Drone Warfare
Drone Warfare
S. Krishnan∗
52
Ethics of Drone Warfare
1 “Drones and the man”, The Economist, June 30, 2011, https://www.econom
ist.com/leaders/2011/07/30/drones-and-the-man.
53
S. Krishnan
Competing narratives
A key premise supporting the use of drones is that they
are more precise than typical aerial bombings and thus,
cause minimal collateral damage. Yet, there continues to be
disagreement as to how accurate these pinpoint assaults are,
and how many civilians are killed.2 Bureau of Investigative
54
Ethics of Drone Warfare
3 Sarah Leo, "A Picture of War: The CIA's Drone Strikes in Pakistan", Bureau
of Investigative Journalism, 2012, http://www.thebureauinvestigates.com/
stories/2012-09-10/a-picture-of-war-the-cias-drone-strikes-in-pakistan.
4 Speaker’s Briefing, “Psychological terror? Lessons from Pakistan and
Yemen”, Washington D.C., 2013, https://appgondrones.files.wordpress.
com/2013/03/speakers-briefings-05-03-2013.pdf.
5 “U.N. expert urges U.S. to reveal civilian drone deaths”, The Japan Times,
October 19, 2013, https://www.japantimes.co.jp/news/2013/10/19/world/
u-n-expert-urges-u-s-to-reveal-civilian-drone-deaths/#.XSLzjugzY2w.
6 New American Foundation, “International Security Data Site”, 2017, http://
securitydata.newamerica.net/.
7 “Pakistan Strikes”, Long War Journal, 2017, http://www. longwarjournal.
org/pakistan-strikes/.
8 “Will I be next? US drone strikes in Pakistan”, Amnesty International,
October 21, 2013, https://www.amnestyusa.org/reports/willi-be-next-us-
drone-strikes-in-pakistan/.
55
S. Krishnan
56
Ethics of Drone Warfare
57
S. Krishnan
58
Ethics of Drone Warfare
Ethical Aspects
Not everyone feels comfortable with all this. The increasing
deployment of military drones raises a wide variety of important
ethical questions, concerns, and challenges. Critics say the
legal and ethical issues surrounding the use of drones have
been neglected. Some of those concerns may be exaggerated,
but others need to be taken seriously, particularly if, as seems
certain, armies will increasingly fight with machines, not men.
19 Ibid.
20 “Civilian harm and conflict in Northwestern Pakistan”, Center for Civilians
in Conflict, October 20, 2010, https://civiliansinconflict.org/publications/
research/civilian-harm-conflict-northwest-pakistan/.
59
S. Krishnan
60
Ethics of Drone Warfare
61
S. Krishnan
25 The term asymmetric war is sometimes used in a more limited way, for
example, to refer to the tactical asymmetry of insurgent groups fighting
an established military power in the light of their ability to employ
62
Ethics of Drone Warfare
64
Ethics of Drone Warfare
30 David Luban, “What Would Augustine Do?”, Boston Review, July 6, 2012,
http://www.bostonreview.net/BR37.3/david_luban_obama_drones_just_
war_theory.php.
31 Bradley Jay Strawser, “Moral Predators: The Duty to Employ Uninhabited
Aerial Vehicles,” Journal of Military Ethics, Volume 9, Number 4, 2010,
pp. 342-368.
65
S. Krishnan
66
Ethics of Drone Warfare
35 Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars, (fourth edition), Basic Books, New
York, 2006, p. xiv.
36 Scott Shane, “Report Cites High Civilian Toll in Pakistan Drone Strikes,”
The New York Times (blog), September 25, 2012.
37 Kenneth Anderson, op. cit.
38 Department of Justice White Paper: Lawfulness of a Lethal Operation
Directed Against a U.S. Citizen Who Is a Senior Operational Leader of
67
S. Krishnan
68
Ethics of Drone Warfare
69
S. Krishnan
odd that, while the US claims that the GWOT is a war, it assigns
the operations of that war to a civilian organisation. As Mary
Ellen O’Connell notes: “Only members of the United States
armed forces have the combatant’s privilege to use lethal force
without facing prosecution. CIA operatives are not trained in
the law of armed conflict.”45 Indeed, in this regard, the US
policy faces a dilemma. Either a targeted killing by drone in
Pakistan, say, is an act of war (as the US claims) or it is not.
If it is an act of war, it is not morally acceptable because the
rules of war require that acts of war be undertaken by military
rather than civilian personnel. If it is not an act of war, then it is
morally unacceptable because it falls under the policing rather
the warring paradigm and does not show the proper respect for
human rights.
In addition to these conceptual and moral objections to
the claim that GWOT is a war in the proper sense, there are
also objections from International Law. These are developed
by Philip Alston.46 He argues that according to International
Humanitarian Law (IHL), there are two conditions that must
be satisfied for hostilities to constitute an armed conflict
(that is, a war). One is that an armed conflict is a struggle
between sufficiently organised and structured “parties.” But
“al Qaeda and other alleged ‘associated’ groups are often only
45 Mary Ellen O’Connell, “Lawful Use.” In dissent, however, Philip Aston,
United Nations Special Rapporteur concerned with targeted killings,
avers that International Humanitarian Law does not prohibit non-military
personnel from engaging in conflict. “Report of the Special Rapporteur
on Extrajudicial, Summary, or Arbitrary Execution: Study on Targeted
Killings,” United Nations Human Rights Council, http://www2.ohchr.org/
english/ bodies/hrcouncil/docs/14session/A.HRC.14.24.Add6.pdf, paragra
phs 70-71.
46 Altston was the United Nations Special Rapporteur on Extrajudicial,
Summary or Arbitrary Executions. “Study on targeted killings”, United
Nations, May 28, 2010, http://www2.ohchr.org/english/bodies/hrcouncil/
docs/14session/A.HRC.14.24.Add6.pdf.
70
Ethics of Drone Warfare
71
S. Krishnan
are just another “delivery tool” to apply lethal force, like a rifle
or a piece of artillery. The point he clearly misses though is that
unlike the rifleman or tank driver, the drone operator is sitting
safely thousands of miles away, and it is this very distance–
both physical and psychological – that is a key ethical issue.
Those who defend drone strikes outside conventional wars
have an added argument to justify these strikes. They claim
that the strikes are an exercise of a right of national self-
defense. For example, the US claims: “Targeting a member of
an enemy force who poses an imminent threat of violent attack
to the United States is not unlawful. It is a lawful act of self-
defense.”49 This claim is interesting because it offers what is
in effect a third way to justify drones strikes, an effort to deny
that the paradigms of policing and warring are exhaustive. In
this spirit, defenders of drones have appealed to a principle of
national self-defense. This principle can be seen as a hybrid
between the two paradigms. Like the warring paradigm, it
permits the killing of individuals without judicial process, and
like the policing paradigm, it is not inconsistent with human
rights.
The national self-defense justification is based on a domestic
analogy with individual self-defense, but the government’s
understanding of it may be based on confusion between the
just war categories of jus ad bellum and jus in bello.50 The
initiation of war under jus ad bellum can be justified on the
72
Ethics of Drone Warfare
73
S. Krishnan
74
Ethics of Drone Warfare
risk.54 There are two responses to this view. First, not all wars
claimed to be humanitarian are just wars. Some wars fought
by powerful states are disingenuously given a humanitarian
rationale or are overall unjust despite having a humanitarian
rationale (as with the 2003 Iraq War). (A humanitarian
intervention, like any war, is unjust in case it fails to satisfy
the criteria of jus ad bellum.) Nor can a state’s belief that its
war is humanitarian guarantee that it is so. Second, justified
humanitarian interventions fought exclusively by drones are
less likely to succeed in their humanitarian purpose. Again,
Kosovo is an example. It is generally acknowledged that more
Kosovars would have been saved from Serb forces had NATO
fought the war with troops on the ground. Overall, the value
of restraining powerful states from fighting drone-only wars
outweighs the risk that some of these would be just wars.
A stronger point may be made about riskless humanitarian
intervention: it may be an incoherent notion. “Riskless
war in pursuit of human rights is,” Kahn argues, “a moral
contradiction.”55 This is because the moral message of riskless
humanitarian war is that the lives of combatants of the
intervening state “are of greater value than the lives of those
who might benefit from these interventions,” which creates
“an incompatibility between the morality of the ends, which
are universal, and the morality of the means,” which favor one
group over another.”56
75
S. Krishnan
76
Ethics of Drone Warfare
58 Ibid.
77
S. Krishnan
78
Ethics of Drone Warfare
Grave Consequences
The prospect of totally autonomous drones would radically
alter the complex processes and decisions behind military
killings. But legal and ethical responsibility does not somehow
just disappear if you remove human oversight. Instead,
responsibility will increasingly fall on other people, including
artificial intelligence scientists.
The legal implications of these developments are already
becoming evident. Under current international humanitarian
law, “dual-use” facilities – those which develop products for
both civilian and military application – can be attacked in the
right circumstances. For example, in the 1999 Kosovo War,
the Pancevo oil refinery was attacked because it could fuel
Yugoslav tanks as well as fuel civilian cars.
With an autonomous drone weapon system, certain lines of
computer code would almost certainly be classed as dual-use.
Companies like Google, its employees or its systems, could
become liable to attack from an enemy state. For example,
if Google’s Project Maven image recognition AI software is
incorporated into an American military autonomous drone,
Google could find itself implicated in the drone “killing”
business, as might every other civilian contributor to such
lethal autonomous systems.
Ethically, there are even darker issues still. The whole point
of the self-learning algorithms – programs that independently
learn from whatever data they can collect – that the technology
uses is that they become better at whatever task they are given.
If a lethal autonomous drone is to get better at its job through
self-learning, someone will need to decide on an acceptable
stage of development – how much it still has to learn – at which
it can be deployed. In militarised machine learning, that means
79
S. Krishnan
Policy Recommendations
Drones present, in terms of the difficulties they have in
satisfying the principles of jus in bello and their tendency to
make possible riskless war, what was referred to earlier as
extraordinary moral problems. Ordinary moral problems can
be resolved by tweaking the technology or altering how it is
used, but extraordinary moral problems are difficult to resolve
in this way. Their solution may require that the technology be
abandoned. The first two objections reveal the ordinary moral
problems that drone use gives rise to. These problems could
be largely avoided by using drones in a different way. But the
last three objections reveal that drone use has moral problems
that are extraordinary, problems effectively inherent in the
technology, problems that are not subject to easy correction by
attempts to limit their use to acceptable forms.
What practical and feasible policy commendations follow
from our conclusions about drone technology? First, any
solution must be systemic. The problems cannot be corrected
unilaterally, by requiring, say, that military commanders
deliberately expose their combatants to unnecessary risk in
order to avoid a situation of extreme asymmetry. Kahn notes:
80
Ethics of Drone Warfare
81
S. Krishnan
62 Nuclear weapons have been only partially banned through the Nuclear
Non-Proliferation Treaty, but they represent a special case.
82
Ethics of Drone Warfare
83