Hello Austen, Goodbye Austin
Hello Austen, Goodbye Austin
The study of law, it might be argued, would be much more enjoyable and
productive if we said goodbye to John Austin and hello to Jane Austen, auf
wiedersehen to Kelsen and wilkommen to Kafka. A pan-European introduction to
law through literature would stretch from the Irish Swift, through the English
Shakespeare and Dickens, on to the Continental Camus and Kafka, down to the
classical Greek Socrates and Sophocles and up to the Russian Dostoevsky. This is a
rich heritage and one which offers a critical yet rounded picture of law in society.
Students would actually read the texts rather than purport to tell me what, for
instance, Mill said when I know full well that they are actually telling me what they
think I said about what Han said about what Devlin said about what Mill said.
Rather than looking askance at being set thirty pages, they would willingly read
hundreds of pages a week. Students would also realize that there was more to law
than the decisions, or even more narrowly the decision-making processes, of
appellate courts. They would discover facts, criminal and civil procedure in
common law and civil law jurisdictions, evidence, witnesses, credibility, corrup-
tion, cynicism about lawyers and many other wondrous things. They would
discover how Portia used black letter tactics of literal interpretation to achieve what
has often been portrayed as justice (although we might differ on the fairness of the
outcome). They would inevitably be drawn into exploring Biblical references to
law, understanding that Ishmael rather than, say, Baby M, was the first surrogate
baby.' As Richard Posner, the leading economic analyst of law and now a United
States federal appeals judge, concludes in Law & Literature:
Law schools should offer courses in law and literature; some are doing so already. Most of
the issues that would be covered in such a course could, it is true, be covered in a course
on jurisprudence or legal process stressing the rhetoric, theoretical underpinnings and
dilemmas, interpretive problems and epistemology of law. But such a course is not likely
to be so vivid, memorable and entertaining as a well-taught course in law and literature
. . . A course in law and literature can also provide an introduction to legal history, legal
t A review of Richard Posner, Law and Liuraturt: A Mwmdmtood Relation (Harvard University Press, 1988),
£19.95 (hereafter Posner, L & L), and Stanky Fish, Doing What Coma Naturally: Change Rhetoric and tkt Practice of
Theory in Literary and LtgalStudies (Oxford University Press, 1989), £35.00 (hardback) (hereafter Fish, DWCN).
* Professor of Law, The Queen's University, Belfast-
1
h re Baby M, 537 A 2d 1227(1988).
• Oxford University Press 1990 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies Vol. 10, No. 2
SUMMER 1990 Law and Literature 253
anthropology, and comparative law . . . It may even provide a solution to the age-old
problem of teaching legal writing. In addition, law and literature provides a way into
feminist legal theory, the law-as-a-humanity movement and the critical legal studies
movement.2
Sociologists of law and some criminologists have, of course, also long been
interested in the ways in which law is perceived through popular culture. Most
obviously, changing images of the police, criminals and the criminal law can be
beyond the territory of those lawyers who have long since realized that Dworkin
was an unsafe guide to all but a few leading American cases on civil liberties. 5 Now
we are told by Fish that Dworkin is wrong, wrong and wrong again whenever he
talks about non-legal interpretation and, for that matter, when he claims that
lawyers in general and judges in particular are always philosophers. As Fish puts it,
in a comment aimed at the Critical Legal Studies movement as well as Dworkin:
'law is not philosophy, and it will not fade away because a few guys in Cambridge
Dworkin declares that to interpret [an Agatha] Christie mystery as 'a novel about the
meaning of death would be a mistake, because it would make the novel a shambles, and
that is not because all novels announce their own genre but because her novels become
wrecks if we try to read them in that particular way". This is a nice sentence because the
basic Dworkin move is performed twice . . . [I]n the same sentence we have a positivist
assertion followed by a repudiation of positivism followed by another—virtually
identical—positivist assertion.''
9
See eg Let, Judging Judges, especially cb 3.
6
See Fish, OWCW at 397.
7
Fish, DWCN at 398. Fiih would also like his baseball players to be good baseball players rather than good
philosophers of baseball. The chapter ii constructed around a journalist's question to Martinez about his coach's words
of wisdom before a game, namely Throw strikes and keep 'em off the bases'. Martinez's response to the coach was
'OK' tnd to the journalist, he added with a precision which Fish thinks Wittgenstein might have envied, "What else
could I say? What else could he say?1 Fish thinks that 'It is hard to imagine why agents genuinely committed to a
practice would hand over responsibility for judging it to some other practice, especially to a practice that takes place
almost exclusively in college classrooms*.
* Although Fish might regard this as inevitable given my professional interest, some legal philosophers agree with
him that the power of jurisprudence is not in its relation to practice, see eg Harris, Legal Phltaophts, at 2.
9
Fan, DWCN at 112. See Levinson Taking Law Seriously; Reflections on Thinking Like a Lawyer* (1978) 30
Stanford Law Review 1071, acknowledged by Fisb and, for a non-lawyer, Brian Barry in Tht Times Literary
Supplement, 25 October 1985, at 1195.
10
Fish, DWCN»t IU.
11
Fish, DWCN n 112.
SUMMER 1990 Law and Literature 255
about Agatha Christie's work.12 As an example, Fish offers his own defence of
Agatha Christie's theory of evil, comparing her amoral and chameleon-like villains
with Shakespeare's Iago and Milton's Satan.13 In words which echo lawyers'
criticisms of Dworkin's legal examples, Fish concludes that 'Dworkin, it would
seem, could not have chosen a worse example to support his case'.14
Fish is equally biting in his criticism of Posner. In the relevant chapter, entitled
'Don't Know Much About The Middle Ages', Fish's point seems to be that Posner
12
See eg Grostvogd, Mystery and Its Fictions:fromOedifms to Agatha Chrisnt (1979).
13
Fnh,DlFCNat96-7.
14
Fish, DWCN at footnote 13 to ch 4, at 360; cf Lee, Judging Judgts, tt 21-2.
" Posner, 'Law & Literature: A Relation Reargued', (1986) 72 Virginia Law Revitw 1351.
16
Fuh,DIPCA/at310.
17
Fish, DWCN at 311.
11
Fuh, DWCN at 308.
19
See eg Posner, L Qt L at 6-9, 71-2.
20
From time to time, admissions tutors are depressed by head-teachers' reference* which sty something like 'Mary
is highly intelligent, not very imaginative but she has a good memory and works hard, so she should make an fir****"!!
lawyer'. Such a verdict on her lack of imagination should not determine poor Mary's future but it should act as a
warning about head-teachers' perceptions of law, lawyers and legal study.
21
See eg Posner, L & L , ch 3 "The Literary Indictment of LegaJ Injustice'.
256 Oxford Journal of Legal Studies VOL.10
22
The law's predilection for censorship is notorious. And as for rhetoric, lawyers
are frequently seen as straining the quality of credulity, if not mercy.
Much of this scepticism is justified and is a valuable corrective to legal smugness.
Nevertheless, some of the cynicism is ill-founded and all of it should be a matter of
concern. Perceptions of law, through high and low culture, are important for the
way in which the law operates in practice. Those who are put off the law by popular
misconceptions may be denied justice.23 Hence it is important to confront the
22
Eg the Spycatcher saga and the Home Secretary 1 ! 1988 Order restricting televised speech by Sinn Fein. For
discussions of both and of other examples, see Lee, Tht Cost of Fret Speech (Faber, forthcoming 1990).
23
Note, eg, the Labour government's concerns to keep courts out of welfare state issues in the 1960s partly because
many Labour voters were wary of courts and would otherwise fail to vindicate their rights, see eg Harlow & Rawlings,
Law & Administration (1984), p 71.
24
Swift, Gulliver's Travels, Pan IV, 'A Voyage to the Houyhnhnms', ch 5 (295-7 in the Penguin Classics edition).
25
Posner, L & L at 180.
SUMMER 1990 Law and Literature 257
26 27
world into intentionalists and New Critics. He is an intentionalist as to legal
texts and a New Critic as to literary texts, primarily because the former constitutes
his business where he is in a powerful position as a judge without the disciphne of a
free market in judging and judicial interpretation, whereas the latter is, for him, a
leisure activity of no great importance where the market will weed out hopeless
interpretations. Dworkin is characterized by Posner as a New Critic in relation to
both kinds of texts, trying to interpret each so as to make them into the 'best' work
* Widgery, Report of the Tribunal appointed to inquire into the evenu on Sunday, 30th January 1972, which led to
Ion of life in connection with the procexsion in Londonderry on that day (London, HMSO 1972, HL 101, HC 220).
" See Treitel (1984) 100 LQR 549.