The Commodity-Form and The Dialectical Method: On The Structure of Marx's Exposition in Chapter 1 of Capital
The Commodity-Form and The Dialectical Method: On The Structure of Marx's Exposition in Chapter 1 of Capital
72,METHOD
ScienceDIALECTICAL No. 3, July 2008, 295–318
295
GUIDO STAROSTA*
ABSTRACT: The last 10 or 15 years have witnessed a renewed
interest in Marx’s dialectical method and its implications for value
theory. However, most works have not sufficiently thematized the
peculiar role of the phase of analysis in Marx’s dialectical inves-
tigation generally and in his presentation in particular. Further-
more, they have not paid sufficient attention to the specific form
of the analytical process within dialectical thought, which distin-
guishes it from the kind of analysis characteristic of formal–logical
methodologies. Those two questions are crucial for a proper
comprehension of the dialectical structure of Marx’s argument
in Chapter 1 of Capital and, in particular, to clarify the determi-
nate place where the unfolding of the explanation of the deter-
minations of privately performed abstract labor as the substance
of value is to be found. That explanation is actually contained in
section 3, where Marx presents the synthetic development of the
expression of value into the money-form.
I
N THE PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION of Capital Marx
makes evident that he was well aware of the complexity of the first
steps in the critique of political economy (Marx, 1976a, 89). In-
deed, the endless debates over the real meaning and implications of
Marx’s discussion of the commodity-form seem to suggest that, if
anything, Marx’s warning actually fell short of the real difficulties at
stake. On the other hand, whether it is explicitly acknowledged or
* I would like to thank Simon Clarke, Juan Iñigo Carrera, Nicolás Grinberg and Axel Kicillof
for helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper. The usual caveat applies.
295
296 SCIENCE & SOCIETY
1 As I have argued elsewhere (see Starosta, 2003), elaboration of the connection between
the specific dialectical form of Marx’s scientific method and its revolutionary content is
perhaps the single most important contribution of Lukács’ History and Class Consciousness.
A discussion of the fundamental political implications of the more abstract determina-
tions of capital can be found in Starosta, 2005.
2 See Clarke, 1994 and Shortall, 1994 for good reconstructions of Marx’s critique of Proud-
honian socialism based on the latter’s misunderstanding of the nature of the commodity
and money-forms. Thus, the gist of Marx’s critique of Gray’s proposal to preserve private
commodity-production while replacing the money-form with labor-time certificates issued
by a national bank, comes down to the latter’s inability to comprehend the immanent
necessity of the value of commodities to take on the independent form of money (Elson,
1979b, 135–136). Similarly, in the Grundrisse Marx ridicules Darimon’s proposal of abol-
ishing the privilege of money (that of being directly exchangeable for all commodities)
by making “by decree” all commodities directly exchangeable (Marx, 1993, 126). In all
these cases, the common thread of the Marxian critique lies in the incapacity of those
authors to grasp the necessary inner connection between the commodity- and money-forms.
This, in turn, is underpinned by a methodological shortcoming. As I argue below, theories
based on formal logic can only grasp social forms as self-subsistent entities or immediate
affirmations and not as the self-negating mode of existence of a more abstract social form
(i.e., the movement of contradiction). As a consequence, they are bound to represent their
necessary inner connections as merely external ones.
COMMODITY-FORM AND DIALECTICAL METHOD 297
3 The distinction between analysis (in the sense of dissection of the “whole” into “parts” or
“identification of differences”) and synthesis (in the sense of reconstitution of the “unity”
of the whole) is not peculiar to dialectics. As I argue below, what sets the latter apart from
formal–logical methodologies is the specific form taken both by the analytical and synthetic
processes in dialectical thought. Zelený (1980, ch. 10) provides a concise discussion of
the different meanings of analysis and synthesis in science and philosophy, which also
traces back their intellectual lineage.
4 These other aspects have not been entirely absent in the literature. However, they came
up in the debate among “new dialecticians” only quite recently (Murray, 2002; Reuten,
2000). See Brown, et al., 2002, for a discussion of some of these issues through a compari-
son between critical realism and systematic dialectics. Also, it is my view that compared to
the light thrown on the synthetic aspects of Marx’s method of presentation, the nature of
the relation between analysis and synthesis in the presentation and the way in which this
relates to the formal determinations of the dialectical inquiry, have not been explored
with the same clarity.
5 In my own reading I draw on the methodological approach to the critique of political
economy developed by Iñigo Carrera (1992; 2003).
298 SCIENCE & SOCIETY
6 On the methodological differences between the early critique of alienated labor in the
Paris Manuscripts and its more developed form in Capital, see Starosta, 2005, chs. 1 and 4.
7 For a critique of the Engelsian orthodoxy on this question see Arthur, 1997; 1998; Robles
Báez, 2000; and Reichelt, 1995.
8 Properly speaking, there is a previous step in Marx’s presentation. He first starts with the
form in which social wealth appears in capitalist society, namely, an “immense collection
of commodities” (Marx, 1976a, 125), the individual commodity being its elementary form.
The unfolding of the determinations behind this appearance is not completed until Vol-
ume II, where the unity of the movement of social capital itself, in the form of the circuit
of commodity-capital, is revealed as positing social wealth in the form of an immense
collection of commodities (Marx, 1978, 174–177).
COMMODITY-FORM AND DIALECTICAL METHOD 299
and theological niceties” (Marx, 1976a, 163), he shows that what de-
termines the commodity as a form of social wealth is not only that, as
any product of labor, it possesses a use-value, but that the latter acts as
the material bearer of a second attribute, namely exchange-value. The
further analysis of the commodity reveals that exchange-value is actu-
ally the form of expression of a content distinguishable from it — the
value-form, or the attribute of general exchangeability of the commodity
— the substance of which resides in the abstract labor congealed in it,
and whose magnitude is consequently determined by the socially neces-
sary abstract labor-time required for its production.
The above line of reasoning has been the subject of all kinds of
objections put forward by the different interpreters of Marx. As I
argue below, those reservations about Marx’s argument have their
source in an inadequate comprehension of, or insufficient attention
to, the nature of the crucial distinction between two different mo-
ments involved in Marx’s dialectical inquiry and presentation, namely
the stage of analysis and that of synthesis. In particular, I think that it
is confusion over these questions that lies at the basis of widespread
critiques of Marx’s line of argument about the determinations of the
commodity-form; not only by well-known critics such as Böhm-Bawerk
(1975), but also among some of Marx’s disciples.9 In brief, the gen-
eral thrust of those objections goes, Marx did not provide in Capital
an adequate “logical proof ” that commodities have a “something” in
common and that that “something” is congealed abstract labor.10
9 Thus both Reuten (1993, 107) and Arthur (1993, 76) agree that Böhm-Bawerk’s objections
to Marx’s line of reasoning about abstract labour as the substance of value are justified; not
because Marx is wrong in seeing an inner connection between abstract labor and value,
but because his grounding of that point is defective from a “systematic–dialectical” per-
spective. Unlike Arthur, who argues that the introduction of abstract labor as the substance
of value should have been postponed until the development of the capital-form, Reuten
goes even further in his distance from Marx’s presentation and makes a case against the
determination of abstract labor as substance of value. Rather, he sees the market as trans-
forming concrete labor into abstract labor (Reuten, 1993, 105).
10 A good and concise account of the essence of this critique can be found in Kay (1979,
48–58; see also Park, 2003). Specifically, Böhm-Bawerk objected that Marx did not take
into consideration common properties other than being products of labor — e.g., utility,
scarcity, and so on — as possible determinants of exchange-value (Böhm-Bawerk, 1975,
74–75). In this sense, it might be worth noting that in the process of inquiry Marx did
consider — but discarded and, hence, excluded from the presentation — “utility in gen-
eral” as the substance of value. This is evidenced by the following remarks from the pre-
paratory Manuscripts of 1861–63:
“We have seen that the basis of value is the fact that human beings relate to each other’s
labor as equal, and general, and in this form social, labor. This is an abstraction, like all
human thought, and social relations only exist among human beings to the extent that they
think, and possess this power of abstraction from sensuous individuality and contingency.
300 SCIENCE & SOCIETY
The first point at stake in this objection has already been force-
fully made by other scholars, so I will refer to it very briefly. In a
nutshell, the question comes down to the radical methodological
difference which, as Meikle insightfully notes, separates Marx’s dia-
lectical approach to science from the formalism and atomism of
bourgeois conceptions (Meikle, 1985, ch. 3). Clearly based on the
latter, Böhm-Bawerk’s objections came from someone who could only
see science as a purely “logical construct” and not the reproduction
in thought of “how things essentially are” (Meikle, 1985, 80). Thus,
with “the characteristic empiricist gap between ‘truths’ and the enti-
ties they are supposed to be true of” (Meikle, 1985, 79), he could only
read Marx’s initial pages as an abstract, formal process of “logical
proof.” The possibility that those pages unfold the real nature and
specific self-movement of a determinate content (the commodity-
form of the product of labor) and do not contain a formal deduc-
tion was beyond Böhm-Bawerk’s formalistic field of vision (Kay, 1979,
51–52).
Second, and more important for the purpose of this paper, at
stake here is another aspect of Marx’s argument in the first pages of
Capital that has not been sufficiently or satisfactorily explored by most
scholars: the specific nature and significance of the difference be-
tween the phase of analysis and that of synthesis within a dialectical
exposition. This double movement in the dialectical presentation is not
an arbitrary stylistic or rhetorical strategy introduced by Marx but
reflects a real difference characterizing the specificity of dialectical
inquiry. The latter must involve both identification of the different
forms taken by the subject whose determinations the dialectical in-
vestigation attempts to reproduce in thought (i.e., the analytical sepa-
ration between social forms according to their relative degree of
concreteness) and the “tracking down of their inner connection” (i.e.,
the synthetic discovery of the immanent real necessity linking those
. . . We have seen that the basis of value is the fact that human beings relate to each other’s
labor as equal, and general, and in this form social, labor. The kind of political economist
who attacks the determination of value by labor time on the ground that the work per-
formed by 2 individuals during the same time is not absolutely equal (although in the
same trade), doesn’t yet even know what distinguishes human social relations from rela-
tions between animals. He is a beast. As beasts, the same fellows then also have no diffi-
culty in overlooking the fact that no 2 use values are absolutely identical (no 2 leaves,
Leibniz) and even less difficulty in judging use-values, which have no common measure
whatever, as exchange values according to their degree of utility” (Marx, 1988, 232).
COMMODITY-FORM AND DIALECTICAL METHOD 301
11 Here my approach differs from both Murray’s and Reuten’s. The former seems simply to
identify inquiry (what he calls “phenomenology”) with analysis and synthesis with presen-
tation (Murray, 2000, 36–38). Reuten does allow for synthetic moments in the process of
inquiry but only as “provisional outlines of inseparability of phenomena” (Reuten, 2000,
143). Moreover, although he is right to see the need for the dialectical presentation to
be fundamentally synthetic, he does not fully explore the possibility that the dialectical
researcher presenting the results of the inquiry may include “stylized” moments of analy-
sis in order to highlight the unity of the dialectical process of cognition. He only men-
tions this possibility in passing when discussing Banaji’s argument about the two-fold
starting point of chapter 1 of Capital (Banaji, 1979, 36–40; Reuten, 2000, 158). But as
I argue below, this presentational strategy plays a central role at least in the whole of
Volume I.
12 On the role and the pros and cons of this analytic moment in the peculiar structure of
the dialectical exposition in Capital I, organized around presentational “nodes,” see Iñigo
Carrera, 1992; 2003, 285.
13 For an illustration of this presentational structure with reference to the transformation
of money into capital, see Starosta, 2005.
14 Marx sometimes includes apparent (hence flawed) analytical paths in his exposition that
are revealed to be such through a movement that leads the reader back to the unmedi-
ated starting point, that is, without making any progress towards the discovery of the
underlying specific determination defining the object under scrutiny (Iñigo Carrera, 2003,
282). The presentational role of the inclusion of these flawed analytical movements is
mainly pedagogical; they serve to place more emphasis on the correct analytical path.
302 SCIENCE & SOCIETY
Marx’s consideration of the possibility that the particular material properties of the com-
modity under investigation constitute the more abstract form behind the attribute of
general exchangeability is an example of this (Marx, 1976a, 127–128). Incidentally, it
is to be noted that this is the real meaning of what Böhm-Bawerk mistakenly saw as Marx’s
“method of exclusion,” through which he allegedly provided a “purely negative proof”
of abstract labor as the substance of value (Böhm-Bawerk, 1975, 68–69).
COMMODITY-FORM AND DIALECTICAL METHOD 303
15 In his Science of Logic, Hegel refers to this distinction between the role of analysis and syn-
thesis as the difference between the apprehension of what is and its comprehension (Hegel,
1999, 793–794).
16 Regarding Chapter 1 in particular, this presentational structure has been broadly recog-
nized quite early in the debate by Banaji (1979) and Elson (1979b). However, they both
seem to reduce the content of the synthetic stage of the presentation simply to the ques-
tion of revealing exchange-value as the necessary mode of expression of value, i.e. to the
formal necessity of the money-form. But as I argue below, the latter is precisely the mo-
ment where Marx is synthetically unfolding the necessity of privately performed abstract
labor as the substance of value. Yet, neither Elson nor Banaji explicitly addresses the ques-
tion of where exactly the “why” of abstract labor as the substance of value can be found.
Elson in particular seems to concur with Rubin (see below) that it is actually in section 4.
Murray (1988, 148–149) rightly sees the structure of Chapter 1 as comprising a “double
movement” of form to content and then from content to form. However, presumably
reducing the dialectical movement to the synthetic stage, he sees nothing particularly
dialectical in the form of the first movement (Murray, 1988, 148); hence his analogy with
Descartes’ analytical reduction of the bit of wax to primary quality matter, i.e. a search for
a “third party” or common element (Murray, 1988, 149). In reality, the general point about
the two-fold movement of analysis and synthesis in Marx’s exposition had already been
made by Rubin in his seminal work on the theory of value (Rubin, 1972, 113). However,
his understanding of the way they structure the exposition is, I think, incorrect. In a nut-
shell, Rubin considers that the content of the section on fetishism is what in reality corre-
sponds to the section on the form of value or exchange-value, i.e. the synthetic exposition
of the reason why the product of labor must take the value-form. Furthermore, although
Rubin does distinguish between the analytic and the synthetic (genetic, as he calls it) stages
of the presentation, he also seems to restrict the specificity of the dialectical argument to
the latter (Rubin, 1978, 110). In this way, the specific form of the dialectical analysis vis-
à-vis the analysis of formal logic is overlooked.
304 SCIENCE & SOCIETY
17 The distinction has been posed in the literature as one between “real abstractions vs.
mental generalization” (Saad-Filho, 2002) or “empiricist abstractions vs. determinate
abstractions” (Gunn, 1992). “Empiricist abstractions” have also been called “formal ab-
stractions” (Clarke, 1991) or “general abstractions” (Murray, 1988).
COMMODITY-FORM AND DIALECTICAL METHOD 305
18 I am indebted to discussions with Juan Iñigo Carrera (personal communication) for this
formulation of the fetishistic character of commodities.
306 SCIENCE & SOCIETY
form presents itself. Again, this is the immediate object of Marx’s ex-
position in the passages that follow, and not the search for a “common
something” or “third thing,” the existence of which the distinction be-
tween form and content presupposes.19 This separation between form
and content reveals that the different particular exchange relations that
a commodity establishes with other commodities are actually expres-
sions of something else that inheres in commodities and which gives
them the identical qualitative potentiality of general exchangeability in a
certain magnitude. Once form and content of the attribute of general
exchangeability are distinguished, Marx continues with the analysis
of the latter, which consists in separating that form of general ex-
changeability from the more abstract form whose realized necessity
it carries within itself as its “other.” The particular form that this
analysis takes is, again, not the search for a common element, but
for the determinate action which posits that specific attribute exist-
ing in commodities. After briefly considering and discarding the
action of purely natural forces, Marx points out that the action at stake
is a human action in one of its facets: productive labor in its general
character, or abstract labor. Commodities have this attribute of gen-
eral exchangeability as products of the abstract character of the labor
objectified in them.
And here there is a tricky aspect in Marx’s presentation, which
might have contributed to much of the confusion. Because, although
at that stage of the argument he has already shown that the common
“something” is the form of general exchangeability, he does not ac-
tually name it until separating, in turn, that form from its material
content or substance.
All these things now tell us is that human labour-power has been expended
to produce them, human labour is accumulated in them. As crystals of this
social substance, which is common to them all, they are values — commodity
values [Warenwerte].
19 In order to avoid confusions, I am not implying that the existence of a common prop-
erty and of exchange equivalence are not important elements of Marx’s arguments. My
point is that Marx is not logically proving the existence of a common property or that the
only possible substance of that common property is abstract labor. He “finds” that com-
mon property immanent in the commodity (actually, its immediate manifestation) and
then proceeds to its dialectical analysis (i.e., separation of form and content). See Kicillof
and Starosta, forthcoming, for a fuller discussion of why being the products of the
abstract character of labor is the only reasonable determination behind the value of
commodities.
COMMODITY-FORM AND DIALECTICAL METHOD 307
We see, then, that everything our analysis of the value of commodities pre-
viously told us is repeated by the linen itself, as soon as it enters into asso-
ciation with another commodity, the coat. Only it reveals its thoughts in a
language with which it alone is familiar, the language of commodities. In
order to tell us that labour creates its own value in its abstract quality of being
human labour, it says that the coat, in so far as it counts as its equal, i.e., is
value, consists of the same labour as it does itself. In order to inform us that
21 In a recent article, Arthur (2004, 41–42) also acknowledges this important aspect of Marx’s
presentation. However, he still maintains that Marx failed to provide in Chapter 1 an
adequate explanation for the determination of abstract labor as the substance of value
and should have postponed the introduction of abstract labor until the level of abstrac-
tion of the capital-form (Arthur, 2005, 119). The shortcoming of this view — also shared
by Lapavitsas (2005) — is that it leads to a formalistic understanding of the value-form,
which obscures the very question that the latter, in its own reified way, is meant to solve:
the establishment of the material unity of social labor when it takes the form of private
labor (Brown, 2004). This idiosyncratic separation of the form of value from its substance
at the level of the commodity-form had already been advanced by Itoh (1988). See Clarke,
1989, for a critique of Itoh’s radical separation of the theory of the form of value and the
theory of the substance of value.
310 SCIENCE & SOCIETY
its sublime objectivity as value differs from its stiff and starchy existence as
a body, it says that value has the appearance of a coat, and consequently
that in so far as the linen itself is an object of value [Wertding], it and the
coat are as like as two peas. (Marx, 1976a, 143–144.)
we can see that the materialized social relation itself — the value-form
— affirms itself as the mediator in the articulation of that division of labor,
i.e., in establishing the relation between different labors as organic
specifications of human labor in general.
As values the commodities are expressions of the same unity, of abstract human
labour. In the form of exchange value they appear to one another as values
and relate themselves to one another as values. They thereby relate themselves
at the same time to abstract labour as their common social substance. Their
social relationship consists exclusively in counting with respect to one another
as expressions of this social substance of theirs which differs only quantita-
tively, but which is qualitatively equal and hence replaceable and inter-
changeable with one another. . . . It is only the kind of thing that can turn
mere objects of use into commodities and hence set into a social rapport. But
this is just what value is. The form in which the commodities count to one
another as values — as coagulations of human labour — is consequently their
social form. (Marx, 1976b, 28–29; italics in original.)
Conclusion
Department of Sociology
University of Warwick
Coventry CV4 7AL
United Kingdom
[email protected]
REFERENCES
Albritton, Robert, and John Simoulidis, eds. 2003. New Dialectics and Political Economy.
Basingstoke, England: Palgrave Macmillan.
Arthur, Christopher J. 1993. “Hegel’s Logic and Marx’s Capital.” Pp. 63–88 in Fred
Moseley, ed., Marx’s Method in Capital: A Reexamination. Atlantic Highlands, New
Jersey: Humanities Press.
———. 1997. “Against the Logical–Historical Method: Dialectical Derivation ver-
sus Linear Logic.” Pp. 9–37 in Fred Moseley and Martha Campbell, eds., New
Investigations of Marx’s Method. Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey: Humanities
Press.
———. 1998. “Engels, Logic and History.” Pp. 3–15 in Bellofiore, ed.
———. 2001. “Value, Labour and Negativity.” Capital and Class, 73 (Spring), 15–39.
———. 2002. The New Dialectic and Marx’s Capital. Lieden, The Netherlands: Brill
Academic Publishers.
316 SCIENCE & SOCIETY
———. 2004. “Money and the Form of Value.” Pp. 35–63 in Riccardo Bellofiore
and Nicola Taylor, eds., The Constitution of Capital. Essays on Volume I of Marx’s
Capital. Basingstoke, England: Palgrave Macmillan.
———. 2005. “Value and Money.” Pp. 111–123 in Fred Moseley, ed., Marx’s Theory
of Money: Modern Appraisals. Basingstoke, England: Palgrave Macmillan.
Banaji, Jairus. 1979. “From the Commodity to Capital: Hegel’s Dialectic in Marx’s
Capital.” Pp. 14–45 in Elson, ed.
Bellofiore, Riccardo, ed. 1998. Marxian Economics. A Reappraisal. Volume 1: Essays on
Volume III of Capital. Method, Value and Money. Basingstoke, England: Macmillan.
Bellofiore, Riccardo, and Roberto Finelli. 1998. “Capital, Labour and Time: The
Marxian Monetary Theory of Value as a Theory of Exploitation.” Pp. 48–74 in
Bellofiore, ed.
Böhm-Bawerk, Eugene von. 1975. Karl Marx and the Close of His System. London:
Merlin Press.
Brown, Andrew. 2004. “The Labour Theory of Value: Materialist Versus Idealist
Interpretations.” Unpublished Manuscript.
Brown, Andrew, Gary Slater, and David A. Spencer. 2002. “Driven to Abstraction?
Critical Realism and the Search for the’Inner Connection’ of Social Phenom-
ena.” Cambridge Jounral of Economics, 26:6, 773–788.
Clarke, Simon. 1989. “The Basic Theory of Capitalism: A Critical Review of Itoh
and the Uno School.” Capital and Class, 37 (Spring), 133–149.
———. 1991. Marx, Marginalism and Modern Sociology. Basingstoke, England: Macmillan.
———. 1994. Marx’s Theory of Crisis. New York: St. Martin’s.
De Angelis, Massimo. 1995. “Beyond the Technological and Social Paradigms: A
Political Reading of Abstract Labour as the Substance of Value.” Capital and
Class, 57 (Autumn), 107–134.
Dimoulis, Dimitri, and John Milios. 2004. “Commodity Fetishism vs. Capital Fetish-
ism: Marxist Interpretations Vis-à-Vis Marx’s Analyses in Capital.” Historical
Materialism, 12:3, 3–42.
Elson, Diane, ed. 1979a. Value. The Representation of Labour in Capitalism. London:
CSE Books.
Elson, Diane. 1979b. “The Value Theory of Labour.” Pp. 115–180 in Elson, ed.
Engels, Friedrich. 1980. “La Contribución a la Crítica de la Economía Política de
Karl Marx.” Pp. 333–343 in Karl Marx, Contribución a la Crítica de la Economía
Política. Mexico City, Mexico: Siglo XXI.
Gunn, Richard. 1992. “Against Historical Materialism: Marxism as a First-Order
Discourse.” In Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn and Kosmas Psychopedis, eds.,
Open Marxism. Volume II: Theory and Practice. London: Pluto Press.
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1999. Hegel’s Science of Logic. Amherst, New York:
Humanity Books.
Iñigo Carrera, Juan. 1992. El Conocimiento Dialéctico. Buenos Aires, Argentina: Centro
para la Investigación como Crítica Práctica.
———. 2003. El Capital: Razón Histórica, Sujeto Revolucionario y Conciencia. Buenos
Aires, Argentina: Ediciones Cooperativas.
Itoh, Makoto. 1988. The Basic Theory of Capitalism: The Forms and Substance of the
Capitalist Economy. Basingstoke, England: Macmillan.
COMMODITY-FORM AND DIALECTICAL METHOD 317
Kay, Geoffrey. 1979. “Why Labour is the Starting Point of Capital.” Pp. 46–66 in
Elson, ed.
———. 1999. “Abstract Labour and Capital.” Historical Materialism, 5 (Winter), 255–
279.
Kicillof, Axel, and Guido Starosta. Forthcoming. “On Materiality and Social Form:
A Political Critique of Rubin’s Circulationist Value-Form Theory.” Historical
Materialism.
Lapavitsas, Costas. 2005. “The Universal Equivalent as Monopoly of the Ability to
Buy.” Pp. 95–110 in Fred Moseley, ed., Marx’s Theory of Money: Modern Apprais-
als. Basingstoke, England: Palgrave Macmillan.
Marx, Karl. 1975. “Notes on Adolf Wagner.” Pp. 161–219 in Terrel Carver, ed., Karl
Marx: Texts on Method. Oxford, England: Basil Blackwell.
———. 1976a. Capital, Volume I. Harmondsworth, England: Penguin.
———. 1976b. Value: Studies by Marx. London: New Park Publications.
———. 1978. Capital, Volume II. Harmondsworth, England: Penguin.
———. 1988. “Economic Manuscripts 1861–63.” Karl Marx and Frederick Engels Col-
lected Works, Volume 30. London: Lawrence and Wishart.
———. 1993. Grundrisse. Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy. Harmonds-
worth, England: Penguin.
Meek, Ronald. 1973. Studies in the Labour Theory of Value. London: Lawrence and
Wishart.
Meikle, Scott. 1985. Essentialism in the Thought of Karl Marx. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court.
Moseley, Fred, ed. 1993. Marx’s Method in Capital: A Reexamination. Atlantic High-
lands, New Jersey: Humanities Press.
Moseley, Fred, and Martha Campbell, eds. 1997. New Investigations of Marx’s Method.
Atlantic Highlands, New Jersey: Humanities Press.
Murray, Patrick. 1988. Marx’s Theory of Scientific Knowledge. Atlantic Highlands, New
Jersey: Humanities Press.
———. 2000. “Marx’s ‘Truly Social’ Labour Theory of Value.” Part I: “Abstract
Labour in Marxian Value Theory.” Historical Materialism, 6 (Summer), 27–65.
———. 2002. “Reply to Geert Reuten.” Historical Materialism, 10:1, 155–176.
Park, Cheol-soo. 2003. “On Replacing Labor as the Substance of Value: Early and
Recent Arguments.” Science & Society, 67:2, 160–172.
Postone, Moishe. 1996. Time, Labor and Social Domination. Cambridge, England:
Cambridge University Press.
Reichelt, Helmut. 1995. “Why did Marx Conceal his Dialectical Method?” Pp. 40–
79 in Werner Bonefeld, Richard Gunn, John Holloway and Kosmas Psycho-
pedis, eds., Open Marxism. Volume 3: Emancipating Marx. London: Pluto Press.
Reuten, Geert. 1993. “The Difficult Labor of a Theory of Social Value, Metaphors
and Systematic Dialectics at the Beginning of Marx’s ‘Capital’.” Pp. 89–114 in
Moseley, ed.
———. 2000. “The Interconnection Between Systematic Dialectics and Historical
Materialism.” Historical Materialism, 7 (Winter), 137–166.
Robles Báez, Mario L. 2000. “La Influencia del Método ‘Lógico-Histórico’ de Engels
en las Interpretaciones Sobre el Objeto de la Sección Primera del Tomo I de
El Capital de Marx: Crítica y Propuesta.” Paper presented at International
318 SCIENCE & SOCIETY