sphere, Sloterdijk’s spheres ranging from microspheres (vol. 1: Bubbles)
and macropheres (vol. 2: Globes) to plurality of spheres (vol. 3: Foams). Sloterdijk demonstrates that
within the womb, “the original sphere” (die Ursphäre), it is impossible to draw a distinction between
the object and the subject. The two are, instead, “coupling” (Globes 41): the fetus does not recognize
itself or the placenta, the “primal companion” (Urbegleiter). A perfect immersion of being in a pair in
a bubble is demonstrated, which is what Sloterdijk related to “negative gynecology.” This immersion
ultimately bursts in birth: once the umbilical cord is cut, the fetus can form an ego and create new
bubbles: “through the gift of separation, [the one who performs the cut] provides the child with the
stimulus for existence in external media” (Bubbles 388). Sloterdijk sees humanity as striving towards
this utopian and biological comfort of the mother’s womb through religion, ideology, and science. A
womb can be seen as a place or a no-place, also in terms of a utopian state, which is literally cut
351
In 1907, American embryologist Ross Harrison demonstrated that fragments of tissue could live in
vitro for weeks at a time. For the first time scientists saw, for example, heart muscle cells pulsating
outside the body—an entirely unexpected level of cell autonomy. The possibility of observing bodily
events outside the body itself was not considered before or thought to be impossible (Landecker 14-
15). At the same time, visual technologies (film, photography, X-ray, etc.) were being developed and
applied to medicine and biological research. “Medical practitioners have been prising open,
touching, listening to, and looking inside the pregnant female body for centuries” with X-ray (1895),
stethoscope (since 1819), and specula (the Roman period) (Blewitt 56). X-ray was the first technique
that would allow the pregnant person to see her fetus, even if it was not routinely shown to the
patients. Additionally, the procedure was quickly shown to be harmful to the fetus; computed
352
Until the use of ultrasound for medical purposes in 1956, “imaging of pregnancy and the developing
fetus remained primitive” (Benson and Doubilet). Only with the ultrasound came the mirror to the
womb with moving images of the “little invisible being,” now available to the expecting woman and
the rest of the world live or in a print. Ultrasound became routine for pregnancy screenings in the
US in the 1970s and has largely demystified the fetus: a pregnant person can see that, indeed, there is
a human(like) being growing inside of her. She could, further, show the image to others, family and
friends, and nowadays, share it on social networks. (Some parents go even further and create a social
network profile for their fetus to share its images and information, building the fetus’s personal
narrative before they are born and before they can actively contribute to it.)
A sonogram (an ultrasound picture) of a growing human, set in the unheimlich womb, the first home
of human beings, brings out familiar and unfamiliar (Blewitt 47). Just like a pregnant person, a fetus
is see-through and disembodied in the sonogram image: the bones, heart, stomach, and kidneys are
353
particularly visible, as well as the four chambers of the brain; a 2D technique grants a profile, and
3D and 4D techniques an approximation of facial features and gestures. Ultrasound allows for
obtaining normal and abnormal measurements of the fetus, a cause for relief or concern. During the
1960s, US doctors began experimenting with dyes, heat and sound to visualize the fetus and perform
procedures on fetuses (‘On the Frontiers’ 64). In addition to the ultrasound, magnetic resonance
(MR) is used for a more detailed diagnostics of fetal abnormalities today. With technology
improving every year, we can learn more and more about our growing fetuses before they are made
visible. This visual technology (and the so-thought objective machinery that renders it) creates the
fetal subject, holds the authority over it, and is assumed to capture its reality. We think of ultrasound
images as photographs (and fetuses as photographic subjects) instead of constructed images offered
through a technological experience. In fact, the more details the sonogram offers, the more it is
constructed (Fraser).
Feminism was quick to point out that sonograms are a cyborg site. The feminist theorist Marilyn
Maness Mehaffy argues that the “sonographic fetus is in many ways the ultimate cyborg in that it is
‘created’ in a space of virtuality that straddles the conventional boundary between an organic body
and a digital text” (181). Imagination and reality come together in a sonogram by making visible a
technologically generated fetal subject. Since we think of machines as objective, the image they
provide for us is taken as a fact and called a photograph, portrait, profile of a subject. When
distributed (in a photo frame, on social media, etc.), the image makes the uterus a public space and
“more specifically by making [their contents] accessible literally elsewhere than at the site of the
354
6.1.1 Fetuses in Space
The Space Age visualized floating fetuses in space, a motif now continued in ultrasound poetry,
authors, in this innovative genre that offered an alternative perspective to sonograms a fetus is
commonly showcased as the Other, an unfamiliar being, by the use of space imagery. For instance,
in Helen Dunmore’s poem ‘Scan at 8 Weeks’ (33), the fetus is imagined as the “spaceman” coming
and wonder,
what you will come to,
A peek into the womb overcomes the uncertainty— “are you staying?”—with a certainty of a life
reflected in the heartbeat: you are there and alive, “you are all heart.” Likewise, Sue Wood’s poem
‘Scan’ addresses the fetus directly and sees is as certainty, even of the scan is a “blur” (Blewitt 54):
“we see you / in the blur of first moon landings” and “know that you are / is all that is” (Wood 24).
The connection between the fetus and the world has been established as an outerworld connection.
The fetus as a spaceman in Dunmore is an “astronaut or alien” in Wood, and the womb is “a
355
The visual connection grows into a personal connection: the fetus has no voice but the (ultra)sound
translates it into a sonogram image. Ultrasound poetry translates poetic language into maternal
experience of seeing the Other that is a part of yourself into the outside of one’s body, not yet ready
for independent life. Emily Blewitt categorizes ultrasound poems as a “resistant, poetic,
The visualization of a fetus as a separate entity was enforced in general culture in 1965 with Lennart
Nilsson’s renowned first photographs of embryos and fetuses, published as the photo essay ‘Drama
of Life Before Birth’ in LIFE magazine. Nilsson first saw a fetus in formaldehyde in 1952, which he
describes as an “information shock,” perhaps because he was about to become a father himself
(‘The Drama’). The editors of LIFE encouraged him to work on this project and Nilsson spent
seven years working on chronicling prenatal human life from conception to birth, “a project that
helped invent the idea of being unborn as a stage of human life” (Lepore The Mansion 17). He had an
agreement with doctors from a hospital in Stockholm who called him immediately when they were
to perform hysterectomies or abortions or when they attested miscarriages so that Nilsson could
photograph dead fetuses. As claimed by the accompanied story in LIFE, all but one embryo was
photographed outside the womb. Again, the mother’s body was depicted as separate.
What had been “billed as portraits of life were, in fact, portraits of death,” and were used by anti-
abortionists, right-to-life movements (Lepore The Mansion 6): “weirder still is that they were portraits
of humans who looked as if they had been incubated in eggshells, like chickens, and launched into
outer space, like so many baby-sized intergalactic rockets” (7). Nilsson’s photographs portray fetuses
in predominantly early gestational ages, from just days after the conception on, and some were
arranged to look like they were floating in the womb—or in space. Placenta is detached from the
356
maternal body, as if the placenta itself, together with the amniotic sac, can preserve the growing
fetus. The original Nilsson’s photo features a fetus in an amniotic sac connected with placenta, all
seemingly floating in a dark, starry space; on the cover of LIFE, placenta was not featured in whole.
Per Sloterdijk, by denying the significance of the placenta we deny our fundamental connection to
the world around us, as we do with fostering modern age individualism. His sphere theory therefore
makes a case for interconnectedness that begins with the very creation of the human.
From: www.lennartnilsson.com/en/a-life-of-stories/the-drama-
of-life-before-birth/
From: http://www.lennartnilsson.com/en/a-
life-of-stories/the-drama-of-life-before-birth/
Nilsson’s work makes a similar case to Huxley’s by making a fetus look as if it is separate from the
body that nurtures it while also changing our visualization and conception of prenatal human life by
showing the face and the body of a human individual before birth. If Huxley’s and Nilsson’s
357
depictions of prenatal life were controversial, imagine the level of controversy a few decades later
when IVF allowed for a commodification of embryos (making large numbers of embryos, discarding
them or using them for research, practicing embryo selection, embryo donation/adoption, etc.) and
A New York publisher released a book version of Nilsson’s photographs, A Child is Born, which has
sold more copies than any other illustrated book. This kind of fetal imagery regularly appeared in
popular culture advertisements: a warning “Pregnant mothers, please don’t smoke” from 1985 is
accompanied by a smoking fetus (Mink 66) and an ad from 1991 uses a sonogram to sell a car: “Is
something inside telling you to buy a Volvo?” (J. S. Taylor 68; see more in McTavish 107).
A gynecologist commented on Nilsson’s photographs, “This is the first look at the back side of the
moon” (Lepore The Mansion 5). A mere three years after Nilsson’s photographs were published, on
Christmas Eve in 1968, three humans were launched into space on the board of Apollo 8 to have
the actual first look at the back side of the moon. Losing connection with the Earth after they
moved to the actual back side of the moon evoked a reading of the Biblical Genesis: in the most
watched television broadcast of all time, the three astronauts—three scientists, three humans—
chose to read a passage about the creation of the heaven and earth (see more in Puchner xi-xxii).
358
Figure 46 The Star Child from the very ending of the film 2001: A Space Odyssey.
Author’s screenshot.
Apollo 8’s circling of the Moon concluded the year 1968, the same year when Arthur Clark and
Stanley Kubrick’s film 2001: A Space Odyssey (1968) was featured in theaters, starring the famous Star
Child at the very end. The ending shows the aged central character, astronaut David Bowman, lying
in bed and dying as an old man and then quickly regressing into a fetus as a re-birth. Both the novel
and the film show the fetus approach the Earth as the “master of the world” (297). The last
sequence of the film shows the fetus in an amniotic sac or a womb-like space, looking towards the
Earth. The Star Child was possibly inspired by Nilsson’s 1965 photographs: the fetus is safely
surrounded by the glowing amniotic sac, not unlike the one from the Nilsson’s original photograph.
The sac could also be interpreted as an egg-like structure, akin to the one from Leonardo da Vinci’s
illustration (see figure 30) which “depicts the womb as a sort of nutshell or egg” (Shell Islandology
160). The Star Child, or the regressed David Bowman, seems much more aware of his
surroundings, with eyes wide open when looking towards the Earth and, finally, the viewer. The
novel’s penultimate chapter, ‘Transformation,’ concludes: “He was back, precisely where he wished
to be, in the space that men called real” (296). The genesis of humanity here takes place in space by
359
centering around human as the “master of the world”—in which the world bears many meanings.
Similarly, Aldous Huxley, in his poetry collection Leda (1920), compares the man and the ape. Man,
“a poor degenerate from the ape […] may not rival him, / save with my mind—a nimbler beast”
(31). The poem proceeds to show the power of the mind and concludes that “Mind, issued from the
monkey’s womb, / Is still umbilical to earth” (ib.). This might simply mean that the human mind, as
developed from apes, is an earthly matter that has not yet been transgressed. The word ‘still’ could
imply that the human mind, as opposed to apes, aims to understand the whole universe. In this light,
we can interpret the imagery of space fetuses as humanity perceiving itself more as a space-bound
In all these instances of a genesis in space, the story about the origin of humankind is told without
women. On the contrary, images sent to space on the Golden Record on Voyagers 1 and 2 in 1977,
meant to represent the essence of our species and humanity (spoken greetings in 55 ancient and
modern languages, music, a human heartbeat, a baby crying…) together with our planetary
geography (whales, the ocean, an avalanche…), do not forget women’s role in childbearing. They
include human anatomy, including sex organs, a sequence of DNA, conception, fertilized ovum,
fetus, fetal growth, a pregnant couple, birth, a nursing mother, and several family portraits.4
Although by the launch of the Voyagers the world’s first IVF baby has already been in the works, no
such technology is mentioned (but space and transport technologies are). Soon afterwards, in 1979,
scientists began experimenting with poultry eggs in space, among other animal and plant species,
hoping to learn in a variety of experiments how bird embryos would develop in a weightless space
and if eggs could hatch. These experiments (as well as most space events mentioned above) were
4Although Lepore writes that Nilsson’s photos were sent into space by NASA in 1977, it was not his but a similar photo
of a fetus by Frank Allan that is still traveling on Voyager.
360
preceded by non-reproductive but ever-reproducing human cells in space. HeLa cells, the first cells
to be successfully cloned and continue to endlessly proliferate, were sent into space on Soviet and
American satellites in 1960. They were shown to divide even faster in a zero-gravity space. As these
cancerous cells, forming a tumor, indefinitely clone themselves, Baudrillard calls their space trips a
quest for immortality: “So it is that the disseminated body of Henrietta Lacks, cloned at the
molecular level, makes its immortal rounds” (5). Preserving life outside of Earth collided with the
With ART, the visuality of the fetus extended to its very beginning, to the
embryo and the egg. It was only with ART that an image of an embryo, and not
fetus, left the laboratories and scientific journals to be exhibited to the public. In
Figure 47 Human this intertextual discourse that includes literature and cinema, the images are left
blastocyst (five-day-old
embryo). “to interpretations varying according to the viewers’ particular cultural
Credit: J. Conaghan,
uploaded on Apr 20, backgrounds, knowledge and life experiences” (Stuart Hall 100). These relatively
2014, Wiki Public
Domain.
new images of embryos differ from the well-known fetal imagery also in the
embryonic structure: the fetus looks human and the embryo does not. This is why anti-abortionists
use fetal images with “perfectly formed fingers and toes” and the proponents of stem cell research
use less humanlike images of embryos (Williams et al. 801). This is also why the first call embryos
‘persons’ and the second ‘lumps of cells,’ using pictures as proof. The subjectivity of these images is
masked with the objectively looking preciseness in the pictures. Subjectivity is at work in the public
5The Von Neumann probe is a hypothetical device, suggested by John Von Neumann (in his native Hungarian
Neumann János Lajos), that could repair and replicate itself—like biology does—from materials easily found in space.
361
discourse but also in the laboratory. A quality embryo is not necessarily good-looking: even a
scientific eye can misjudge the embryo’s morphology as uneven and opaque and thus poor quality,
resulting in smaller chance of transfer. Besides, rating systems in different laboratories contribute to
which and how many embryos are chosen for the transfer (Desai et al.). Presented in a mediated
microscopic picture, a developing embryo is frozen in time—although in real time its genetic
material is replicating and recombining while the visual technology used to take its picture is
The cyborg status of a clearly biological and technological IVF embryo is revealed, for example, with
simultaneous computational assessment of cellular morphology and kinetics (Hanevik et al. 1399) or
with a pipette sticking into the blastocyst blastomere to biopsy a cell for PGD with a 98 percent
accuracy. “Though it is fully human (for what else can it be?), it is born of science, inhabits the
timeless ice land of liquid-nitrogen storage tanks, and feeds on special (pure) culture in its petri dish.
At once potential research material (scientific object), quasi-citizen (it has legal rights), and potential
person (human subject), the embryo has a cyborg liminality in its contested location between science
and nature” (Franklin ‘Postmodern’ 336). This in-between status of the embryo is particularly
relevant in the current moment as approximates of artificial embryos are being developed. For now,
they are not exactly like ‘natural’ embryos and are not yet able to develop into a person (Zheng et
al.). As Antonio Regalado writes with a reference to Huxley, “[t]he concern is that if scientists could
make human embryos in the lab, someone might use the systems to generate genetically modified
people, a dystopian scenario similar to the central hatcheries described in the novel Brave New World”
362
Visual technology has always been a part of IVF with scanning, laparoscopic, x-ray, and microscopic
techniques. In its beginnings, egg retrieval was done through a laparoscopy, an invasive procedure
that reaches the ovary through the abdomen (today, an ultrasound needle is used to retrieve the eggs
transvaginally). The video technology that accompanies laparoscopies today was only developed in
the late 1970s and early 1980s (Kelley 35). The camera accompanying surgical instruments into the
body has joined the ultrasound in visualizing the ova—and eventually separating them from the
body in “all the reality of a metonymic assimilation” (Vasseleu 56). “For a woman patient in an IVF
clinic […] scientific images are not merely a form of photo-graphy; they participate in vita-graphy”
(57).
surgeon (who works like a cameraman) and magician (who works like a painter).6 “[B]y penetrating
into the patient’s body” (13), the cameraman loses the natural distance and with it the ability to
create original (artistic) work. As opposed to a painter who creates a total work of art, the
cameraman creates a replica of what the camera has seen, putting together “multiple fragments
which are assembled under a new law” (14). In a documentary film, this realism of the camera is
taken for granted: the camera creates an entity from the objects and subjects it depicts as if they are a
fact. Julian Huxley was a central figure of documentary film in London of the 1930s, most known
for the film From Generation to Generation produced by the Eugenic Society (Squier ‘Embryos’ 140,
142). His younger brother Aldous also made plans to put Brave New World on screen; Aldous paid
6“The magician heals a sick person by the laying on of hands; the surgeon cuts into the patient’s body. The magician
maintains the natural distance between the patient and himself; though he reduces it very slightly by the laying on of
hands, he greatly increases it by virtue of his authority. The surgeon does exactly the reverse; he greatly diminishes the
distance between himself and the patient by penetrating into the patient’s body, and increases it but little by the caution
with which his hand moves among the organs” (Benjamin 13).
363
special attention to his vision of the film as well as the actual conduct of the camera, because it could
be easily manipulated considering the controversy of bottled babies (153). Aldous was blind for
more than a year as a teenager and lived with a severely impaired sight for most of his life. He knew
from personal experience that physical vision is not the only way to see and how crucial is vision to
conceptualizing ideas: “It is possible to make use of the movies to improve our vision of objects and
In a poem by Aldous Huxley’s from the 1920s, ‘Fifth Philosopher’s Song’ (Leda 33), the lyrical
subject takes a microscopic view of eggs and sperm and portrays the competitive environment
between spermatozoa to reach a metaphorical Noah’s ark (which, in itself, is a metaphor for the
7 Getting rid of the women’s bodies for reproduction yet again, Huxley offered a postmodern and posthuman view of
modernity and technology already in his first novel, from 1921, Crome Yellow: “With the gramophone, the cinema, and
the automatic pistol, the goddess of Applied Science has presented the world with another gift, more previous even than
these—the means of dissociating love from propagation. […] An impersonal generation will take place of Nature’s
hideous system. In vast state incubators, rows upon rows of gravid bottles will supply the world with the population it
requires. The family system will disappear; society, sapped at this very base, will have to find new foundations; and Eros,
beautifully and irresponsibly free, will flit like a gay butterfly from flower to flower through a sunlit world” (Chapter V).
364
In Huxley’s poem, Susan Merrill Squier describes the twentieth-century view of reproduction as a
“literary articulation [of the paralleled] scientific articulation in the germinal and scopophilic
obsessions of Edwards and Steptoe,” who succeeded in creating the world’s first IVF baby
(‘Embryos’ 167). The collective and active sperm floats in “an interstellar uterine space, no maternal
to ancient Greece, where many texts subscribe to the ideology of preformationism—the view that a
tiny human is transferred from the father and planted in the mother’s body—which prevented
women to take part in generation.8 The debate between preformationism (which is the belief that
8See an example from Aeschylus’s Eumenides, the final play of Oresteia: “The mother of what is called her child is no
parent of it, but nurse only of the young life that is sown in her. The parent is the male, and she but a stranger, a friend,
who, if fate spares his plant, preserves it till it puts forth” (121).
365
organisms develop from tiny versions of themselves and that the embryo/fetus is thus a static and
preformed entity) and epigenetics (which beliefs that organisms develop from lesser to greater
organization during gestation)9 continues through history, most notably with Darwin and genetics
battle.
Epigenetics contributes to the division between the mother and the future child during pregnancy by
sketching the fetus as a self-made and self-developing entity: paternal inheritance and mother’s labor
are left out of the equation (Henderson 112). In literature, this representation of the Romantic fetus
as “a perfect bourgeois subject” (113) developed with the literary genre of the novel. The novel is
the ultimate human genre because it taught the bourgeoise how to be a subject, which coincided
with the modern concept of the human. The novel thus prescribed the human state through
subjective experiences and enforced humanist conception of a genetic human as an upper class,
white, free, able-bodied, heterosexual man. Starting in the last decade, the novel itself became a
target of identity politics criticisms: novels written by straight white males are being boycotted by
feminist readers, many of whom only read novels written by women, non-white, and/or gender-
non-conforming persons (see Cunningham, Cosslett). Mary Shelley’s novel Frankenstein (1818),
thematizing the modern human, is a prescient case of criticizing this humanist view of the universal
human. Donna Haraway writes that the bourgeois novel and realism have been replaced with science
fiction and postmodernism in the posthuman era, together with the shift from “white capitalist
patriarchy” to “informatics of domination” (Simians 161). Again, Frankenstein anticipates these shifts
as, according to some scholars, the first text of the science fiction genre.
366
Shelley’s novel is also representative of the Romantic and epigenetic conceptions of reproduction.
Like all other texts on humanoid creation, Frankenstein’s creature is motherless—a mother is not
even in question. Andrea Henderson finds the gap between the fetus and woman’s body grew wider
with the shift in representation that portrayed gestation and birth as mechanical (103). This scientific
representation and the epigenetic belief fed into the Romantic construction of reproduction by
eliminating the mother and giving all credit to the father. Modernity built on the Romantic notion of
reproduction by industrializing the body, as presented in Brave New World, by completely mechanical
ectogenesis and by putting the products, test-tube babies, into assembly lines (Squier ‘Reproducing’
117).
Birth is an event that physically separates one body from another. Maggie Nelson writes in her queer
family memoir The Argonauts that to give birth is to surrender the body “to go into pieces” (84). IVF,
on the other hand, separates the inseparable: a woman is separated from her eggs that develop
outside of her for at least two and up to six days under the watchful eye of an embryologist. Patients
undergoing IVF today are routinely given photos of their few-days-old embryos before they are
transferred into the uterus—the very first portrait of a potential child. Huxley prophesizes this idea
in Brave New World as well: “Embryos are like photographic film” (21)—they can only stand red light
Another aspect where vision, and particularly photography and film, takes the role in reproduction is
in the room for sperm donation, sterile but amply equipped with pornographic materials. If a
10With new technology of 4D ultrasounds it could be said that ‘fetuses are like videos.’ Walter Benjamin has, in fact,
called the technique of mechanical reproduction—the cinema.
367
woman’s role in IVF is orchestrated through the hormonal chemistry by her physician, a man’s role
is set up through visuality in order to obtain sperm. In Richard Meier’s third cycle of his poem
Building Matilda, titled ‘The Science Bit,’ this contrast is especially prominent: “all the time these
chemicals control / the essence of you, you are null, an absence.” The depiction of the woman is
again rather her disappearance while “ten eggs appear, collected to be mixed / with what the male
produces in a small // white room before some pictures of a blonde / who looks completely up for
it, and not there” (25). The detached sexual act for the sake of “the science bit” trumps the judged-
upon artificiality of charting temperature to trace ovulation in Sharon Olds’s ‘The Planned Child.’
The sexual act of the IVF process has a solely technological purpose of fertilizing the eggs and must
be performed in a much stricter time frame than the natural ovulation window. As in a ritual,
everything and everyone participating—from the strength of light and the level of room temperature
to the preciseness of the technician’s work and the patient self-administering the hormonal
injections—must perform just right. At this point in the process, the perspective is zoomed in to the
petri dish. Likewise, Meier’s perspective is microscopic when he presents the activity around the
obtained eggs and sperm as crucial to the process of ‘building’ his daughter, piece by piece,
procedure by procedure.
Few inventions in science and technology have not previously been imagined in film and literature.
Fiction operates in a privileged cultural space where speculation can grow on current, historicized, or
fabricated cultural, societal, scientific, and technological developments. Just as fiction is inspired by
scientific inventions and speculations, science gets inspired by, for example, fictional Eliza Doolittle
to create the first chatbot ELIZA and, further, a Star Trek computer which updated the basic
chatbot into a virtual assistant, nowadays a part of every personal phone and computer. Science
368
speculates, experiments, and builds on the established knowledge and, likewise, fiction speculates,
experiments, and builds on already existing texts; for example, Shelley’s Frankenstein is a predecessor
Odyssey (Evans et al. xiii). Science fiction, in particular, plays with the “worlds of if” which are
connected to the reader’s world through a logical relationship (linear, causal, extrapolative) while at
the same time permitting for a metaphorical or symbolic reading (Evans et al. xv). According to
novum (cognitively explicable but strange innovation) in the world of if. Science fiction shows readers
a distorted, metamorphosed image of the present as transported into the future; by being tied to the
present, this literary genre makes for a perfect philosophical exercise in reflecting on the
When Andrew Niccol’s Gattaca appeared in theaters back in 1997, much of what the film depicted
was not possible. Only twenty years later, the basics of Gattaca’s genetical engineering through IVF
and PGD are possible and sometimes practiced. Unfettered developments of PGD application have
already put prospective parents into a position where they can choose their child’s genetic make-up.
Scientists dream on: Based on already available technologies of comparing the prospective parents’
DNAs before the couple would even meet, American geneticist George Church created a start up
for a dating application that would allow matching of people whose children could not get one of
the 7,000 rare genetic diseases (Pelley par. 71, 74). And writers dream on as well.
GENETICIST
You've already specified blue eyes, dark
hair and fair skin. I have taken the liberty
of eradicating any potentially prejudicial
conditions – premature baldness, myopia,
alcoholism and addictive susceptibility,
propensity for violence and obesity –
369
MARIA
(interrupting, anxious)
– We didn't want—diseases, yes.
ANTONIO
(more diplomatic)
We were wondering if we should leave some
things to chance.
GENETICIST
(reassuring)
You want to give your child the best possible
start. Believe me, we have enough imperfection
built-in already. Your child doesn't need
any additional burdens. And keep in mind,
this child is still you, simply the best of you.
You could conceive naturally a thousand times
and never get such a result.
The scene from the beginning of Gattaca reveals what I call the identity problem: inquiring about and
designing desired features in a not-yet-existing person. The discomfort of the couple and the
dissonance between them and the geneticist is palpable. Maria and Antonio naturally conceived their
first child who was born with a heart defect, which is why they decided to take the in vitro
fertilization (IVF) route with preimplantation genetic testing (PGD) for their second child. In the
futuristic world of Gattaca, IVF with PGD is an ordinary way of procreating. By conceiving their
Have Maria and Antonio harmed their first son? The nonidentity problem,11 first devised by Derek
Parfit in Reasons and Persons (1984), sees to suggest that Maria and Antonio have not wronged him.
The nonidentity problem calls attention to the fact that some decisions we make now will change
11 The nonidentity problem, also called a paradox of future individuals, is a philosophical problem vaguely related to what
I call the identity problem. In ethics, the nonidentity problem is common in the area of prenatal life and mostly all
future-directed choices. The paradox holds to three main intuitions: 1) a person-affecting view, which says that an act
can only be bad if it is bad for someone, 2) bringing someone into existence is not bad for that person, even if their
existence is difficult, meaning that life inherently holds more value than nonlife, and 3) which contradicts 1) and 2), that
bringing someone into existence can be wrong even if it is not bad for someone. This means that at least one of the
three intuitions is false (see Parfit, Woodward, Kavka).
370
who comes into existence at a future time by affecting the timing of conception. For example, in the
case of Maria and Antonio, if they had decided to use IVF with PGD instead of having their son
naturally, the child who would subsequently be born would be a different individual than the one
who was in fact conceived and born, since it would grow from a different sperm and egg. In identity
changing cases like this one, Parfit argues that our decisions do not make a person worse off than
they otherwise would be, unless the life they have is worse than never having existed.
It seems to follow that the couple did not do harm to their son if we assume that the son they had
naturally would likely not have been chosen among the available IVF embryos due to his heart
defect. Alternatively, the pregnancy might result in selective termination due to prenatal testing
results. In a futuristic scenario, the fetal heart defect might be fixed before or during the pregnancy,
which would ultimately block the nonidentity problem from arising. It would not, however, prevent
It is not only in a sonogram image that a fetus can be separate from the womb. “When the genetic
text of the unborn child can be embedded in a biological site far removed from its origin, the
intimate connection between child and womb which once provided a natural context for gestation
has been denatured,” writes Katherine Hayles as an example of denaturing the context (Chaos 272).
Prenatal information is all the more crucial for the identity problem when a not-yet implanted
embryo is being evaluated. First of all, evaluation of embryo morphology, mosaicism, and other
factors that contribute to the embryo being chosen for the transfer or discarded is based on a well-
researched but overall changing scoring systems which vary among the clinics and include three
prominent biases, all mentioned in this chapter: the subjective view of an embryologist, the
supposedly objective perspective offered by the visual technology, and the fact that the evaluation
371
events take place sporadically.
Prenatal information is useful for patients and clinicians—testing is encouraged so that proper
assessment can be in place—but it is also a burden. When a prenatal test diagnoses a human being at
an embryo or a fetal stage with a heart defect, spina bifida, and short stature or identifies an
abnormality, such as eleven digits, it crosses a boundary into a physician-patient discourse where at
least five value systems meet: the patient’s, their partner’s, and the clinician’s, as well as that of the
institution and wider society. In Gattaca, the mainstream ethical values are obvious: the couple is able
to choose superfluous features while the society, with the geneticist as its proxy, takes over to
eliminate the undesirable ones. The most salient boundary crossing is made, however, when the
identity of the future person is labeled deviant by one or the other value system, and especially when
In Western healthcare settings, the four main ethical principles (of justice, nonmaleficence and
beneficence, and respect for the patient’s autonomy) play a crucial part in reaching ethical decisions
on prenatal life. Briefly summarized, these principles advocate—in the same order as above—for the
medical personnel to give a fair treatment when needed, do no harm and be of benefit to the patient,
and require the patient to be a rational person with a capacity to act freely, with a voluntary act, and
Potentially problematic decisions in IVF that may not satisfy all four ethical principles are
transferring two embryos at the same time, choosing an embryo of a certain sex although it is of
lower quality than other available embryos, or choosing donor gametes when the partner is fertile or
subfertile but not infertile. Not choosing against deafness or Down’s Syndrome is a controversial
372
decision at the PGD stage of IVF: in the UK, for example, it is forbidden to transfer an embryo
with known aneuploidy (while Iceland has close to eradicated people with Down’s Syndrome
through prenatal testing and abortion). Physicians might view choosing an embryo with known
aneuploidy as voting for non-health over health, thus going against the essence of medicine
(Galarneau). It is in such cases where the borderline lies and where we need to listen to individual
stories and contexts, many of which are found in fiction and nonfiction.
The identity problem has existed even before ultrasound first offered a peek into the uterus,
revealing the sex and health status of the fetus. In a broader sense, it has been around, albeit
unnoticed, at least since the idea of eugenics was discussed in fictional utopias, such as Samuel
Butler’s Erewhon: or, Over the Range (1872) and Francis Galton’s Kantsaywhere (1910), both highly
influenced by Charles Darwin’s ideas. Yet, the identity problem grows larger and more obvious with
the advanced technology of prenatal diagnostic and screening tests as well as with assisted
reproductive technologies, which can manipulate embryos even before they are created.
Granted, people already make choices about their potential child’s genetic, cultural, and partly
environmental characteristics when choosing their partner. Yet, when these decisions are made in
the realm of assisted reproductive technologies, they are much more rational and intentional—and
sometimes agonizing. Choosing a donor is a task that cannot be taken easily. The commercialization
of sperm and eggs tells us that. For example, Ivy League donors are paid better, even if everyone is
aware this money is only buying a chance of the progeny being similar to the donor. Another set of
373
issues comes from the fact that these patients are disproportionally wealthy, white, and older, while
Various prenatal tests offer more certainty about the forming individual in vitro or in the uterus, but
are, despite similar results, a target of vastly different levels of controversy. PGD and chromosome
blood testing are such an example: they often reveal the same information on aneuploidies and sex
of the embryo, but PGD incites much controversy while chromosome blood tests receive little
reflection on their ramifications (see Kaposy). PGD is invasive and can be harmful to the embryo by
suppressing its development, albeit rarely, while chromosome blood testing involves only non-
invasive blood draw. From an ethical perspective, however, prenatal blood tests often result in
heavier consequences for the patients, if acted upon. Chromosome blood testing takes place at the
end of the first trimester of pregnancy and prospective parents who opt to terminate a previously
wanted pregnancy must undergo an abortion. PGD, on the other hand, takes place days before the
embryo is ready to implant in the womb, at the point when the pregnancy is far from a certainty.12
For some conservative people, not choosing an embryo that underwent a PGD with poor or
inconclusive results is already at the level of murder. For others, it does not come even close to
abortion. During the Alabama heart bill legislative debate the state senator and sponsor of the
abortion bill Clyde Chambliss said: “The egg in the lab doesn’t apply. It’s not in a woman. She’s not
12Although the days of the cycle before the implantation or missed period count retroactively as the first days of
pregnancy, when, in the natural course of the process, the fertilized ovum travels from the ovary to the uterus, the
implantation is only to take place a few days after the transfer of the embryo to the womb.
374
By virtue of PGD, a three-day-old embryo can have its identity revealed, in some aspects, more
clearly than that of a child or even adult whose genetic predispositions show up only through the
course of life or, perhaps, never at all. Such embryos can be identified as female or male, abled or
disabled, blue, brown, or green-eyed, right and wrong. New tests open new ethical questions. We
will soon be able to point out other relevant and irrelevant genetic factors as well, for example, later-
onset diseases, such as BRCA1 and 2 mutations which greatly increase the risk of developing certain
types of cancer later in life (Robertson 214). Eliminating Tay-Sachs disease is less controversial than
eliminating conditions such as Down’s syndrome or genetic blindness because Tay-Sachs disease
reaches two criteria that are commonly concerned as justifiable for germline editing: the disease gets
severe very early in life and results in childhood death. Genetic diseases with late onset, such as
Huntington’s disease (30-50 years old), are more likely to be generally condoned simply due to the
chronological development of the disease. Likewise, eliminating genetic diseases where death may be
prevented with treatment (e.g. cancers) and genetic diseases with a wide range of severity (e.g.
A technology similar to PGD was depicted in Brave New World. In the Hatchery, a factory in which
all human beings are created via technology similar to a combination of IVF and artificial wombs,
each embryonic and fetal information chart is labeled with information of “[h]eredity, date of
fertilization, membership of Bokanovsky Group [a caste].” The narrator makes an argument that the
knowledge of fetal characteristics makes the prospective human “[n]o longer anonymous, but
named, identified” (20-21). Information about their identity reduces the human, individual, and
personal statuses of these embryos and fetuses: it might be a fetus, but we also know that she is a
375
female with perfect pitch who will experience an early onset of Alzheimer’s disease. We thus estimate
and evaluate the individual’s identity and future on the basis of their genes. Like Huxley, I argue that
there is a profound difference in our relationship to an embryo or a fetus that is a blank slate vs. an
“Even queer theorists are sobered to learn the sex of an embryo,” writes Andrea Long Chu, queer
theorist and a trans woman (67). Another issue with sex selection is that embryos of transgender
people can, so far, render only their sex but not gender; it is not difficult to imagine consequences if
studies examining transgender genetics prove fruitful for prenatal testing. No information is simple
and straightforward in prenatal life, not even the sex, as widely attested by sexual discrimination
against female fetuses in many cultures. IVF allows, by the mere protocol of the technology, for a
manipulation of the birth and sex orders of potential siblings. While this choice may simply be a
collateral luxury secondary to treatment (such as the physical features Maria and Antonio chose via
PGD) and possibly the last thing on the mind of patients suffering the pain of infertility, this is not
the case for everyone. Those willing to undergo IVF with PGD, and those who can afford it, are
able to choose from a growing repertoire of features. Where to draw the line, then? “Diseases, yes,”
Maria and Antonio’s first child exhibits extreme will and ability by (illegally) penetrating into the
group of genetically modified people. On the contrary, some genetically superior people in Gattaca as
well as Brave New World fail at genetically conditioned prospering or have unexpected health issues.
The only guarantee these two dystopias offer is that the world will get grimmer and more stratified,
more scientific and superficial—overall, less of what makes us human. The suffering and harm are
376
still there, in a different form. Humans are there in a different form. In utopias, human diversity and
Principles of contemporary bioethics in the West (principle of justice, beneficence and non-
maleficence, and respect for autonomy), together with cultural traditions and values (such as
solidarity, virtue and professional ethics, etc.), serve a noble goal, but not all suffering and harm is to
be alleviated at the stage of prenatal life. There are other, often times safer, ways of dealing with
deafness and some types of heart defects after, rather than before, birth. (As a matter of fact,
deafness brings with it not only the deaf community but a whole deaf culture, with language as its
central point.) As technology progresses, there will always be newer and better solutions at all stages.
With every new invention we will need to evaluate which intervention at which stage is the most
appropriate and ethical in a given case and in general. In vitro gene editing made crucial steps
towards clinical use much faster than it was predicted or allowed, eliminating undesirable conditions
from an already-identified embryonic or fetal individual. IVF thus serves at least two roles: treatment
of prospective parents’ infertility (as restitutio ad integrum) and selection (and potential treatment) of
prospective children’s genetics (which could be viewed as restitutio ad integrum when eliminating a
The quest for perfection is in human nature. All the same, the very essence of human nature is
diversity and pathology (diseases, yes). Pathology, per George Canguilhem, is not a deviance of the
norm, but rather a different kind of norm. In Octavia Butler’s Lilith’s Brood: The Xenogenesis Trilogy
(1987-89), every genetic anomaly is treated. Yet, humanity is doomed due to a Human
essential for our species (Adulthood 467). In the buzzing biotechnological (r)evolution we are
377
undergoing, we should turn to fictional and (auto)biographical narratives before we make any
6.3 Donors
Related but distinct from the identity problem is what we might call the likability problem.
Homogenity and affinity, as in being alike someone and as in finding someone likeable, are key to
pairing the couple with their child in gamete donation, which ultimately results in another type of
affinity—that of blood.13 Sperm and egg donation are now commonly discussed in the light of
designing rather than creating a child with so-called designer babies. There are also other prominent
materials. When choosing a donor, one cannot choose the sex of the child (as can be done with
PGD) but can choose against or for a disability, race, or cultural background and against or for
musical or athletic talents—the donor search is designed on the basis of these identities and
affinities. Genes and environment are believed to make us who we are, which is why medical
information, from seasonal allergies to family members’ causes of death, is basic for the donor files.
In an essay on A Cup of Jo, one of the most read and community-fostering women lifestyle blogs in
the USA (Forbes ‘Top 10’), led by Joanna Goddard, Caitlin describes the process in California
13 Apart from gamete donation, liking is not a common directive with IVF and PGD, despite the sensationalized and
targeted talk about embryo selection of designer babies. Granted, it does take place in IVF and PGD procedures of
which the purpose is non-medical sex selection—but these are rare. In a more ethical practice, it can only take place, for
example, when a couple undergoing IVF has more embryos of the same quality and they are asked which one to implant
first; they can freely choose the sex of their child or select against or—less freely—for a disability, such as leukemia or
deafness genes. (It is unethical and sometimes also impossible to de-select embryos that are carriers of genetic
conditions, i.e. would not have them themselves but could transfer the genes to their progeny.)
378
Cryobank, the dominant bank in the industry: “You have a million factors though which you can
story these donors. They list the obvious stuff—height, age, ethnicity, eye color, hair color—but
then they also have ‘staff impressions’ of the person and ‘artistic contribution’ (they can choose to
draw a picture or write an essay). They share SAT scores and a full medical history. Most of them
include childhood photos” (Goddard par. 3). Not far from “ordering from a menu” (Goddard par.
9), in marked-based USA and other commercial banks across the world, gametes are now
predominantly bought by homosexual couples and single people on the basis of a wholesome donor
When choosing a sexual partner for procreation, the subconscious usually takes the role of finding
the likeable in the partner. Animals that we are, our pheromones led us to people to whom we are
most genetically compatible in order to produce the most optimal offspring—or so says science
(More and Grady 200). People describe it as “an intuitive non-cognitive experience— ‘I just felt she
was the one’, ‘it just felt right’ and ‘my ovaries were singing’” (Farsides 352). In the infertility
subgroup of parents, this process involves choosing new people: a physician and sometimes also a
donor (in about 14 percent of cases in the US (Kenney and McGowan 15) the solution involves a
third party).
When choosing a donor, creating a child is more intentional and the reproductive choices more
rational. In gamete transaction, the two methods of choice seem rather separate: liking or disliking
the person does not come in the package with calculating the desired genetic traits. One can go with
a subjective or an objective method or try to balance both. More and more agencies offer in-depth
information about their donors, from age and medically relevant information to hobbies and essays
written exactly for this purpose, commonly including pictures and sometimes also audio or video
recordings. All this information testifies that gamete transaction is considered much more than a
379
reproductive, merely biological, event. This is also why asking a friend or a relative for a donation is
In ‘Who’s Your Daddy?,’ an episode (2.23) of House, M.D., one of the world’s most watched series in
the 2000s, physician Lisa Cuddy (Lisa Edelstein), single and nearing her forties, decides to pursue
IVF. She firsts tests a colleague as a potential donor by taking him out for a date, but finally decides
against it. She then looks through medical and personal data of available sperm donors and cannot
decide between two men with the ‘cleanest’ profile: no inheritable diseases, “four living
grandparents,” etc. (12:15). When she asks another physician, the antagonistic protagonist, Greg
House (Hugh Laurie), for a “medical opinion on genetics” of the two candidates, he tells her such
rational choices are wrong when creating a child. In his typical manner, he assumes from their
personal information that the chosen donors are “losers” and reminds Cuddy that she is “designing
a kid—a loser kid” (11:55; 12:41). Instead, he advises Cuddy to find “someone you like” (35:45). She
explains that she is “not going dancing with [the donor], I’m looking for a healthy sperm,” to which
he responds, “Who they are, what they do, that doesn’t matter?” (12:20). In his opinion, the whole
380
picture needs to be considered: genes and their expression as well as epigenetic factors.14 To make
the point, House violates confidentiality of the donor process and invites the chosen donor, a young
medical student, for a false job interview from which Cuddy realizes she dislikes the donor as a
person. “You gotta know who you’re getting in bed with,” preaches House at Cuddy (32:15)15 and
reiterates: “you should know: genes matter. Who you are matters. Pick someone you trust” (35:35).16
It is never revealed which donor she finally chose and she does not succeed in having a live birth,
but suffers two unsuccessful transfers and a miscarriage (a result of choosing bad genes?). After
giving up on IVF, Cuddy finally becomes a mother in her second attempt at adoption. In her
adoption cases, the birth parents’ genetics or their likeability are not considered, and neither is
attested substance abuse during one of the pregnancies. The dilemma, at least in House, M.D., exists
only with donation, where the choice of who will the child be rests solely on the patient.
Caitlin, who went through similar dilemmas like Cuddy,17 asked herself, “Ultimately, how important is
your choice? You have no idea and no way of checking. It’s a mystery” and concluded, “After all, my
14House backs up his method of wholesome choice on the theory of natural selection, which is largely based on
genetics. He compliments Cuddy: “I was just thinking what your mother looked like, because your father obviously
chose her for breeding purposes” (2:06). Cuddy, who is Jewish, aligns this theory with German views on eugenics during
the Holocaust, revealing the dangerous and unethical side of what was thought to be the purifying of the genetic pool.
15This sentence alludes to the Bible stories in which to know someone means, in some occasions, to have sex with them. In
one such story, Leah becomes Jacob’s wife in a plot of deception orchestrated by the father of the two sisters: Jacob
marries Leah thinking he married her sister Rachel, whom he prefers—but did not get to know.
16 Including trust into the process of choosing a donor could be interpreted in the light of the subplot rather than
general advice: referring to trust as a factor in the decision might be House’s way of telling Cuddy that he is trust-worthy
since he is one of the rare people she told about her treatment and even asked him to administrate her progesterone
injections. Cuddy, despite being sexually and intellectually attracted to House, decides to test House’s best friend as a
potential donor but stops herself from asking House (5:30)—another choice of Cuddy’s that puzzles and bothers House.
17Caitlin and her wife Claire describe an “interesting […] shift in expectations:” “When we went in, I thought, ok, we’ll
get a 6’2’’ Olympian with a Ph.D. Because why wouldn’t you? But then you start thinking, okay, what IS a barometer of
success and potential, and what’s really just your interpretation? It turns out to be a real value test” (Goddard par. 5). For
Caitlin and Claire, “the subjective things made a difference, like the staff impressions saying, oh, he’s friendly or he was
smiling. One guy seemed perfect on paper—he was on the Persian Olympic soccer team (my wife is Arab; I’m super
athletic)—but the staff described him as moody” (par. 6). The banks take some burden off the buyer’s shoulders by
pointing out the candidates’ talents and achievements, asking them to undergo donor psychological screening, and
381
brother, sister and I are all genetically of the same stock, but you could not pick three more different
people” (Goddard par. 10). Yet, the weight of this choice is exactly how the donor industry earns
billions.18 Even if we know genetics is largely unpredictable (that choosing an athletic donor does not
guarantee an athletic child),19 the donor industry flourishes around elite universities. “We try to
always place the labs near strong universities,” says Scott Brown, VP for Communications at
California Cryobank, who notes that clients show a “slight bias” for donors with advanced degrees
(Eber par. 2). Aaron D. Levine’s study has shown that the bias is more than slight, as it is the
strongest presence outside the banks among donor agencies and individual couples (27). The banks
are merely following the trends, clearly fostering “eugenic implications […] since social class and
financial constraints limit users’ access, while social preferences and medical ‘standards’ limit men’s
Established in 1977, Cryobank, Inc., later California Cryobank, opened its first branch in Palo Alto,
California, the second in Cambridge, Massachusetts, and the third in New York City (‘About’). The
now largest sperm bank in the USA and one of the biggest in the world “says its donors are the cream
of the cup. Less than 1 percent of the 20,000 men who apply to be donors each year are accepted.
‘It’s tougher to get into California Cryobank than it is Harvard or Stanford,’ brags Brown” (Eber
screening their behavior whenever they visit the clinic. In the end, Caitlin and Claire chose a non-Arab (“there weren’t
many Arab donors”), “celebrity look-a-like” donor, “mainly because he seemed nice” which “translated across the page
in an unexpected way” and “weighted out some of the more impressive credentials” of other donors (par. 7-8). In this
case, liking the donor as a person (“he seemed nice”) trumped his physical likeness (non-Arab) with the couple.
Nonetheless, the donor was like the couple in other ways, for instance, his athleticism was a factor, although it turned
out that the child “might not be naturally sporty” (par. 13). After a play of genes, the couple was surprised to see their
son “is a lot like [Caitlin], even though [her] wife carried him and [she] had no genetic stake in the endeavor” (par. 11).
18“[T]he global sperm market is valued at more than $3.5 billion and is expected to reach nearly $5 billion by 2025
thanks to improving reproductive technology and growing acceptance of same-sex marriage” (Eber par. 1).
19California Cryobank lists a “legend” on their website when “the world renowned dancer, Isadora Duncan once wrote
to George Bernard Shaw, ‘You have the greatest brain in the world, and I have the most beautiful body, so we ought to
produce the most perfect child.’ To which Shaw is alleged to have answered, ‘My dear woman, what if the child inherits
my body and your brains?’” (‘Sperm’ par. 58).
382
par. 2) who says that the trend has “increasingly [been about] who is this person, not just what is this
person” (par. 7). Sperm banks “reproduce masculine ideals through their representation of
phenotypic, biological, and social characteristics” (Moore and Grady 186), focusing on the physical
dominance (height, weight, favorite sports) and social survivability (occupation, grade average,
With a few prominent differences from sperm donors,20 the oocyte donation centers search for
young, pretty, educated, and accomplished women. Both types of centers search for what seems
superficial rather than significant medical qualities. Thus, in matching donors with clients, being alike
in blood type, ethnicity, or some other significant medical factor is often just as important as a
quality that is less certain to be inherited but is nonetheless highly valued in the world, such as
beauty and education.21 Unfortunately, again on the expense of clients, sperm banks have a
20Obtaining the eggs involves hormonal ovarian simulation and subsequent egg retrieval, which are much more invasive,
painful, costlier, and physically riskier than sperm donations. Moreover, the American Society of Reproduction Medicine
recommends egg donation to not be performed more than “approximately six” times (The Practice 195) while sperm
donation could be, and often requires to be, a long-term commitment: “men must typically donate at least once a week
for a year” because screening the donors is costly (Almeling 69). Furthermore, “[e]gg donors must conform to rigorous
height/weight ratios; sperm donors do not. Women over 30 are unlikely to be accepted as donors; men can donate until
they are 40. Sperm banks require that men be at least 5’8” tall; egg agencies do not set height minimums. Most sperm
banks require that men be enrolled in college or have a college degree; egg agencies do not. Most egg agencies require
psychological evaluations to assess how women feel about having children out in the world; sperm banks do not require
that men discuss this possibility with a mental health professional” (ib.).
21Donor Concierge, an agency for finding Ivy League egg donors, reinforces “The Myth of the Ivy League Egg Donor”
while rebuking it in a disclaimer: “While many people have an ‘ideal’ donor in mind who attends Harvard or Yale, the fact is
that many young women who choose to donate their eggs are just as intelligent, attractive and ambitious as Ivy League egg
donors. And there is a question of availability—young women who attend exclusive Ivy-League schools often don’t choose
to be egg donors because they may not have the time or inclination to do so” (‘Find’). Nonetheless, compensation for an
Ivy League donor used to be $5,000, which is nowadays an average number, and is now closer to $20,000. Three identical
advertisements in Harvard Crimson, the Daily Princetonian, and Yale Daily News from 2006 offered $35,000 on behalf of a
couple who sought an exceptional woman, and that same year $50,000 was offered in Brown Daily Herald (Levine 31),
despite the American Society of Reproductive Medicine guidelines prohibiting the linking of compensation to donors’
personal characteristics (Ethics 15-16). “To avoid putting a price on human gametes or selectively valuing particular
human traits, compensation should not vary according to the planned use of the oocytes (e.g. research or clinical care,
the number or quality of oocytes retrieved, the outcome of prior donation cycles, or the donor’s ethnic or other personal
characteristics)” (Ethics Committee of The American Society for Reproductive Medicine, Financial Compensation of Oocyte Donors
(2007) in Levine 28). This view has not changed in the latest 2016 report, and neither has its warning (Ethics 15-16).
383
problematic history: one such example is the Repository for Germinal Choice, founded by Robert
Graham, an enthusiast in eugenics, whose bank sold their customers semen of Nobel Prize winners in
1980s and 1990s—the Nobel part of which turned out to be completely false (Plotz). Although many
believe eugenics have fallen out of favor after the horrors of the Nazi regime, ART and related
technologies bring back its practices in a less organized and unified form.
California Cryobank points out that “[a] sperm bank cannot genetically determine or in any way
manipulate the intelligence, talents or physical characteristics of any child conceived from the sperm
it supplies” (‘Sperm’ par. 55). Genes are, of course, never a guarantee; yet, the business model these
successful gamete banks have been built on is precisely a personal approach to genetics.22 Commercial
egg and sperm banks make a great effort to help buyers find eggs they like and that are like them, for
instance, finding donors with artistic talents, sports achievements, or celebrity-look-a-likes is California
Cryobank specialty. The “distinction between a ‘need’ and a ‘want’ which is often engaged in a health-
related discourse” (Farsides 355) goes against the “‘good enough’ donor” narrative (356). Many
websites and applications are made today to match people with donors based on searching ‘the right
sort of person,’ and their gamete samples are often available through a simple internet search.
Not unlike Sophie Wenzel Ellis’s Doctor Mundson who wanted to pair the most perfect people, the
dating landscape is adjusting to pairing only the most genetically compatible people. Harvard geneticist
George Church is developing a dating app, called Digi8, which would match people with compatible
22Sperm and egg banking might be one of the reasons why studies to determine genetic basis for these traits are well-
funded, despite the preoccupation with innate traits as a social consequence being all too familiar from the past eugenic
efforts and the danger that the results of these studies are easily misinterpreted and misused (Rohlfs par. 9). Rori Rohlfs’s
guest post also points out how the eugenic history of the field of genetics is easily overlooked in scientific practices and
calls for scientific accountability in unwittingly supporting eugenic arguments (par. 10).
384
genetic profiles, meaning that “about 5 percent of population” (Pelley 74, Noor par. 7) would not be
matched because they could (but not will) produce offspring with genetic defects. Although Church
himself suffers from narcolepsy, attention deficit disorder and dyslexia, which he sees as “an
advantage” but which would also disqualify him from most searches, he still “hope[s] that society sees
the benefit of diversity” (Pelley par. 75-76). Church calculates the financial benefit of his service: “It’s
7,000 diseases. […] It’s about a trillion dollars a year, worldwide” (Pelley par. 74). The argument of
the great costs related to gene therapy over the use of his app could convince many people. But, as
Janus Rose points out, “for anyone not white, cis, able-bodied, or male, it’s obvious where all this is
going”—modern eugenics is a real danger (par. 5). Church’s lab was famously one of the first such
places to hire a full-time ethicist, who in this case to works with the goal of “genetic equity” that
would give all people access to genetic technology (Rose par. 11).
Male donors have never been hard to find for Cryobank: “It’s a way of making money without really
doing anything,” one commented. The other, although seeing it as a help to “couples who otherwise
cannot have children” and “the money [as] the incentive,” had some moral impediments: “You
shouldn’t try to mold the child before he or she is born” (Mucklo 17). A study of egg donors has
shown that 88 percent thought the best thing about donating was “being able to help someone”
(Ethics 17) rather than the financial incentive. Rene Almeling’s study shows the opposite result: the
In addition to these differences, egg agencies and sperm banks assume women and men have different
motivations for providing sex cells. While my interviews with egg and sperm donors reveal that most are
motivated by money, staff portray the transactions in highly gendered terms. Drawing on the stereotype of
women as nurturing caregivers, egg agencies emphasize the plight of infertile couples in selecting women who
want to ‘help’ people by giving the ‘gift of life.’ In contrast, sperm banks encourage men to earn money with an
easy ‘job’ (Almeling 68).
385
Figure 50 Posters advertising gestational surrogacy.
Featured in Rene Almeling’s article (69): “Equipped with puns that alleviate the heaviness of the topic, the altruism of egg donation is
accentuated by depicting another woman who would benefit from such donation with a resulting pregnancy.”
Credit: Circle Surrogacy. Used with permission.
Paid and unpaid donations both bring their own set of problems. The way the fertility industry is set
often exploits donors and patients. Like usury, the (often illegal) practice of lending money where
money is ‘unnaturally’ increased by unreasonably high interest rates, the donor industry thrives on the
exchange of ‘natural’ gametes for money. “Among its other wrongs, usury destabilizes the relation of
money to goods” (Berry 432). Usury is, in its essence, the reproduction or breeding of money: “usury
takes money whose natural telos is to facilitate exchange, and uses it for the unnatural end of
reproduction” (Hawkes 346). Just like sex became free of reproduction with contraception and thus
made what some saw as an act of breeding into a barren act, usury turns sterile money into the
Such unnatural reproduction of tokos (meaning ‘offspring’ but also ‘interest’) is a key theme in Oedipus
the King. While the economy of the Theban state (polis) suffers from infertility, Oedipus’s household
386
(oikos) is reproduced in an unnaturally redundant and socially perverse way (Shell The Economy 96-98).
Oedipus does not realize his wrongdoings because he does not understand his own generation, i.e.
who generated him and who he generated. “Do you know who your parents are?” Teiresias asks him,
implying a related question: Do you know who you are? (Sophocles 240). Only at the end of the play
does Oedipus realize the true status of himself as tokos and the price tha his family and his state paid
for his blind actions: what he believed to be bad luck (tuche), was in fact bad birth (100). Reproduction
Ezra Pound, building on Dante’s Inferno, also writes against usury in his Cantos LI (1937, 33):
The wide and long-lasting condemnation of usury comes from the Old Testament (Exodus 22:25 and
Deuteronomy 23:19), however, many that condemn usury overlook Deuteronomy 23:20 which reads,
“Unto a stranger thou mayest lend upon usury; but unto thy brother thou shalt not lend upon usury:
that the Lord thy God may bless thee in all that thou settest thine hand to in the land whither thou
goest to possess it.” In the US, most donations and surrogacies are paid, except for those that count as
a favor to relatives or close friends. Aristotle, in The Nicomachean Ethics, condemned usury—or money,
gold and silver, for that fact, seeing money as unnatural because it does not increase as do products of
farming, hunting, and herds. As such, usury is also against nature. Aristotle classes usurers with
pimps—which is also one of the meanings of the word usurer; a pimp is a sexual usurer (Shell The End
126). Is a company buying and selling human gametes for profit a human trafficker as well?
The Donor Concierge website welcomes potential clients in search of an egg donor: “We know that
you begin the journey of egg donation with expectations of finding a highly educated, genius egg
387
donor with good SAT scores, with advanced degrees from a prestigious university—someone just like
you, […] a younger version of you with similar values and background” (par. 6). The theory of
imitation goes back to Aristotle who established a generally accepted theory of generation (human begets
human) and with it three highly influential beliefs regarding the inheritance: first, that women only
contribute by nurturing to their child while men contribute the material, second, that every seed’s
perfected result is a male child, while a female child is an imperfection, a “mutilated” male (2.3, 4.1),
and third, that children who resemble their mothers instead of their fathers, both in form as well as in
character, are an anomaly, especially some “resembling none of their relations, yet do at any rate
resemble a human being, but others are not even like a human being but a monstrosity” (4.3).
Departing from the type is a monstrosity for Aristotle as well as in the World State order. It is already
in Aristotle that the women’s part in creating generations is taken away, as they merely serve as a vessel
for creation performed by men: “The product of her labor is not hers” (Cline Horowicz 197). As we
have seen above with ART and other technologies used for reproductive care (ultrasound), all of
which are focused on women, women are again considered more as nurturers, renting their wombs
This long-existent discrepancy between the two sexes is also evident from Almeling’s study which
found that male donors are more likely to view themselves as fathers of the children produced from
their donation than female donors are to view themselves as such a child’s mother. (A similar finding is
reported by a therapist who works with infertile couples: male partners are “much more attached to
these ideas of ownership and [the child being] ‘mine,’ and much more tied to the genetic connection
in terms of what it means psychologically or what it means emotionally” (Fetters ‘The Overlooked’
par. 5)). Almeling suggests that fatherhood is “more often reduced to a cultural equation in which
sperm equals dad” while motherhood is more separable than fatherhood: one woman can give her egg,
388
the other the uterus, and the third can raise the child (69). In her conclusion, Almeling also sees our
beliefs as stemming from the Greeks’, where the father provided the generative seed and the mother
the nurturing soil. Although IVF and its related technologies have shaken these beliefs and are
revolutionizing our conceptions of family and kinship, the longstanding cultural understandings of
reproduction remain.
Reproduction has never been a private event since it is just as much a social act. Assisted
reproductive technologies brought novelty into this process by erasing intimacy from the act of
conception and including into conception the actual human labor: “[M]edically, legally and ethically
other parties will have a role in determining how and if a pregnancy is established,” altogether
“restricted by financial considerations or by scarcity of donated gametes” (Farsides 353). The two
people conceiving the child are not present during the conception which is handed over to
technicians: a clinic becomes a site of procreation and the clinicians the actors in conception. For
some, the other person is a donor (possibly a stranger), the inclusion of whom into one’s or a
couple’s procreation is never a light decision, as I show above. Further, the loss of privacy and
sexuality in relation to reproduction during the infertility evaluation and treatment is often
humiliating to couples (in the evaluation of fertility, the mere first step, consider finding out about
one’s infertility or subfertility and the timed and intrusive nature of post-coital tests) (see more in
Raphael-Leff 41, Fetters ‘The Overlooked’ par. 5). Last but not least, “[w]hat was once a private act
of love, intimacy, and secrecy is now a public act, a commercial transaction, and a professionally
Jodi Picoult’s novel, Sing You Home (2011), depicts how infertility struggles and pregnancy loss can
become unbearable for some partners. In a typical Picoult manner, the novel gathers a whole array
389
of issues that arise with infertility and the use of ART. After a painful breakup, a new dilemma
forms for Zoe and Max, the protagonist heterosexual couple: What to do with their frozen embryo?
Zoe enters a homosexual relationship and wishes to have her embryo implanted into her partner,
and Max moves in with his brother and sister-in-law who suffer from infertility and would gladly
accept Max’s embryo donation. The former couple takes the matter to the court. Although the court
decides otherwise, Zoe ultimately gets the embryo and raises a daughter in a three-parent family,
with her wife, who carried the child, and Max as the biological father and social parent. Most people
live in non-nuclear families today that include stepparents. In this view, a three-person baby, in
which the third ‘parent’ gives the mitochondrial DNA, or a baby grown from an adopted embryo
(i.e. created by two people and carried by a gestational surrogate or mother) should be less
controversial: at stake is the origin of genes but not the place and style of upbringing, education,
family dynamics, etc. But, as it turns out, for many, these stakes are (too) high.
6.4 Biases
In the section on biases, I will first look into different groups of people that are biased against in the
fertility practice, starting with women, infertile people, children conceived through ART, and ending
with LGBTQIA+ people. I hope to show how the intersection of these biases changes our
Feminist critics have written extensively on the topic of reproduction. Since the woman’s body is the
site of natural and assisted reproduction, all bioethical debates around birth control, abortion,
delivery practices, woman’s rights in pregnancy in relation to the fetus, and ART foremost affect
woman’s health and politics on women’s (and thus human) rights. As Heather Latimer concludes in
her examination of reproduction and sexual politics in North American fiction and film, “the fight
390
over women’s fertility is at the centre of discussions about humanity” (161) and “[a]s long as
battleground for the state’s interest in definitions of who or what is considered a person and a
citizen” (162). This is also the case for transgender and non-binary people. Ironically, women and
people who identify as LGBTQIA+ need to campaign for equal rights and their own personhood as
much as for reproductive rights, both of which can conflict with the fetal personhood.
The fertility industry inevitably exploits women by putting their health and lives at risk as much as it
helps them to have children—any kind of human reproduction so far has been based on this
paradox. ART tends to focus on treating women solely, even if women are not the cause or the only
cause of infertility and even if they are perfectly healthy themselves. This means that if a woman
does not suffer from infertility but her (male or female) partner does, the treatment as it is today will,
in a majority of cases, be conducted on the healthy patient. As Irma van der Ploeg points out (156),
women are often willing to undergo these treatments with a not-easily-achievable and sometimes
unrealizable goal of having a child for overcoming medical problems of their significant others, be it
their partner or their potential offspring (for example, in order to prevent some congenital
anomalies). Another consequence of this focus on women is that research on male infertility and
treatment options is so scarce. Male hormone therapy and varicose removal are rather underutilized
though “highly effective and widely available” (‘Nonsurgical’) in contrast to commonly used
intracytoplasmic sperm injection (ICSI), which can only be done during the IVF process. To sum
up, it is only the woman’s body that this advanced technology can improve and rarely cure, for now.
We can see this lack of interest for the male side of reproduction already in Brave New World, which
lists details about obtaining and growing eggs but gives no information on how the many sperm
samples, needed for the massive reproduction in Bokanovsky’s Process, are obtained and handled.
391
Although bearing less stigma than in the past, the diagnosis of infertility is still significantly
stigmatized, especially outside Western nations, with some people considering those who are
infertile, particularly women, as a “second-class person” (Ergin et al. 47). The condition is not always
curable, which results in involuntary childlessness23 (Lechner et al.), and the solutions to the
problems of infertility, such as paying for PGD, a donor or a surrogate, are often judged, especially
if these solutions are not the last resort for having one’s own progeny.24 Besides numerous medical
and social challenges that infertile people need to overcome, infertility is challenging not only for the
Ageism is a known bias regardless of the use of ART because fertility drastically decreases after one’s
mid-thirties. Clinics tend to discriminate against older patients because the success rate of these
patients is lower and might affect their overall success rates. Prenatal testing and procedures for
pregnant persons over 35 are more common. Moreover, the medical label for such pregnancies used
to be ‘geriatric pregnancy’ and was changed to ‘advanced maternal age.’ Due to the ethical
responsibility towards the future child, ART pregnancies after the maternal age of 42 tend to be
discouraged. However, since a small percentage of pregnancies was achieved even after the maternal
age of 45, some scholars argue that the decision whether a person should be allowed to undergo
fertility treatments should not be based on age alone (Gleicher et al.). Besides that, studies in embryo
mosaicism, which is believed to be more common in older patients, have shown that even an
24In children’s literature and folklore, a couple without children will inadvertently animate an object or meet an animated
object that will become their child: a ball jumps into their house through a window (as in Jan Malík’s puppet play), the
woman bakes cookies and one turns to be alive (as in Gingerbread Man), etc.
392
embryo with abnormal cells may develop into a healthy baby (Karow, Stephen Hall). These studies
gave older patients a chance of having a genetic child despite the mainstream practice that would
never transfer an embryo with abnormal cells. All embryos and people are mosaic to some level, but
we are wary of mosaicism as we do not know possible negative effects (e.g. cancer).
Another issue with ART and theory around it is that it has only recently started questioning the
products of this technology: the children created by its means. Before they were ever created, IVF-
conceived children were stigmatized, considered as nonhumans and scientific creatures and
monsters. In 1938, the British magazine Tit-Bits predicted that the test tube babies are only “a few
years” away in a report titled ‘Could You Love a Chemical Baby? For That’s What Science Looks
Like Producing Next.’ “Will these sexless, soulless creatures of chemistry conquer the true human
beings” (Burke 3), thus presenting them as oppressive to the desired development of society, like
Aldous Huxley’s, Olaf Stapledon’s, and many other dystopias (Duncan Wilson 51). In 1969, only
fifty percent of the Americans polled by LIFE magazine said they could feel love toward an IVF
baby conceived from their gametes and only a good fifty percent imagined that such child would
When Landrum Shettles attempted to create an IVF-conceived baby in 1973 and was halted by the
chief of obstetrics gynecology Vande Wiele, who destroyed the embryo, the consenting but poorly
informed parents-to-be, the Del Zio couple, filed a lawsuit against Dr. Wiele and the Columbia
Presbyterian Hospital for causing them severe physical and mental anguish. The lawyer of the
defendants argued: “These physicians […] had no way of knowing whether their efforts would
produce a ‘monster birth’ or a normal child” (‘2 Charge’ par. 8). Coincidentally, the Del Zio trial
took place while the world welcomed the first IVF-conceived baby, Louise Brown.
393
After the children were born, the prejudice was still going strong. When Louise Brown, or “the
superbabe” as Britain’s (at that time tabloid) newspaper the Evening News called her, was born on July
25, 1987, the image of her “tiny newborn body was overwhelming evidence that a revolution in
human biology was underway” (Hurlbut 39). Brown herself said: “Had there been anything at all
wrong with me, it would have been the end of IVF” (Nugent par. 6). As a child, Brown toured the
USA and Japan with her parents, who explained to her that she was “born a little bit different than
everybody else” (CBS 2:10). In Brown’s opinion, they did the tour so that the world could see that
she was a normal child (1:00-1:40). Nonetheless, she was teased by children at the playground and
sometimes even by adults, and asked if she is wholly human by comedians: “What would you do on
Father’s Day? Do you send a card to the Dupont [chemicals] Corporation?” (Ball 208).
When Natalie, Louise’s sister and the fortieth child in the world to be conceived via IVF, had her
first child, the newspapers avidly reported that her child was conceived naturally (‘First’). Natalie was
the world’s first IVF-conceived person to have her own child—and the world heaved a sigh of relief
to the news that the generation continues ‘naturally.’ When Gilles Deleuze writes in ‘Desert Islands’
of an animal “whose mode of reproduction remains unknown to us,” he labels it as a thing which
“has not yet taken a place among living beings” (13),25 because “it is not the production of life that
we look for when we judge it to be life, but its reproduction” (13). An IVF-conceived baby that
would grow up unable to reproduce without the technology that created him or her would likely be
25“Nous pouvons trouver en nous la source d’un tel thème : pour la juger nous attendons la vie non pas à sa production,
mais à sa reproduction. L’animal dont on ignore le mode de reproduction n’a pas encore pris place parmi les vivants”
(16).
394
Children created via donor offspring were also viewed negatively. Loren, one of the first babies in
Australia to be conceived through embryo donation, testifies: “It wasn’t until I was an adult that I
realised that some people perceived my existence as problematic or my mother as a lesser being”
(par. 8). A famous Italian gay couple, Domenico Dolce and Stefano Gabbana, expressed their desire
for children in 2005 when they were featured on the cover of Vanity Fair holding four prop babies,
yet in 2015 they attacked gay adoption and IVF in the Italian magazine Panorama, condemning
“chemical offspring and rented uterus” explaining that “life has a natural flow, there are things that
should not be changed”26 (Ward par. 3-4). Stefano Gabbana added that “family is not a fad. In it
there is a supernatural sense of belonging.” Domenico Dolce said procreation “must be an act of
love” and called IVF children “children of chemistry, synthetic children”27 as “uteri [should not be
for] rent, semen chosen from a catalog” (par. 5-7). After a backlash, most prominently by Elton
John, another gay star who had two children with his husband via surrogate, they later apologized. A
couple of years later, a Google search reveals the most common questions regarding IVF children
are full of prejudice and fear: “Do IVF babies look different? Are IVF children infertile? Can IVF
babies be delivered naturally? Is [sic] IVF babies are normal? Are IVF babies healthy adults?” and so
on. Some of these questions (such as, are IVF babies at higher risk for birth defects or low birth
26“Sono gay, non posso avere un figlio. Credo che non si possa avere tutto dalla vita, se non c’è vuol dire che non ci
deve essere. È anche bello privarsi di qualcosa. La vita ha un suo percorso naturale, ci sono cose che non vanno
modificate. E una di queste è la famiglia” (Marocco).
27 “O almeno dovrebbe essere così, per questo non mi convincono quelli che io chiamo i figli della chimica, i bambini
sintetici. Uteri in affitto, semi scelti da un catalogo. E poi vai a spiegare a questi bambini chi è la madre. Ma lei
accetterebbe di essere figlia della chimica? Procreare deve essere un atto d’amore, oggi neanche gli psichiatri sono pronti
ad affrontare gli effetti di queste sperimentazioni” (Marocco).
395
Such reactions are not unexpected, as already attested in the early speculations on what was then
called the test tube babies. Assisted reproductive technology is intrinsically linked to creating
humanlike entities because they mimic natural processes with a final goal of fulfilling (perfecting) the
imitated creation. That is to say, ART offers “a promise of delivering children who are ‘just like’
other offspring, but through a process of mimicry that is not quite the same as the original process
on which it is based” (Franklin Biological 34). The goal of robotics, AI and related disciplines is to re-
create and imitate the humanlike (e.g. make AI virtual assistant voices more humanlike), and the
collateral goal is to perfect the humanlike into the best possible human version or even better than
human (e.g. make carebots or AI psychotherapist more attune to human emotions than a human
could be). Similarly, the goal of ART is to treat infertility (into fertility to create humans), and the
collateral goal of ART is to select undesirable human traits (and thus eliminate the undesirable
traits). It is unethical to not treat a known and preventable condition, nonetheless, there are many
questionable cases (such as selecting deafness or against deafness (see Scott ‘Uses’)), many of which
are ethically related to the non-identity problem. Such twofold practice therefore subjects human
reproduction to the fascinating and daunting task of creating and designing the human. If the
creating part is considered an infertility treatment (restitutio ad integrum), the designing part is
Discrimination is ample at every step for people who identify themselves as LGBTQIA+ and
choose to have children by the means of ART. For example, although sperm banks now mostly
work with “lesbian couples and single mothers by choice, which now make up 80 percent of its
business” (Eber par. 7), homosexual couples still tell stories about how the physician thought the
partner of the patient was a friend of the family (Emre 27). Transgender, asexual and intersex people
are fewer in comparison and receive even less accommodation. The preservation of fertility is a
396
controversial topic in and outside the transgender community because one needs to make a decision
before transitioning or stop the transitioning for a few months to subject themselves to ART, often
before they are ready to think about having children. “It’s unrealistic to expect trans teenagers or
even young trans adults to know whether they want to have their own children. They are eager to
start transitioning, a momentous, all-consuming next step in their lives, meant to relieve what has
been a painful fact of life” (Spataro par. 10).28 Adoption brings up its own issues for people in this
community, which micha cárdenas sums up perfectly in her hybrid poetry/bioart project ‘Pregnancy’
Transgender identity permits the fathers to be mothers and the parents to be nonbinary. The parent
who fathers the child (gives sperm) could be a trans woman and thus a mother, as in the case of
cárdenas and Joanne Spataro. Joanne Spataro, a lesbian engaged to a trans woman, wrote in an op-ed
that the trans community focuses more on hormones and surgical procedures of transitioning, while
“fertility is almost taboo” (par. 9). Joanna and her fiancée, who transitioned four years ago, are able
to try “the way fertile cisgender people do: They simply couple up, and boom — a child is born”
28Only a third of trans teenagers considered having biological children in the future. 45 percent said they would prefer
to adopt, 22 percent stated they did not want to have children, 8 percent said the cost of fertility preservation is too high,
1 percent found masturbation to produce the sample too uncomfortable and 1 percent were unwilling to undergo
fertility preservation due to concern about potentially delaying hormone treatment (Nahata et al. 42). All of them might
change their mind.
397
(par. 2) just like privileged cis-hetero reproduction. Both heavily weaned of hormones, Joanna off
birth control pills and her fiancée off estrogen, they attempted to recreate a male-female
The process of imitating natural reproduction is even more challenging for cárdenas, as a trans
Latina woman, who writes: “They told me I would be sterile / the doctors and brochures, / that I
couldn’t do this, / what I’m doing / But they don’t know / and they lied to me / other trans women
/ have done it” (54). Aligning the “viciousness of the lie” with the “truth of the fatal violence that
disproportionately affect trans women of color” (Emre 28). cárdenas writes: “the feeling of urgency
of reproducing in the face of a world that wants me dead” (49). At the 2014 Civil Liberties and
Public Policy Conference, Morgan Robyn Collado stated that “violence against trans women of
color is a reproductive issue because they are prevented from living long enough to realize their
dreams of having children” (48). Suicide is another fear: “I take hormones every day of my life out
of necessity, / just to have a body I can live in, / to avoid death, / to survive, / both to avoid my
own suicidal ideations […] / And to avoid death at the hands of others” (54).
If anyone, a transitioning or transitioned trans woman is used to taking estrogen, which is also a
required part of IVF cycles. cárdenas realizes that “in these pills there is a home for me” as they
have “heal[ed] the deepest wounds” (45). To achieve a pregnancy, the unwelcome transformation is
required: “the hormonal chemistry I was born with bubbling up in my body / it feels so foreign”
(ib.). cárdenas does not have medical support of her “lying doctors” so her only resource to achieve
“a woman pregnant with life” are “other trans women” who “have done it:” “Sadie said, get a
microscope, / don’t pay hundreds of dollars for doctor visits to check your semen, / with a $50 kids
microscope, / you can see sperm, / morphology and motility” (55). In this poetry collection,
398
cárdenas sheds light on the many implicit biases working against queer and transgender people as
well as people of color—and against their access to reproduction and ART. The accessibility that
these communities often lack includes social normativity, physical and mental ability, financial
means, as well as support of the law and healthcare system, including biases of individuals working
In Pregnancy, Cárdenas links her journey to a genetically related child to a sex change because she
needs to transition back from a trans woman in order to produce viable sperm. Andrea Long Chu, a
queer theorist and also a trans woman, sees sex change as the closest change to a pregnancy:
“pregnancy is a form of body modification so extreme that its result is another person. In this, it
resembles nothing—except, perhaps, sex change” (68). In her description of an upcoming sex
change surgery (also called gender confirmation surgery) she seems to desire an easier and more
efficient way to achieve the transformation: “Later this year, I will pay another person a lot of
money to carve me into a different shape. She will probably do a good job, but it will be
disappointing anyway. What I want isn’t surgery; what I want is never to have needed surgery to
begin with. I will never be natural, but I will die trying” (67). Her desired sex will be human-made,
sculpted out of her body like Pygmalion’s desired woman is sculpted out of ivory.
The intersection of these biases reveals a common theme: the naturalness of reproduction is
repressed by every single deviation from the normative fertile human male-and-female reproduction.
donor over partner’s gametes in the cases where the partner could transfer a genetic disorder to the
child—is transgressive and needs bioethical (that is medical, societal, and moral) justification. The
artificiality in all these biases is of a human intervening into what is perceived to be in the domain of
399
nature. According to this view, natural reproduction is closer to a sacred act (for example, in
Christianity, the God controls conception and ‘knits’ the fetus in the womb (Psalm 139:13)).
This view of nature stems from the eighteenth century’s perception of nature which is considered a
metaphysical ontological realm rather than the domain of scientific knowledge and engineering.
The attitude towards these biases in ART has improved, however. Nowadays fertility clinics feature
a list of fictional and non-fictional books on the topic of infertility and raising and educating
children who resulted from ART. Many children’s literature and young adult fiction books are
available on the topic, particularly for the children of donors. This literature unanimously encourages
the parents to share (k)information about their children’s origins with their children. Margaret K.
Nelson surveys young adult fiction which features donor children and concludes that as opposed to
texts focusing on adoption, which is often depicted as “a shameful secret, a problem to be solved, or
a legally suspect event” (Parsons et al. 70 in Nelson 52), 30 texts from her analysis present donor
conception as normalized: “That is, being donor-conceived does not dictate the plot in the majority
of these books” (52). The purpose of writing about donor conception in young adult fiction is both
to familiarize and normalize this way of conception among donor-conceived children and their peers
(Nelson 38), while the purpose of children’s literature on ART is to help parents disclose to their
children how they came to be and to equip them with age-appropriate language to explain the
science or the struggle behind it. Literature for very young children is especially rich in presenting
varieties of ART trajectories from an emotional and technical angle. Many of these books are part of
a series, each with a different scenario. For example, Our Story: How We Became a Family, The Pea That
Was Me, You Were Made For Me, and Happy Together all present variants of how ART structures of
families come to be: heterosexual couples using IVF, solo mothers through donor intrauterine
insemination, two fathers through a gestational surrogate, etc. Children’s literature, adjusted to the
400
understanding of the topic by age range, tends to use symbolism (e.g. You Were Made For Me by Sheri
Sturniolo and Hannah Pak explains making babies with making puzzles) and sometimes also animal
symbolism (rabbit, bear or elephant couples struggling to conceive, and “the very kind koala” as a
surrogate for a human couple in The Pea That Was Me) or plant metaphors (embryo as a pea,
surrogacy as being “grown in another garden”). Surprisingly, authors rarely take advantage of the
many folkloristic or other known children’s stories where a childless couple often gets an
unconventional child (such as a ball in Mlíček Flíček [tran. as Roly Poly] by Jan Malík) in an
unconventional way (the ball jumps through the window of an elderly couple when they wish for a
child, a gingerbread man is baked by a childless old woman). Some books focus on the struggle and
challenges that couples undergo, for example, in The Extra Button by Jules Blundell the couple needs
to go through an inhospitable forest and meet frightening animals. Grown in Another Garden by
Crystal Falk labels the infertile woman as “broken,” and You Were Made For Me presents the infertile
couple unsuccessful in finishing a puzzle. Since they “just couldn’t make the puzzles fit right,” they
asked “wonderful, giving people […] who happen to have just the pieces you need” for “the most
precious pieces made with love and with care,” goes the text alongside an illustration with people
passing each other puzzle pieces and DNA depicted in a double helix. Other books focus on the
technical side of the ART process and some also include a religious explanation. For example, Hope
and Will Have a Baby by Irene Celcer and Horatio Gatto describes the child as a gift from God. All
books emphasize how much the baby was wanted, often using the concept of a miracle and the
rather recent term rainbow baby (a baby born after a previous miscarriage, still birth, or death of an
infant). With an exception of My Story by the Donor Conception Network that was first published in
late 1980s, these books are all written after 2000 and received a special library label, e.g. “children of
401
With CRISPR-modified IVF-conceived babies we are yet to learn about possible reproductive quirks
caused by in-vitro genome editing. So far, only Chinese twins dubbed Nana and Lulu are known to
be conceived and modified with the help of these technologies; the public learned the twins are
healthy and that some of their brains were likely altered (inadvertently enhanced cognition and
memory) in the gene editing process (Regalado ‘China’s’). The most current paper (still under peer
review) on germline editing shows that it might be too dangerous to practice genome modification
on human embryos any time soon as the on-target effects, i.e. inadvertent deletions or additions to
the DNA, can be many and serious (Alanis-Lobato et al.). U. S. National Academies, U. K. Royal
Society, and the World Health Organization are currently working on establishing international
standards for germline genome editing. These organizations have no enforcement power, however;
Producing ideal children is one of the tasks in forming utopias. In other words, utopians are true
designer babies. Utopias are exclusive gated communities, keeping humanity as we know it excluded
from their world (like ‘savages’ kept in Reservations in Brave New World) or transforming native
‘savages’ into ideal citizens (like Abraxans in Thomas More’s Utopia).30 The transformation of regular
humans into utopian superhumans is most commonly achieved through creating new generations of
30 “But they report (and there remain good marks of it to make it credible) that this was no island at first, but a part of
the continent. Utopus that conquered it (whose name it still carries, for Abraxa was its first name) brought the rude and
uncivilized inhabitants into such a good government, and to that measure of politeness, that they now far excel all the
rest of mankind; having soon subdued them, he designed to separate them from the continent, and to bring the sea quite
round them. To accomplish this, he ordered a deep channel to be dug fifteen miles long; and that the natives might not
think he treated them like slaves, he not only forced the inhabitants, but also his own soldiers, to labor in carrying it on.
As he set a vast number of men to work, he beyond all men's expectations brought it to a speedy conclusion. And his
neighbors who at first laughed at the folly of the undertaking, no sooner saw it brought to perfection than they were
struck with admiration and terror” (50).
402
citizens whose formation could be supervised since their very beginnings with the ideological and
literal conception.
Even if not all utopias establish technologized or eugenicized reproduction, they begin with the
abolition of the family already in the earliest approximation of a utopia, Plato’s The Republic (380
BC)31 (see more in Carley xvi). Social and biological kinship is overridden in The Republic by the
children’s kinship to the state: in Plato’s ideal polis any child-parent bonding is discouraged since
children are required to be given to the state, allowing the state to mold them into model citizens.
Effectively, the ideal polis laws require that “the children shall be common, and that no parent shall
know its own offspring nor any child his parents” (457d)—the children are thus common. Thomas
More built on Plato’s view in his Utopia (1516): children live together with parents, but their bonding
is discouraged because the children, if the original family grows too large, might be sent to live with
a less prolific family. The state is responsible for population balance in utopias, including Brave New
World.
As a result of scientific revolution, utopias tend to turn their task to regulate reproduction into a
matter of science and technology. Feminist utopias, like Charlotte Gilman’s Herland (1915) and
James Tiptree Jr.’s Houston, Houston, Do You Read? (1976), allow for parthenogenesis and cloning in
order to reduce or eliminate women’s reproductive labor. In science fiction, such as Sophie Wenzel
Ellis’s ‘Creatures of the Light’ and Lilith Lorraine’s ‘Into the 28th Century,’ reproduction is fabricated
as partly natural and partly technological. Genetic (eugenic) technologies are also a popular choice,
for example, in Samuel Butler’s Erewhon; or, Over the Range (1872), H. G. Wells’s The Island of Dr
31 Plato’s The Republic realized in the pseudo-historic embodiment of the island of Atlantis.
403
Moreau (1896), Francis Galton’s Kantsaywhere (1910), and Andrew Niccol’s Gattaca (1997). Besides
Butler, Wells and Galton, a number of other prominent socialists, such as G. B. Shaw and Havelock
Ellis, advocated eugenics as a tool of social engineering. As a matter of fact, eugenics was
mainstream science until the infamous Nazi practices in Europe and forced sterilizations of
‘undesirable’ citizens in USA were publicly condemned. As in Brave New World, many newer utopias
try to eliminate sexual reproduction in favor of scientifically perfected procreation. Utopias outside
of the science fiction genre tend to establish natural reproduction by connecting men and women
through a state-led scheduled intercourse, such as in Yevgeny Zamyatin’s We (My) (1924), Margaret
Atwood’s The Handmaid’s Tale (1985), and Berta Bojetu’s Filio Is Not at Home (Filio ni doma) (1990).
Genetic kinship is weak in each of these works as it is subordinate to a new dystopian social order.
In Brave New World, there is but one known nuclear genetic family in which the child was conceived
through sexual intercourse and born (not decanted), as still practiced in the Savage Reservation.
Linda and, ironically, the Director of the Hatchery himself conceived John on their retreat to the
Savage Reservation in New Mexico. For the Director, who has no idea he fathered a child, such
paternity is considered obnoxious per social convictions of the World State. When John confronts
him, calling him by the obscene word “father” (140), the Director is utterly shocked (as is everyone
else witnessing the event) and runs away in embarrassment. Not unlike some sperm donors, the
Director does not want to be contacted by his offspring and does not consider himself a father of
this child. The institution of a family is abolished and judged upon in the World State and likely
unimaginable to him. In addition to that, the Director cannot be certain that the child is genetically
his. He can either trust John and Linda’s words or turn to a DNA test or genetic finger printing.
Such genetic proof would likely not change anything in a state where any kind of kinship is ignored
and considered perverse. Linda, on the other hand, acknowledges her kinship to John who she
404
birthed and mothered in a Reservation where social and genetic kinship still play a role. She can also
be sure about being John’s mother as the umbilical cord between them was cut only after his birth.
The world of ART challenges traditional views on kinship with new arrangements, imaginable only
through ART. (Genetic) kinship used to be predominantly built on hierarchical order of lineage of
consanguinity (blood ties) or affinity (marriage ties),32 the rules of which are now subjected to ART
regulations and often blurred. For mothers that underwent IVF, the umbilical cord is not a proof of
genetic connection with their child—although one could argue that genetic kinship is established
also through gestation or nursing through the mixing of bodily materials. The embryo could get
mixed up in the laboratory, which can leave all parties clueless about the lack of genetic connection.
In more than one case of such mix up, the already-born babies were identified to be of a different
race than the birth parents and the court returned them to their genetic parents (Zhang ‘IVF’ par. 5,
8); the settlements of cases where the children already bonded with the families that raised them are
In third-party reproduction, random families with half-siblings (sometimes called diblings) are
genetically related through a donor they have likely never met. Families with the same donor can
find each other through this information and some consider themselves a family. The three-person
baby is another such biological kinship where the third person is usually only a donor but not a
parent, even though the more common term is three-parent baby. Biological kinships get quite complex
with the use of ART: an embryo might get adopted for the adoptive mother to carry the pregnancy
or for the surrogate to carry the pregnancy for the adoptive mother. In the latter case, the child
would have a genetic mother (embryo donor), a birth mother (surrogate), and a social mother (the
32 These are the so-called true kinships as opposed to fictive kinships, which represent chosen kinship ties.
405
one who would effectively and legally mother the child), as well as a genetic father (donor) and a
social father (the effective and legal father). Adoption is one of the traditional roles in kinship that
comes closest to such arrangements, which are nonetheless unique and far more literal in ART.
Not all of these kinship relations are entirely new, but they do take a new form through ART. IVF
and artificial insemination made virgin birth possible in a literal sense. In Christianity, virgin birth
designates another reproductive transgression: God the father is not human. “The foundling
mythology of Christianity, like that of Rome, involves a god’s abandoning the child that he generates
by a virgin: God and Mary parented Jesus who was raised by another father (Joseph) just as Mars
and the Vestal parented Romulus and Remus, who were raised by another mother (the she-wolf)”
(Shell Children 139). Jesus, like embryos today, was “interpreted as not only a miracle child, born to
the extraordinarily virginal Mary, but also as an ordinary bastard” (ib.). (I will look more closely into
When called a bastard (plastos, primarily meaning counterfeit), Oedipus hurries to the oracle to learn
the truth he then refuses to recognize, believing too strongly and literally in kinship as it presents
itself, i.e. that his adoptive parents are his biological parents. He also beliefs he transcended his
natural conditions (of birth) and physical limitations (his limp body) with his mind when he becomes
a king of Thebes. Ironically, in aristocracy birth and blood lines matter much more than one’s
abilities—or luck (tychē). He believes himself to be a self-made, foreign king (tyrannus) of Thebes and
does not ever consider himself a born, native king (basileus). With his unnatural reproduction he
unwittingly violates the laws of the state (polis) and the household (oikos), which results in the
transformation of Thebes into a tyranny. A plague renders infertile all forms of life (crops, livestock,
humans) in his state while his own household is involved into a socially perverse human production,
406
as attested in the name of his daughter-sister Antigone (anti-gonē: against generation). Oedipus
believes that his life is ruled by chance (tychē) and not fate conducted by gods. Reproduction as the
technology (techné) of the gods is skewed by Oedipus who, per Geoffrey Hartman, makes it
“redundant […] in replacing his own progenitor”: “By killing his father and marrying his mother he
has destroyed the triad of father, mother and son. He is not a third one over and beyond his origins,
but is at one with them” (Shell The Economy 98). For a similar reason of unknown biological origins,
2500 years after Sophocles’s Oedipus The King, sperm banks developed a need to regulate that certain
donors do not over-reproduce and a need to share with the donor-created progeny information of
their biological relatives outside their family in order to prevent potential couplings among siblings or
children and their biological parents. At the same time, ART also allows for destruction of generational
for example, in the case where a mother carries her daughter’s genetic child as a surrogate. And then
there is synthetic biology which allows us to propagate living organisms without any generation: when
biological systems are disposable, reproduction is irrelevant and generation is untraceable. If one really
wanted to have something like generation and evolution in printing the genome of their offspring, they
would introduce an element of chance into synthetic design—like Oedipus we like to believe that our
Modern genetics has been a focus of science and the public for the last hundred years, and
increasingly due to ART. ART knits strangers together into closer biological relations while enabling
no-contact reproduction and allows for what used to be impossible, for example, for two men to
have a child. Their child could be genetically related to both of his male parents: with sperm
donation and a relative who serves as a gestational surrogate, one man becomes a social and
biological father and the other genetically an uncle but socially also a father. ART therefore leaves
407
space for other ways of forming familial connections: “Which of the following is fundamental—the
genes I share with my genitor, the love between my adoptive parent and myself, the milk I sucked
from my mother, the blood I commingled with my blood brother, the wafer and wine I shared at a
communal feast, or the dust from which all things (including myself) are made?” (Shell Children 4).
Genetic and biological kinships are reified and valued in ART, as attested, for example, in adopted
and donor children’s desire to search for their roots, i.e. biological parents or siblings they have not
yet met. However, genetic kinship does not automatically prevail over parental love or over religious
beliefs (such as cult-like Christian communities that expel any outcasts: the universal siblinghood
between the members of the community prevails over genetic connection). Some researchers claim
that we live in an era that tries to discard hyper-individualism and the nuclear family model of the
second half of the twentieth century by setting family structures through created kinship, most often
through an extended chosen family, sometimes also called forged family or fictive kinship (Brooks).
Queer people and other marginalized groups often build so-called chosen families. Sophie Lewis
returned to the 1970s feminist call33 for the abolition of the family in her 2019 monograph Full
Surrogacy Now, where she argues that we should establish new radical kinships where everyone takes
care of everyone. Everyone is a mother and a child at the same time: every child is raised in a village
and the elderly are taken care of according to their needs. In Lewis’s utopian and anti-capitalist
arrangement, genetics and biology are completely irrelevant as a part of changing family relations
into the Harawayan kin. Ignoring the embodiment of pregnancy and birth accentuates the
33Among radical feminists, Shulamith Firestone is credited with the idea of family abolition in her 1970 manifesto The
Dialectic of Sex, where she identifies biological family as the basis of women’s oppression because it forces women to bear
the brunt of reproductive labor. The idea had been popular for about a decade, with feminism largely embracing family
values afterwards and leaning towards reforming the nuclear family structure rather than abolishing it—which is also a
preferred solution in most of the fictional texts mentioned above.
408
involuntariness of the experiences, especially if related with a gender transition, and “makes ideas of
compensation and reproductive exchange poor solutions for the potential disruption to the self”
Regardless, couples who use ART with a third-party donation tend to use the same donor for their
children (Keshavan par. 15-25, Goddard par. 12), supposedly because they like the donor and/or
they like the idea that their children will be genetically related. This means they often need to
continue to pay storage fees for the gametes donated for their first child for when/if they decide to
have another child. Although described as a mere commodity in many cases,34 couples enter into a
special kind of kinship with their donor (or, similarly, surrogate). Caitlin comments: “I don’t think
about the donor very much anymore, but there are tiny moments where I’m like, that’s my wife, and
maybe that’s the guys, and maybe that’s me” (Goddard par. 11). In a lesbian couple, one partner can
carry the embryo created by the other partner and sperm donor, making both parents biologically
related to their child: one being the genetic parent, the other being the birth parent (and thus also
mixing their genes and bodily fluids with their progeny). The embryo enriched definitions of genetic
Defining kinship in ART where multiple parties are involved through donation, adoption, or
surrogacy begins with the embryo and resolves with the child being placed into a family. For Sarah
Franklin, the embryo yields “liminal kinship” not only to specific family relations but to human
family as a whole, as a human species: we all were once embryos (‘Postmodern’ 336). This reinforces
the idea that all of humanity is our family—that we are of the same kind and kin. In biologist Michael
Caitlin writes: “Some of these guys have a lot in stock. The bank can email you if it’s selling out, in case you want
34
409
Ghiselin’s view, biological species are not “kinds, or classes, or organisms” but “wholes composed
of organisms” (448). He argues that a species is an abstract class (like a planet) while Homo sapiens
should be viewed as an individual with a history and location (like Jupiter). In this way, like David
Hull proposes, “there are no laws of nature for particular species” (449). Ghiselin further argues for
his view of a particular species as an individual because “organism in the abstract cannot
reproduce—only an individual organism can do that” (ib.). Charles Darwin thought of the
reproduction of species the same way: in his theory, the species evolves as an individuum and
reproduces as one body, composed of many organisms. Darwin also warns about the term species
misleading us to think of a species as a stable entity where there is, in fact, steady change. In seeing a
particular species as one, we are all related, all of the same kin and kind, which implies that sharing
gametes through asexual reproduction is only a cunning way of mixing and improving our genetic
6.6 Hybridity
410
Hybridity is found in nature but considered extremely unnatural. For example, female horses and
male donkeys can produce a mule. Only rare species can interbreed, and the sterility of their progeny
is considered a sign of insuperability. Another, less known example is that of twin embryos merging
into a single entity. Some humans are born with their never-developed twin in their bodies (even
fraternal twins might have up to eight percent of cells from their twin (Robson par. 12)). Some
animals within certain species (with less complex sex determination, such as chickens, lobsters,
cardinals, moths, etc.) are born with one side of the body as male and the other as female, joined
down the center into the so-called bilateral gynandromorphic entity. Such animals might seem as an
entirely unnatural phenomenon: even among their own species these animals are ignored and
unlikely to find a mate (the cardinal of this kind never tried to sing (Robson par. 18)). Biological
hybridity has a long history in reproduction: one in which it is considered a boundary of biological
difference, as in the case of mules, and the other, familiar from lab experiments, where new
An example for the latter hybridity is cell fusion, a cellular process of recombination of cultured cells
that takes place during embryogenesis or morphogenesis, for example. Cell fusion was mobilized as
a way to forgo sexual breeding: “it was often described as ‘parasexuality’ or ‘genetics without sex’”
(Landecker 184). (Parasexuality is also a common designation for pygmalionism, as shown in chapter
3.) This parasexual approach— “going to the same end by different means” (217)—resulted in a
surprise: anything could be crossed with anything else. Lewis Thomas commented in 1980 that “the
‘laboratory trick’ of cell fusion seemed to reconfigure ideas and practices of the individuality of living
things to an extraordinary degree” and mused that, “in a way, it is the most unbiologic of all
phenomena, violating the most fundamental myths of the last century, for it denies the importance
of specificity, integrity, and separateness in living things” (183-84). The use of the term ‘unbiologic’
411
implies that biologically cell fusion does not make sense—that it is somehow unnatural, artificial, an
exception to the natural order or rules of logic. Cell fusion is not unbiologic per se but demands a re-
In a reproductive sense, cell fusion opened an option of asexual approach for higher-level
organisms; as Guido Pontecorvo wrote in 1962: “If fungi could have both sexual and parasexual
systems, so could higher organisms” (81; also in Landecker 188). “Barriers of species, immunological
incompatibilities between individuals—in fact, any form of biological difference that could be
thought of—fell away” (Landecker 218). Cell fusion has fundamentally shifted our views of
hybridity as it has shown there are no “intracellular mechanisms for recognizing incompatibility
between individuals or species” (184). Biological difference thus exists only at the higher levels of
organisms, where boundaries of species integrity and organismal individuality are signaled through
infertility and immune reactions. At the level of cell fusion, a hybrid cell could be made that could
This internal homology of organisms enables experimentation with human-derived tissues carried in
animals and vice versa: a promising venue for medicine. Fiction and science have long played with
this concept. For example, Michael Crichton35 imagined the revival of the dinosaur species in his
1990 novel Jurassic Park (also turned into a successful blockbuster film). Thirty years later, famed
geneticist George Church and the Broad Institute are working on bioconservation to bring back the
35Michel Crichton also created a 1973 film Westworld which was an inspiration for the Westworld series (2016–), where
sentient and conscious humanoid robots serve for fun and terrible exploitation in a Western-themed amusement park.
We might have such parks one day—we already have such humanoids in shopping malls to give us directions or, frankly,
for admiration and to satisfy our curiosity about these new creatures.
412
woolly mammoth through interspecific pregnancy (also called interspecies pregnancy or
xenopregnancy) performed by their relatives, Asian elephants (‘Progress’, Nicholls). The idea of an
interspecific pregnancy for the purpose of recreating an extinct species is not that unusual
considering that it was recently shown that different species of elephants have interbred in the past
(Palkopoulou et al.) and that some animal species can grow in a different species animal somewhat
successfully (e.g. giant panda embryos with rabbit ooplasm were gestated by a domestic cat (Chen et
al.)). Interspecific pregnancies run into many immunological and genetic barriers, even with related
species, such as domestic goat and sheep (Fernández-Arias et al.). Although at a cellular level such
hybridity works as any other mixing, the biological damage of interbreeding is high: unsuccessful
implantation, miscarriage, genetic defects, etc. Knotty concerns keep emerging: growing organs or
fetuses of one species in another species might actually influence the gestating animal’s behavior or
abilities through residual cells of the organ or fetus. Crossing these boundaries with a human mind
trapped in animal’s body is a nightmare fit for H. G. Wells, Franz Kafka, and Mikhail Bulgakov.
Although cell fusion as a hybrid method fell out of favor in labs due to the view that modern
genetics and molecular biology are drivers of change in the twentieth century, its exploration during
1960s pointed out “the notion of the reversibility of biological states [which] has become central to
the idea of ‘reprograming’ cells with cloning and stem cells in the first decade of the twenty-first
century” (183). With the invention of this new approach to hybridity, the human-induced artificiality
manifested in biology as an array of options that have previously not yet been imagined, except in
A year before Doctor Moreau was published, H. G. Wells worked as a biology instructor and wrote a
short newspaper piece called ‘The Limits of Individual Plasticity.’ In a very Dr. Moreau manner,
413
Wells criticized the prevailing fatalism of hereditary thinking and speculated about organismal
plasticity—similar to what was later discovered with the above-mentioned cell fusion. In words he
later placed in mouth of Dr. Moreau, he pointed out “that there is in science, and perhaps even
more so in history, some sanction for the belief that a living thing might be taken in hand and so
moulded and modified that at best it would retain scarcely anything of its inherent form and
disposition” and that “the thread of life might be preserved unimpaired while shape and mental
super-structure were so extensively recast as even to justify our regarding the result as a new variety
of being” (90). And just like cell fusion has shown that on a cellular level, where everything goes
with everything, Wells argued that “these principles […] have never been shown conclusively to be
In this short essay as well as in the novel, Wells poses questions to the limits of plasticity: How far
can humans push biological materials before “the thread of life” is broken? The Island of Dr. Moreau
ends with human-animal chimeras quickly reverting to their inherent animal form and behavior. He
further addresses the basic question of what is today known as synthetic biology: does the origin of a
human-made organism make any difference in regard to a naturally occurring organism? (Landecker
8). His answer seems to lie in-between: the nature of life is set in advance but can also be reversed
The outline of the idea of plasticity is sketched already in Charles Darwin’s The Descent of Man (1871),
of which alarming extensions present the human as “not fixed, but entirely mutable” and evolution
without a sense of purpose or direction (Luckhurst xx). In the conclusion to his On the Origin of the
Species (1859), Darwin already tries to hold back this vision, suggesting that evolution might work
414
towards perfecting the species36 and that this progressive development applies to humans in particular.
As Wells’s novel reminds us, the qualities of plasticity bring new puzzles to the table: the material
living things can be vastly manipulated but biological matter can also react in unexpected ways (as
we see today, for example, in gene editing that can produce off-target effects we may not be aware
Chimeras are regularly created in laboratories but generally prohibited in the clinical practice.
Already in laboratories ethical concerns abound. When, for example, structures of human origin are
inserted into the brains or reproductive systems37 of nonhuman animals, “the chief worry seems to
be that in the process of biologically humanizing a research animal, scientists might inadvertently
morally humanize the resulting chimera” (Munsie et al. 944). Even when chimerism is not on the
table, the use of stem cells and embryotic cells in laboratories causes fear. For example, embryonic
stem cells can grow into embryo-like structures called gastruloids. The moral question poses itself:
We have recently learned that fetuses are more biologically intertwined with their carriers than
previously thought. Research has shown that pregnant persons may carry genetic material of the
children they gestated for years, sometimes decades, after the birth (Rijnink et al.).38 Some of the
36“And as natural selection works solely by and for the good of each being, all corporeal and mental endowments will
tend to progress towards perfection” (Darwin On 165).
37“Making hybrid cells may sound like transgenesis, which is the use of recombinant DNA techniques to cross species
boundaries without sexual reproduction. Transgenis animals are made by inserting a foreign gene into an egg, and
thereby into the germline of the resulting organism; the adult animal then carries the gene in all of its cells and passes it
on to the next generation” (Landecker 182).
38This microchimerism is most obvious with women who carried male fetuses as their Y chromosomes were found all
over their bodies.
415
children’s cells were not only found in mother’s abdomen but also in her brain. A pregnant person’s
body is a chimera in itself, but it has not been known until recently that women who have given
birth remain microchimeras for some time, sometimes decades, after birth. Women with an x
number of children are therefore chimeras of x+1 organisms. This is a particularly fascinating
finding for gestational surrogates and persons pregnant with donor eggs, i.e. anyone who has carried
children that are not genetically related to them—as this turned out to not be entirely the case.
The case for reproductive chimerism is often made in science fiction and children’s literature works.
In Dr. Seuss’s 1940 children’s picture book Horton Hatches the Egg, the chimera is not the parent, as
with women described above, but the interspecies child. A lazy and irresponsible bird Mayzie leaves
her egg in care of a loyal elephant Horton who sits on it during her break that turns into a
permanent vacation. After a long wait, the egg hatches at the moment the elephant and the bird
meet again, and the bird argues that the egg is rightfully hers. Her argument is lost, however, as soon
as an elephant-chick emerges from the egg. Horton’s dutiful surrogate gestation made the gestating
chick grow elephant ears, a tail, and a trunk: “And it should be, it should be, it SHOULD be like that!
/ Because Horton was faithful! He sat and he sat!” concludes the narrator. Interspecies reproduction
is also the topic of the following three science fiction texts I discuss in the following section.
6.6.1.1. On Microbes
are more aware of social and biological collectiveness of the human existence. For example, that our
416
biological bodies—and every other organism—co-exist with bacteria, fungi, archaea, and viruses in
what Haraway calls “multispecies flourishing” (Staying 2, 120, etc.), Anna Tsing “interspecies
entanglements” (vii, 137-142, etc.), and Rosi Braidotti “a colossal hybridization of the species […]
consolidated by pervasive technological mediation” (26). We are thus cross-species bodily forms
living among other multi-species assemblages in an equally microbial habitat and a species that
technologized itself into techno-biological cyborgs—and might do so as well with other species or
We cannot exist nor function without the microbes, and we would have never evolved without them
either. Learning that eight percent of human genetic makeup is of viral origin or that a level of
serotonin, the ‘happiness hormone’ which affects how we feel and think, depends on
neurotransmitters produced by our gut bacteria (rather than genetics, for example), should make us
reevaluate how we perceive posthuman bodies. Since microbes make for a large percentage of our
body’s cells and are an important part of our physiology, does that mean that being human includes
a multitude of agencies that operate simultaneously on levels as diverse as microbiome and glands?
In this sense, the exodus of anthropocentrism is solely a shift in perspective from the human as the
center to the nonhuman, including nonhuman entities and agencies existing in the human body.
Looking at nature from the perspective of the microbiome reveals our interconnectedness with the
biosphere. Viruses are dangerous but indispensable agents of evolution. They move DNA between
species, provide new genetic material for evolution, and regulate vast populations of organisms. As
Wai Chee Dimock argues in her new book, Weak Planet, we should not perceive them as
pathological but rather symbiotic to us humans, despite the risk of this symbiosis (quite a bold but
necessary calling, as it turned out, in the midst of the COVID-19 pandemic.) Scientists are finding
417
viruses in the soil, the ocean and even deep caves, as they can infect all types of life forms. Tobias
Rees’s essay strikes a similar note: it is striking that “the evolution of life seems to have emerged
Viruses also challenge other biological categories, such as categorizing basic life forms. Biologically,
they are not alive in the same sense as animals: their life depends on a living host cell of an organism
(animals, plants, microorganisms, including bacteria and archaea) which they infect and where they
replicate. As such, they cannot die and could be considered immortal. As organisms at the edge of
life, viruses are considered a life form by some biologists because they carry genetic material,
reproduce, and evolve through natural selection, even if they lack some other basic criteria for life
(e.g. cell structure). They must, however, invade some other organism in order to live and reproduce:
crossing the species in order to live and breed is a prerogative of their existence.
Evaluating the human from the microbial perspective is fairly new to science but—again—not to
literature. In 1905, Mark Twain began writing a novel he never finished titled Three Thousand Years
among the Microbes. The fragment states that it was translated by Twain from the Original Microbic
language. Inspired by scientific monographs on microbes, especially H. W. Conn’s The Story of Germ
Life, Twain turns the narrator, one of Conn’s students named Huck (on a bizarre version twist on
Twain’s earlier and more famous novel The Adventures of Huckleberry Finn), into a cholera bacterium
named Bkhsp which lives in a body of a Hungarian immigrant. Huck retains human consciousness
while simultaneously experiencing the world as a microbe. Through this hybrid narratological
experiment (not unlike that in Cortázar’s ‘Axolotl’), Twain is able to reevaluate the human through a
nonhuman perspective in a way yet inaccessible to science. By pointing out the similarities of the
two species that live is such a different world frame, Twain defamiliarizes the human, which is
418
exactly the opposite of how scientists of the time framed the relationship between the human and
microbes. “Conn recuperates human significance by framing the microbe and its value in human
terms,” designating pathological and “friend[ly]” germs in terms of human mastery over the world
(Weed 221), and Twain satirizes this view, making the human an insignificant, microscopic player
“concealed in the blood of some vast creature’s veins” (Twain 24). In their introduction to Carl
Zimmer’s A Planet of Viruses (2011), Judy Diamond and Charles Wood point out that viruses should
not be viewed only as pathological because they are valuable as “dynamic players in the ecology of
Earth” (xi). This is also the argument Twain made on the case of bacteria more than hundred years
earlier, when viruses had only begun to be discovered (the yellow fever virus, one of which is also a
character in Twain’s text, among them). This microbial perspective is also an original position from
which microbiology, especially when intertwined with ecology and its nonhuman agencies in the
As our technologies have become biologized and, vice versa, biology has become technologized
(Franklin Biological 3), we use viruses as a tool of agency in CRISPR-Cas9, TALEN and ZNF
genome editing technologies, some of which have been used as a part of IVF. CRISPR is a
technology derived from bacterial DNA and works in humans because we are, like all living beings,
descendants of bacteria. Humans have thus repurposed a completely natural technology, invented by
bacterial and archaeal immune systems to fight off viruses. Another example of biologized
technology is the creation of induced pluripotent stem cells, for which “viruses are used to transport
the required genes, and the genes, or factors, themselves become tools in the process of forcing a
cell to reorganize itself” (ib.). In relation to new biologized technologies, Jean Baudrillard concludes
that “we must ask if this final solution toward which we unconsciously work is not the secret
419
The framing of technology as juxtaposed to nature, posited in Enlightenment, does not hold up
when faced with the concepts of hybridity, cyborgs, and interconnectivity. Hobbes’s uncivilized
nature became a realm of nonhuman animals perceived to be without any reason and thus separate
from the human animal; whereas the human is in the realm of politics, a genuine human state of law
and order which is an artifice and anti-nature. The pre-Enlightenment concept of technology as
contingent on nature cannot encompass today’s technologies either: in this view, nature and humans
are both a common part of the cosmos. The ontology of modernity clearly distinguishes between
natural, human, and technological; yet, the nineteenth-century view of technology as an imitation of
nature has quickly proved inadequate. Even if we agree that ART processes imitate nature, synthetic
biology does not fit the simple imitation of nature; and although AI was conceived as an imitation of
human intellect, it has since also forged into directions that are clearly not pursuing our imitation. It
was already with Darwin’s theory of evolution that these views on technology were shaken up: if we
approach nature in terms of evolution, then innovation is just as much a work of nature as it is a
human contribution. In fact, some biotechnologies that we use today were invented by microbes:
antibiotics, plasmids, CRISPR-Cas9 (Rees par. 64). A microbial view of nature brings the nature
from the realm of nonhuman, as ontologically and politically separated from the human in the
Enlightenment, back to the human: viruses are an essential part of us and also an essential part of
animals, bacteria, and other living beings. In the light of this view our differences diminish.39
39 It is not unusual that science cannot always determine if a virus such as SARS-CoV-2 was a natural occurrence or, as
conspiracy theorists would like to believe, human-made in a lab (which is not impossible since many labs create new
types of coronaviruses). The 1977 pandemic H1N1 strain, for example, was likely “a laboratory accident, a live-vaccine
trial escape, or deliberate release as a biological weapon” (Rozo and Gronvall). If it is so difficult—and close to
impossible in some cases—to draw the line of origin of a pandemic virus, then we must adjust the definition and outline
of technology into nature and biology as technological inventors, which are always evolving together with their creations.
Clearly, this perspective is useless for categorization of natural vs. human creating and editing, which is ontologically
necessary even if the origins might remain unknown sometimes.
420
Categorizing different types of technologies, however, has lost its purpose: We are no less cyborgs
had we been edited or created through a biological technology than through a computational or
some other visibly inorganic technology. Consider neuro implants, typically electrodes surgically
implanted under the skull, which are both a computational and biological technology at once and are
studied in the field of brain-computer interfaces, i.e. the field that connects neural systems and
computers chips. Biotechnologists and programmers who work together on creating individualized
gene drugs for patients with rare genetic defects talk about inscription—“genetic typos” (Hayden
par. 4)—and say that their work “is all code” (par. 6). Synthetic biologists, like Stanford bioengineer
Drew Endy team, have already built a biocomputer, called the transcriptor, which uses proteins and
DNA in place of silicon chips to store and transmit information based on a logical system (Bonnet
et al.); overall, the analogy between computational and biological codes is growing closer in
complexity of each with neural nets, which biologize the computational technology. Further
discussion on how novel technologies like AI and synthetic biology influence our conceptions of the
human, nature, technology, etc. is needed, but out of the scope of this dissertation. Nonetheless, the
concept of posthumanist biology, as described by Pramod Nayar, might prove fruitful when placed
Another example of hybridity we have recently become aware of is the variety of genetic evidence
that members of the Neanderthal species mixed with humans (Zimmer). Our DNA is therefore
mosaic in more ways than we have imagined, crossing into a different hominoid species. (As
mentioned above, this interspecies breeding was also proven in animals, e.g. elephants (Palkopoulou
et al.).) Nathaniel Hawthorne imagined a similar but more species-distant and science-based
421
interbreeding of the human species with plants in his well-known short story Rappaccini’s Daughter
(1844).40 This story follows a Pygmalionesque motif in which a young naïve suitor Giovanni falls in
love with a beautiful, hardly human woman Beatrice, the daughter of a rogue scientist Rappaccini.
Rappaccini turns Beatrice into a poisonous plant-woman, ultimately killing her and turning her lover
With this story, Hawthorne describes a principle of posthuman biology that reinvents human origins
as a part of a larger transformation of the human into a posthuman entity. The next step in
posthuman biology is, per Pramod Nayar, posthumanist biology, in which the human species
“Fiction such as Butler’s moves toward a species cosmopolitanism via configuration of biology and new modes
of biological citizenship. The preliminary stage is a posthuman biology in which authors like Butler present a
new theory of origins and move toward the idea of species domestication and deracination. This domestication
marks the moment when a new kind of posthumanist biology becomes visible. Individuals are now trained to
deal with their new biology, but also to acquire a biological citizenship in more than one species through
memoirs acts and a newly instilled sense of the ethical” (Nayar 127).
Nayar’s proposal of posthuman/ist biology is a rather short account (a journal article’s worth) that
deserves more attention, which is why I extend it here to the Rappaccini stories and investigate it
further in Butler’s opus. Building on the whole discussion from this chapter, I pinpoint three
The American science fiction writer Anthony Boucher continued Hawthorne’s story in a two-page
short story ‘Rappaccini’s Other Daughter’ (sometimes titled ‘The Other Rappaccini’s Daughter’)
(1999) by turning Hawthorne’s preliminary stage of posthuman biology into posthumanist biology.
40Octavio Paz dramatized the story in 1953 and argued in the prologue that the story originates in an ancient Indian tale
that traveled to the West through Gesta Romanorum and Robert Burton’s The Anatomy of Melancholy (3).
422
In Hawthorne, Rappaccini’s work on Beatrice was a failed experiment: she was made poisonous to
humans and could not be saved from being poisoned herself. Boucher imagines another
Rappaccini’s daughter, Laura, who managed to cultivate herself into society as a human woman,
despite her partly plant DNA. “That shallow youth” Giovanni fell in love with Laura as he did with
Beatrice (Boucher 447). Worried since he himself was also poisonous as a “victim of the Rappaccini
method,” Giovanni was fortunate to find “a living object [to which] he was to discharge the normal
impulses of youth” (ib.). (Calling Laura a living object not only underlines the objectification of
women but also the fact that she was not wholly human.) Laura and Giovanni were Rappaccini’s
newest guinea pigs and “[l]ike guinea pigs they bred—if not indeed like hurkles,” spreading their
nonhuman genes via reproductive means (as in in vitro gene editing technology).
The beautiful couple was obviously not quite human, however: everyone around them needed to use
masks and still felt “the dulcet and balsamous breath” (447). This problem was obscured in their
progeny: women used their masks unnoticed and men inserted filters
believed to carry disease; for example, the plague doctors stuffed the
themselves from inhaling the infected air. The progeny of Laura and
423
Namely, people with plant DNA were still poisonous to humanity untouched by their plant genes.
The problem was solved by “a Rappaccini” who suggested advertising “the sweet Rappaccini
breath” to the rest of the world who “had always shown a liking for [it]” (448). All humanity was
imbued by Rappaccini-Guasconti’s venomous fragrance by the late twentieth century, this time not
with reproduction but with mass-selling of chlorophyll that alternates one’s genes (as in in vivo gene
editing technology). Using both, first in vitro and then in vivo gene editing technologies, Laura and
Giovanni have become Lilith and Adam of the new interbred humanity. Unknown to anyone but a
few Rappaccinis, the new humanity was unethically subdued in a scientific experiment (just like
Rappaccini’s first daughter Beatrice) and the old humanity died off on its expense.
6.6.3 Butler
Like Anthony Boucher continuing Nathanael Hawthorne’s famous story, Octavia Butler perfected
the transition from the posthuman to posthumanist biology in her own works. In her memorable
and disturbing short story ‘Bloodchild’ (1984), humans would have gone extinct had they been not
forced to gestate an extraterrestrial species. The short story served as an inspiration for her later
trilogy, called The Xenogenesis Trilogy or Lilith’s Brood (1987-1989), which includes novels titled Dawn,
‘Bloodchild’ takes place in indefinite future on an extraterrestrial world where humans serve as
gestational beings to a higher, insect-like species known as the Tlic. The Tlic can only reproduce in
symbiosis with animals—of which humans have proved to be the easiest to work with—who are
required to host their eggs inside their bodies for the time of pregnancy. In exchange for this
procreation-based oppression, humans are given a special compound to live in (with Earth
presumably uninhabitable) and sterile Tlic eggs to enjoy as a kind of opiate that keeps them calm and
424
content (not unlike soma in Brave New World). Although many people read this story as an allegory of
slavery, Butler renounced this reading in the afterword (30). The core of the story is the familial love
the humans feel for the Tlic that are affiliated with their families. Due to the strong familiar bonds
of the Tlic with the Terrans, these connections cannot be written off as a Stockholm syndrome
either. The Tlic choose human families they want to reproduce within, take care of them by giving
them opioid eggs, and stay in close relationships with the matriarchs or patriarchs of the families as
The story focuses on a boy named Gan who had been chosen to host the eggs for T’Gatoi, an
important member of the Tlic. We meet Gan at the point where he is ready to bear children but has
not consented yet to be impregnated. While agonizing over the decision, he sees a birth of larvae
going terribly wrong: a man giving birth is screaming of pain due to being eaten alive by the
emerging larvae before T’Gatoi comes to help, numbs him and surgically removes the young. Gan is
given the option for his sister to be the carrier of T’Gatoi’s children: “It will be easier for Hoa. She
has always expected to carry other lives inside her. […] Human lives. Human young who should
someday drink at her breasts, not at her veins” (26). He, nonetheless, feels obligated and honored to
be the gestational surrogate for T’Gatoi, whom he respects and loves (“I loved watching her move”
(9)) and to whom he has connected since his very birth (“I was told I was first caged within
In fact, Gan (or any human) does not have much agency in his relationship with the superior
species, but he overcomes his fear even if that means sacrificing his own life. Resistance is futile. By
“joining the families […] everyone had a personal stake in keeping the peace [among the two
species]” (12). “Firearms were illegal in the Preserve” (12), but Gan manages to find a gun and
admits to T’Gatoi: “I wouldn’t have shot you” (29). His familial love and a sense of duty towards the
425
other prevails over the coercion, fear, or disgust he might feel when gestating endoparasitic worms:
“[T’Gatoi] had been taken from my father’s flesh when he was my age” (29). Gan’s and T’Gatoi’s
families form an interspecies family that developed through chosen kinship: T’Gatoi and Gan’s
mother “had grown up together” (7), “T’Gatoi had even introduced [Gan’s] mother to the man who
became [Gan’s] father” (8), and T’Gatoi chose Gan when he was still an infant to become a bearer
of her own children when he matures. The beauty of Butler’s story is in this multidimensionality:
Terrans are not entirely victimized by this relationship. They are corporeally vulnerable, sometimes
risking their lives in the Tlic gestation; yet, the Tlic are vulnerable too as their future generations lie
in the other species’ gestational acts. Rather, the relationship between the species is a matter of co-
In Lilith’s Brood, the first novel of The Xenogenesis Trilogy, humans again find themselves at the edge of
extinction: they have almost gone extinct in a nuclear war which left the Earth uninhabitable and
their only option to continue the species is to mingle their genes with an extraterrestrial species
called the Oankali. The Oankali made humans infertile to breed among themselves without the
extraterrestrial third party so that, like in ‘Bloodchild’, humans are eventually forced to participate in
a symbiogenesis41 of the Oankali-human hybrids: “For humanity to survive, it must become posthuman
with other species” (Nayar 133). Some of the ‘old-world’ humans survive, but they need to comply with
the interbreeding. The most capable of these Oankali-altered or space-born humans are sent back to
Earth after they are prepared to live on the changed, wild planet, made livable for humankind by the
Oankali. These preserved humans on the verge of extinction have to make a mental, conscious shift
towards the posthumanist biology of their origins and bodily existence in order to survive.
41Symbiogenesis is a term from evolutionary biology by Lynn Margulis. In When the Species Meet, Haraway writes about
symbiogenesis with her dogs: “Ms Cayenne Pepper continues to colonize all my cells […]. I bet if you were to check our
DNA, you’d find some potent transfections between us” (When 15).
426
Undergoing this colossal existential change, humans struggle especially with reinventing and
procreating themselves through a symbiogenesis. Mating is not always a choice: Lilith, a black
woman, is chosen by the Oankali to be the mother of the reborn humanity. Even those who are
willing to mate are repulsed by a mere thought of touching, living and breeding with the Oankali.
The Oankali, on the contrary, thrive on the genetic trade, difference, diversity, exploration of the
other, and symbiogenesis (they have used this reproductive process numerous times in their history,
incorporating traits from other extraterrestrial lifeforms). Before the Oankali meet with the humans,
they change their shape from slug-like creatures to a more human-like shape—a shape that, as they
are aware, is nonetheless shocking and fear-inducing to humans at first. Even before the procreation
system is established with Lilith, humans are altered by the Oankali: Lilith is made cancer-less,
physically stronger and more resistant to injuries. Lilith at first resist to “be tampered with” (76); in
particular, she is worried that correcting her brain tumor and altering her brain chemistry will change
her. After this first unwilling contact with the Oankali, all life on Earth already carries its organelle.
To interbreed, from the Oankali perspective, is therefore only a benefit to humans but redundant to
them because the Oankali had managed to subdue the humans and mix with them asexually before
the first human accepts to interbreed. Besides that, before the ‘old-world- humans were in conscious
contact with the Oankali, the aliens have taken their gametes, “stuff from men and women who
didn’t know each other and put it together and made babies in women who never knew the mother
or the father of their kid—and who maybe never got to know the kid. Or maybe they grew the baby
in another kind of animal. They have animals they can adjust to—to incubate human fetuses, as they
427
Posthuman humans can be zealous in their scientific curiosity and technological invention:
“Humankind does not discriminate; it willingly becomes its own guinea pig under the same terms as
the rest of the world, animate and inanimate. Humankind blithely plays with its own future as a
species in the same way that it plays with the future of all other creatures. In its blind quest to
possess greater knowledge, humankind programs its own destruction with the same casual ferocity
that it applies to the destruction of everything else” (Baudrillard 16-17). The shift towards a more
inclusive and interconnected posthumanist world—in which the spaceship is alive, composed of
solely organic materials, feeding people but also being fed, growing and being grown—is a challenge
to humanity used to reckless life before the nuclear war that destroyed the Earth.
In all the fictional works discussed above, Butler works with three novelties in the shift towards
posthumanist biology: ecological (all life is connected), biotechnological (biology as technology), and
symbiotic (positive exchange). Humans have grown to be more aware of our interdependency and
interconnectedness with flora and fauna, living in, on and around our own bodies: “To be one is
always to become with many. […] my companion species who are my maker” (Haraway When 4).
This realization is related to how we view and practice biology as technology (biology as
biotechnology) and also as art (bioart). In relation to both previous shifts, we have also re-evaluated
our relationship to human pathology (human body is full of errors, human character is fallible). As
etc.), we use natural processes—some of which could be pathological—to work into our zealous
goal of perfecting ourselves (for example, viruses or animals’ biomaterials to heal or enhance ours).42
42For example, in 2019, a woman in Japan was the first to receive an ‘artificial’ cornea transplant to improve her vision.
The cornea was made from induced pluripotent stem (iPS) cells that were ‘reprogrammed’ with the help of a virus.
Before this treatment, people with damaged or diseased corneas received transplants from dead donors (Cyranoski).
428
At the same time, the turn towards ecology and sustainability demands not only human symbiosis at
the level of our bodies but at a planetary level. The ecological shift, with a common goal to prevent
further climate change, makes an assumption (prevalent in studies on the Anthropocene) that
everything nonhuman holds a moral authority over pathological, violent humanity. Posthumanist
biology believes that only technology can correct this fault in human character and make a better
These shifts are, in short, the Oankali philosophy of life, based entirely on (posthumanist) biology.
The following passage from Butler’s Dawn, the first novel of the trilogy, encompasses the
posthumanist message of the extraterrestrials that ultimately manages to re-structure human values
“Nikanj44 smoothed its body tentacles in amusement. ‘Anything to do with Humans always seems to involve
contradictions.’ It paused. ‘Examine Tino. Inside him, so many very different things are working together to
keep him alive. Inside his cells, mitochondria, a previously independent form of life, have found a haven and
trade their ability to synthesize proteins and metabolize fats for room to live and reproduce. We’re in his cells
too now, and the cells have accepted us. One Oankali organism within each cell, diving with each cell,
extending life, and resisting disease. Even before we arrived, they had bacteria living in their intestines and
protecting them from other bacteria that would hurt or kill them. They could not exist without symbiotic
relationships with other creatures. Yet such relationships frighten them” (426).
As Pramod Nayar points out in relation to the passage, it is “practically a paraphrase of Lynn
Margulis, Scott Gilbert and other theorists of evolutionary biology; […] all biology is multispecies,
symbiotic and mutually dependent” (128). The humanity in ‘Bloodchild’ as well as in Lilith’s Brood
breaks off into a radical re-birth, a second origin. This means that the old ways have likely proved to
43The exploitation of the environment seems to—predictably—be moving into space. Butler’s texts all take place there
and consider the symbiosis at the level of the universe. Other science fiction works address this issue as well, many in the
fashion of Robinsonade (e.g. Kim Stanley Robinson’s The Mars Trilogy or Ridley Scott’s film The Martian, based on Andy
Weir’s novel).
44Nikanj is an Oankali of the third sex (that use the pronoun ‘it’), called Ooloi. The Ooloi are capable healers of human
pathologies and have a strong urge to breed with a human couple. Nikanj breeds with Lilith, the first human to create
new interspecies humans.
429
be wrong; we learn in Lilith’s Brood that humanity was close to eradicated and the Earth
impoverished and that they both need to be rebuilt in order for humans to ever live on Earth again.
Although “human contradiction”—as human pathology, self-centrism and violent dominance are
called throughout the trilogy—prevents humanity to thrive, humans might be able to overcome it
through posthumanist biology that leads us to interconnectedness with the world and the universe.
In Ovid’s Metamorphoses, transformation is the ultimate goal and solution to Pygmalion’s problem,
metamorphosis is also the goal and solution, but requires a series of metamorphoses across the
human species (here, as in Michael Ghiselin, the whole human species is treated as an individuum).
In Butler, humanity is the creator and the created at the same time. The first metamorphosis of
humans is the contact and the crossbreeding with the Oankali which affects their biology and, more
drastically, the genetics. This new hybrid humanity, called constructs, needs to learn an interspecies
way of living in a posthumanist world that includes Earth and space. This metamorphosis affects
human character, behavior, and culture. Another metamorphosis, to which Butler dedicates the
second and third book of the trilogy, Adulthood Rites and Imago, is physical metamorphosis of the
constructs in puberty and adolescence, when, to a varying degree, constructs grow sensory tentacles
and patches (and some learn about their sex only then as they can be sexless during childhood). The
hybridity of constructs is on a spectrum, physically and mentally: some might ‘pass’ as a human
physically (like a racially non-white person can pass as white), they might look more Oankali (and
thus nonhuman), or they might turn to be the Ooloi, the third sex (it), which requires another
physical and mental metamorphosis. A construct Ooloi, the protagonist of Imago, serves as a final
430
Butler’s fiction is focused on depicting the process of intraspecies transgressions. The confrontation
of the two species is always violent and acerbated by disgust in humans. In ‘Bloodchild,’ growing
parasitic larvae under one’s skin is a repulsive thought, but less so when considered an action of
gestational surrogacy based on familial love and connection. Similarly, in The Xenogenesis Trilogy, these
familial connections need to be fostered into a kinship (for example, this connection does not occur
between human hybrid Akin and his sibling as they are not able to grow up together and bond). The
violent birth scene in ‘Bloodchild’ is shocking and intense, as any birth, but more so because of the
imagery of slaughter with larvae emerging from the man’s flesh and his near death. Disgust that
humans would otherwise feel towards the worm-like Tlic or towards the tentacled Oankali is
without the acceptance of the new human condition, of which the first step is the loss of repulsion
towards the nonhuman and eventual affection for the nonhuman reproductive partner. The literal
mixing of human DNA with another species is only a consequence of a more significant change. By
breaching the fatal human flaw, “the human contradiction,” humanity is improving itself in its
physical (diseases, injuries, any bodily disfunction) and mental pathologies (violence, selfishness,
racism, etc.). It should be noted, however, that this breaching of humanity as we know it can also be
everything ‘beyond the human’ as a continuous good and a moral authority, be it nature or
6.6.4 Bioart
Bioart was born at the turn of the twentieth century and fiction has far preceded bioart in addressing
biological hybridity. Bioart uses visuality to address social and philosophical questions posed by
working with live tissues with the help of biotechnology. By visualizing an aspect of technological
431
practice, bioart helps us rethink these technological or scientific tools under the aesthetic, social, or
ethical inquiry as covered by the artificial humanities. (micha cárdenas’s poetry, mentioned in the
LGBTQIA+ section, could also be considered bioart since she worked with human tissues.) Bioart
uses technologies available in practice, such as visualizing technologies used in reproductive care, but
not necessarily the way they are practiced in healthcare or elsewhere due to utilitarian, ethical, or
Art became more important in researching the fundamental contradiction of the contemporary
human, for which the standard concept of the human as an autonomous self-contained being —and
perhaps the conceptual category as the human itself—fails us. This rupture was filled with
technologies as fields for establishing the new conception and practice of the human. Bioart, much
like engineering, formulates research questions in situ of their practices, a manner utterly distinct
from that of literature and philosophy from which both could extract a proof of principle and build
I would like to offer an illustrative example of this posthumanist practice in Slovenian bioartist Maja
432
seclusion of the artist and her dogs, during which the artist stimulated her milk production with
breast pumping and breastfed her puppy Ada. For a human to nurse a puppy is obscene: it
compromises human dignity, regardless of the co-development of the human and dog species. Our
pets, and particularly dogs, are largely a part of our families and thus our kin, but not of kind (Shell
Children 148-50). Smrekar comments on this project from a perspective of a dog-mother, which led
her to introspect the faults of her own human species: “A side effect was the increase in oxytocin
hormone levels, which led to an increase in empathy and my personal resistance to the cynicism of
the zeitgeist. By being pregnant with a meaning, and thus becoming (m)Other, I was further drawn
Haraway, 2016)” (‘Hybrid’ par. 1). By mixing fluids, this time not blood as in consanguineous
kinship but through collactaneous affinity of milk and saliva, familial kinship is transmitted
Smrekar performed a reverse situation from the foundation myth of Rome, in which twins Romulus
and Remus were suckled by a she-wolf and later parented by a shepherd and his wife. The practice
of animals nursing humans is not considered as obscene as the other way around because humans
consume animal products, including milk, albeit not usually suckling milk directly from the
source.4546 Both practices, however, have been present in different cultures for a variety of health,
religious, and cultural reasons. A wet nurse is therefore not always human.
45This does not mean, however, that debates about the animalizing effect of drinking animal milk and about the harmful
affinity when nursed by other women than the mother were not common already in Montaigne’s time (Shell Children
159). Vaccinations are also related to animals and therefore animalization, not only in terminology (Lat. vacca means cow,
and the term vaccination comes from Edward Jenner’s work on smallpox vaccine) but also in the related practices of
inventing new vaccines in human and veterinary medicine.
46Treating animals as a separate species by milking them, riding them, eating them is an anthropocentric act that gets
disqualified only with the rare cases of talking animals (discussed in Chapter 2) or with treating animals (or other
nonhuman objects) as our pets (our kin, but not our kind; as discussed in Chapter 3).
433
Michel de Montaigne writes in an essay Of the Affection of Fathers to Their Children about the exclusively
mothering act of nursing on the case of an interspecies connection between goats that are taught to
suckle infants as wet nurses. Displaying vehement care towards the foster-child they connect with,
“Beasts do as easily alter and corrupt their natural affections as we:” the goats “well-knowing
[children’s] voices when they cry […] come running to them; when if any other than that they are
acquainted with be presented to them, they refuse to let it suck, and the child, to any other goat, will
do the same” (252). In the same essay, Montaigne also writes of the affection that develops between
“pitiful” human wet nurses and the children they nurse: “we see in most of them an adulterate
affection [affection bastarde], begot by custom toward the foster children, more vehement than the
natural; and a greater solicitude for the preservation of those they have taken charge of, than their
own” (ib.).47
Figure 54 The cover of the Belle and lost kitten and feeds her with her own milk: “Le chat la prenant
Sebastian’s first album Tigermilk (1996).
WikiMedia.
pour sa mère / Se mit à téter tout de go / Emue, Margot le laissa
en.wikipedia.org/wiki/File:BelleAndSebasti
anTigermilk.jpg
47 In Slovenian literature and history Montaigne’s observation has a strong presence. First, it is most known as a
folkloristic and literary motif of the beautiful Vida (lepa Vida), a young mother who leaves her elderly husband and young
infant to become a wet nurse for the future king of Spain. Second, it is also attested as a historical account of a period
from the second half of the nineteenth century until the Second World War, when women from Slovenian littoral region
left for Egypt in order to serve as maids and wet nurses, often to never return home to their own children. They were
called Alexandrinians (Sln. Aleksandrinke) and their stories have been depicted in literary accounts (Josip Jurčič, Ivan
Cankar, Alojz Gradnik, Edvard Kocbek) and documentary films (Metod Pevec’s Aleksandrinke).
434
faire / Brav’ Margot.”48 Margot’s nursing becomes a daily curiosity for male onlookers and makes
the women of the village jealous to an extent that they put the kitten down—curiosity literally killed
the cat. Another example, not influenced by Brassens, is the cover of the Scottish band Belle and
Sebastian’s album, a photograph that the band’s lead singer and songwriter Stuart Murdoch made of
his then-girlfriend Joanne Kenney. Per Murdock’s description on how the album got its name and
the cover photograph, Kenney was sitting in a bathtub naked and spontaneously took a stuffed tiger
toy to cover her breasts and, as he recounts, “I supposed it was the obvious thing that she might
The breastfeeding practice in Smrekar’s projects alludes to human cultures in which nursing an
infant is formative of kinship. In the continuation of the ‘ARTE_mis’ project, one of Smrekar’s
emptied ova was used as a host for her dog Ada’s somatic cell and was grown in a laboratory like an
IVF embryo would have been grown until the blastocyst stage. “The resulting hybrid cell was never
possibilities, from which the impossibility of the mythological man-wolf emerges in all its poetics.
Instead, it suggested that if we care for Planet Earth and our survival upon it, we might as well
morph into creatures that treat their environment with more consideration than we do” (‘K-
“The cat mistook her for her mother / And began suckling right away, / Moved, Margot let it carry on / Good girl
48
435
Smrekar’s vision in this project is close to Butler’s The
Figure 55 The lion-man sculpture from Germany Greek mythology). The novelty of Smrekar’s project is
(dated to 37,000 years ago).
the technological application of the hybridity and the
Wikimedia Commons, public domain.
commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File:Lion_man_photo
provocative approach to it, i.e. stepping in the socially
human/nonhuman embryos, regardless of their social kinship. Bioart further illuminates the fact that
in science today, hybrid organisms are both a fact and a science-fiction fantasy that operates in the
realm of a factual scientific seriousness. Cartography, literature, visual arts, and other disciplines have
long merged fact and fiction as well as human form with nonhuman forms—something that is not
traditionally expected of quantitative disciplines. For example, in Pliny the Elder’s The Natural History
(77-79 CE) the natural world is a construction of the mythic and the empirical, seamlessly without
contradiction. Literature and the arts have found means of addressing and coming to terms with the
change of the most fundamental practices and concepts around the human. Through the proposed
framework of the artificial humanities, they can be studied by extracting their vocabularies, concepts,
436
7 Conclusion: Back to Mythologies
This dissertation examines the twentieth-century Western literature that fits into the Pygmalion
paradigm or relates to the Pygmalion myth and, more broadly, to questions of human creation and
investigating what is human, already-human, and not-yet-human in terms of language, paralysis, pathology,
reproduction, and hybridity, this project builds a novel interdisciplinary framework, which I have
through a literary lens. The artificial humanities framework could be extended to other technologies
and natural sciences. This dissertation is based in comparative literature and stretches from medical
and health humanities to bioethics and artificial intelligence ethics, the history of science and
technology, disability studies, and future studies, providing scaffolding for literature-based inquires
in women and gender studies, ethnic studies, film and media studies, and further directions.
Attempting to outline the fundamental ontological question of the human essence is an ambitious
and self-defeating goal that nonetheless helps to inform ethical dilemmas brought forth by new
technologies that we as a society need to deal with immediately. In this dissertation I have examined
the question What is human? is examined from different angles and disciplines, with a focus on AI
chatbots, neurotechnology used for heavily paralyzed people, and assisted reproductive technology.
My main thesis lies on the premise that current framing and defining of the human takes place in
STEM, unbeknown to engineers and scientists who are creating and re-defining the human by their
practices which seemingly focus on the nonhuman alone. I argue that literature and literary
scholarship have been in a privileged position to be able to reflect on the questions pertaining to
new technologies, thanks to the philosophical insights and space for speculation that are largely
437
inaccessible to quantitative sciences. The finding that the humanities should be a part of every
technological practice calls for a reevaluation and restructuring of research and education.
Interdisciplinarity was the first step towards the merging of disciplines, but a more practical and
malleable approach is needed in which both humanities and engineering benefit from each other.
This dissertation shows that literary contributions to scientific and technological developments
could and should be more substantial and beneficial to the most pertinent technological dilemmas in
research as well as in general conversation. The main goal of this project is to pave the way for
literary studies and related disciplines to research the philosophical stakes and the human
implications of novel technologies. Specifying the relevance of literature and humanities in fields
where they are not traditionally present and conventionally found is especially pertinent to the crisis
Animation and humanization of a nonhuman entity is the heart of the Pygmalion myth, the central
trope of this dissertation. The axis of the human-nonhuman relationship as examined here is always
between the human creator or the human user and the (technological) creation. As a counterpart to
creator-created and lover-beloved relationships, this axis is paralleled with the characters from a
variety of the Pygmalion paradigm texts. These factual-fictional parallels are especially useful in
discussing ethical dilemmas raised by novel technologies and building a framework that enables non-
In this project, the Pygmalion myth framing helps to indicate three related phenomena relevant to
today’s technologies which the myth has introduced throughout its literary and cinematic history: 1)
438
medical diagnoses, and 3) human-nonhuman reproduction. Although the Pygmalion myth has been
widely discussed in literary scholarship and beyond (e.g. the Pygmalion effect in psychology), the
three phenomena in focus here have been largely disregarded. New technologies and the ethics
surrounding them have been addressed in a variety of humanities, social sciences, and STEM fields,
which tend to employ literary examples to present an issue at stake or illustrate a point, assuming
some references, such as Frankenstein or Gattaca, as common knowledge. Nonetheless, studies that
delve into an actual analysis of literary works in relation to novel technologies are surprisingly rare in
literary scholarship (as opposed to social sciences). In this dissertation, using literature as a baseline
for discussing challenges in technology ethics turned out to be fruitful with findings not only in texts
that have not yet received much scholarly attention (such as the Slovenian and Serbian short stories)
but also within canonized texts (such as Pygmalion and Brave New World).
The overall finding of this dissertation concerns the theory of posthumanism, which has split into
two streams, the more practical ontological posthumanism and more theoretical critical
posthumanism, the latter of which often makes claims that it has overcome anthropocentrism. I
show that anthropocentrism still permeates both streams and suggest a more interconnected
approach to defining the human. The evidence for this approach is found in every chapter. In the
posthuman language chapters (1 and 2), I demonstrate the demand for galateas of all sorts—AI
systems, social robots, animals of different species, and humans of lower class—to mimic normative
human language, behavior, and identity. In the first four chapters, I show the rising interest in
creating humanlike objects (virtual assistants, social robots, sex dolls, etc.) as companions. In the
pygmalionism and paralysis chapters (3 and 4), I address the increasing possibility of enhancing
human bodies and minds with neurotechnology in relation to the levels of personhood ascribed to
severely paralyzed humans and to humanlike entities. In the final chapters on assisted reproduction
439
and hybridity (5 and 6), I find that biotechnology has overcome the mimicry of natural reproductive
processes in in-vitro fertilization, threating to alter human evolution in a most anthropocentric way:
by experimenting with our own body tissues, which in the past included living fetuses (e.g. Robert
Goodlin’s experiments with artificial wombs) and most recently IVF embryos and now-living infants
(the Chinese CRISPR-edited twins dubbed Lulu and Nana). All the technologies discussed here act
both to cure human pathology and to enforce a Pygmalionesque dream of the human as the creator
Besides this general theoretical argument, the six chapters build a practical framework for using
literature to address current ethical and philosophical dilemmas. Each chapter shows how literature
reflects on current and speculated developments in science and technology. In Chapter 1, I show
how literature anticipates the nascent science of machine language training on the example of G. B.
Shaw’s Pygmalion. In chapter 2, I take Richard Powers’s Galatea 2.2 and Andrej Tomažin’s and Roald
Dahl’s short stores as examples of literature anticipating questions that will arise with developing AI
also examine actual and fictional examples (Karel Čapek, Ted Chiang, Julio Cortázar) of animal
communication with animals as well as machines. In chapter 3, I explore pygmalionism (i.e. ascribing
personhood to objects and humanlike virtual galateas) as a medical and social condition, finding that
our attitudes about this growing practice have shifted towards acceptance. In chapter 4, I
demonstrate through short stories by Zoran Nišković, James Tiptree Jr. (Alice Sheldon), and Roald
Dahl and through memoirs by Phillipe Vigand and Jean-Dominique Bauby how bodily paralysis
affects patients to develop a personal relationship with their co-agents, be they human or
nonhuman. In chapter 5, I detail how Aldous Huxley’s Brave New World anticipated in-vitro
440
fertilization technology (together with some other technologies it enables, such as gene editing and
artificial wombs) and delve deeper into bioethical issues around current and speculated assisted
reproductive technologies. In chapters 5 and 6, I show how the scientific terminology and visual
such. In addition, on the basis of the previous five chapters, I advocate in the final chapter for a
The project concludes with exploring the notions of hybridity (as transgressing and blending
borders) and interconnectedness (connecting over borders), bringing the Pygmalionesque topic back
to mythologies, which are full of transgressive acts that may result in hybrid creatures. I address
these notions in the biological and reproductive sense; however, the cyborgian idea of an
interconnected hybrid is much broader and also includes computational technology. One such
example is the Estonian mythological creature Kratt which became a synonym for AI in Estonia:
Kratt was a hybrid created out of hay and household objects who became alive when a (Faustian)
pact was made between Kratt’s master and the devil, allowing the master to make the creature do
any kind of menial labor (Haynes par. 1). If we began with a simple examination of the vocabulary
around terms like human and humanlike as they are used by AI and social robotics companies as
well as by neurotechnological and biotechnological laboratories, we would pave the way for
extracting new vocabularies and ideas that support their practices. Literature, as an active podium for
carrying and reinterpreting mythologies and traditions, a pioneer of ideas and their repercussions,
and a critical tool to reshape conceptualizations and values, offers a venue to distinguish, appraise,
441
8 Bibliography
Aeschylus. The ‘Eumenides’ of Aeschylus. Tran. by A. W. Verrall. Macmillan and Co.: London, 1908.
A.I. Artificial Intelligence. Directed by Stephen Spielberg. Performances by Haley Jude Osment, Jude
Law, Frances O’Connor, Brendan Gleeson, William Hurt. Warner Bros, 2001. DVD.
A.I.Rising (Ederlezi Rising). Directed by Lazar Bodroža. Performances by Sebastian Cavazza, Stoya,
Maruša Majer, Kirsty Besterman. Creative Century Entertainment, 2018.
Anstey, F. [pseud. for Thomas Anstey Guthrie]. The Tinted Venus: A Farcical Romance. 1885. EBook
Guttenberg, released Jan 7, 2008. Accessed on 3 Nov 2018.
Alcott, Louisa May. ‘A Marble Woman, or The Mysterious Model.’ Plots and Counterplots: More
Unknown Thrillers of Louisa May Alcott. New York: Morrow, 1976.
Apollodorus, of Athens (Pseudo-Apollodorus). Bibliothēkē/ The Library. Tran. Sir James George
Frazer. Vol. 3. London: W. Heinemann, 1921.
Barbauld, Anna Laetitia. ‘To a Little Invisible Being Who is Expected Soon to Become Visible.’ The
Broadview Anthology of Literature of the Revolutionary Period 1770-1832. Ed. D. L MacDonald and
Anne McWhir. Peterborough, Ontario: Broadview P, 2010. 113.
Bauby, Jean-Dominique. The Diving Bell and the Butterfly. [Le scaphandre et le papillon.] Trans. New York,
NY: A. A. Knopf, 1997.
Blade Runner 2049. Directed by Dennis Villeneuve. Performances by Ryan Gosling, Harrison Ford,
Ana de Armas, Robin Wright. Warner Bros, 2017. DVD.
Boucher, Anthony. ‘Rappaccini’s Other Daughter.’ The compleat Boucher: the complete short science fiction
and fantasy of Anthony Boucher. Framingham, MA: The NESFA P, 1998. 447-48.
Butler, Octavia. Adulthood Rites. New York, NY: Warner Books, 1988.
---. ‘Bloodchild.’ Bloodchild and Other Stories. 2nd ed. New York, NY: Seven Stories P, 2005. 1-32.
442
Butler, Samuel. Erewhon: or, Over the Range. London: Trübner, 1872.
cárdenas, micha. ‘Pregnancy: Reproductive Features in Trans Color Feminism.’ Transgender Studies
Quarterly 3/1-2 (2016): 48-57.
Chiang, Ted. ‘Documentary: Liking What You See.’ Stories of Your Life and Others. New York, NY:
Tor, 2002. 281-323.
---. ‘Story of Your Life.’ Stories of Your Life and Others. New York, NY: Tor, 2002. 117-178.
---. ‘The Great Silence.’ Exhalation: Stories. New York, NY: Alfred A. Knopf, 2019. 231-236.
Cortázar, Julio. ‘Axolotl.’ Cuentos Completos 1 (1945-1966). México: Alfaguara, 1996. 381-85
---. ‘Axolotl.’ End of the Game and other stories. Tran. Paul Blackburn. New York, NY: Pantheon Books,
1967. 3-9.
Čapek, Karl. R.U.R.: Rossum’s universal robots: kolektivní drama o vstupní komedii a 3 dějstvích. Praha:
Aventinum, 1922.
---. War with the Newts. Tran. by Ewald Osers. Highland Park, NJ: Catbird P, 1990.
---. ‘William and Mary.’ The Collected Short Stories of Roald Dahl. Vol. 1. Ed. Jeremy Treglown. New
York, NY: Alfred A Knopf, 2006. 460-487.
Dante. The Divine Comedy. 2: Purgatorio. Trans. and commentary by John D. Sinclair. New York, NY:
Oxford UP, 1939.
Darwin, Erasmus. Temple of Nature: Or, The Origin of Society: A Poem, with Philosophical Notes.
knarf.english.upenn.edu/Darwin/templetp.html Accessed on 8 Mar 2019.
Dr. Seuss [Theodor Geisel]. Horton Hatches the Egg. New York, NY: Random House, 1940.
Ellis, Sophie Wenzel. ‘Creatures of the Light.’ Astounding Stories of Super Science ½ (1930): 196-220.
443
---. ‘Slaves of the Dust.’ Astounding Stories of Super Science 4/3 (1930): 295-309.
Flagg, Francis [George Henry Weiss]. ‘The Machine Man of Ardathia.’ Amazing Stories 2/8 (1927):
798-804.
Forster, E. M. ‘The Machine Stops.’ The Wesleyan Anthology of Science Fiction. Middletown, CN:
Wesleyan UP, 2010. 50-78.
Galton, Francis, The Eugenic College of Kantsaywhere 1910. Digitized by University College London,
1996.
Gattaca. Directed by Andrew Niccol. Performances by Ethan Hawke, Uma Thurman, Alan Arkin,
Jude Law. Jersey Films, 1997. DVD.
Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von. Faust. Der Tragödie zweiter Teil. Stuttgart: J. G. Cotta’schen
Buchhandlung, 1832.
---. Faust I and II, Vol. 2: Goethe’s Collected Works – Updated Edition. Ed. and tran. by Stuart Atkins.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP, 1984.
---. Motherhood and Its Enemies. London: Chatto and Windus, 1927.
Hardy, Thomas. ‘Barbara of the House of Grebe.’ A Group of Noble Dames. Leopzig: B. Tauchnitz,
1891.
---. ‘Rappaccini’s Daughter.’ Nathaniel Hawthorne’s Tales: Authoritative Texts, Backgrounds, Criticism. Ed.
James Mcintosh. 2nd ed. New York, NY : W.W. Norton & Co, 2013. 228-253.
---. ‘Drowne’s Wooden Image.’ Nathaniel Hawthorne’s Tales: Authoritative Texts, Backgrounds, Criticism.
Ed. James Mcintosh. 2nd ed. New York, NY : W.W. Norton & Co, 2013. 218-227.
---. ‘The Golden Touch.’ A Wonder Book. London: Hodden & Sttoughton, 1922. 47-67.
---. ‘The Marble Faun.’ The Portable Hawthorne. New York: Penguin Books, 2005.
Hazlitt, William. Liber Amoris; or the new Pygmalion. London: Printed for John Hunt, 1923.
Her. Directed by Spike Jonze. Performances by Joaquin Phoenix, Scarlett Johansson, Amy Adams.
Warner Bros, 2013. DVD.
444
Heti, Sheila. Motherhood. New York: Henry Holt and Company, 2018.
House M.D. Who’s Your Daddy. 2.23. Directed by Martha Mitchell. Performances by Hugh Laurie,
Lisa Edelstein. Original air date: May 16, 2006. iTunes.
Huxley, Aldous. ‘Brave New World.’ Brave New World and Brave New World Revisited. New York:
Harper Collins, 2004.
---. The Art of Seeing. New York, NY: Harper & Bros, 1942.
Huxley, Julian. ‘The Tissue-Culture King.’ Amazing Stories 2/5 (1927): 451-459.
Ishiguro, Kazuo. Never Let Me Go. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 2005.
James, Henry. ‘Watch and Ward.’ Watch and Ward; Longstaff’s marriage; Eugene Pickering and Other Tales.
London: Macmillan, 1923.
Kazemi, Darius. Teens Wander Around a House: a NoNoGenMo Draft. Nov 12, 2013.
tinysubversions.com/nanogenmo/novel-2.pdf Accessed on 5 Feb 2020.
Kingsley, Charles. The Water-Babies: A Fairy Tale for a Land-Baby. London: Macmillan & Co., 1922.
First published in 1863.
Lars and the Real Girl. Directed by Craig Gillespie. Performances by Ryan Gosling, Emily Mortimer,
Paul Schneider. Metro-Goldwyn-Mayer, 2007. DVD.
Leroux, Gaston. ‘La Machine à assassiner.’; ‘La Poupée sanglante.’ Aventures incroyables. Paris: R.
Laffont, 1992.
Lessing, Doris. The Fifth Child. New York, NY: Knopf (Random House), 1988.
Lofting, Hugh. The story of Doctor Dolittle: Being the history of his peculiar life at home and astonishing
adventures in foreign parts. New York, NY: Frederick A. Stokes Company, 1920.
Lorraine, Lilith [Mary Maud Dunn Wright]. ‘Into the 28th Century.’ Science Wonder Quarterly 1/2
(1930): 250-76.
445
Magnus, Hugo. Pygmalion. 1892. P. Ovidius Naso, Metamorphoses. Ed. Brookes More.
www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.02.0028%3Abook%3D
10%3Acard%3D243 Accessed on 30 Jun 2018.
Marlowe, Christopher. The Tragical History of the Life and Death of Doctor Faustus. In: Old English Plays:
Selection from the Early Dramatic Writers. Vol. 1. London: Whittingham and Rowland, 1814. 1-
92.
McCaffrey, Anne. ‘The Ship Who Sang.’ Women of Wonder: Science Fiction Stories by Women about Women.
Ed. Pamela Sargent. New York, NY: Vintage Books, Random House, 1975. 82-107.
Mérimée, Prosper. ‘La Vénus d’Ille.’ La Vénus d’Ille et autres nouvelles. Paris: Flammarion, 1982.
Montaigne, Michel de. The Essays of Michael Seigneur de Montaigne: With Notes and Quotations and Account
of the Author’s Life. Tran. by Charles Cotton. 3rd ed. London: Alex Murray & Son, 1870.
Moon, Elizabeth. Speed of Dark. New York, NYL Balantine Books, 2003.
More, C. L. ‘No Woman Born.’ The best of C. L. Moore. Ed. Lester del Rey. New York, Ballantine
Books, 1976.
My Fair Lady. Directed by George Cukor. Performances by Rex Harrison, Audrey Hepburn. Jack L.
Warner, 1964. DVD.
More, Thomas. De Optimo Reipublicae Statue deque Nova Insula Utopia. Libri II. Glasgow, UK: In
Aedibus Academicis, excudebant Robertus et Andrea Foulis, 1750.
www.thelatinlibrary.com/more.html
---. Utopia: a revised translation, backgrounds, criticism. Trans. and ed. Robert M. Adams. 2. ed. New York:
Norton, 1991.
O’Brien, Mark. ‘Breathing.’ Poetry Foundation July 1988. From Breathing. Lemonade Factory P, 1998.
www.poetryfoundation.org/poems/56112/breathing Accessed on 20 May 2020.
---. ‘For Clifford Bernel.’ Poetry Foundation From Breathing. Lemonade Factory P, 1998.
www.poetryfoundation.org/poems/56109/for-clifford-bernel Accessed on 20 May 2020.
---. ‘The Morning Routine.’ Poetry Foundation January 1990. From The Man in the Iron Lung. Lemonade
Factory P, 1997. www.poetryfoundation.org/poems/56111/the-morning-routine Accessed
on 20 May 2020.
Olds, Sharon. The Wellspring: Poems. New York, NY: Alfred A. Knopf, 1996.
446
---. Ovid’s Metamorphoses. Tran. Sir Samuel Garth, John Dryden, et al. Adelaide: The U of Adelaide
Library, 2008. eBook.
Nešković, Zoran. ‘Predveče se nikako ne može…’ Tamni vilajet: Izbor jugoslavneskog SF. Vol. 1. 2nd
extended edition. Beograd: Samostalno autorsko izdanje, Boban Knežević, 1989. 175-190.
Nilsson, Lennart. ‘Drama of Life Before Birth.’ LIFE 58/17 (1965): 54-72.
---. ‘The Drama of Life Before Birth.’ Lennart Nilsson Webpage www.lennartnilsson.com/en/a-life-of-
stories/the-drama-of-life-before-birth/ Accessed on 27 Jun 2019.
Picoult, Jodi. Handle with Care. New York, NY: Atria Books, 2009.
---. Sing You Home. New York, NY: Atria Books, 2011.
Poe, Edgar Allan. ‘The Man That Was Used Up.’ The selected writings of Edgar Allan Poe: Authoritative
texts, backgrounds and contexts, criticism. New York: W.W. Norton, 2004.
---. The Oval Portrait.’ The selected writings of Edgar Allan Poe: Authoritative texts, backgrounds and contexts,
criticism. New York: W.W. Norton, 2004.
Pohflepp, Sascha. ‘Recursion.’ Sascha Pohflepp Personal Webpage. pohflepp.net/Recursion Web 21 Sep
2018.
Pound, Ezra. The Cantos of Ezra Pound. New York, NY: New Directions Pub. Corp., 1972.
Powers, Richard. Galatea 2.2. New York: Farrar Strauss Giroux, 1995.
Racter (William Chamberlain, Thomas Etter). The Policeman’s Beard is Half Constructed: First Book Ever
Written by a Computer. New York, NY: Warner Books, 1984.
Rostand, Edmond. Cyrano de Bergerac: A Play in Five Acts. London: Neely, 1898.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. Pygmalion: scène lyrique. Paris: Theatre Contemporain Illustré: 1878.
Scalzi, John. Lock in. New York, NY: Tom Doherty Associates Book, 2014.
Seward, Anna. ‘Ode to Poetic Fancy.’ The Poetical Works of Anna Seward: With Extracts from her Literary
Correspondence. Vol. 2/3. Edinburgh: J. Ballantyne and co., 1820. 106.
Shaw, George Bernard. Back to Methuselah: a Metabiological Pentateuch. New York: The Limited
Editions Club, 1939.
447
---. Pygmalion: a romance in five acts. Definitive text. Ed. by L. W. Conolly. London: Metheuen Drama,
2008.
Shelley, Mary Wollstonecraft. Frankenstein; or the modern Prometheus. Ed. Maurice Hindle. New York:
Penguin Books, 2003.
Shoemaker, Martin. ‘Today, I Am Paul.’ Nebula Awards Showcase 2017. Ed. Julie Czerneda. Amherst,
NY: Pyr, 2017.
Sophocles. Oedipus The King. Tran. Stephen Berg and Diskin Clay. New York, NY: Oxford UP, 1978.
Space Odyssey. Directed by Stanley Kubrick. Performances by Keir Dullea, Gary Lockwood. Metro-
Goldwyn-Mayer, 1968.
Spomenicima ne treba verovati [Don’t Believe in Monuments]. Directed by Dušan Makavejev. 1958. YouTube
Jan 17, 2018 www.youtube.com/watch?v=c_BZPumapSk Accessed on 17 Feb 2019.
Stapledon, Olaf. Last and First Men: A Story of The Near and Far Future. New York, NY: J. Cape and
H. Smith, 1931.
Stäel, Germaine de. Le Mannequin. From: An Extraordinary Woman: Selected Writings of Germaine de Stäel.
Trans. By Vivian Folkenflik. New York, NW: Columbia UP, 1987. 325-347.
Tiptree, James Jr. [pseud. of Alice Sheldon]. ‘The Girl Who Was Plugged In.’ Her Smoke Rose Up
Forever. San Francisco, CA: Taychon Publications, 2004. 43-78.
Tomažin, Andrej. ‘Heroes, Lackeys, and Artificial Intelligence.’ Tran. by Michael Biggins. Not yet
published. April 2020. 1-8.
---. ‘Hlapci, heroji in umetna inteligenca.’ Anonimna tehnologija. Ljubljana: LUD Literatura, 2018. 17-
31.
Trumbo, Dalton. Johnny Got His Gun. New York, NY: Monogram Pub, 1939.
Twain, Mark [Samuel Clemens]. ‘Three Thousand Years among the Microbes.’ Which Was the Dream?
and Other Symbolic Writing of the Later Years. Ed. John S. Tuckey. Berkeley, CA: U of California
P, 1966.
Vigand, Philippe and Stéphane Vigand. Only the Eyes Say Yes: A Love Story. [Putain de silence.] No
translator given. New York, NY: Arcade Publishing, 1999.
448
Villiers de l’Isle-Adam, Auguste. L'Ève Future. Paris: Charpentier, 1891.
Wells, H. G. The Island of Dr. Moreau: A critical edition, with an introduction and appendices. Jefferson, NC:
McFarland, 1996.
Zola, Émile. Thérèse Raquin. Glasgow: U of Glasgow French and German Publications, 1990.
‘2 Charge ‘Jealous’ Doctor Killed ‘Test-Tube Baby.’’ New York Times July 18, 1978: B9
‘Academy Statement on ‘Test Tube Babies.’’ New York Times May 10, 1934. P. 9.
www.nytimes.com/1934/05/10/archives/academy-statement-on-test-tube-babies-
physicians-warn-that-problem.html Accessed on 11 Jul 2019.
Acosta Alvarado, Paola Andrea, Daniel Rivas-Ramírez. ‘A Milestone in Environmental and Future
Generations’ Right Protection: Recent Legal Developments before the Colombian Supreme
Court.’ Journal of Environmental Law 30/3 (2018): 512-26.
Adiwardana, Daniel, and Thang Luong. ‘Towards a Conversational Agent that Can Chat About …
Anything.’ AI Google Blog Jan 28, 2020 ai.googleblog.com/2020/01/towards-conversational-
agent-that-can.html Accessed on 3 Feb 2020.
Adams, Tim. ‘The charge of the chatbots: how do you tell who’s human online?’ The Guardian Nov
18, 2018 www.theguardian.com/technology/2018/nov/18/how-can-you-tell-who-is-
human-online-chatbots Accessed on 20 Feb 2020.
Adler, Alexa. ‘Japan Uses Robots in Nursing Home Care; An Example for America?’ Medill Reports
Chicago Feb 27, 2018 news.medill.northwestern.edu/chicago/japan-uses-robots-in-nursing-
home-care-an-example-for-america/ Accessed on 1 Feb 2019.
Agamben, Giorgio. The Man and the Open. Ed. Werner Hamacher. Tran. Kevin Atell. Stanford, CA:
Stanford UP, 2004.
Ahmad, Ferhaan. ‘Anencephalic Infants as Organ Donors: Beware of the Slippery Slope.’ Canadian
Medical Association Journal 146/2 (1992): 236-244.
Airbib, Michael A. ‘Mirror systems: evolving imitation and the bridge from praxis to language.’ The
Oxford Handbook of Language Evolution. Eds. Kathleen R. Gibson, Maggie Tallerman. Oxford:
Oxford UP, 2012. 208-215.
449
Akbari, Hassan, Bahar Khaligginejad, Jose L. Herrero, Ashesh D. Mehta, and Nima Mesgarani.
‘Towards reconstructing intelligible speech from the human auditory cortex.’ Scientific Reports
9/874 (2019). doi.org/10.1038/s41598-018-37359-z
Almeling, Rene. ‘The business of egg and sperm donation.’ Contexts (Fall 2017): 68-70.
Alvarez Manninen, Berta. ‘Are human embryos Kantian persons?; Kantian considerations in favor
of embryonic stem cell research.’ Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 3/4 (2008): 1-6.
American Psychiatric Association. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM-5). 5th
edition. Arlington, VA: American Psychiatric Association.
dsm.psychiatryonline.org/doi/book/10.1176/appi.books.9780890425596 Accessed on 9
Nov 2018.
Aoun, Joseph. Robot-Proof: Higher Education in the Age of Artificial Intelligence. Cambridge, MA: MIT P,
2017.
Appleby, John B., and Annelien L. Bredenoord. ‘Should the 14-day rule for embryo research
become the 28-day rule?’ EMBO Molecular Medicine 10/9 (2018): 9437.
Araoz, Manuel. ‘OpenAI GPT-3 might be the biggest thing since bitcoin.’ Manuel Araoz, Personal
Webpage. Jul 18, 2020 maraoz.com/2020/07/18/openai-gpt3/ Accessed on 18 Aug 2020.
Aristotle. Generation of Animals. Tran. A. L. Peck. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1943.
‘Artificial.’ American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 2018.
AHDictionary.com Accessed on 15 Jul 2019.
Aquinas, Thomas. Summa Theologica. Ed. Kevin Knight. Trans. Fathers of the English Dominican
Province, 1920. Second and revised edition. www.newadvent.org/summa/ Accessed on May
6, 2020.
Athanasiadis, Apostolos P., Aikaterini Karavida, Sergios Tzitzimikas, Dimitrios Vavilis, Grigoris
Grimbizis, Basil C. Tarlatzis, John Bontis. ‘Fetal Reduction in A Nontuplet Pregnancy:
Technical and Ethical Considerations.’ European Journal of Obstetrics and Gynecology and
Reproductive Biology 120 (2005): 227-229.
450
Ball, Philip. How to Grow a Human: Adventures in How We Are Made and Who We Are. Chicago,
IL: U of Chicago P, 2019.
---. Unnatural: The Heretical Idea of Making People. London: Bodley Head, 2011.
Baird, Gillian, Hannah Rose Douglas, and M Stephen Murphy. ‘Recognising and diagnosing autism
in children and young people: summary of NICE guidance.’ British Medical Journal 343 (2011):
900-905.
Balon, Richard. ‘Controversies in the Diagnosis and Treatment of Paraphilias.’ Journal of Sex and
Marital Therapy 39/1 (2013): 7-20.
Banks, Eric. ‘Return to Fantasy Island. An Embattled Scholar Still Champions His Dream
Experiment in Language Formation.’ Chronicle of Higher Education May 23, 2008. 54/37
(2008): B7-B10.
‘Barbarian.’ American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 2018.
AHDictionary.com Accessed on 15 Aug 2018.
‘Barbarism.’ American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 2018.
AHDictionary.com Accessed on 15 Aug 2018.
Batt, Sarah. ‘Human attitudes towards animals in relation to species similarity to humans: a
multivariate approach.’ Bioscience Horizons 2/2 (2009): 180-90.
Baudrillard, Jean. ‘The Final Solution: Cloning Beyond the Human and Inhuman.’ The Vital Illusion.
Ed. Julia Witwer. New York, NY: Columbia UP, 2000. 1-30.
Beale, Thomas. The Natural History of the Sperm Whale. London: J. Van Voorst, 1839.
Beech, Anthony R., and Leigh Harkins. ‘DSM-IV paraphilia: Descriptions, demographics and
treatment interventions.’ Agression and Violent Behavior 17/6 (2012): 527-539.
Beer, Gillian. Darwin’s Plots: Evolutionary Narrative in Darwin, George Eliot, and Nineteenth-century Fiction,
London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1983. 176-177.
Begoña Valero Ciscar, Maria. ‘Verification Report.’ Ivi. June 6, 2018. ivi-fertility.com/wp-
content/uploads/sites/12/2018/11/Resultado-2017_EN.pdf Accessed on 25 June 2019.
Beguš, Gašper. ‘CiwGAN and fiwGAN: Modeling lexical learning from raw acoustic data in
Generative Adversarial Phonology.’ PsyArXiv Apr 21, 2020. Accessed on 21 May 2020.
451
---. ‘Generative Adversarial Phonology: Modeling Unsupervised Allophonic Learning with Neural
Networks.’ Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence. May 19, 2020
www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/frai.2020.00044/abstract Accessed on 20 May 2020.
Benedikter, R., and K. Siepmann. ‘‘Transhumanism’: A New Global Political Trend?’ Challenge 59
(2016): 47-59.
Benjamin, Walter. ‘The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction’. Illuminations. Ed.
Hannah Arendt. Tran. Harry Zohn from the 1935 essay. New York, NY: Schocken Books,
1969. 1-26.
Benson, Carol B., and Peter M. Doubilet. ‘The History of Imaging in Obstetrics.’ Radiology 273/2S
(2014): 92-110.
Bentham, Jeremy. An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation. Ed. James Henderson Burns,
Herbert Lionel Adolphus. London: Athlone P, 1970.
Bertolini, John. The Playwriting Self of Bernard Shaw. Carbondale, IL: Southern Illinois UP, 1991.
Bess, Michael. ‘Enhanced Humans versus ‘Normal People:’ Elusive Definitions.’ Journal of Medicine
and Philosophy 35: 641/55.
Bettini, Maurizio. The Portrait of The Lover. Tran. Laura Gibbs. Berkeley, CA: University of California
Press, 1999.
Bhalla, Jag. ‘It Is in Our Nature to Need Stories.’ Scientific American Guest Blog. May 8, 2013.
blogs.scientificamerican.com/guest-blog/it-is-in-our-nature-to-need-stories/ Accessed on 11
Jan 2020.
Bhugra, Dinesh, Dmitri Popelyuk, and Isabel McMullen. ‘Paraphilias Across Cultures: Contexts and
Controversies.’ Journal of Sex Research 47/2-3 (2010): 242-256.
Birnbaum, Michael H. Eliza, the Rogerian Therapist. 1999. California State University, Fullerton.
psych.fullerton.edu/mbirnbaum/psych101/Eliza.htm Accessed on 1 Jun 2018.
Bickerton, Derek. Language and Species. Chicago, IL: Chicago UP, 1990.
Blewitt, Emily. ‘An (Un)familiar Story: Exploring Ultrasound Poems by Contemporary British
Women Writers.’ Motherhood in Literature and Culture: Interdisciplinary Perspectives from Europe.
New York, NY: Routledge, 2018. 47-57.
Blight, Alysse. ‘David Michael Rorvik (1844-).’ Embryo Project Encyclopedia July 5, 2018.
embryo.asu.edu/pages/david-michael-rorvik-1944 Accessed on 28 Jun 2019.
Bloch, Chana. ‘My Sessions with Mark.’ Poetry Foundation Feb 13, 2013
www.poetryfoundation.org/articles/69959/my-sessions-with-mark Accessed on 30 May
452
2020.
Boas, Frantz. Tsimshian Mythology; Based on texts recorded by Henry W. Tate. 31st Annual Report of the
Bureau of American Ethnology to the Secretary of the Smithsonian Institution (1909-1910).
Washington, D.C., 1916: 29-1037.
Boellstorff, Tom. Coming of age in second life: An anthropologist explores the virtually human. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton UP, 2015. [2009.]
Boer, Anthonius de, Jan C. Oosterwijk, Catharina A.E. Rigters-Aris. ‘Determination of a Maximum
Number of Artificial Inseminations by Donor Children per Sperm Donor.’ Fertility and
Sterility 63/2 (1995): 419-421.
Bohannon, John. ‘The synthetic therapist: Some people prefer to bare their souls to computers
rather than to fellow humans.’ 250-251. Science 249/6245 (2015): 250-251.
Bołtuć, Piotr. ‘Church-Turing Lovers.’ Robot Ethics 2.0: From Autonomous Cars to Artificial Intelligence.
Eds. Patrick Lin, Keith Abney, and Ryan Jenkins. New York, NY: Oxford UP, 2017. 214-
227.
Bonnet, Jerome, Peter Yini, Monica E. Ortiz, Pakpoom Subsoontorn, and Drew Endy. ‘Amplifying
Genetic Logic Gates.’ Science 340/6132 (2013): 599-603.
Bornstein, Aaron M. ‘Is Artificial Intelligence Permanently Inscrutable? Despite new biology-like
tools, some insist interpretation is impossible.’ Nautilus 40 (2016). Sep 1, 2016
nautil.us/issue/40/learning/is-artificial-intelligence-permanently-inscrutable Accessed on 6
Sep 2018.
Bostrom, Nick and Julian Savulescu. ‘Introduction: Human Enhancement Ethics: The State of the
Debate.’ Human Enhancement. Julian Savulescu and Nick Bostrom, eds. New York: Oxford
UP, 2009. 1-22.
‘Bottles Are Mothers: Rearing of Embryos in Glass Is Aided by Hormones.’ New York Times Apr 21,
1935. Accessed on 11 Jul 2019.
Braidotti, Rosi. ‘Four Theses on Posthuman Feminism.’ Anthropocene Feminism. Ed. Richard Grusin.
Minneapolis, MN: U of Minnesota P, 2017. 21-48.
Braidotti, Rosi, and Maria Hlavajova. ‘Introduction.’ Posthuman Glossary. London: Bloomsbury
Academic, 2017. 1-14.
453
Breazeal, Cynthia, and Rodney Brooks. ‘Robot Emotions: A Functional Perspective.’ Who Needs
Emotions: The Brain Meets the Robot. Eds. J.-M. Fellous and M. Airbib. Oxford, New York, NY:
Oxford UP, 2005. 271-310.
Breazeal, Cynthia, and Rosalind Picard. ‘The Role of Emotion-Inspired Abilities in Relational
Robots.’ Neuroergonomics: The Brain at Work. Eds. Raja Parasuraman and Matthew Rizzo.
Oxford, 2006. 275-292.
Brody, Jane E. ‘Multiple Births: How to Have A Baby or Nine.’ New York Times Jun 20, 1971: E7.
Brogan, Jacob. ‘The Real Reasons You Shouldn’t Clone Your Dog.’ The Smithsonian Magazine Mar 22,
2018 www.smithsonianmag.com/science-nature/why-cloning-your-dog-so-wrong-
180968550/ Accessed on 9 Jan 2019.
Brooks, David. ‘The Nuclear Family was a Mistake.’ The Atlantic March 2020
www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2020/03/the-nuclear-family-was-a-
mistake/605536/ Accessed on 26 Feb 2020.
Brown, Jane. Goethe’s Faust: The German Tragedy. Ithaca, NY: Cornell UP, 1986.
Brown, Jennings. ‘The Last of the Iron Lungs.’ Gizmodo Nov 20, 2017 gizmodo.com/the-last-of-the-
iron-lungs-1819079169 Accessed on 1 Dec 2018.
Brown University. ‘Brain-computer interface enables people with paralysis to control tablet devices.’
ScienceDaily Nov 21, 2018. www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2 Accessed 8 Jan 2020.
Bryner, Nicholas. ‘Colombian Supreme Court Recognizes Rights of the Amazon River Ecosystem.’
International Union for Conservation of Nature Apr 20, 2018 www.iucn.org/news/world-
commission-environmental-law/201804/colombian-supreme-court-recognizes-rights-
amazon-river-ecosystem Accessed on 11 Jan 2020.
Buchanan, A., D. Brock, N. Daniels and D. Wikler, From Chance to Choice: Genetics and Justice.
Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2000.
Buckley, Jennifer. ‘Talking machines. Shaw, Phonography, and Pygmalion.’ Shaw 35/1 (2015): 21-45.
Burke, Norah. ‘Could You Love a Chemical Baby? For That’s What Science Looks Like Producing
Next.’ Tid-Bits Apr 16, 1938.
‘Bushman Shares A Cage With Bronx Park Apes; Some Laugh Over His Antics, but Many Are Not
Pleased. Keeper Frees Him At Times Then, with Bow and Arrow, the Pygmy from the
Congo Takes to the Woods.’ The New York Times Sep 9, 1906
www.nytimes.com/1906/09/09/archives/bushman-shares-a-cage-with-bronx-park-apes-
some-laugh-over-his.html Accessed on 1 Aug 2020.
Buttar, Aliya. ‘Gregory Goodwin Pincus (1903-1967).’ Embryo Project Encyclopedia November 24, 2008
embryo.asu.edu/pages/gregory-goodwin-pincus-1903-1967 Accessed on 28 Jun 2019.
454
Cairns, H., R. C. Oldfield, J. B. Pennybacker, D. Whitteridge. ‘Akinetic mutism with an epidermoid
cyst of the third ventricle.’ Brain 64/273 (1941): 90.
Canguilhem, Georges. Knowledge of life. [La Connaisance de la Vie.] Paola Marrati, Todd Meyers. New
York, NY: Fordham UP, 2018.
Carley, John, ed. The Faber Book of Utopias. London: Faber & Faber, 2000.
Carstens, Pieter, and Philip Stevens. ‘Paraphilia and sex offending — A South African criminal law
perspective.’ International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 47 (2016): 93-101.
Carter-Walshaw, Sarah. ‘In Vitro Gametogenesis: The End of Egg Donation?’ Bioethics 33/1 (2018):
1-8.
Cavanagh, John R. ‘Sexual Anomalies.’ The Catholic Lawyer 9/1 (1963): 4-31.
CBS Sunday Morning. ‘Louise Brown on Growing Up the First Test Tube Baby.’ YouTube Sep 14,
2019. www.youtube.com/watch?v=YeQeNoKlcfc Accessed on 19 Jun 2019.
Chamorro-Premuzic, Tomas. ‘Virtual Love: Is Your Valentine an Avatar?’ The Guardian 9 Feb 2015
www.theguardian.com/media-network/2015/feb/09/virtual-love-valentine-day-romance-
technology Accessed on 9 Dec 2018.
Chandra, Anjani, Casey E. Copen, and Elizabeth Harvey Stephen. ‘Infertility and Impaired
Fecundity in the United States 1982-2010: Data From the National Survey of Family
Growth.’ National Health Statistics Reports 67 (2013): 1-19.
Chavannes, Edouard. Cinq cents contes et apologues: extraits du Tripitaka chinois. 3 vols. Paris: E. Leroux,
1911.
Check Hayden, Erica. ‘If DNA is like software, can we just fix the code?’ MIT Technology Review
Feb 26, 2020 www.technologyreview.com/2020/02/26/905713/dna-is-like-software-fix-
the-code-personalized-medicine/ Accessed on 7 Aug 2020.
Chen, D. Y., D. C. Wen, Y. P. Zhang, et al. ‘Interspecies implantation and mitochondria fate of
panda-rabbit cloned embryos.’ Biology of Reproduction 67/2 (2002): 637-42.
Cheok, Adrian David, Kasun Karunanayaka, and Emma Yann Zhang. ‘Lovotics: Human–Robot
Love and Sex Relationships.’ Robot Ethics 2.0: Autonomous Cars to Artificial Intelligence. Ed.
Patrick Lin, Keith Abney, Ryan Jenkins. New York, NY: Oxford UP, 2017.
Chikaraishi, Takenobu, Yuichiro Yoshikava, Kohei Ogawa, Oriza Hirata, and Hiroshi Ishiguro.
“Creation and Staging of Android Theatre ‘Sayonara’ towards Developing Highly Human-
Like Robots.” MDPI Future Internet 9/75 (2017): 1-17.
455
Chu, Andrea Long. ‘Extreme Pregnancy.’ Once and Future Feminist (Boston Review Forum). Ed. Merve
Emre. Cambridge, MA: MIT P, 2018. 66-79.
Chung, Emily, Melanie Glanz, Vik Adhopia. ‘Donor-conceived People are Tracking Down
Biological Fathers, Even If They Want to Hide.’ CBC News Jan 25, 2018
www.cbc.ca/news/technology/sperm-donor-dna-testing-1.4500517 Accessed on 21 Jul
2019.
Cisco. Cisco Annual Internet Report (2018-2023) White Paper. Updated Feb 17, 2020.
www.cisco.com/c/en/us/solutions/collateral/executive-perspectives/annual-internet-
report/white-paper-c11-741490.html Accessed on 20 Feb 2020.
Cigna’s U.S. Loneliness Index. ‘New Cigna Study Reveals Loneliness at Epidemic Levels in
America.’ May 1, 2018 www.multivu.com/players/English/8294451-cigna-us-loneliness-
survey/ Accessed 12 Feb 2019.
Clark, Andy. Natural-born Cyborgs: Minds, Technologies, and the Future of Human Intelligence. New York,
NY: Oxford UP, 2003.
Cline Horowitz, Mary Anne. ‘Aristotle and Woman.’ Journal of the History of Biology 9/2 (1976): 183-
213.
Cohen, Glenn I., George Q. Daley, and Eli Y. Adashi. ‘Disruptive Reproductive Technologies.’
Science Translational Medicine 9/372 (2017): 1-3.
Coleman, D. C. ‘Bernard Shaw and ‘Brave New World.’’ The Shaw Review 10/1 (1967): 6-8.
Collinger, Jennifer L., Brian Wodlinger, John E. Downey, et al. ‘High-performance neuroprosthetic
control by an individual with tetraplegia.’ The Lancet 381/986 (2013): 557-564.
Committee on the Health and Medical Dimensions. Social Isolation and Loneliness in Older Adults:
Opportunities for the Health Care System. A Consensus Study Report of The National Academies of
Sciences, Engineering. Washington, DC: The National Academies P, 2020.
‘Conception.’ American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 2018.
AHDictionary.com Accessed on 8 Jul 2019.
‘Conception.’ Online Etymological Dictionary. Maoning Tech. Douglas Harper, 2001-2019. Accessed on
15 Jul 2019.
Cooper, Carol. Twins and Multiple Births: The Essential Parenting Guide from Pregnancy to Adulthood.
Second revised edition. London: Vermilion, 2004.
Cooper, Henry S. F. Jr. ‘The Loneliness of The Long-duration Astronaut.’ Air and Space Magazine
11/2 (1996): 36-45.
456
‘Conceived to Save Her Sister, a Child Is Born.’ New York Times Apr 7, 1990.
www.nytimes.com/1990/04/07/us/conceived-to-save-her-sister-a-child-is-born.html
Accessed on 1 Feb 2019.
Cosslett, Rhiannon Lucy. ‘The novel is dead – again. And this time it’s women who have murdered
it.’ The Guardian Jul 10, 2020. www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2020/jul/10/novel-
dead-again-women-murdered-it-sally-rooney Accessed on 13 Jul 2020.
Cox, Patrick, and Katy Clark. ‘A linguistic island experiment.’ PRI Apr 24, 2009
www.pri.org/stories/2009-04-24/linguistic-island-experiment Accessed on 8 Nov 2019.
Craig, Hugh, and Brett Greatley-Hirsch. Style, Computers, and Early Modern Drama: Beyond Authorship.
Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2017.
Crew, F. A. E., C. D. Darling, J. B. S. Haldane, et al. ‘Social Biology and Population Improvement.’
Nature 144 (1939): 521-22. www.nature.com/articles/144521a0 Accessed on 8 Jun 2020.
Crowe, Christine. ‘Whose Mind Over Whose Matter?’ New Reproductive Technologies. Eds. Maureen
McNeil, Ian Varcoe, and Steven Yearley. London: The Macmillan P, 1990. 27-57.
Cunningham, Katie. ‘Jessie Tu: ‘I will probably never read another novel by a straight white male.’
The Guardian Jul 1, 2020 www.theguardian.com/books/2020/jul/01/jessie-tu-when-you-
dont-see-yourself-on-the-page-you-literally-dont-exist Accessed on 13 Jul 2020.
---. ‘Sperm Banking History: An Excerpt from Sperm Banking: A Reproductive Resource by Sonia Fader.”
2019. www.cryobank.com/learning-center/sperm-banking-101/sperm-banking-history/
Accessed on 20 Jul 2019.
Cyranoski, David. ‘Woman is first to receive cornea from ‘reprogrammed’ stem cells.’ Nature Sep 2,
2019 www.nature.com/articles/d41586-019-02597-2 Accessed on 8 Jun 2020.
Dahaner, John. ‘Should We Be Thinking about Robot Sex?’ Eds. John Dahaner and Neil McArthur.
Robot Sex: Social and Ethical Implications. Cambridge, MA: The MIT P, 2017. 47-69.
Dahaner, John, Brian Earp, and Anders Sandberg. ‘Should We Campaign Against Sex Robots?’ Eds.
John Dahaner and Neil McArthur. Robot Sex: Social and Ethical Implications. Cambridge, MA:
The MIT P, 2017. 47-71.
457
Darling, Kate. ‘“Who’s Johnny?” Anthropomorphic Framing in Human-Robot Interaction,
Integration, and Policy.’ Robot Ethics 2.0: From Autonomous Cars to Artificial Intelligence. Eds.
Patrick Lin, Keith Abney, and Ryan Jenkins. New York, NY: Oxford UP, 2017. 173-188.
Darwin, Charles. On the Origin of Species; or, The Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life.
London: J. Murray, 1861.
---. The Descent of Man, and Selection in Relation to Sex. London: Murray, 1871.
Davids, C. A. F. Rhys, Anton von Scheifner, W. R. S. Ralston, eds. The Bible of Tibet: Tibetan tales from
Indian sources. London, New York: Kegan Paul and Columbia UP, 2003.
Davis, Deena. Genetic Dilemmas: Reproductive Technology, Parental Choices, and Children’s Futures. 2nd ed.
Oxford, NY: Oxford UP, 2010.
Degener, Almuth, ed. and tran. Das Kathināvadāna. Bonn: Indica et Tibetica Verlag, 1990.
Deglicerti, A., G.F. Croft, L.N. Pietila, M. Zernicka-Goetz, E.d. Siggia, A.h. Brivanlou. ‘Self-
organization of the in vitro attached human embryo.’ Nature 533 (2016): 251-254.
Deleuze, Gilles. ‘Desert Islands.’ Desert Islands and Other Texts (1953-1974). Ed. David Lapoujade.
Tran. Michael Taormina. Cambridge, MA: MIT P, 2004. 9-14.
---. ‘Causes et raisons des îles désertes.’ L’île déserte et autres textes. 1953-1974. Ed. David Lapoujade.
Paris: Les Éditions de Minuit, 2002. 11-17.
De Los Angeles, A., N. Pho, DE Redmond, Jr. ‘Generating Human Organs via Interspecies
Chimera Formation: Advances and Barriers.’ Yale Journal of Biology and Medicine 91/3 (2018):
333-342.
Delvaux, Mary. Draft Report: With Recommendations to the Commission on Civil Law Rules on Robotics;
2015/2103(INL). European Parliament: Committee on Legal Affairs. May 31, 2016. 1-22.
www.europarl.europa.eu/sides/getDoc.do?pubRef=-
//EP//NONSGML%2BCOMPARL%2BPE-
582.443%2B01%2BDOC%2BPDF%2BV0//EN Accessed on 18 Jan 2019.
Desai, Nina N., Jessica Goldstein, Douglas Y. Rowland, and James M. Goldfarb. ‘Morphological
evaluation of human embryos and derivation of an embryo quality scoring system specific
for day 3 embryos: a preliminary study.’ Human Reproduction 15/10 (2000): 2190–2196.
Deutsch, David. ‘Quantum Theory, the Church-Turing Principle and the Universal Quantum
Computer.’ Proceedings of the Royal Society (1985): 97–117.
Diamond, Judy, and Charles Wood. Foreword to A Planet of Viruses, by Carl Zimmer. Chicago: U of
Chicago P, 2011.
458
Dimock, WaiChee. ‘Threat Assessment.’ Artforum May/June 2020
www.artforum.com/print/202005/wai-chee-dimock-on-living-with-risk-82815 Accessed on
11 Jun 2020.
Dolar, Mladen. A Voice and Nothing More. Cambridge, MA: MIT P, 2006.
Dschi, Hiän Lin. “Parallelversionen zur tocharischen Rezension des Puṇyavanta-Jātaka.” Zeitschrift
der Deutschen Morgenländischen Gesselschaft 22/2 (1943): 284-324.
Donald, Merlin. ‘The mimetic origins of language.’ The Oxford Handbook of Language Evolution. Eds.
Kathleen R. Gibson, Maggie Tallerman. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2012. 180-184.
Dudzinski, Denise. ‘The Diving Bell Meets the Butterfly: Identity Lost and Re-membered.’ Theoretical
Medicine 22 (2001): 33-46.
Eastlake, Lady Elizabeth Rigby, ed. Life of John Gibson, R.A., Sculptor. London: Longmans Green and
Co., 1870.
Eber, Hailey. ‘This L.A. Sperm Bank Is More Exclusive Than an Ivy League College.’ LA Magazine
Apr 2, 2019 www.lamag.com/citythinkblog/sperm-bank-california-cryobank/ Accessed on
21 Jul 2019.
Edwards, J. H., Tessa Dent, and Jacob Kahn. ‘Monozygotic Twins of Different Sex.’ Journal of
Medical Genetics 3 (1966): 117-123.
Edwards, Monica, Laurie Abadie. ‘NASA Twins Study Confirms Preliminary Findings.’ NASA Jan
31, 2018. www.nasa.gov/feature/nasa-twins-study-confirms-preliminary-findings Accessed
on 31 Jan 2019.
Elliott, Anthony, and Julie Hare. ‘Will talking to AI voice assistants re-engineer our human
conversations?’ The Conversation Jan 14, 2019 theconversation.com/will-talking-to-ai-voice-
assistants-re-engineer-our-human-conversations-108922 Accessed on 20 Feb 2020.
Ellis, Alexander John. On early English pronunciation: With especial reference to Shakspere and Chaucer […].
Part I. London, Asher & Co., 1869.
Ellis, Havelock. Sexual Selection in Man: Touch. Smell. Hearing. Vision. Philadelphia, PA: D. A. Davis
Company, 1905.
459
Embury-Dennis, Tom. ‘Elon Musk Predicts Human Language Will Be Obsolete in as Little as Five
Years: ‘We Could Still Do It For Sentimental Reasons.’’ The Independent May 9, 2020.
www.independent.co.uk/life-style/gadgets-and-tech/news/elon-musk-joe-rogan-podcast-
language-neuralink-grimes-baby-a9506451.html Accessed on 9 May 2020.
Emre, Merve. ‘On Reproduction.’ Once and Future Feminist (Boston Review Forum). Ed. Merve Emre.
Cambridge, MA: MIT P, 2018. 7-32.
Engber, Daniel. ‘The Neurologist Who Hacked His Brain—And Almost Lost His Mind.’ Wired Jan
26, 2016 www.wired.com/2016/01/phil-kennedy-mind-control-computer/ Accessed on 13
Jul 2020.
Ergin, Rahime Nida, Aslihan Polat Bülent Kars, Deniz Ötekin, et al. ‘Social stigma and familial
attitudes related to infertility.’ Turkish Journal of Obstetrics and Gynecology 15/1 (2018): 46-49.
Eulenburg, Albert. Sexuale Neuropathie: Genitale Neurosen und Neuropsychosen der Männer und Frauen.
Leipzig: Verlag von F. C. W. Vogel, 1895.
Evans, Arthur B., Istvan Csicsery-Ronay Jr., Joan Gordon, Veronica Hollinger, Rob Latham, and
Carol McGuirk, eds. ‘Introduction.’ The Wesleyan Anthology of Science Fiction. Middletown, CN:
Wesleyan UP, 2010. Xi-xviii.
Facchin, Federica, Barbara Giussy, Vittorio Cigoli. ‘Sex Robots: The Irreplaceable Value of
Humanity.’ British Medical Journal 358 (2017): 3790.
Fallon, Jimmy. ‘Tonight Showbotics: Jimmy Meets Sophia the Human-Like Robot.’ The Tonight Show
Starring Jimmy Fallon. YouTube Apr 25, 2017.
www.youtube.com/watch?time_continue=2&v=Bg_tJvCA8zw Accessed on 8 Aug 2018.
‘Fancomi Anemia; IVF, PGD used to produce sibling stem-cell donor.’ OBGYN & Reproduction
Week (2004): 19.
Fanon, Frantz. Black Skin, White Masks. Tran. Charles Lam Markmann. London: Pluto P, 1986.
Farsides, Bobbie. ‘The informational needs of prospective parents: An ethical perspective.’ Regulation
Reproductive Donation. Eds. Susan Golombok, Rosamund Scott, John B. Appleby, Martin
Richards, Stephen Wilkinson. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge UP, 2016. 352-372.
Fauser, Bart, and Paul Devroey. Baby-Making: What the New Reproductive Treatments Mean for Families
and Society. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2011.
Fauser, Bart, Paul Devroey, and Nick S. Maclon. ‘Multiple birth resulting from ovarian stimulation
for subfertility treatment.’ The Lancet 356/9473 (2005): 1807-16.
Feder, Philip. ‘Med School Doctor Attack Fetal Research Ban.’ The Stanford Daily 164/16 (1973): 1.
460
Fernández-Arias, A., J. L. Alabart, et al. ‘Interspecies Pregnancy of Spanish Ibex (Capra Pyrenaica)
Fetus in Domestic Goat (Capra Hircus) Recipients Induces Abnormally High Plasmatic
Levels of Pregnancy-Associated Glycoprotein.’ Theriogenology 51/8 (1999): 1419-30.
Ferreira, Aline. ‘The Sexual Politics of Ectogenesis in the To-day and To-morrow Series.’
Interdisciplinary Science Reviews 34/1 (2009): 32-55.
Fetters, Ashley. ‘Finding the Lost Generation of Sperm Donors.’ The Atlantic May 18, 2018.
www.theatlantic.com/family/archive/2018/05/sperm-donation-anonymous/560588/
Accessed on 21 Jul 2019.
---. ‘The Overlooked Emotions of Sperm Donation.’ The Atlantic Jul 9, 2018
www.theatlantic.com/family/archive/2018/07/sperm-donations-emotional-
consequences/564587/ Accessed on 21 Jul 2019.
Firestone, Shulamith. The Dialectic of Sex: The Case for Feminist Revolution. New York, NY: Bantam
Books, 1970.
‘First baby for mum born of IVF.’ BioNews 18. Jul 26, 1999 www.bionews.org.uk/page_87917
Accessed on 25 Jul 2019.
Fitzpatrick, Kathleen. ‘Becoming Human.’ Kathleen Fitzpatrick’s Blog. Jan 11, 2020.
kfitz.info/becoming-human/ Accessed 13 Jan 2020.
Fjermedal, Grant. The Tomorrow Makers: A Brave New World of Living-Brain Machines. Redmond, WA:
Tempus Books of Microsoft P, 1987.
Flood, Alison. ‘Plagiarism, ‘book-stuffing’, clickfarms … the rotten side of self-publishing.’ The
Guardian Mar 28, 2019 www.theguardian.com/books/2019/mar/28/plagiarism-book-
stuffing-clickfarms-the-rotten-side-of-self-publishing Accessed on 4 Feb 2020.
---. ‘What Not: lost feminist novel that anticipated Brave New World finally finds its time.’ The
Guardian Dec 10, 2018 www.theguardian.com/books/2018/dec/10/what-not-lost-feminist-
novel-that-anticipated-brave-new-world-finally-finds-its-time Accessed on 18 Nov 2019.
Foucault, Michel. ‘Des espaces autres. Hétérotopies.’ Conférence au Cercle d’études architecturales (1967)
in Architecture, Mouvement, Continuité 5 (1984): 46-49.
---. ‘Of Other Spaces: Utopias and Heterotopias.’ Rethinking architecture: a reader in cultural theory. Ed.
Neil Leach. Tran. not given. London: Routledge, 1997. 349-367.
‘Frankenstein: Freak events that gave birth to a masterpiece.’ BBC May 19, 2016
www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/articles/3rvWSR2rhndMTylClzGzTDy/frankenstein-freak-
events-that-gave-birth-to-a-masterpiece Accessed on 16 May 2020.
461
Franklin, Sarah. Biological Relatives: IVF, Stem Cells, and the Future of Kinship. Durham, NC: Duke UP,
2013.
---. ‘Postmodern Procreation: A Cultural Account of Assisted Reproduction.’ Conceiving the New
World Order: The Global Politics of Reproduction. Eds. Faye D. Ginsburg and Rayna Rapp.
Berkeley, CA: U of California P, 1995. 323-345.
Frazer, Liz. Problematizing Ultrasound: Cyborg Babies and Midwifery Care. Ppt. Ryerson University. Sep 22,
2012. Accessed on 14 Feb 2020.
Fricker, Martin. ‘Grand daddy: Sperm donor scientist may have fathered 1,000 babies at clinic he
ran.’ Mirror Apr 8, 2012. www.mirror.co.uk/news/uk-news/sperm-donor-may-have-
fathered-1000-babies-784615 Accessed on 20 Jul 2019.
Frobenius, Léo. Volksmärchen der Kabylen. Vol. I/III. E. Diederichs: Jena, 1921.
Fukuyama, Francis. ‘Transhumanism.’ Foreign Policy October 23, 2009 Accessed on 23 March 2018.
Furr, Allen, Mark A. Hardy, Juan P. Barret, and John H. Barker. ‘Surgical, ethical, and psychosocial
considerations in human head transplantation.’ International Journal of Surgery 41 (2017): 190-
195.
‘Future Generations v. Ministry of the Environment and Others: Demanda Generaciones Futuras v.
Miniambiente.’ Climate Case Chart 2018 climatecasechart.com/non-us-case/future-
generation-v-ministry-environment-others/ Accessed on 4 Feb 2020.
Gabbett, Michael T., Johanna Laporte, Renuka Sukar, et al. ‘Molecular Support for Heterogenesis
Resulting in Sesquizygotic Twins.’ The New England Journal of Medicine 380/9 (2019): 842-849.
Galarneau, Charlotte, “Many ‘Ways of Looking’: Physician Refusal of Embryo Transfer. Harvard
Medical School Bioethics Journal Summer 2019. bioethicsjournal.hms.harvard.edu/summer-
2019/many-“ways-looking”-physician-refusal-embryo-transfer Accessed on 13 Sep 2019.
Gernsback, Hugo. ‘The Future: Electronic Mating.’ Sexology 30/7 (1964): 452-55.
Ghiselin, Michael T. ‘Natural Kinds and Supraorganismal Individuals.’ Folkbiology. Ed. Douglas L.
Medin and Scott Atran. Cambridge, MA: MIT P, 1999. 447-60.
Gibbons, Amy. ‘Bonobos Join Chimps as Closest Human Relatives.’ Science Magazine Jun 13, 2012
www.sciencemag.org/news/2012/06/bonobos-join-chimps-closest-human-relatives
Accessed on 8 Nov 2019.
Gibson, Kathleen R. ‘Are other animals as smart as great apes? Do others provide better models for
the evolution of speech or language?’ The Oxford Handbook of Language Evolution. Eds.
Kathleen R. Gibson, Maggie Tallerman. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2012. 120-130.
462
---. ‘Language or protolanguage? A review of the ape language literature.’ The Oxford Handbook of
Language Evolution. Eds. Kathleen R. Gibson, Maggie Tallerman. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2012.
41-58.
Giles, Martin. The GANfather: The man who’s given machines the gift of imagination.’ MIT
Technology Review Feb 21, 2018 www.technologyreview.com/2018/02/21/145289/the-
ganfather-the-man-whos-given-machines-the-gift-of-imagination/ Accessed on 3 Dec 2019.
Gleicher, Norbert, Andrea Weghofer, and David Barad. ‘Too old for IVF: are we discriminating
against older women?’ Journal of Assisted Reproductive Genetics 24/12 (2007): 639-44.
Goddard, Joanna. ‘The One Thing That Surprised Me About Choosing a Sperm Donor.’ A Cup of
Jo: Motherhood Series. Nov 13, 2017 cupofjo.com/2017/11/choosing-a-sperm-donor/
Accessed on 21 Jul 2019.
Goering, Sara, Eran Klein, Darin D. Dougherty, and Alik S. Widge. ‘Staying in the Loop: Relational
Agency and Identity in Next-Generation DBS for Psychiatry.’ AJOB Neuroscience 8/2 (2017):
58-70.
Goering, Sara and Rafael Yuste. ‘On the Necessity of Ethical Guidelines for Novel
Neurotechnologies.’ Cell 167 (2016): 882-885.
Goertzel, Ben, Julia Mossbridge, Eddie Monroe, David Hanson, and Gino Yu. Loving AI: Humanoid
Robots as Agents of Human Consciousness Expansion (summary of early research progress). Sep 25,
2017. 1-16.
Gopnik, Adam. ‘Can Science Explain Why We Tell Stories?’ The New Yorker May 12, 2012.
www.newyorker.com/books/page-turner/can-science-explain-why-we-tell-stories Accessed
on 11 Jan 2020.
Gosden, Roger. Designing Babies: The Brave New World of Reproductive Technology. New York, NY: W. H.
Freeman, 1999.
Gosseries, Olivia, Marie-Aurélie Bruno, Audrey Vanhaudenhuyse, Steven Laureys, and Caroline
Schnakers. ‘Consciousness in the Locked-In Syndrome.’ The Neurology of Consciousness:
Cognitive Neuroscience and Neuropathology. Eds. Steven Laureys and Giulio Tononi.
Amsterdam, Boston, MA: Elsevier Academic P, 2009. 191-203.
Graham, Elaine L. Representations of the Post/Human: Monsters, Aliens, and Others in Popular Culture. New
Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers UP, 2002.
463
Grant, Richard. ‘Do Trees Talk to Each Other?’ Smithsonian Magazine March 2018
www.smithsonianmag.com/science-nature/the-whispering-trees-180968084/ Accessed on
16 May 2020.
Griffith, Chris. ‘Your New Friend is a Humanoid Robot.’ The Australian Oct 26, 2017. Par. 1-38.
www.theaustralian.com.au/life/say-hello-to-your-new-friend-sophia-the-humanoid-
robot/news-story/070299a8d11b7d636848f1b8dd753530 Accessed on 2 Jun 2018.
Guthrie, Stewart. Faces in the Clouds: A New Theory of Religion. New York, NY: Oxford UP, 1993.
Gwern. “Turns out you can ask GPT-w to pretend to be a poetry-writing AI, and it will do so and
even provide helpful commentaries explaining the AI’s poems to you. / Also, it’s happy to
write poetry about the Singularity.” Jun 20, 2020 1: 19PM Tweet.
twitter.com/gwern/status/1274436814535888896
Haan, Joost. ‘Locked-in: The syndrome as depicted in literature.’ Progress in Brain Research (2013): 19-
34.
Haas, Benjamin. ‘Chinese man ‘married’ robot he built himself.’ The Guardian April 4, 2017
www.theguardian.com/world/2017/apr/04/chinese-man-marries-robot-built-himself
Accessed on 12 Feb 2019.
Haldane, Charlotte. ‘Brave New World: A Novel.’ Nature 129/3260 (1932): 597-598.
Haldane, J. B. S. Daedalus: or Science of the future: A paper read to the Heretics, Cambridge, on February 4,
1923. London: K. Paul, Trench, Trubner, 1924.
Hall, Delaney. ‘The Eliza Effect.’ 99 Percent Invisible December 10, 2019.
99percentinvisible.org/episode/the-eliza-effect/ Accessed 8 Jan 2020.
Hall, Stephen S. ‘A New Last Change: There could soon be a baby-boom among women who
thought they’d hit an IVF dead end.’ The Cut Sep 18, 2017 www.thecut.com/2017/09/ivf-
abnormal-embryos-new-last-chance.html Accessed on 18 Nov 2018.
Hall, Stuart. ‘Encoding, decoding.’ The Cultural Studies Reader. Ed. by S. During. New York, NY:
Routledge, 1993. 90–103.
Hamilton, Melissa. ‘Adjudicating Sex Crimes as Mental Disease.’ Pace Law Review 33/2 (2013): 536-
599.
Hanevik, Hans Ivar, Dag O. Hessen, Arne Sunde, and Jarle Breivik. ‘Can IVF influence human
evolution?’ Human Reproduction 31/7 (2016): 1397-1402.
Hankins, Thomas and Robert J. Silverman. ‘Vox Mechanica: The History of Speaking Machines.’
Chapter 8. Instruments and the Imagination. Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP, 2014. 178-220.
Hannan, Sarah. ‘Why Childhood is Bad for Children.’ Journal of Applied Philosophy 35/1 (2018): 11-28.
464
Hansen, Michèle, Jennifer J. Kurinczuk, Carol Bower, and Sandra Webb. ‘The Risk of Major Birth
Defects after Intracytoplasmic Sperm Injection and in Vitro Fertilization.’ The New England
Journal of Medicine 346/10 (2002): 725-30.
Hanson Robotics. ‘About Me.’ Sophia. Hanson Robotics 2017. sophiabot.com/aboutme Accessed
on 8 Aug 2018.
---. ‘Could You Fall in Love with This Robot?’ Sophia. Hanson Robotics 2017.
sophiabot.com/could-you-fall-in-love-with-this-robot Accessed on 8 Aug 2018.
Harari, Yuval Noah. Homo Deus: A Brief History of Tomorrow. Tran. by the author. New York, NY:
Harper, 2017.
Haraway, Donna J. Simians, Cyborgs, and Women: The Reinvention of Nature. New York, NY: Routledge,
1991.
---. Staying with the Trouble: Making Kin in the Chthulucene. Durham, NC: Duke UP, 2016.
Harvard University Embryonic Stem Cell Research Oversight Committee. ‘Ethical Issues Related to
the Creation of Synthetic Human Embryos.’ April 26, 2017
petrieflom.law.harvard.edu/assets/publications/Harvard_ESCRO_Report_on_Synthetic_H
uman_Embryos.pdf Accessed on 2 May 2020.
Haslam, Michael T. ‘Psycho-sexual Disorders and Their Treatment. Part III: Sexual Deviation.’
Current Medical Research and Opinion 3/10 (2008): 726-735.
Hassold, T., M. Merrill, K. Adkins, S. Freeman, S. Sherman. ‘Recombination and Maternal Age-
dependent Nondisjunction: Molecular Studies of Trisomy 16.’ American Journal of Human
Genetics 57/4 (1995): 867-74.
Hayles, N. Katherine. Chaos Bound: Orderly Disorder in Contemporary Literature and Science. Ithaca, NY:
Cornell UP, 1990.
---. How We Became Posthuman? Virtual Bodies in Cybernetics, Literature and Informatics. Chicago, IL: U of
Chicago P, 1999.
---. My Mother Was a Computer: Digital Subjects and Literary Texts. Chicago: Chicago UP, 2005.
Haynes, Amanda. ‘New e-Estonia factsheet: National AI ‘Kratt’ Strategy.’ E-Estonia June 2020. e-
estonia.com/new-e-estonia-factsheet-national-ai-kratt-strategy/ Accessed on 29 Jun 2020.
465
Hauser, CJ. ‘‘This is small talk purgatory:’ what Tinder taught me about love.’ The Guardian Dec 7,
2019 www.theguardian.com/lifeandstyle/2019/dec/07/small-talk-purgatory-what-tinder-
taught-me-about-love?fbclid=IwAR34iwRY5dG5egVLwx5jjizb6R-
9wIquRsxzCTWQlN_v8ipLD2dmnO7bAV0 Accessed on 8 Nov 2020.
Hauser, Marc and Nathan Wolfe. ‘Review: Language Comprehension in Ape and Child (Monograph
no. 233) by E. Sue Savage-Rumbaugh, J. Murphy, R. A. Sevcik, K. E. Brakke, S. L. Williams
and D. M. Rumbaugh.’ American Anthropologist (New Series) 96/3 (1994): 745-747.
Hawkes, David. ‘Sodomy, usury, and the narrative of Shakespeare’s Sonnets.’ Renaissance Studies 14/3
(2000): 344-361.
Henderson, Andrea. Romantic identities: Varieties of Subjectivity, 1774-1830. Cambridge: Cambridge UP,
1996.
Henrix, Howard V. ‘Baby’s Next Step: Überkinder and the Burden of the Future.’ Nursery Realms:
Children in the Worlds of Science Fiction, Fantasy, and Horror. Eds. Gary Westfahl and George
Edgar Slusser. Athens, GA: U of Georgia P, 1999. 100-110.
Henry, Joseph. The Papers of Joseph Henry. Vol. 6. January 1844-December 1846: the Princeton years. Edited
by Marc Rothenberg, Kathleen W. Dorman, John C. Rumm and Paul H. Theerman.
Washington: Smithsonian Institution P, 1992.
Hersey, George L. Falling in Love with Statues: Artificial Humans from Pygmalion To The Present. Chicago:
The University of Chicago Press, 2009.
Hicks, Heather. ‘“Whatever It Is That She’s Since Become:” Writing Bodies of Text and Bodies of
Women in James Tiptree, Jr.’s “The Girl Who Was Plugged In” and William Gibson’s “The
Winter Market.”’ Contemporary Literature 37/1 (1996): 70-73.
Hofinger, Marcel. Légendes des anciens (Sthavirāvadāna). Vol. 1 of Le congrès du lac Anavapta, (vies de saints
bouddhiques): extraits du Vinaya de Mūlasarvāstivādin Bhaisajyavastu. 2nd edition. Louvain-La-
Neuve: Université catholique de Louvain, Institut orientaliste, 1990.
Hofstadter, Douglas. Fluid Concepts and Creative Analogies: Computer Models of the Fundamental
Mechanisms of Thought. New York, NY: Basic Books, 1996.
Hofstadter, Douglas and David Moser. ‘To Err is Human; To Study Error-Making is Cognitive
Science.’ Michigan Quarterly Review 82/3 (1989): 185-215.
Hogan, Jordan. ‘AI Dungeon game made in Utah uses AI to take you on adventure.’ Dec 29, 2019
fox13now.com/2019/12/29/ai-dungeon-game-made-in-utah-uses-ai-to-take-you-on-an-
adventure/ Accessed on 4 Feb 2020.
Hold-Lunstad, J., T.B. Smith, M. Baker, T. Harris, D. Stephenson. ‘Loneliness and social isolation as
risk factors for mortality: a meta-analytic review.’ Perspectives on Psychological Science 10/2
(2015): 227-237.
466
Holmes, Ronald M. The Sex Offender and the Criminal Justice System. Springfield, IL: C. C. Thomas,
1983.
Holmes, Stephen T. and Ronald M. Holmes. Sex Crimes: Patterns and Behavior. 3rd edition. CA: SAGE
Publications, 2009.
‘How to Care for Your Pet Rock.’ Wiki How www.wikihow.com/Care-for-Your-Pet-Rock Accessed
on 26 Dec 2018.
Hubback, David. ‘Julian Huxley and Eugenics.’ Evolutionary Studies: A Centenary Celebration of the Life of
Julian Huxley. Eds. W. Milo Keynes and G. A. Hartman. London: The Macmillan P, 1989.
194-206.
Huling, Ryan. ‘Maps Are Biased Against Animals.’ Wired Jan 21, 2020.
www.wired.com/story/opinion-maps-are-biased-against-animals/ Accessed on 27 Jan 2020.
Hulme, Peter and William H. Sherman. ‘Preface.’ ‘The Tempest’ and Its Travels. Philadelphia, PA: U of
Pennsylvania P, 2000.
Hurlbut, Benjamin J. Experiments in Democracy: Human Embryo Research and the Politics of Bioethics. New
York, NY: Columbia UP, 2017.
Huxley, Aldous. ‘Economists, Scientists and Humanists.’ Science in the Changing World. Ed. Mary
Adams. London: George Allen and Unwin, 1933. 208–23.
Huxley, Andrew, Sir. ‘Research and the Embryo.’ New Scientist 106/1451 (1985): 2.
Huxley, Julian. ‘Transhumanism.’ New Bottles for New Wine. London: Chatto & Windus, 1957. 13-17.
Huxley, Leonard. The Life and Letters of Thomas Henry Huxley. Vol.3. New York, NY: D. Appleton,
1901.
Hyun, Insoo, Amy Wilkerson, and Josephine Johnston. ‘Revisit the 14-Day Rule.’ Nature 533 (2016):
169-171.
Ida, Ryuichi. ‘Should We Improve Human Nature? An Interrogation from an Asian Perspective.’
Julian Savulescu and Nick Bostrom, eds. Human Enhancement. New York, NY: Oxford UP,
2009. 39-70.
‘Infant.’ American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 2018.
AHDictionary.com Accessed on 15 May 2018.
467
Jain, Shomik, Balasubramanian Thiagarajan, Zhonghao Shi, Caitlyn Clabaught, and Maja J. Matarić.
‘Modeling engagement in long-term, in-home socially assistive robot interventions for
children with autism spectrum disorders.’ Social Robotics 5/29 (2020): 1-9.
Janicaud, Dominique. On the Human Condition: Thinking in Action. Trans. Eileen Brennan. London:
Routledge, 2005.
‘Japanese Cafe Used Robots Controlled by Paralysed People.’ BBC Dec 6, 2018
www.bbc.com/news/technology-46466531 Accessed on 30 Dec 2018.
Jarvis, Claire. ‘Tell Me About Your Mother, or: You Should Come Twice a Week.’ The Hedgehog
Review Summer 2020 hedgehogreview.com/issues/questioning-the-quantified-
life/articles/tell-me-about-your-mother Accessed on 10 Jul 2020.
Jecker, Nancy S. ‘Anencephalic Infants and Special Relationships.’ Theoretical Medicine 11/4 (1990):
333-342.
---. ‘Commentary: The Moral Status of Patients Who Are Not Strict Persons.’ The Journal of Clinical
Ethics 1/1 (1990): 35-38.
---. ‘Appeals to nature in theories of age-group justice.’ Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 33/4 (1990):
517-27.
Johansson, Veronica, Surjo R. Soekadar, and Jens Clausen. ‘Locked Out: Ignorance and
Responsibilty in Brain-Computer Interface Communication in Locked-in Syndrome.’
Cambrdge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 26 (2017): 555-576.
Joshua, Essaka. Pygmalion and Galatea: The history of a narrative in English literature. Ashgate Publishing
Limited: Aldershot, Burlington, 2001.
Joyal, Christian C. ‘Controversies in the Definition of Paraphilia.’ The Journal of Sexual Medicine 201
15/10 (2018): 1378-1380.
Jung, Carl Gustav. Memories, Dreams, and Reflections. New York: Pantheon Books, 1963.
Kaiser, Andreas M, and Marvin L. Corman. ‘History of Laparoscopy.’ Surgical Oncology Clinics of North
America 10/3 (2001): 482-492.
Kanner, Leo. ‘Autistic Disturbances of Affective Contact.’ Nervous Child: Quarterly Journal of
Psychopathology, Psychotherapy, Mental Hygiene, and Guidance of the Child 2 (1943): 217–50.
Kaposy, Chris. Choosing Down’s Syndrome: Ethics and New Prenatal Testing Techniques. Cambridge, MA:
The MIT P, 2018.
Karbo, Karen. ‘Jane Goodall.’ In Praise of Difficult Women: Life Lessons from 29 Heroines Who Dared to
Break Rules. Washington, D.C.: National Geographic, 2018. 176-197.
468
Karow, Julia. ‘New Study Bolsters View That Mosaic Embryos From IVF Can Develop Into
Healthy Babies.’ GenomeWeb July 14, 2017 www.genomeweb.com/molecular-
diagnostics/new-study-bolsters-view-mosaic-embryos-ivf-can-develop-healthy-
babies#.XlQuZi2ZPjA Accessed on 18 Nov 2018.
Keeling, Diane Marie, and Marguerite Nguyen Lehman. ‘Posthumanism.’ Oxford Research Encyclopedia:
Communication. Oxford UP. Accessed on 19 April 2020.
Kelley, William E. ‘The Evolution of Laparoscopy and the Revolution in Surgery in the Decade of
the 1990s.’ Journal of the Society of Laparoendoscopic Surgeons 12/4 (2008): 351-357.
Kelly, Sean Dorrance. ‘A Philosopher argues that AI can’t be an artist.’ MIT Technology Review Feb 21,
2019 www.technologyreview.com/2019/02/21/239489/a-philosopher-argues-that-an-ai-
can-never-be-an-artist/ Accessed on 2 Jul 2020.
Kemp, Alan J. ‘The History and Development of a Universal Phonetic Alphabet in the 19th Century:
From the Beginnings to the Establishment of the IPA.’ History of Language Sciences/Geschichte
der Sprachwissenschaften/Histoire des sciences du langage. Vol. 1. Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton 2008.
1572-1584.
Kenney, Nancy J., and Michelle L. McGowan. ‘Egg Donation Compensation: Ethical and Legal
Challenges.’ Medicolegal and Bioethics 4 (2014): 15-24.
Keshavan, Meghana. ‘‘There’s no such thing as anonymity’: With consumer-DNA tests, sperm
banks reconsider long-held promises to donors.’ Stat Sep 11, 2019
www.statnews.com/2019/09/11/consumer-dna-tests-sperm-donor-anonymity/ Accessed
on 19 Feb 2020.
Khatchadourian, Raffi. ‘Degrees of Freedom: A Scientist’s Work Linking Minds and Machines
Helps a Paralyzed Woman Escape Her Body.’ New Yorker Nov 26, 2018.
www.newyorker.com/magazine/2018/11/26/how-to-control-a-machine-with-your-brain
Accessed on 15 Feb 2019.
Kiessling, Ann A. ‘What Is an Embryo?’ Connecticut Law Review 36/4 (2004): 1051-1093.
Kleeman, Jenny. ‘‘Parents can look at their foetus in real time’: are artificial wombs the future?’ The
Guardian Jun 27, 2020 www.theguardian.com/lifeandstyle/2020/jun/27/parents-can-look-
foetus-real-time-artificial-wombs-future 3 Jul 2020.
Knight, Will. ‘A Plan to Advance AI by Exploring the Minds of Children.’ MIT Technology Review Sep
12, 2018 www.technologyreview.com/s/612002/a-plan-to-advance-ai-by-exploring-the-
minds-of-children/ Accessed on 2 Jan 2020.
469
---. ‘Put Humans at the Center of AI.’ MIT Technology Review Oct 9, 2017
www.technologyreview.com/2017/10/09/3988/put-humans-at-the-center-of-ai/ Accessed on 8
Aug 2019.
Kondziella, Daniel. ‘Roald Dahl and the complete locked-in syndrome: “Cold dead body, living
brain.”’ Journal of the Neurological Sciences 379 (2017): 276-278.
Koplin, Julian, and Julian Savulescu. ‘Fresh urgency in mapping out ethics of brain organoid
research.’ Nov 20, 2019. theconversation.com/fresh-urgency-in-mapping-out-ethics-of-
brain-organoid-research Accessed on 8 Jan 2020.
Kovach, Steve. ‘We Talked To Sophia — The AI Robot That Once Said It Would ‘Destroy
Humans.’’ Tech Insider. YouTube Dec 28, 2017 www.youtube.com/watch?v=78-1MlkxyqI
Accessed on 8 Aug 2018.
Kovalevsky, George, and Christos Coutifaris. ‘Low and Very Low Birth Weight after Use of
Assisted Reproductive Technology.’ The New England Journal of Medicine 347/18 (2002): 1451-
52.
Krafft-Ebing, Richard von. Psychopathia Sexualis, With Especial Reference to the Antipathic Sexual Instinct:
A Medico-forensic Study. Brooklyn, NY: Rebman Company, 1926.
Kukla, Rebecca. Mass hysteria: Medicine, Culture, and Mothers’ Bodies. Lanham, MG: Rowman and
Littlefield, 2005.
Kurowski, Kathleen M., Sheile E. Blumstein, and Michael Alexander. ‘The Foreign Accent
Syndrome: A Reconsideration.’ Brain and Language 54 (1996): 1-25.
Kurrik, Juhan. ‘Kuldnaine.’ Ilomaile: Anthology of Estonian folk songs with translations and commentary.
Tortono: Maarjamaa, 1985. 108-111.
Kuwabara, Yoshunori, Takashi Okai, Yukio Imanishi, et al. ‘Development of Extrauterine Fetal
Incubation System Using Extracorporeal Membrane Oxygenator.’ Artificial Organs 11/3
(1987): 224-227.
Lafrance, Adrienne. ‘Why Do So Many Digital Assistants Have Feminine Names?’ The Atlantic Mar
30, 2016 www.theatlantic.com/technology/archive/2016/03/why-do-so-many-digital-
assistants-have-feminine-names/475884/ Accessed on 20 March 2019.
Landecker, Hannah. Culturing Life: How Cells Became Technologies. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 2007.
Lane, George. ‘The Tocharian Punyavantajataka: Text and Translation.’ Journal of the American Oriental
Society 67/1 (1947): 33-53.
Lapinkivi, Pirjo. The Sumerian sacred marriage in the light of comparative evidence. Helsinki: Neo-Assyrian
Text Corpus Project, 2004.
470
La Rochebrochard, Élise de. ‘One in thirty children in France conceived through assisted
reproductive technology.’ Population and Science (Institut national d’études démographiques) 556
(2018): 1-3.
‘Last of the Nonuplets Dies at Sydney Hospital.’ New York Times Jun 20, 1971: 4.
www.nytimes.com/1971/06/20/archives/last-of-the-nonuplets-dies-at-sydney-hospital.html
Accessed on 23 Jul 2019.
Latimer, Heather. Reproductive Acts Sexual Politics in North American Fiction and Film. McGill-Queen’s
UP: Montreal, 2013.
Laureys, Steven, Frédéric Pellas, Philippe Van Eeckhout, et al. ‘What is like to be conscious but
paralyzed and voiceless?’ Progress in Brain Research 150 (2005): 496-512.
Lechner, L., C. Bolman, A. van Dalen. ‘Definite involuntary childlessness: Associations between
coping, social support and psychological distress.’ Human Reproduction 22/1 (2007): 288-294.
Lee, Lillian. “‘I’m sorry, Dave, I’m afraid I can’t do that’: Linguistics, Statistics, and Natural-language
Processing Circa 2001.” Computer Science: Reflections on the Field, Reflections from the Field.
Washington, D.C.: The National Academies P, 2004. 111-118.
Lepore, Jill. The Mansion of Happiness: A History of Life and Death. New York, NY: Alfred A. Knopf,
2012.
---. ‘The Strange and Twisted Life of Frankenstein.’ The New Yorker Feb 5, 2018
www.newyorker.com/magazine/2018/02/12/the-strange-and-twisted-life-of-frankenstein
Accessed on 5 Feb 2018.
Levine, Aaron D. ‘Self-regulation, Compensation, and the Ethical Recruitment of Oocyte Donors.’
The Hastings Center Report 40/2 (2010): 25-36.
Lewis, Danny. ‘An AI-Written Novella Almost Won A Literary Prize.’ Smithsonian Magazine Mar 28,
2016 www.smithsonianmag.com/smart-news/ai-written-novella-almost-won-literary-prize-
180958577/ Accessed on 6 Feb 2020.
Lewis, Sophie A. Full surrogacy now: feminism against family. London: Verso, 2019.
Lewis, Tanya. ‘Rise of Fembots: Why Artificial Intelligence Is Often Female.’ Live Science Feb 29,
2017 www.livescience.com/49882-why-robots-female.html Accessed on 20 Mar 2019.
Lindemann, Hilde. Holding and Letting Go: The Social Practice of Personal Identities. New York, NY:
Oxford UP, 2014.
Light, Jennifer S. ‘When Computers Were Women.’ Technology and Culture 40/3 (1999): 455-83.
471
Litynski, Grzegorz D. ‘Patrick C. Steptoe: Laparoscopy, Sterilization, the Test-Tube Baby, and Mass
Media.’ Journal of the Society of Laparoendoscopic Surgeons 2/1: (1998): 99-101.
Lock, Margaret. ‘The Alienation of Body Tissue and the Biopolitics of Immortalized Cell Lines.’
Commodifying bodies. Eds. Nancy Scheper-Hughes and L. Wacquant. London: SAGE, 2002.
63-92.
Loesel, Gunter, Piotr Mirowski, and Kory Mathewson. ‘Do Digital Agents Do Dada? Paper Type:
CC Bridges.’ International Conference on Computational Creativity (2020): 1-4.
Loftis Freeman, Sonya. Imagining Autism: Fiction and Stereotypes on the Spectrum. Bloomington, IN:
Indiana UP, 2015.
Loren. ‘I’m a grown-up IVF baby – here’s what I want IVF parents to know.’ News.com.au October
23, 2007 www.news.com.au/lifestyle/parenting/babies/im-a-grownup-ivf-baby-heres-what-
i-want-ivf-parents-to-know/news-story/cccd62e0a698712cfe29a4c6a02afc01 Accessed on 2
Jul 2019.
Luckhurst, Robert. ‘Introduction.’ H. G. Wells, The Time Machine. Ed. By Robert Luckhurst. Oxford:
Oxford UP, 2017. Vii-xxv.
‘Machines that learn language more like kids do.’ Robotics at MIT robotics.mit.edu/machines-learn-
language-more-kids-do Accessed on 11 Jan 2020.
Maddox, Teena. ‘Tech leaders share how Star Trek inspired them to pursue a career in technology.
‘The Republic. Jan 23, 2020 www.techrepublic.com/article/tech-leaders-share-how-star-trek-
inspired-them-to-pursue-a-career-in-technology/ Accessed on 8 Aug 2020.
Mampe, Birgit, Angela D. Friederici, Anne Christophe, and Kathleen Wermke. ‘Newborns’ Cry
Melody Is Shaped by Their Native Language.’ Current Biology 19 (2009): 1994-1197.
Malzahn, Melanie. A Comprehensive Edition of Tocharian Manuscripts. University of Vienna, 17 Feb 2011.
Accessed on 10 May 2016.
Marcel, Gabriel. The Mystery of Being. I. Reflection and Mystery. Tran. G. S. Fraser. Chicago, IL: Henry
Regnery Co., 1960.
Marcus, Gary. ‘GPT-2 and the Nature of Intelligence.’ The Gradient Jan 25, 2020
thegradient.pub/gpt2-and-the-nature-of-intelligence/ Accessed on 3 Feb 2020.
Marocco, Terry. ‘Figli e famiglia, la verità di Dolce e Gabbana.’ Panorama Mar 16, 2015
www.panorama.it/news/cronaca/dolce-gabbana-lunica-famiglia-quella-tradizionale/
Accessed on 26 Jul 2019.
Marshall, Gail. Actresses on the Victorian stage: feminine performance and the Galatea myth. Cambridge UP,
2006.
472
Marsh, Amy. ‘Love Among Objectum Sexuals.’ Electronic Journal of Human Sexuality 13/1 (2010).
www.ejhs.org/volume13/ObjSexuals.htm Accessed on 30 Sep 2018.
Marx, Patricia. ‘Learning to Love Robots.’ The New Yorker Nov 26, 2018
www.newyorker.com/magazine/2018/11/26/learning-to-love-robots Accessed on 26 Nov
2018.
Mason, Christopher, Ari Melnick, George S. Grills Francine E. Garrett-Bakelmann. ‘The Landscape
of DNA and RNA Methylation Before, During, and After Human Space Travel.’ NASA Jan
16, 2019 www.nasa.gov/mission_pages/station/research/experiments/2104.html Accessed
on 31 Jan 2019.
Materassi, Mario. “Artificial Women, the Pygmalion Paradigm, and Faulkner’s Gordon in
Mosquitoes.” Global Faulkner: Faulkner and Yoknapatawpha. Eds. Annette Trefzer and Ann J.
Abadie. Jackson, MS: UP of Mississippi, 2009. 135-150.
Matheson, Rob. ‘Machines that learn language more like kids do.’ MIT News October 31, 2018.
news.mit.edu/2018/machines-learn-language-human-interaction-
1031?fbclid=IwAR1R4gN5pq-rbnT54NXuVI19hlhxrOqwd9KpK0LCvWZbjx-
VjyjmwPKiF60 Accessed on 18 Mar 2019.
Mathewson, Kory W. ‘Building an Artificial Improvisor.’ Kory Mathewson, Personal Website. April 8,
2016 korymathewson.com/building-an-artificial-improvisor/ Accessed on 17 Aug 2020.
Mathewson, Kory W., and Piotr Mirowski. ‘Improvised Theatre Alongside Artificial Intelligences.’
Proceedings of the Thirteenth AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Interactive Digital
Entertainment 2017. 66-72.
Matthews, Debra J.H., Peter J. Donovan, John Harris, Robin Lovell-Badge, Julia Savulescu, Ruth
Faden. ‘Pluripotent Stem Cell-Derived Gametes: Truth and (Potential) Consequences.’ Cell
Stem Cell 5 (2009): 11-14.
Mazer, Cary M. ‘Statues: Mary Anderson, Shakespeare and Statuesque Acting.’ Shakespearean
Illuminations: Essays in Honor of Marvin Rosenberg. Eds. Jay L. Halio and Hugh Richmond.
Newark, NJ: U of Delaware P, 1998.
McArthur, Douglas. ‘Le langage considéré comme une technologie.’ Cahiers de Lexicologie 50/1
(1987): 157-164.
McArthur, Neil. ‘The Case for Sexbots.’ Eds. John Dahaner and Neil McArthur. Robot Sex: Social and
Ethical Implications. Cambridge, MA: The MIT P, 2017. 31-45.
McArthur, Neil, and Markie L. C. Twist. ‘The rise of digisexuality: therapeutic challenges and
possibilities.’ Sexual and Relationship Therapy 32/3-4 (2017): 334-344.
McCarthy, J., M. L. Minsky, N. Rochester, and C.E. Shannon. ‘A Proposal for the Darmouth
Summer Research Project on Artificial Intelligence.’ Aug 31, 1955 www-
formal.stanford.edu/jmc/history/dartmouth/dartmouth.html Accessed on 10 Apr 2020.
473
McCauley, Lee. ‘AI Armageddon and the Three Laws of Robotics.’ Ethics and Information Technology
9/2 (2007): 153-164.
McCulloch, Gretchen. ‘Coding is for Everyone—as Long as You Speak English.’ Wired Apr 8, 2019
www.wired.com/story/coding-is-for-everyoneas-long-as-you-speak-english/ Accessed on 11
Feb 2020.
McIlwraith, Thomas Forsyth. The Bella Coola Indians. Toronto: Toronto UP, 1992.
McTavish, Lianne. ‘‘Healthy’ human embryos: A visual dialogue on ‘healthy’ human embryos from
the sixteenth to the twenty-first centuries.’ The ‘healthy’ embryo: social, biomedical, legal, and
philosophical perspectives. Ed. By Jeff Niesker et al. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2010. 97-115.
Mehaffy, Marilyn Maness. ‘Fetal Attractions: The Limit of Cyborg Theory.’ Women’s Studies 29
(2000): 177-194.
Miah, Andy, and Emma Rich. The Medicalization of Cyberspace. New York, NY: Routledge, 2008.
Mialet, Hélène. Hawking Incorporated: Stephen Hawking and the Anthropology of Knowing Subject. Chicago,
IL: Chicago UP, 2012.
---. ‘Interview: Hélène Mialet Remembers Stephen Hawking: Berggruen Fellow Hélène Mialet on the
Collective Intelligence of Stephen Hawking.’ Berggruen Institute April 2, 2018.
www.berggruen.org/ideas/articles/interview-with-helene-mialet/ Accessed on 8 Jan 2020.
Milgram, Stanley. The Individual in A Social Word. Eds. Stanley Milgram, John Sabini, Maury Silver.
New York, NY: McGraw-Hill, 1992.
Miller, Arthur I. ‘Best Screenplay Goes to the Algorithm: Learning to Appreciate the Future of
Literature.’ Dec 5, 2019 nautil.us/issue/79/catalysts/best-screenplay-goes-to-the-algorithms
Accessed on 5 Feb 2020.
Miller, Nick, Jill Taylor, Chloe Howe, and Jennifer Read. ‘Living with foreign accent syndrome:
Insider perspectives.’ Aphasiology 25/9 (2011); 1053-1068.
Mink, B. ‘American Cancer Society’s ‘smoking fetus.’’ American Cinematography 66 (1985): 77-80.
Misak, Cheryl. ‘Philosophy Must Be Useful.’ Aeon Jan 23, 2019 aeon.co/essays/what-is-truth-on-
ramsey-wittgenstein-and-the-vienna-circle Accessed on Feb 5, 2019.
Mitaros, Elle. ‘No More Lonely Nights: Romantic Robots Get the Look of Love.’ Sydney Morning
Herald, March 28, 2013 www.smh.com.au/technology/no-more-lonely-nights-romantic-
robots-get-the-look-of-love-20130327-2guj3.html Accessed on 15 Feb 2019.
474
Montiel-Castro, Augusto J., Rina M. González-Cervantes, Gabriela Bravo-Ruiseco, and Gustavo
Pacheco-Lopez. ‘The microbiota-gut-brain axis: neurobehavioral correlates, health and
sociality.’ Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience 7/70 (2013): 1-16.
More, Lisa Jean, and Marianna Grady. Mori, Masahiro. ‘The Uncanny Valley.’ IEEE Robotics and
Automation Magazine. Tran. Karl F. MacDorman and Norri Kageki. 19/2 (2012): 98-100.
Moser, Benjamin. ‘Sontag in Sarajevo.’ The New York Review of Books Daily Sep 9, 2019
www.nybooks.com/daily/2019/09/09/sontag-in-sarajevo/Accessed on 9 Nov 2019.
Mucklo, Matt. ‘Sperm Bank Opens Cambridge Branch.’ The Tech 113/49 (1993): 1, 17.
Mufwene, Salikoko. ‘Language as Technology: Some questions that evolutionary linguistics should
address.’ In Search of Universal Grammar: From Norse to Zoque. Ed. by Terje Lohndal.
Philadelphia, PA: John Benjamins, 2013.
---. The Evolution of Language as Technology: The Cultural Dimension, 2015. Beyond the Meme: Development and
Structure in Cultural Evolution. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Eds. William Wimsatt
and Alan Love. Minneapolis, MN: U of Minnesota P, 2016.
Mulkay, Michael. ‘The Triumph of the Pre-Embryo: Interpretations of the Human Embryo in
Parliamentary Debate Over Embryo Research.’ Social Studies of Science 24/4 (1994): 611-639.
Mullin, Emily. ‘Reached Via a Mind-Reading Device, Deeply Paralyzed Patients Say They Want to
Live.’ MIT Technology Review Jan 31, 2017 www.technologyreview.com/s/603512/reached-
via-a-mind-reading-device-deeply-paralyzed-patients-say-they-want-to-live/ Accessed on 24
Feb 2019.
Munitić, Rajko. Kino klub Beograd ili trojanski konj jugoslavenskog modernog filma. Belgrade: Centar Film,
2003.
Murdoch, Stuart. ‘Sleevenotes - Tigermilk.’ Belle and Sebastian. March 15, 2016
belleandsebastian.com/sleevenotes-tigermilk/ Accessed on 11 Aug 2020.
Murray, Stuart. Representing Autism: Culture, Narrative, Fascination. Liverpool UP, 2008.
‘Mutast.’ Fran: Slovarji Inštituta za slovenski jezik Frana Ramovša ZRC SAZU. ZRC SAZU, March 7,
2017 fran.si Accessed on 29 September 2018.
Nahata, Leena, Amy C. Tishelman, Nicole M. Caltabellotta, Gwendolyn P. Quinn. ‘Low Fertility
Preservation Utilization Among Transgender Youth.’ Journal of Adolescent Health 61/1 (2017):
40-44.
Nast, Heidi J. ‘Into the arms of dolls: Japan’s declining fertility rates, the 1990s financial crisis and
the (maternal) comforts of the posthuman.’ Social and Cultural Geography 18/6 (2017): 758-
785.
475
Nathan, Lisa P., Predrag V. Klasnja, and Batya Friedman. ‘Value Scenarios: A Technique for
Envisoning Systemic Effects of New Technologies.’ Computer-Human Interaction Conference
Proceedings 2007: Extended Abstracts on human factors in computing systems (2007): 2585-2590.
National Institutes of Health. Report of the Human Embryo Research Panel [Final Draft]. Bethesda, MD:
National Institutes of Health, 1994.
Neaves, William. ‘The status of the human embryo in various religions.’ Development 144 (2017):
2541-43.
Needham, Joseph. ‘Review.’ Scrutiny May 1932. 76-79. In Aldous Huxley: The Critical Heritage. Ed.
Donald Watt. London: Routledge, 1975. 202-05.
Nelson, Georgia. ‘Retirement Busy for Local Poet.’ Corpus Christi Caller Times Nov 7, 1965: 22.
www.newspapers.com/clip/24681672/lilith_lorraine_1965/ Accessed on 7 Nov 2019.
Nelson, Margaret K. ‘The Presentation of Donor Conception in Young Adult Fiction.’ Journal of
Family Issues 41/1 (2020): 33-61.
‘Nem.’ Fran: Slovarji Inštituta za slovenski jezik Frana Ramovša ZRC SAZU. ZRC SAZU, March 7, 2017
fran.si Accessed on 29 September 2018.
Newkirk, Margaret. ‘Why Alabama’s Abortion Law Includes an Exemption for Infertility.’ Bloomberg
Businessweek May 29, 2019 https://www.bloomberg.com/news/articles/2019-05-29/why-
alabama-s-abortion-law-includes-an-exemption-for-infertility Accessed on 16 June 2019.
Ngai, Sianne. Our Aesthetic Categories: Zany, Cute, and Interesting. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 2012.
Nicholls, Henry. ‘Darwin 200: Let’s make a mammoth.’ Nature 456 (2008): 310-14.
‘Nonsurgical Treatment for Male Infertility Caused by Varicoceles: Highly Effective Widely
Available Treatment is Underutilized.’ UCSF Department of Radiology and Biomedical Imaging.
The Regents of the University of California, 2019. radiology.ucsf.edu/patient-
care/sections/ir/advanced-services/varicocele Accessed on 12 Jun 2019.
Noor, Poppy. ‘Dating app based on genetic matching not eugenics, scientist says.’ The Guardian Dec
16, 2019 www.theguardian.com/science/2019/dec/16/dating-app-genetic-matching-not-
eugenics-scientist-says Accessed 18 May 2020.
Nugent, Ciara. ‘What It Was Like to Grow Up as the World’s First ‘Test-Tube Baby.’ Time July 25,
2018 time.com/5344145/louise-brown-test-tube-baby/ Accessed on 25 Jul 2020.
O’Bryhim, Shawn. ‘The Economics of Agalmatophilia.’ The Classical Journal 110/4 (2015): 419-429.
476
Olds, Jacqueline, and Richard Schwartz. The lonely American: Drifting apart in the twenty-first century.
Boston: Beacon P, 2009.
Olewitz, Chloe. ‘A Japanese A.I. program just wrote a short novel, and it almost won a literary
prize.’ Digital Trends Mar 23, 2016 www.digitaltrends.com/cool-tech/japanese-ai-writes-
novel-passes-first-round-nationanl-literary-prize/ Accessed on 6 Feb 2020.
Ohry, Abraham. ‘The Locked-In Syndrome and Related States.’ Paraplegia 28 (1990): 73-75.
Onishi, Norimitsu. ‘A Generation in Japan Faces a Lonely Death.’ New York Times Nov 30, 2017
www.nytimes.com/2017/11/30/world/asia/japan-lonely-deaths-the-end.html Accessed 12
Feb 2019.
‘On the Frontiers of Medicine: Control of Life.’ LIFE Sep 10, 1965: 59-79.
Orenstein-Brown, David. ‘Will VF Make Egg and Sperm Optional for Reproduction?’ Futurity Jan
12, 2017 www.futurity.org/in-vitro-gametogenesis-ivg-1334182-2/ Accessed on 5 Jul 2019.
OryLab. ‘Solving human loneliness through communication technology.’ OryLab Inc. 2020
orylab.com/en/ Accessed on 11 Jul 2020.
Osborne, Cynthia S., and Thomas N. Wise. ‘Paraphilias.’ Handbook of Sexual Dysfunction. Ed. by
Richard Balon and R. Taylor Segraves. Boca Raton, FL: Taylor and Francis, 2005. 293-330.
Ostler, Rosemaire. Dewdroppers, Waldos, and Slackers: A Decade-by-Decade Guide to the Vanishing
Vocabulary of the Twentieth Century. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2003.
‘Otrok.’ Fran: Slovarji Inštituta za slovenski jezik Frana Ramovša ZRC SAZU. ZRC SAZU, March 7,
2017 fran.si Accessed on 15 May 2018.
Ottosen, Lars D. M., Johhny Hindkjær, and Jakob Ingerslev. ‘Light Exposure of the Ovum and
Preimplantation Embryo during ART Procedures.’ Journal of Assisted Reproduction and Genetics
24/2-3 (2007): 99-103.
Oudeyer, Pierre-Yves. ‘What do we learn about development from baby robots?’ Wiley
Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science 8/1-2 (2017): 1-7.
Palkopoulou, Eleftheria, Mark Lipson, et al. ‘A comprehensive genomic history of extinct and living
elephants.’ Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America. 115/11
(2018): E2566-74.
Parens, Erik. Shaping Our Selves: On Technology, Flourishing, and a Habit of Thinking. New York, NY:
Oxford UP, 2014.
477
Parker, Ian. ‘Yuval Noah Harari’s History of Everyone, Ever.’ The New Yorker Feb 10, 2020
www.newyorker.com/magazine/2020/02/17/yuval-noah-harari-gives-the-really-big-picture
Accessed on 11 Feb 2020.
‘Parrot.’ American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language, 2018. AHDictionary.com Accessed on 28
Aug 2018.
Partridge, Emily A, Marcus G. Davey, Matthew A. Hornick, Patrick E. McGovern, et al. ‘An Extra-
uterine System to Physiologically support the Extreme Premature Lamb.’ Nature
Communications 8 (2017): 151-121.
Patterson, Andrew C. and Gerry Veenstra. ‘Loneliness and risk of mortality: A longitudinal
investigation in Alameda Country, California.’ Social Science and Medicine 71/1 (2010): 181-186.
Peak, Kenneth J. ‘‘Things Fearful to Name:’ An Overview of Sex Crimes and Perversions.’ Journal of
Contemporary Criminal Justice 12/2 (1996): 204-214.
Pauly, Philip J. Controlling Life: Jacques Loeb and the Engineering Ideal in Biology. Berkeley, A: CUP, 1990.
Pearce, J. M. S. ‘The Locked In Syndrome.’ British Medical Journal 294/6566 (1987): 198-199.
Peate, Ian. ‘How’s it going? The silent epidemic of loneliness.’ British Journal of Nursing 27/11 (2018):
591.
Pelley, Scott. ‘A Harvard geneticist’s goal: To protect humans from viruses, genetic diseases, and
aging.’ CBS News Dec 8, 2019 www.cbsnews.com/news/harvard-geneticist-george-church-
goal-to-protect-humans-from-viruses-genetic-diseases-and-aging-60-minutes-2019-12-08/
Accessed on 10 Dec 2019.
Perez-Muñoz, Maria Elisa, Marie-Claire Arrieta, Amanda E. Ramer-Tait, and Jens Walter. ‘A critical
assessment of the ‘sterile womb’ and ‘in utero colonization’ hypotheses: implications for
research on the pioneer infant microbiome.’ Microbiome 5 (2017): 1-19.
‘Person.’ American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language, 2018. AHDictionary.com Accessed on 18
June 2018.
Pepperberg, Irene. ‘Evolution of communication and language: insights from parrots and songbirds.’
The Oxford Handbook of Language Evolution. Eds. Kathleen R. Gibson, Maggie Tallerman.
Oxford: Oxford UP, 2012. 110-120.
---. The Alex Studies: cognitive and communicative abilities of grey parrots. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP,
1999.
Petersen, Steve. ‘Is It Good for Them Too? Ethical Concerns for the Sexbots.’ Eds. John Dahaner
and Neil McArthur. Robot Sex: Social and Ethical Implications. Cambridge, MA: The MIT P,
2017. 155-171.
478
Pettman, Dominic. Human Error: Species-Being and Media Machines. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P,
2011.
Phelan, Peggy. Unmarked: The Politics of Performance. Chapter 7. London, Routledge: 1996. 147-152.
Phillips, Julie. James Tiptree, Jr.: The Double Life of Alice B. Sheldon. New York, NY: St Martin’s Press,
2006.
Picard, Rosalind W. ‘Affective computing.’ Oxford Companion to Emotion and the Affective Sciences. Eds.
David Sander, Klaus Scherer. 11-15.
Pinchuk, Stacey. ‘A Difficult Choice in a Different Voice: Multiple Births, Selective Reduction and
Abortion.’ Duke Journal of Gender Law and Policy 7/29 (2000): 29-56.
Ploeg, Irma, van der. ‘‘Only Angels can do Without Skin:’ On Reproductive Technology’s Hybrids
and the Politics of Body Boundaries.’ Body and Society 10/2-3: 152-181.
---. Prosthetic Bodies: The Reconstruction of the Fetus and the Couple as Patients in Reproductive Technologies.
Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2011.
Plotz, David. The Genius Factory: The Curious History of the Nobel Prize Sperm Bank. New York, NY:
Random House, 2006.
Plum, Fred, and Jerome B. Posner. The Diagnosis of Stupor and Coma. Philadelphia, PA: F. A. Davis &
Co., 1966.
---. ‘The Locked In Syndrome.’ British Medical Journal 294/ 6580 (1987): 1163.
Pomeroy, Kimball O., and Michael L. Reed. ‘The Effect of Light on Embryos and Embryo Culture.’
Troubleshooting and Problem-Solving in the IVF Laboratory. Eds. Kay Elder, Marc Van Der Bergh,
and Bryan Woodward. London: Cambridge UP, 2015. 104-116.
‘Pornography.’ American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language, 2018. AHDictionary.com Accessed
on 19 Jul 2019.
Porr, Liam. ‘My GPT-3 Blog Got 26 Thousand Visitors in 2 Weeks.’ Liam Porr, Personal Webpage.
Aug 3, 2020 liamp.substack.com/p/my-gpt-3-blog-got-26-thousand-visitors Accessed on 18
Aug 2020.
Porter, Allen. ‘Bioethics and Transhumanism’ Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 42 (2017): 237-60.
Preidt, Robert. ‘Meet ‘Huggable,’ the Robot Bear Who’s Helping Hospitalized Kids.’ US News Jun
28, 2019 www.usnews.com/news/health-news/articles/2019-06-28/meet-huggable-the-
robot-bear-whos-helping-hospitalized-kids Accessed 13 Jul 2020.
479
Preston, Douglas. ‘Op-Ed: Online book-selling scams steal a living from writers.’ Los Angeles Times
Jul 26, 2019 www.latimes.com/opinion/story/2019-07-25/amazon-books-counterfeit-
authors-copyright Accessed on 4 Feb 2020.
‘Prosthesis.’ American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language, 2018. AHDictionary.com Accessed
on 19 Jun 2018.
‘Prostitute.’ American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language, 2018. AHDictionary.com Accessed on
19 Jun 2018.
Puchner, Martin. The Written World: The Power of Stories to Shape People, History, Civilization. New York,
NY: Random House, 2017.
Radford, Alec, Jeffrey Wu, Dario Amodei, et al. ‘Better Language Models and Their Implications.’
OpenAI Feb 14, 2019 openai.com/blog/better-language-models/ Accessed on 3 Feb 2020.
Raphael-Leff, Joan. ‘Eros and Art.’ Inconceivable Conceptions: Psychological Aspects of Infertility and
Reproductive Technology. Eds. Jane Haynes and Juliet Miller. Hove, East Sussex: Brunner-
Routledge, 2003. 30-47.
Reardon, Sara. ‘Lab-grown ‘mini brains’ produce electrical patterns that resemble those of premature
babies.’ Nature Nov 15, 2018. www.nature.com/articles/d41586-018-07402-0 Accessed 8 Jan
2020.
Rees, Tobias. ‘From The Anthropocene To The Microbiocene.’ Noema Magazine Jun 10, 2020
www.noemamag.com/from-the-anthropocene-to-the-microbiocene/ Accessed on 11 Jun
2020.
Reeves, Byron, and Clifford Nass. The Media Equation: How People Treat Computers, Television, and New
Media like Real People and Places. New York: Cambridge UP: 1996.
Regalado, Antonio. ‘China’s CRISPR twins might have had their brains inadvertently enhanced.’
MIT Technology Review Feb 21, 2019 www.technologyreview.com/s/612997/the-crispr-twins-
had-their-brains-altered/ Accessed on 21 Feb 2019.
480
---. ‘Meet the ‘artificial embryos’ being called uncanny and spectacular.’ MIT Technology Review Sep 11,
2019 www.technologyreview.com/s/614292/meet-the-artificial-embryos-being-called-
uncanny-and-spectacular/ Accessed on 21 Feb 2020.
Ren, Xiaoping, and Sergio Canavero. ‘From Hysteria to Hope: The Rise of Head Transplantation.’
International Journal of Surgery 41 (2017): 203-204.
Reynolds, Emily. ‘The agony of Sophia, the world's first robot citizen condemned to a lifeless
career in marketing.’ Wired Jun 1, 2018 www.wired.co.uk/article/sophia-robot-citizen-
womens-rights-detriot-become-human-hanson-robotics Accessed on Jun 1 2019.
Richardson, Kathleen. Challenging Sociality: An Anthropology of Robots, Autism, and Attachment. Cham:
Palgrave Maximillan, 2018.
Rijnink, Emilie C., Mrlies E. Penning, Ron Wolterbeek, et al. ‘Tissue microchimerism is increased
during pregnancy: a human autopsy study.’ Molecular Human Reproductioin 21/11 (2015): 857-
864.
Rimmer, Abi. ‘RCGP calls for national campaign to tackle loneliness.’ British Medical Journal Publishing
Group 361 (2018).
Robitzski, Dan. ‘Artificial Intelligence Writes Bad Poems Just Like An Angsty Teen.’ Futurism Apr
26, 2018 futurism.com/artificial-intelligence-bad-poems Accessed on 5 Feb 2020.
‘Robot.’ American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language, 2018. AHDictionary.com Accessed on 15
May 2018.
Robins, Ben, R. Te Boekhorst, Kerstin Dautenhahn, and Aude Billard. ‘Robotic Assistants in
Therapy and Education of Children with Autism: Can a Small Humanoid Robot Help
Encourage Social Interaction Skills?’ Universal Access in the Information Society 4/2 (2005): 105–
120.
Robson, David. ‘These animals are male on one side and female on the other.’ BBC Sep 22, 2015
www.bbc.com/earth/story/20150916-these-animals-are-male-on-one-side-and-female-on-
the-other Accessed on 13 Jun 2020.
Rockmore, Dan. ‘What Happens When Machines Learn to Write Poetry?’ The New Yorker Jan 7,
2020. www.newyorker.com/culture/annals-of-inquiry/the-mechanical-muse Accessed on 9
Apr 2020.
481
Rodero, Emma. ‘Effectiveness, Attention, and Recall of Human and Artificial Voices in an
Advertising Story. Prosody Influence and Functions of Voices.’ Human Behavior 77 (2017):
336-346.
Rodrick, Stephen. ‘The Trouble With Johnny Deep.’ Rolling Stone Jun 21, 2018
www.rollingstone.com/movies/movie-features/the-trouble-with-johnny-depp-666010/
Accessed on 22 Jul 2019.
Rohleder, Hermann. Test Tube Babies: Tran. New York, NY: The Panurge P, 1934.
Rohlfs, Rori. ‘Understanding our eugenic past to take steps towards scientific accountability.’ Genes to
Genomes: A Blog of Genetic Society of America. Jun 8, 2020 genestogenomes.org/understanding-
our-eugenic-past-to-take-steps-towards-scientific-accountability/ Accessed on 8 Jun 2020.
Romanis, Elizabeth Chloe. ‘Artificial womb technology and the frontiers of human reproduction:
Conceptual differences and potential implications.’ Journal of Medical Ethics 44/11 (2018): 751-
755.
Rosen, Christine. ‘Why Not Artificial Wombs?’ New Atlantic 3 (2003): 67-76.
Roser, Max. ‘Fertility Rate.’ Our World in Data. First published in 2014, substantive revision in Dec
2017. ourworldindata.org/fertility-rate#the-number-of-children-per-woman-over-the-very-
long-run Accessed on 25 Jun 2019.
Roskies, Adina L. ‘Assessing the Effects of Deep Brain Stimulation on Agency.’ The Neuroethics Blog
Feb 11, 2020 www.theneuroethicsblog.com/2020/02/assessing-effects-of-deep-
brain_11.html Accessed on 11 Feb 2020.
Rothman, Lily. ‘Margaret Atwood on Serial Fiction and the Future of the Book.’ Interview with
Margaret Atwood. Time Oct 8, 2012 entertainment.time.com/2012/10/08/margaret-
atwood-on-serial-fiction-and-the-future-of-the-book/ Accessed 27 Jan 2020.
Rozo, Michelle, and Gigi Kwik Gronvall. ‘The Reemergent 1977 H1N1 strain and the Gain-of-
Function Debate.’ mBio 6/4 (2015): 1-5.
Rubin, Rita. ‘Loneliness Might Be a Killer, but What’s the Best Way to Protect Against It?’ JAMA
318/19 (2017): 1853-1855.
Ruffenach, Stephen C. ‘Test-Tube Baby.’ Embryo Project Encyclopedia January 13, 2009.
embryo.asu.edu/pages/test-tube-baby Accessed on 28 Jun 2019.
482
Russo, Francine. ‘The Cost of Camouflaging Autism.’ Spectrum News Feb 21, 2018.
www.spectrumnews.org/features/deep-dive/costs-camouflaging-autism/ Accessed on 20
Mar 2019.
Saltsman, Kirstie. ‘Voice Matters! Speech Researcher Rupal Patel Builds Personalized Voices for
People with Severely Impaired Speech.’ National Institute of Deafness and Other Communication
Disorders (NIDCD). March 10, 2016 www.nidcd.nih.gov/newsletter/2014/spring/voice-
matters-speech-researcher-rupal-patel-builds-personalized-voices-people Accessed on 10 Feb
2019.
Sandel, Michael J. The Case Against Perfection: Ethics in the Age of Genetic Engineering. Cambridge, MA:
The Belknap P of Harvard UP, 2007.
Satariano, Adam, Elian Peltier, and Dmity Kostyukob. ‘Meet Zora, the robot that may help change
care in nursing homes.’ The Seattle Times Nov 23, 2018
www.seattletimes.com/business/meet-zora-the-robot-caregiver/ Accessed on 1 Feb 2019.
Savage-Rumbaugh, Sue, Jeanine Murphy, Rose A. Sevcik, Karen E. Brakke, Shelly L. Williams,
Duane M. Rumbaugh and Elizabeth Bates. Language Comprehension in Ape and Child. Chicago:
U of Chicago P, 1993. (Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development 58/3-4 (1993):
1-222.)
Savulescu, Julian. ‘Enhancing Equality.’ The Posthuman Condition: Ethics, Aesthetics and Politics of
Biotechnological Challenges. Eds. Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen, Mads Rosendahl Thomsen, Jacob
Wamberg. Aarhus: Aarhus UP, 2012.
Scheib, Joanna E., and Alice Ruby. ‘Contact Among Families Who Share the Same Sperm Donor.’
Fertility and Sterility 90/1 (2008): 33-34.
Schlomo, Lipiz, Yuval Yaron, Josef Shalev, Reuven Achiron, Mati Zolti, and Shlomo Masiach.
‘Improved Results in Multifetal Pregnancy Reduction: A Report of 72 Cases.’ Fertility and
Sterility 61/1 (1994): 59-61.
Schiefner, Anton. Übersetzungen aus dem tibetischen Kanjur: Beiträge zur Buddhismuskunde und zur
zentralasiatischen Märchenforschung. Wiesbaden: Otto Harrassowitz Verlag, 2007.
Schoenwolf, Gary, Steven Bleyl, Philip Brauer, Philoppa Francis-West. Larsen’s Human Embryology.
Fifth edition. New York, NY: Churchill Livingstone, 2014.
Scobie, A., Taylor, A. J. W. ‘Perversions ancient and modern: I. Agalmatophilia, the statue
syndrome.’ Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences 11/1 (1975): 49-54.
483
Scott, Rosamund. Choosing Between Possible Lives: Law and Ethics of Prenatal and Preimplantation Genetic
Diagnosis. Oxford, UK: Hart, 2007.
---. ‘Uses of Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis – Choosing Between Possible Lives. Law and Ethics
of Prenatal Diagnosis. London: Hart P, 2007. 297-350.
‘Sculpture.’ American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language, 2018. AHDictionary.com Accessed on
19 Jun 2018.
Seal, Thomas. ‘Rock Star and Web Founder Teaming Up on Technology.’ Bloomberg Jul 17, 2020
www.bloomberg.com/news/articles/2020-07-17/rock-star-and-internet-founder-team-up-
on-dr-dolittle-technology Accessed 17 Jul 2020.
Seed, David. ‘Aldous Huxley: Brave New World.’ A Companion to Science Fiction. Ed. David Seed.
Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing, 2005. 477-488.
Segerdahl, Për, William Fields and Sue Savage-Rumbaugh. Kanzi’s Primal Language: The Cultural
Initiation of Primates into Language. New York, NY: Palgrave Maximilian, 2005.
Seibel, Machelle M. ‘Cadaveric Ovary Donation.’ The New England Journal of Medicine 330/11 (1994):
796.
Servick, Kelly. ‘Artificial Intelligence Turns Brain Activity into Speech.’ Science Magazine Jan 2, 2019
www.sciencemag.org/news/2019/01/artificial-intelligence-turns-brain-activity-speech
Accessed on 2 Jan 2019.
Shah, Huma, and Kevin Warwick, Jordi Vallverdú, Defeng Wu. ‘Can machines talk? Comparison of
Eliza with modern dialogue systems.’ Computers in Human Behavior 58 (2016): 278-295.
Shane, Janelle. “I recently read Harrow the Ninth and can think of no more appropriate tribute than
this AI-generated poem. / (1st line is the prompt I gave GPT-3; the rest is what it added)”
Aug 20, 2020 10:29AM Tweet. twitter.com/JanelleCShane/status/1292875829299511296
Shaw, Jonathan. ‘Language as Litmus Test for AI.’ Harvard Magazine Jan-Feb 2019
harvardmagazine.com/2019/01/language-as-litmus-test-ai Accessed on 4 May 2019.
Shell, Marc. Children of the Earth. New York, NY: Oxford UP, 1993.
---. Islandology: Geography, Rhetoric, Politics. Stanford, CA: Stanford UP, 2014.
---. Polio and Its Aftermath: The Paralysis of Culture. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 2005.
---. Money, Language, and Thought: Literary and Philosophical Economies from the Medieval to the Modern Era.
Berkeley, CA: U of California P, 1982.
484
---. The Economy of Literature. Baltimore, MD: JHU P, 1978.
Shulevicz, Judith. ‘Alexa, should we trust you?” The Atlantic Nov 2018
www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2018/11/alexa-how-will-you-change-us/570844/
Accessed on 8 May 2019.
‘Silicone Sally: Japanese Men Find True Love with Sex Dolls.’ Channel News Asia Jun 20, 2017
https://www.channelnewsasia.com/news/asia/silicone-sally-japanese-men-find-true-love-
with-sex-dolls-8991648 Accessed on 30 Nov 2018.
Simpson, Aislinn. ‘Woman with object fetish marries Eiffel Tower.’ The Telegraph Jun 8, 2008
www.telegraph.co.uk/news/newstopics/howaboutthat/2074301/Woman-with-objects-
fetish-marries-Eiffel-Tower.html Accessed on 19 Sep 2018.
Singer, Peter. Animal Liberation: The Definitive Classic of the Animal Movement. EBook. New York, NY:
Integrated Media, 2015. [1975.]
Sloterdijk, Peter. Bubbles: microspherology. Spheres I. [Sphären I. Blasen.] Tran. Wieland Hoban. Los
Angeles, CA: Semiotexte, 2011.
---. Foams: plural spherology. Spheres III. Tran. Wieland Hoban. Los Angeles, CA: Semiotexte, 2016.
---. Globes: macrospherology. Spheres II. Tran. Wieland Hoban. Los Angeles, CA: Semiotexte, 2013.
‘Slovenski.’ Fran: Slovarji Inštituta za slovenski jezik Frana Ramovša ZRC SAZU. ZRC SAZU, March 7,
2017 fran.si Accessed on 22 Aug 2018.
Smajdor, Anna. ‘In Defense of Ectogenesis.’ Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 21/1 (2012): 90-
103.
Smilek, D., K. Malcolmson, J. Carriere, M. Eller, D. Kwan, and M. Reynolds. ‘When “3” is a Jerk
and “E” is a King: Personifying Inanimate Objects in Synesthesia.’ Journal of Cognitive
Neuroscience 19:6 (2007): 981–992.
485
Smrekar, Maja. ‘K-9_Topology, on the human/dog co-evolution: An interview with Maja Smrekar.’
we-make-money-not-art.com/k-9_topology-on-the-human-dog-co-evolution-an-interview-
with-maja-smrekar/ Accessed on 25 Feb 2020.
Solon, Olivia. ‘Google’s robot assistant now makes eerily lifelike phone calls for you.’ The Guardian
May 8, 2018. www.theguardian.com/technology/2018/may/08/google-duplex-assistant-
phone-calls-robot-human Accessed on 8 Jan 2020.
Soloski, Alexis. ‘When a star doesn’t know the script, send for the earpiece.’ The Telegraph Nov 11,
2015 www.theguardian.com/stage/2015/nov/11/theatre-earpiece-prompting-bruce-willis-
al-pacino Accessed on 22 Jul 2019.
Spallone, Patricia. Beyond Conception: The New Politics of Reproduction. London: Macmillian Education,
1989.
Spataro, Joanne. ‘Adventures in Transgender Fertility.’ The New York Times Apr 24, 2018
www.nytimes.com/2018/04/24/opinion/transgender-fertility-preservation.html Accessed
on 26 Jul 2019.
Speer, Shari R. and Kiwako Ito. ‘Prosody in First Language Acquisition – Acquiring Intonation as a
Tool to Organize Information in Conversation.’ Language and Linguistics Compass 3/1 (2009):
90-110.
Spemann, H. Embryonic Development and Induction. New Haven: Yale UP, 1938.
‘Spike Jonze Opens His Hear For ‘Her.’’ NPR Dec 16, 2013
www.npr.org/2013/12/16/251625458/spike-jonze-opens-his-heart-for-her Accessed on 4
Feb 2020.
Squier, Susan Merrill. ‘Embryos Are Like Photographic Film.’ Babies in Bottles: Twentieth-century Visions
of Reproductive Technology. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers UP, 1994. 133-167.
---. Liminal Lives: Imagining the Human at the Frontiers of Biomedicine. Durham: Duke UP, 2004.
---. ‘Reproducing the Posthuman Body: Ectogenetic Fetus, Surrogate Mother, Pregnant Man.’
Posthuman Bodies. Eds. Judith M. Halberstam and Ira Livingston. Bloomington, IN: Indiana
UP, 1995. 14-134.
---. Poultry Science, Chicken Culture: A Partial Alphabet. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers UP, 2011.
Standage, Tom. ‘An artificial intelligence predicts the future.’ The Economist
worldin.economist.com/edition/2020/article/17521/artificial-intelligence-predicts-future
Accessed on 3 Feb 2020.
---. ‘How I (sort of) interview an artificial intelligence.’ Medium Dec 9, 2019
medium.economist.com/how-i-sort-of-interviewed-an-artificial-intelligence-2a9c069a1680
Accessed on 3 Feb 2020.
486
Steinberg, Jeffrey. ‘Choose Your Baby’s Eye Color: Taking Advantage of the Ever-expanding Role
of Modern Genetics.’ The Fertility Institutes www.fertility-docs.com/programs-and-
services/pgd-screening/choose-your-babys-eye-color.php Accessed on 24 Jul 2019.
Sterling, Bruce. ‘Patently untrue: fleshly defibrillators and synchronized baseball are changing the
future.’ Wired Oct 11, 2013 www.wired.co.uk/article/patently-untrue Accessed on Apr 23,
2020.
Stevenson, Melissa. ‘Trying to Plug In: Posthuman Cyborgs in the Search for Connection.’ Science
Fiction Studies 34.1 (2007): 95-96.
Stinson, Lisa F., Mary C. Boyce, Matthew S. Payne, and Jeffrey A. Keelan. ‘The Not-so-Sterile
Womb: Evidence That the Human Fetus Is Exposed to Bacteria Prior to Birth.’ Frontiers in
Microbiology 10 (2019): 1-15.
Stol, Marten. ‘The Sacred Marriage.’ Women in the Ancient Near East. Tran. Helen Richardson, Mervyn
Edwin John Richardson. Boston, MA, Berlin: Walter De Gruyter, 2016. 645-661.
Stoll, Josef, Camille Chatelle, Olivia Carter, Christof Koch, Steven Laureys, and Wolfgang
Einhäuser. ‘Pupil responses allow communication in locked-in syndrome patients.’ Current
Biology 23/15 (2013): 647-648.
Sugarman, J., and D.P. Sulmasy. Methods in Medical Ethics. 2nd ed. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown UP,
2010.
Suskin, Zaev D., and James J. Giordano. Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 13/10 (2018): 1-
6.
Suvin, Darko. ‘Cognitiono and Estrangement.’ Strange Horizons Nov 24, 2014 (First published in
Foundation in 1972.) strangehorizons.com/non-fiction/articles/estrangement-and-cognition/
Accessed 19 May 2020.
Suzuki, Yutaka, Lisa Galli, Ayaka Ikeda, Shoji Itakura, and Michiteru Kitazaki. ‘Measuring empathy
for human and robot hand pain using electroencephalography.’ Nature Scientific Reports
5/15924 (2015): 1-9.
Swanson, Kara W. ‘Adultery by Doctor: Artificial Insemination, 1890-1045.’ Women’s Legal History: A
Global Perspective 87/2 (2012): 591-633.
Swinton, John R. ‘Tlingit Myths and Texts.’ Bureau of American Ethnology Bulletin 39 Washington:
Government Printing Office, 1909. 7-472.
Switzky, Lawrence. ‘ELIZA Effects: Pygmalion and the Early Development of Artificial Intelligence.’
SHAW: The Journal of Bernard Shaw Studies 40/1 (2020): 5-68.
Tahara, Yutaka, and Katsuya Obara. ‘A Novel Shell-less Culture System for Chick Embryos Using a
Plastic Film as Culture Vessels.’ Journal of Poultry Science 51 (2014): 307-212.
487
Taniguchi, Kenichiro, Idse Heemskerk, Deborah L. Gumucio. ‘Opening the Black Box: Stem Cell-
based Modeling of Human Post-implantation Development.’ The Journal of Cell Biology 218/2
(2019): 410-421.
Tännsjö, Torbjörn. ‘Medical Enhancement and the Ethos of Elite Sport.’ Human Enhancement. Julian
Savulescu and Nick Bostrom, eds. New York, NY: Oxford UP, 2009. 315-326.
Taylor, J.S. ‘The public fetus and the family car: from abortion politics to a Volvo advertisement.’
Public Culture 4 (1992): 67-80.
Taylor, Matthew A. ‘Life’s Returns: Hylozoism, Again.’ PMLA 139/3 (2020): 474- 91.
Terrace, Herbert S. Why Chimpanzees Can’t Learn Language and Only Humans Can. New York, NY:
Columbia UP, 2019.
Thompson, Joel. ‘Transhumanism: How far is too far?’ The New Bioethics 23/2 (2017): 165-82.
Thornber, Karen Laura. Global Healing: Literature, Advocacy, and Care. Leiden: Brill, 2020.
Tingley, Kim. ‘The Brave New World of Three-Parent I.V.F.’ New York Times Jul 13, 2014: SM6.
The Endowment for Human Development, Inc. The Virtual Human Embryo: Digitally Reproduced
Embryonic Morphology. 2001-2019. www.ehd.org/virtual-human-embryo/ Accessed on Aug 8,
2019.
The Nuffield Council on Bioethics. ‘Ideas about naturalness in public and political debates about
science, technology and medicine.’ November 2015: 1-108.
www.nuffieldbioethics.org/assets/pdfs/Naturalness-analysis-paper.pdf Accessed on 14 May
2020.
The Practice Committee of the American Society for Reproductive Medicine. ‘Repetitive Oocyte
Donation.’ Fertility and Sterility 90/5 (2009): 194-195.
Thomas, James W., Christian LaMantia, and Terry Magnuson. ‘X-ray-induced Mutations in mouse
Embryonic Stemcells.’ Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 95/3 (1998): 1114-1119.
Thompson, Clive. ‘May A.I. Help You?’ The New York Times Nov 14, 2018
www.nytimes.com/interactive/2018/11/14/magazine/tech-design-ai-chatbot.html Accessed
on 20 Feb 2020.
Timeto, Federica. Diffractive Technospaces: A Feminist Approach to the Meditations of Space and
Representation. New York, NY: Routledge, 2015.
Toomey, Diane. ‘Exploring How and Why Trees ‘Talk’ to Each Other.’ YaleEnvironment360 Sep 1,
2016 e360.yale.edu/features/exploring_how_and_why_trees_talk_to_each_other Accessed
on 16 May 2020.
488
Torjesen, Ingrid. ‘Sixty Seconds on… Sex with Robots.’ British Medical Journal 358 (2017): 3353.
---. ‘Society Must Consider Risk of Sex Robots, Report Warns.’ British Medical Journal 358 (2017):
3267.
Trestman, Michael. ‘Clever Hand, Alex the Parrot, and Kanzi: What can Exceptional Animal
Learning Teach Us.’ Biological Theory 10 (2015): 86-99.
Tsing, Anna. The mushroom at the end of the world: On the possibility of life in capitalist ruins. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton UP, 2015.
Turkle, Sherry. Alone together: Why we expect more from technology and less from each other. New York, NY:
Basic Books, 2011.
Turing, Alan M. ‘Computing Machinery and Intelligence.’ Mind: A Quarterly Review of Psychology and
Philosophy. 59/236 (1950): 433-460.
Twist, Markie L. C., and Neil McArthur. ‘Introduction to special issue on sex and technology.’ Sexual
and Relationship Therapy 32/3-4 (2017): 249-268.
UNESCO and EQUALS Skill Coalition. ‘I’d blush if I could: closing gender divides in digital skills
through education.’ Authors: Mark West, Rebecca Kraut, and Han Ei Chew. EQUALS and
UNESCO, 2019. unesdoc.unesco.org/ark:/48223/pf0000367416.page=1 1-145.
University of California Institute for Creative Technologies. ‘SimSensei & MultiSense: Virtual
Human and Multimodal Perception for Healthcare Support.’ YouTube Feb 7, 2013.
www.youtube.com/watch?v=ejczMs6b1Q4 Accessed on 8 Jan 2020.
University of Redding. ‘Turing Test Success Marks Milestone in Computing History.’ Newts and
Events: Press Release. June 8, 2014. www.reading.ac.uk/news-and-
events/releases/PR583836.aspx Accessed on 2 Jun 2018.
Usborne, Simon. ‘‘I thought – who will remember me?’: the man who fathered 200 children.’ The
Guardian Nov 24, 2018 www.theguardian.com/science/2018/nov/24/sperm-donor-man-
who-fathered-200-children Accessed on 7 Jul 2019.
US Department of Health and Human Services. Assisted Reproductive Technology: National Summary
Report 2015. National Center for Chronic Disease and Health Promotion, Division of
Reproductive Health, 2017.
489
‘Utopia.’ Online Etymology Dictionary 2001-2020 Douglas Harper. www.etymonline.com/word/utopia
Accessed 1 May 2020.
Vainio, Martti. Juhani Järkvikivi, Stefan Werner, Nickolas Volk, Jarmo Välikangas. ‘Effect of
prosodic naturalness on segmental acceptability in synthetic speech.’ Proceedings of 2002 IEEE
Workshop on Speech Synthesis (2002): 143-146.
Vance, Ashlee. ‘This Might Be the Most Life-Like (And Creepiest) Robot Ever Built.’ Bloomberg.
YouTube Oct 31, 2016 www.youtube.com/watch?v=oRlwvLubFxg Accessed on 28 Aug
2018.
Vasseleu, Cathryn. ‘Life Itself.’ Cartographies: Poststructuralism and the Mapping of Bodies and Spaces. Ed.
Rosalyn Diprose and Robyn Ferrell. Melbourne: Allen and Unwin, 1991. 55-64.
Vaswani, Ashish, Noam Shazeer, Niki Parmar, et al. ‘Attention Is All You Need.’ 31st Conference on
Neural Information Processing Systems (NIPS 2017), Long Beach, CA, USA. 1-15. Jun 17, 2017.
arxiv.org/abs/1706.03762 Accessed on 3 Feb 2020.
Vidan, Aida. ‘Irresistible irreverence: Dušan Makavejev’s amateur films and the Yugoslav cine-club
scene.’ Studies in Eastern European Cinema 7/1 (2016): 53-67.
Wakefield, Jerome C. ‘DSM-5 proposed diagnostic criteria for sexual paraphilias: Tensions between
diagnostic validity and forensic utility.’ International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 34/3 (2011);
195-209.
Waldemar, Kaempffert. ‘Rabbits Born in Glass: Haldane-Huxley Fantasy Made Real by Harvard
Biologists.’ New York Times May 13, 1934. Accessed on 11 Jul 2019.
Wang, Jeanette. ‘Five things to know about IVG – a new way to have babies by turning any cell in
our bodies into sperm or egg cells.’ South China Morning Post Jan 23, 2017
www.scmp.com/lifestyle/health-beauty/article/2064567/five-things-know-about-ivg-new-
way-have-babies-turning-any Accessed on 18 Jul 2019.
Ward, Victoria. ‘Sir Elton John boycotts Dolce & Gabbana after row over same-sex families.’ The
Telegraph Mar 15, 2015 www.telegraph.co.uk/news/celebritynews/11473198/Sir-Elton-John-
calls-for-Dolce-and-Gabbana-boycott-after-row-over-same-sex-families.html Accessed on 26
Jul 2019.
Warnock, Mary, Dame, et al. Report of the Committee of Inquiry into Human Fertilization and Embryology.
London: Department of Health and Social Security, 1984.
490
Waytz, Adam, Nicholas Epley, and John T. Cacioppo. ‘Social Cognition Unbound: Insights Into
Anthropomorphism and Dehumanization.’ Current Directions in Psychological Science 19/1
(2010): 58-62.
Weed, Kym. ‘Microbial Perspectives: Mark Twain’s Imaginative Experiment in Ethics.’ Literature and
Medicine 37/1 (2019): 219-40.
Weightman, John. ‘Language as Prosthesis.’ The Hudson Review 53/1 (2000): 53-62.
Weizenbaum, Joseph. ‘The Last Dream.’ Is Computer a Tool? Ed. by Bo Sundin. Stockholm: Almquist
& Wiksell International: 1980. 100-115.
Weisinger, Kenneth D. ‘Discourse Wars: Literary Seduction and Retrieval in Faust II.’ Cabinet of the
Muses: essays on classical and comparative literature in honor of Thomas G. Rosenmeyer. Ed by Mark
Griffith and Donald J. Mastronarde. Atlanta, GA: Scholars P, 1990. 387-402.
Weizenbaum, Joseph. Computer power and human reason: from judgment to calculation. San Francisco, CA:
W. H. Freeman, 1976.
Wells, H. G. ‘The Limits of Individual Plasticity.’ Saturday review of politics, literature, science and art
79/2047 (1895): 89-90.
Westlund, Jacqueline M. Kory, Sooyeon Jeong, Hae W. Park, Samuel Ronfard, Aradhana Adhikari,
Paul. L. Harris, David DeSteno, and Cynthia L. Breazeal. ‘Flat vs. Expressive Storytelling:
Young Children’s Learning and Retention of a Social Robot’s Narrative.’ Front Hum
Neuroscience 11/295 (2017).
Whitehurst, Grover J., and Ross Vasta. ‘Is Language Acquired Through Imitation?’ Journal of
Psycholinguist Research 4/1 (1975): 37-59.
Wiesling, Urban. ‘The History of Medical Enhancement: From Restitutio ad Integrum to Transformatio
ad Optimum?’ Medical Enhancement and Posthumanity. Eds. Bert Godijn and Ruth Chadwick.
Dordrecht: Springer, 2009. 9-24.
Williams, C., J. Kitzinger, and L. Henderson. ‘Envisaging the embryo in stem cell research: rhetorical
strategies and media reporting of the ethical debates.’ Sociology of Health and Illness 25 (2003):
793-814.
Wilson, Barbara A., Paul Allen, Anita Rose, and Veronika Kubickova. Locked-In Syndrome after Brain
Damage: Living Within My Head. London: Routledge, 2018.
Wilson, Duncan. Tissue Culture in Science and Society: The Public Life of a Biological Technique in Twentieth
Century Britain. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan, 2011.
491
Wilson, Mark. ‘The world’s first genderless AI voice is here. Listen now.’ March 2, 2019. Fast
Company www.fastcompany.com/90321378/the-worlds-first-genderless-ai-voice-is-here-
listen-now Accessed on 18 March 2019.
Winick, Erin. ‘Actors are digitally preserving themselves to continue their careers beyond the grave.’
MIT Technology Review Oct 16, 2018. www.technologyreview.com/s/612291/actors-are-
digitally-preserving-themselves-to-continue-their-careers-beyond-the-grave/ Accessed on 18
Mar 2019.
Wolchover, Natalie. ‘As Math Grows More Complex, Will Computers Reign?’ Wired Mar 4, 2013
www.wired.com/2013/03/computers-and-math/ Accessed on 4 Feb 2020.
---. Zoontologies: The Question of the Animal. Minneapolis, MN: U of Minnesota P, 2003.What is
Posthumanism? Minneapolis, MN: U of Minnesota P, 2010.
Woolley, Samuel C., and Philip N. Howard. ‘Political Communication, Computational Propaganda,
and Autonomus Agents.’ International Journal of Communication 10 (2016): 4882-90.
X.ai. ‘It’s a baby boy – Andrew Ingram.’ X.ai Blog. March 2, 2015 x.ai/blog/its-a-baby-boy-andrew-
ingram/ Accessed on 20 March 2019.
Xuan Ho, Beatrice, Sharon Jia Hui Loh, Woon Khiong Chan, Boon Seng Soh. ‘In Vivo Genome
Editing as a Therapeutic Approach.’ International Journal of Molecular Sciences 19/9 (2018): 2721.
Yao, Mariya. ‘Can Bots Manipulate Public Opinion?’ Topbots Nov 15, 2016. www.topbots.com/can-
bots-manipulate-public-opinion/ Accessed on 21 Jan 2020.
Yong, Ed. ‘The CRISPR Baby Scandal Gets Worse by the Day.’ The Atlantic Dec 3, 2018
www.theatlantic.com/science/archive/2018/12/15-worrying-things-about-crispr-babies-
scandal/577234/?utm_source=twb Accessed on 3 Dec 2018.
Young, Mark. The Guinness Book of World Records. New York, NY: Bantam Books, 1998.
Zeifman, Igal. ‘Bot Traffic Report 2016.’ Jan 24, 2017 www.imperva.com/blog/bot-traffic-report-
2016/?utm_campaign=Incapsula-moved Accessed on 16 Jun 2019.
Zetlin, Minda. ‘Kindle Unlimited Book Stuffing Scam Earns Millions and Amazon Isn’t Stopping It.’
Inc Jun 13, 2018 www.inc.com/minda-zetlin/amazon-book-stuffing-authors-scam-chance-
carter-romance-kindle-unlimited.html Accessed on 4 Feb 2020.
Zhang, John, Hui Liu, Shiyu Luo, Shuo Lu, Alejandro Chávez-Badiola, et al. ‘Live Birth Derived
from Oocyte Spindle Transfer to Prevent Mitochondrial Disease.’ Reproductive BioMedicine
Online 34/4 (2017): 361-368.
492
Zhang, Sarah. ‘It’s Possible to Inherit More DNA From One Parent Than the Other.’ The Atlantic
Oct 10, 2019 www.theatlantic.com/science/archive/2019/10/when-you-have-more-dna-
one-parent-other/599812/ Accessed on 20 Oct 2019.
---. ‘IVF Mix-Ups Have Broken the Definition of Parenthood.’ The Atlantic July 11, 2019
https://www.theatlantic.com/science/archive/2019/07/ivf-embryo-mix-up-
parenthood/593725/ Accessed on 20 Feb 2020.
Zheng, Yi, Xufeng Xue, Yue Shao, et al. ‘Controlled modelling of human epiblast and amnion
development using stem cells.’ Nature 573 (2019): 421-25.
Zhu, Tian. ‘In Vitro Fertilization.’ Embryo Project Encyclopedia July 22, 2009
embryo.asu.edu/pages/vitro-fertilization Accessed on 28 Jun 2019.
Zimmer, Carl. ‘Ghost DNA Hints at Africa’s Missing Ancient Humans.’ The New York Times Feb 12,
2020 www.nytimes.com/2020/02/12/science/west-africa-ancient-humans.html Accessed
on 3 Mar 2020.
Živković. Marko. Serbian Dreambook: National Imaginary in the Time of Milošević. Bloomington, IN:
Indiana UP, 2011.
493