George Novack's - Understanding History
George Novack's - Understanding History
under imperialism — 120 ! After the Russian Revolution — 121 ! ‘The truth is
concrete’ — 122
THE PROBLEM OF TRANSITIONAL FORMATIONS ............................................... 123
The exceptional duality of transitional states — 124 ! Problems of classification —
126 ! The transition from food gathering to food production — 129 ! Village, town and
city — 132 ! The transition from Roman slavery to feudalism — 133 ! Manufacture:
the stepping stone from the craft guild to machine industry — 136 ! Transitional
regimes and societies in the 20th century — 137
SOCIOLOGY AND HISTORICAL MATERIALISM ................................................... 143
The place of sociology among the sciences — 143 ! Sociology and the philosophy of
history — 145 ! Types of sociological theory — 146 ! Historical materialism — 149
! The class character of sociology — 150
POSITIVISM AND MARXISM IN SOCIOLOGY ........................................................ 155
MARXISM VERSUS EXISTENTIALISM ...................................................................... 167
Science and the absurdity of reality — 168 ! The predominance of ambiguity — 170
! Individuals and their environment — 173 ! Freedom, necessity and morality — 176
! The destiny of humanity — 179 ! Alienation in modern society — 181 ! The
meaning of life and death — 184 ! Can existentialism and Marxism be reconciled? —
186
IS NATURE DIALECTICAL? ........................................................................................ 189
A comment and a response — 203
TROTSKY’S VIEWS ON DIALECTICAL MATERIALISM ........................................ 211
ALIENATION ................................................................................................................... 229
The people and their rulers — 229 ! The new socialist humanists — 230 ! Hegel’s
contribution — 232 ! The young Marx — 235 ! Development of the concept of labour
— 238 ! Primitive source of alienation — 239 ! Dialectical development of alienation
— 239 ! Alienation of labour under capitalism — 241 ! The great fetishes of capitalism
— 242 ! Alienation between the state and society — 243 ! Alienation of science from
society — 245 ! The humanism of Erich Fromm — 246 ! Is alienation everlasting? —
247 ! Prime cause of alienation in deformed workers’ states — 249 ! The ultra-
bureaucratic state and the workers — 252 ! Organisation of industry — 252 !
Dictatorship of the lie — 253 ! Cult of the individual — 254 ! The cure for bureaucratism
— 255 ! Stalinism and capitalism — 256 ! Toward the abolition of alienation — 258
! Labour time and free time — 261
APPENDIX: EXISTENTIALISM AND MARXISM by Doug Lorimer ..................... 263
The origins of existentialism— 263 ! Sartrean existentialism — 264 ! Althusserian
structuralism — 266 ! Existentialism and post-structuralism — 267
NOTES .............................................................................................................................. 268
ABOUT THE AUTHOR
George Novack was born in Boston in 1905 to Jewish immigrant parents from
Eastern Europe.
Radicalised by the 1929 economic crash, he moved toward Marxism. In 1933 he
joined the Trotskyist Communist League of America, the organisation founded by
veteran revolutionary James P. Cannon after his break with the Stalinised Communist
Party in 1928. Novack remained active in the Trotskyist movement — first the CLA
and then its successor organisations, most notably the Socialist Workers Party —
until his death in 1992.
Novack early developed an interest in philosophy. In the 1930s he belonged to a
broad layer of radical New York intellectuals who were attracted to Marxism. However,
while the small US Trotskyist movement in this period attracted a significant milieu of
fellow-travelling intellectuals, very few actually joined the movement and became
revolutionary activists. Some — like Felix Morrow and James Burnham — did so but
either did not fully make the transition or did not stay the distance.
George Novack stands out as one of the handful of radical intellectuals of the
Depression years who remained true to his early convictions. As he wrote in an
autobiographical memoir in 1976:
I had to watch most of my generation fall by the wayside and conclude a separate
peace with the ruling powers in the universities, the publishing fields, the professional
and business worlds. Today, at the age of 70, I am one of a very few: a radical
intellectual of 1930s vintage who remains active as an unrepentant Marxist and fulltime
professional in the revolutionary movement.1
Novack had a long involvement in civil rights defence campaigns. In 1932 he
became active in the CP-aligned National Committee for the Defence of Political
Prisoners. In 1937-40 Novack served as the secretary of the American Committee for
the Defence of Leon Trotsky. This body initiated the celebrated 1937 Dewey
Commission of Inquiry into the charges made against Trotsky in the Moscow show
trials and whose verdict pronounced them a complete frame-up. In 1941-50 Novack
6 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
was secretary of the Civil Rights Defence Committee. It was through this body that
the SWP organised support for the 18 party leaders and members indicted and jailed
in the wartime Minneapolis sedition trial.
In 1940 Novack was elected to the SWP National Committee and served on it until
1973. From 1965 to 1974 he was an associate editor of the International Socialist
Review, the SWP’s monthly journal. Most of the articles in this selection first appeared
in the ISR (many under the name William F. Warde, the pseudonym he frequently used
in his party work).
Apart from the example of a life of steadfast commitment and activity in the
revolutionary socialist movement, Novack’s greatest contribution to socialism consists
of his Marxist historical and philosophical writings. Over the years he wrote numerous
articles for the theoretical journals of the US Trotskyist movement (successively New
International, Fourth International and then International Socialist Review) as
well as a number of books.
Many of his writings are historical studies of the development of US capitalism
through two great revolutions (the War of Independence and the Civil War), the
question of slavery, the destruction of native American society, and of resistance to
the new bourgeois plutocracy. A number of his historical contributions appear in the
collection he edited, America’s Radical Heritage (Pathfinder Press: New York, 1976).
However, Novack will be most remembered as an outstanding exponent and
populariser of Marxist philosophy and theory. He produced a number of books on
various aspects of this question: An Introduction to the Logic of Marxism (Pioneer
Publishers: New York, 1942), The Origins of Materialism (Merit Publishers: New York,
1968), Empiricism and Its Evolution (Merit, 1968), Democracy and Revolution
(Pathfinder, 1971), Understanding History (Pathfinder, 1972), Humanism and Socialism
(Pathfinder, 1973), Pragmatism Versus Marxism (Pathfinder, 1975), Polemics in Marxist
Philosophy (Pathfinder, 1978).
Although ignored by bourgeois academia, Novack had an undoubted impact on
generations of activists in the revolutionary socialist movement, not only in the United
States but also in Australia (which he toured for the Democratic Socialist Party and
Resistance in 1973, speaking to large campus and city meetings). The publishers hope
that this selection of George Novack’s writings will help equip new generations of
fighters for socialism with the Marxist education which is so essential for the struggle.
Dave Holmes
January 2002
George Novack, secretary of the Civil Rights Defence Committee, in
Washington on April 2, 1944 to present pardon applications for Minneapolis
prisoners.
8 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
These two talks were originally given at the West Coast school and camp held
near Los Angeles, California, in September 1955. They offer a popularised account of
the main line of evolution from fish to mankind, from savagery to civilisation, and from
Indian life to contemporary capitalism in the United States. This is an extremely
simplified outline of the immense and complex range of that evolutionary process.
The facts set forth are well enough known — but their interpretation here differs from
that taught in the schools and universities of capitalist America.
These talks were designed as an introduction to a study of the march of mankind
from the viewpoint of scientific socialism.
It is especially directed toward newly awakened minds, concerned about the
fundamental problems of life in our time and seeking enlightenment on the main
issues of the social and political struggle.
Its arguments are aimed against two prevailing notions which tend to reinforce
antisocialist prejudices and uphold belief in the sanctity of the existing system. One is
the general idea that it is impossible, undesirable or somehow unscientific to seek out
the central course of development in history, above all in the history of society; to link
together its successive stages and place them in proper sequence; to distinguish the
lower form from the higher; and indicate the nature of the next steps.
The second prejudice is more specific, although it is supported by the first. This
is the assumption that the established capitalist regime in the United States embodies
the highest attainable mode of life and an unsurpassable type of social organisation.
These propositions, I hope to show, are wrong in theory and thoroughly reactionary
in their practical consequences. Socialist theory has the merit of explaining how and
why the growing discontent with the existing setup among the working people and
their strivings for a better way of life are reasonable, realistic, and founded on sound
scientific premises. The instinctive drive of the workers toward a fundamental
10 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
reorganisation of the capitalist social and political structure accords with the main line
of human progress.
These conclusions are already taken for granted in many parts of the globe which
are usually regarded as backward by the American people. However, it must be said
that although our country is the most modernised in many respects, from
superhighways to colour television, it is most backward in recognising — and acting
upon — the elementary truths of evolutionary science and revolutionary socialism.
I hope this little pamphlet will help some fellow countrymen and women to catch
up with the thinking of the more progressive sections of mankind by clearing away
capitalist-fostered prejudices, which obscure the real meaning of American history
and block the road to the next stage of American civilisation.
October 1956
1. HOW HUMANITY CLIMBED TO CIVILISATION
I propose first to trace the main line of human development, from our remote
animal ancestors to the present, when humanity has become lord of the earth but not
yet master of its own creations, not to mention its own social system. After that, I will
deal with the central course of evolution in that specific segment of society that
occupies the bulk of North America and represents the most developed form of
capitalist society.
I will try to show not only how our national history is related to world development
but also how we, collectively and individually, fit into the picture. This is a broad and
bold undertaking, a sort of jet-propelled journey through the stratosphere of world
history. It is forced upon us by the urge to grasp the whole vast spread of events and
to understand our specific place within them, as well as by the very dynamic of
scientific theory in sociology, which has its highest expression in Marxism. The
movement based upon scientific socialism, which prepares most energetically for the
future, likewise must probe most deeply into the past.
feature of the fish was the fact that it became the starting point for the entire hierarchy
of backboned creatures that has culminated in ourselves.
These first vertebrates subsequently advanced from the fish through the
amphibians (which lived both in water and on land), through the reptiles, and finally
branched off into the warmblooded creatures: birds and mammals. Mankind is the
culminating point of mammalian development. This much of animal evolution is
accepted by all scientific authorities.
But these ideas and facts, so commonplace today, were the subversive thoughts
of yesterday. We readily adopt this scientific view of organic evolution without realising
that this very act of acceptance is part of a reversal in human thinking about the world
and the creatures in it, which has taken place on a mass scale only during the past
century. Recall, for example, the prevalence of the Biblical myth of creation in the
Western world up to a few generations ago.
Two aspects of the facts about the vertebrates deserve special discussion. First,
the transfer of the bony parts of the fish from the outside to the inside embodied a
qualitatively new form of organic structure, a break in the continuity of development
up to that time, a jump onto a higher level of life. Every biologist acknowledges this
fact. But this fact has a more profound significance, which tells us much about the
methods of evolutionary change in general. It demonstrates how, at the critical point
in the accumulation of changes outside and inside an organism, the conflicting elements
that compose it break up the old form of its existence, and the progressive formation
passes over, by way of a leap, to a qualitatively new and historically higher state of
development. This is true not only of organic species but of social formations and
systems of thought as well.
This radical overturn is undeniable in the case of the birth and evolution of the
fish and its ultimate surpassing by higher species. But it is much harder for many
people to accept such a conclusion when it comes to the transformation of a lower
social organisation into a higher social organisation. This reluctance to apply the
teachings of evolution consistently to all things, and above all to the social system in
which we live, is rooted in the determination to defend powerful but obsolete and
narrow class interests against opposing forces and rival ideas that aim to create a
genuinely new order of things.
The second point to be stressed is the fact that the fish, as the first vertebrate,
occupies a specific place in the sequence of the evolution of organisms. It is one link
in a chain of the manifestations of life extending from one-celled protozoa to the most
complex organisms. This first creature with a backbone came out of and after a host of
creatures which never had such a skeletal structure and in turn gave rise to superior
The Long View of History 15
old order to do them!” However, the resistance of inertia did not prevent some water
dwellers from turning into land animals.
Animal life continued to move forward as species were modified and transmuted
in response to decisive changes in their genetic constitutions and natural habitats.
Amphibians turned into reptiles, which had better developed brains, were rib-breathing,
egg-laying, had limbs for locomotion, and well-developed eyes. The reptile kingdom
evolved gradually toward the mammal, with transitional types that had features
belonging to both, until once again a full-fledged new order stepped into the world.
About 135 million years ago, the animal prototype that gave rise to our own tree-
living ancestor emerged. This was a rodentlike creature which took another big leap in
evolutionary adaptation and activity by quitting the land for the trees. Arboreal
existence over six hundred thousand years so altered our animal ancestors from head
to toe, from grasping functions to teeth changes, that they elevated themselves to
monkey and ape forms. The kinship of the latter with our own kind is so close that it
is difficult to distinguish an embryo of the highest apes from that of a human.
The natural conditions had at last been created for the emergence of mankind. It
seems likely that changes in climate and geographical conditions connected with the
first Ice Age drove certain species of primates down from the trees, out of the forests
and onto the plains. A series of important anatomical developments paved the way
for the making of the human race. The shortening of the pelvic bone made it possible
for the primate to stand erect, to differentiate forelimbs from hindlimbs and emancipate
the hands. The brain became enlarged. Binocular vision and vocal organs made human
sight and speech possible.
The central biological organ for the making of mankind was the hand. The hands
became opposed to the legs, and the thumb became opposed to the four fingers. This
opposition between the thumb and the other fingers has been one of the most fruitful
and dynamic of all the unions of opposites in the evolution of humanity. The thumb’s
ability to counterpose itself to each of the other fingers gave the hand exceptional
powers of grasping and manipulating objects and endowed it with extreme flexibility
and sensitivity. This acquisition made possible the biological combination of hand-
eye-brain. Combined with the prolonged period of care by the mother for her offspring,
the natural prerequisites for social life were at hand.
the use, and later the manufacture, of implements for that purpose. The third was the
development of speech and of reasoning, which arose from and was promoted by
living and working together. The fourth was the use, the domestication, and the
production of fire. Fire was the first natural force, the first chemical process, put to
socially productive use by ascending humanity.
Thanks to these new powers, emerging mankind enormously speeded up the
changes in our own species and later in the world around us. The record of history for
the past million years is essentially one of the formation of humanity and its continual
transformation. This in turn has promoted the transformation of the world around us.
What has enabled mankind to effect such colossal changes in himself and his
environment? All the biological changes in our stock over the past million years,
taken together, have not been a prominent factor in the advancement of the human
species. Yet during that time humanity has taken the raw material inherited from our
animal past, socialised it, humanised it, and partially, though not completely, civilised
it. The axis of human development, contrasted to animality, revolves around these
social rather than biological processes.
The mainspring of this progress comes from the improvement of the powers of
production, acquired along the way and expanded in accordance with man’s growing
needs. By discovering and utilising the diverse properties and resources of the world
around him, man has gradually added to his abilities of producing the means of life.
As these have developed, all his other social powers — the power of speech, of
thought, of art, and of science, etc. — have been enhanced.
The decisive difference between the highest animals and ourselves is to be found
in our development of the means and forces of production and destruction (two
aspects of one and the same phenomenon). This accounts not only for the qualitative
difference between man and the other animals but also for the specific differences
between one level of human development and another. What demarcates the peoples
of the Stone Age from those of the Iron Age, and savage life from civilised societies,
is the difference in the total powers of production at their disposal.
What happens when two different levels of productive and destructive power
measure strength was dramatically illustrated when the Spanish conquerors invaded
the Western Hemisphere. The Indians were armed with bows and arrows and slings;
the newcomers had muskets and gunpowder. The Indians had canoes and paddles;
the Spaniards had big sailing ships. The Indians wore leather or padded jackets for
protection in warfare; the Spaniards had steel armour. The Indians had no domesticated
draught animals but went on foot; the Spaniards rode horses. Their superior equipment
inspired terror and enabled the conquistadores to defeat their antagonists with inferior
The Long View of History 19
manpower.
This basic proposition of historical materialism should be easier for us to grasp
because we are privileged to witness the first stage of a technological revolution
comparable in importance to the taming of fire a half million years ago. That is the
acquisition of control over the processes of nuclear fission and fusion. This new
source of power has already revolutionised the relations among governments and the
art of warfare; it is about to transform industry, agriculture, medicine, and many other
departments of social activity.a
What brought this technological revolution about? Mankind underwent no
biological changes in the preceding period. Nor were there any sudden alterations in
human modes of thinking, in their sentiments, or their moral ideas. This incalculably
powerful force of production and destruction issued from the entire previous
development of society’s productive forces and all the scientific knowledge and
instruments connected with them. Atomic power is the latest link in the chain of
acquired powers that can be traced back to the earliest elements of social production:
associated labour in securing the necessities of life, tool using and making, speech,
thought, and fire. Atomic energy is the latest fruit of the seeds planted back in ancient
society, which have been cultivated and improved by humanity in its upward climb.
a The reader should bear in mind that these comments about nuclear power were made in
1955. Since then, the life-threatening hazards of the nuclear industry have become appallingly
clear. I concur with the growing worldwide antinuclear movement that because of the dangers
inherent in disposing nuclear wastes as well as in mining and processing nuclear fuels the entire
nuclear industry should be dismantled. [Note by George Novack, 1979]
20 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
window.
a It should be stressed that these terms are not judgements on the moral values of the given
society but refer to their objective stage of historical development. In the history of the Marxist
movement this terminology itself has a history. The great utopian socialist Charles Fourier
(1772-1837) used a similar categorisation, as did the pioneer anthropologist Lewis Henry
Morgan (1818-81) on whom Frederick Engels drew so heavily in his Origin of the Family,
Private Property and the State. In this great work of historical materialism, Engels enthusiastically
contrasts the communal democracy and social solidarity of the economically more primitive
stages of “savagery” and “barbarism” with the class oppression and exploitation which
characterises technologically-developed bourgeois “civilisation”. — Ed.
The Long View of History 23
consumption. The Indians of southern California were at this stage when the first
white settlers arrived two centuries ago.
Barbarism is the second stage of social organisation. It was based upon the
domestication of animals and the cultivation of plants. Food is now not merely collected
but produced. The domestication of cattle, sheep, pigs, and other animals provided
reserves of meat as well as food in the form of milk from goats and cows. The planting
and growing of crops made regular and plentiful food supplies available.
This food-producing revolution, which started in Asia from six to ten thousand
years ago, relieved mankind from subjection to external nature for the first time. Up to
that point humanity had to rely upon what the natural environment contained to take
care of its needs and had been dependent for survival upon completely external and
uncontrollable natural conditions. Entire stocks and cultures of people arose, flourished,
and then succumbed, like plant or animal species, in response to the beneficence or
hostility of nature around them.
For example, about twenty to thirty thousand years ago, there arose a society
centred around southern France called the Reindeer Culture. These people thrived by
hunting huge reindeer and other herds that browsed upon the lush vegetation there.
The drawings they made, which have been discovered in caves over the past 75
years, testify to the keenness of their eyes and minds and the trained sensitivity of
their hands and place them among the most superb artists that have ever appeared on
earth. However, when changed climatic and botanic conditions caused the reindeer
herds to vanish, their entire culture, and very likely the people as well, died out.
The early hunters had no assured control over their mobile sources of food. The
insecurity of savage life was largely overcome, or at least considerably reduced, with
the advent of stock breeding, and especially with the development of agricultural
techniques. For the first time, methods were instituted for obtaining extensive and
expanding supplies of food products and fibres by systematic and sustained activities
of working groups. These branches of economic activity made much larger and more
compact populations possible.
These activities and their increased output provided the elements for the higher
culture of barbarism. Farming and stock raising led to the development of such
handicrafts as smelting and pottery, as accumulated food supplies generated the
need to store and transport articles for the first time. Men became more stationary;
denser populations aggregated; permanent dwellings were built; and village life sprang
into existence.
In their further and final development, the economic activities under barbarism
created the prerequisites for the coming of civilisation. The material foundation for
24 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
civilisation was the capacity acquired by the most advanced peoples for the regular
production of far more food and goods than were required for the physical maintenance
of their members. These surpluses had two results. They permitted specific sections
of the communities to engage in diversified activities other than the direct acquisition
and production of the basic means of life. Such specialists as priests, nobles, kings,
officials, smiths, potters, traders, builders, and other craftsmen made their appearance.
With the growth of specialisation and the extension of trade, the top layers of
these groups moved into strategic positions that enabled the more fortunate and
powerful to appropriate large personal shares of the surplus of wealth. The drive to
increase personal wealth flowing from the growing social division of labour and
exchange of goods, led in time to the development of private property, the family,
slavery, class divisions, commodity production on a large scale, trade, money, the
city, and the territorial state with its army, police, courts, and other relations and
institutions characteristic of civilisation.
persistence.
Science demands that every phenomenon be approached, analysed, and appraised
with objectivity, setting aside personal reactions of admiration or abhorrence. Historical
materialism has to explain why slavery came to be adopted by the most advanced
contingents of mankind. The principal reason was that, along with the private ownership
of the means of production and the widening exchange of its products, slave labour
increased the forces of production, multiplied wealth, comforts and culture — although
only for the lucky few — and, on the whole, spurred mankind forward for an entire
historical period. Without the extension of slave labour, there would not have been
incentives unremitting enough to pile up wealth on a sizable scale that could then be
applied to further the productive processes.
The historical necessity for slavery can be illustrated along two lines. The peoples
who failed to adopt slave labour likewise did not proceed to civilisation, however
excellent their other qualities and deeds. They remained below that level because their
economy lacked the inner drive of the force of greed and the dynamic propulsion
arising from the slaveholder’s need to exploit the slave to augment his wealth. That is
a negative demonstration.
But there is more positive proof. Those states based on some form of servitude,
such as the most brilliant cultures of antiquity from Babylon and Egypt to Greece and
Rome, also contributed the most to the civilising processes, from wheeled carts and
the plough to writing and philosophy. These societies stood in the main line of social
progress.
But if slavery had sufficient reasons for becoming the beginning and basis of
ancient civilisation, in turn and in time it generated the conditions and forces which
would undermine and overthrow it. Once slavery became the predominant form of
production either in industry, as in Greece, or in agriculture, as in Rome, it no longer
furthered the development of agricultural techniques, craftsmanship, trade, or
navigation. The slave empires of antiquity stagnated and disintegrated until after a
lapse of centuries they were replaced by two main types of feudal organisation:
Asiatic and West European.
Both of these new forms of production and social organisation were superior to
slavery, but the West European turned out to be far more productive and dynamic.
Under feudalism the labourers got more of their produce than did the slaves; they
even had access to the land and other means of production. Serfs and peasants had
greater freedom of activity and could acquire more culture.
As the result of a long list of technological and other social advances, merging
with a sequence of exceptional historical circumstances, feudalised Europe became
26 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
the nursery for the next great stage of class society, capitalism. How and why did
capitalism originate?
Once money had arisen from the extension of trading several thousand years ago,
its use as capital became possible. Merchants could add to their wealth by buying
goods cheap and selling them dear; moneylenders and mortgage holders could gain
interest on sums advanced on the security of land or other collateral. These practices
were common in both slave and feudal societies.
But if money could be used in precapitalist times to return more than the original
investment, other conditions had to be fulfilled before capitalism could become
established as a separate and definite world economic system. The central condition
was a special kind of transaction regularly repeated on a growing scale. Large numbers
of propertyless workers had to hire themselves to the possessors of money and the
other means of production in order to earn a livelihood.
Hiring and firing seem to us a normal way of carrying on production. But such
peoples as the Indians never knew it. Before the Europeans came, no Indian ever
worked for a boss (the word itself was imported by the Dutch), because they possessed
their own means of livelihood. The slave may have been purchased, but he belonged
to and worked for the master his whole life long. The feudal serf or tenant was likewise
bound for life to the lord and his land.
The epoch-making innovation upon which capitalism rested was the institution of
working for wages as the dominant relation of production. Most of you have gone
into the labour market, to an employment agency or personnel office, to get a buyer
for your labour power. The employer buys this power at prevailing wage rates by the
hour, day, or week and then applies it under his supervision to produce commodities
that his company subsequently sells at a profit. That profit is derived from the fact
that wage workers produce more value than the capitalist pays for their labour.
Up to the 20th century, this mechanism for pumping surplus labour out of the
working masses and transferring the surpluses of wealth they create to the personal
credit of the capitalist was the mightiest accelerator of the productive forces and the
expansion of civilisation. As a distinct economic system, capitalism is only about 450
years old; it has conquered the world and journeyed from dawn to twilight in that time.
This is a short life span compared to savagery, which stretched over a million years or
more, or to barbarism, which prevailed for four thousand to five thousand years.
Obviously, the processes of social transformation have been considerably speeded
up in modern times.
This speeding up in social progress is due in large measure to the very nature of
capitalism, which continually revolutionises its techniques of production and the
The Long View of History 27
entire range of social relations issuing from them. Since its birth, world capitalism has
passed through three such phases of internal transformation. In its formative period,
the merchants were the dominant class of capitalists because trade was the main
source of wealth accumulation. Under commercial capitalism, industry and agriculture,
the pillars of production, were not usually carried on by wage labour but by means of
small handicrafts, peasant farming, slave or serf labour.
The industrial age was launched around the beginning of the 19th century with
the application of steam power to the first mechanised processes, concentrating large
numbers of wage workers into factories. The capitalist captains of this large-scale
industry became masters of the field of production and later of entire countries and
continents as their riches, their legions of wage labourers, social and political power,
swelled to majestic proportions.
This vigorous, expanding, progressive, confident, competitive stage of industrial
capitalism dominated the 19th century. It passed over into the monopoly-ridden
capitalism of the 20th century, which has carried all the basic tendencies of capitalism,
and especially its most reactionary features, to extremes in economic, political, cultural,
and international relations. While the processes of production have become more
centralised, more rationalised, more socialised, the means of production and the wealth
of the world have become concentrated in giant financial and industrial combines. So
far as the capitalist sectors of society are involved, this process has been brought to
the point where the capitalist monopolies of a single country, the US, dictate to all the
rest.
We have reviewed the course by which humanity climbed out of the animal state,
and we have marked the successive steps in that climb. Mankind had to crawl through
savagery for a million years or more, walk through barbarism, and then, with shoulders
hunched and head bowed, enter the iron gates of class society. There, for thousands
of years, mankind endured a harsh schooling under the rod and rule of private property,
which began with slavery and reached its highest form in capitalist civilisation. Now
our own age stands, or rather struggles, at the entrance to socialism.
Let us now pass from the historical progress of mankind, viewed as a whole, to
inspect one of its parts, the United States of North America. Because US imperialism
is the mainstay of the international capitalist system, the role of the American people
is crucial in deciding how quickly and how well humanity crosses the great divide
between the class society of the past and the reorganisation and reinvigoration of the
world along socialist lines.
I shall try to give brief answers to the following four questions: What has been the
course of American history in its essentials? What are its connections with the march
of the rest of humankind? What has been the outcome to date? Finally, where do we
fit into the picture?
streams of migration may have brought the practices of gardening with them. It is
upon these bequests that the Indians fashioned their type of existence.
Whoever regards the Indians as insignificant or incompetent has defective
historical judgment. Humanity has been raised to its present estate by four branches
of productive activity. The first is food gathering, which includes grubbing for roots
and berries as well as hunting and fishing. The second is stock raising. The third is
agriculture. The fourth is craftsmanship, graduating into large-scale industry.
The Indians were extremely adept at hunting, fishing, and other ways of food
gathering. They were ingenious craftsmen whose work in some fields has never been
excelled. The Incas, for example, made textiles which were extremely fine in texture,
colouring, and design. They invented and used more different techniques of weaving
on their hand looms than any other people in history.
However, the Indians showed the greatest talent in their development of agriculture.
They may even have independently invented soil cultivation. In any case they brought
it to diversified perfection. We are indebted to the Indians for most of the vegetables
that today come from the fields and through the kitchens onto our tables. Most
important are corn, potatoes, and beans, but there is in addition a considerable list
including tomatoes, chilli, pineapples, peanuts, avocados, and for after dinner
purposes, tobacco. They knew and used the properties of 400 separate species of
plants. No plant cultivated by the American Indians was known to Asia, Europe, or
Africa prior to the white invasion of America.
Much is heard about all that white men brought over to the Indians, but little
about what the Indians gave the European whites. The introduction of the food
plants taken from the Indians more than doubled the available food supply of the
older continent after the 15th century and became an important factor in the expansion
of capitalist civilisation. Over half of the agricultural produce raised in the world today
comes from plants domesticated by the Indians!
From the first to the 15th centuries, the Indians themselves created magnificent,
even astounding cultures on the basis of their achievements in agriculture. Agriculture
enabled some of the scattered and roving hunting tribes of Indians to aggregate in
small but permanent settlements where they supported themselves by growing corn,
beans, and other vegetables. They also raised and wove cotton, made pottery, and
developed other handicrafts.
The Incas of the Andes, the Mayans of Guatemala and Yucatan, and the Aztecs of
central Mexico, unaffected by European civilisation and having developed
independently, constituted the most advanced of the Indian societies. Their cultures
embodied the utmost the Indians were able to accomplish within the 25,000 years or
The Long View of History 31
so allotted them by history. In fact, the Mayans had made mathematical and
astronomical calculations more complex and advanced than those of the European
invaders. They had independently invented the zero for use in their number system
— something even the Greeks and Romans had lacked.
Indians progressed as far as the middle stage of barbarism and were stopped
there. Whether or not, given unlimited time and no interference from more powerful
and productive peoples, they would have mounted all the way to civilisation must
remain unanswered. This much can be stated: they had formidable obstacles to
overcome along such a path. The Indians did not have such important domesticated
animals as the horse, cow, pig, sheep, or water buffalo that had pulled the Asians and
Europeans along toward civilisation. They had only the dog, turkey, guinea pig, and,
in the Andean highlands, llamas, alpacas, and, in some places, bees. Moreover, they
did not use the wheel, except for toys, did not know the use of iron or firearms, and did
not have other prerequisites for civilising themselves.
However, history in the other part of the globe settled this question without
further appeal. For, while the most advanced Indians had been moving up from
wandering hunters’ lives to those of settlers in barbaric communities, the Europeans,
themselves an offspring of Asiatic culture, had not only entered class society but had
become highly civilised. Their most progressive segments along the Atlantic seaboard
were passing over from feudalism to capitalism.
This uneven development of society in the Old World and the New provided the
historical setting for the second great turning point in American history. What was
the essential meaning of the upheaval initiated by the west European crossing of the
Atlantic? It represented the transition from the Stone Age to the Iron Age in America,
from barbaric to civilised modes of life, from tribal organisation based upon collectivist
practices to a society rooted in private property, production for exchange, the family,
the state, and so forth.
Few spectacles in history are more dramatic and instructive than the confrontation
and conflict between the Indian representatives of communal Stone Age life and the
armed agents of class civilisation. Science fiction tells about visitations to this planet
by Martians in flying saucers. To the Indians, the first visitations of the white men
were no less startling and incomprehensible.
To the Indians, these white men had completely alien customs, standards, and
ways of life. They were strange in appearance and behaviour. In fact, the differences
between the two were so profound as to be irreconcilable. What was the root cause of
the enduring and deadly clash between them? They represented two utterly
incompatible levels of social organisation that had grown out of and were based upon
32 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
characterised by the conjuncture of two revolutionary processes. The first was the
shift of maritime Europe from a feudal to a bourgeois basis. Part of this revolutionising
of Western Europe was a push outward as the capitalist traders extended their
operations throughout the globe. Their exploring, marketing, pirating expeditions
brought the emissaries of the budding bourgeois society in Europe across the ocean
and into collision with the Indians. The rape of the ancient cultures of the Aztecs and
Incas, the enslavement and extermination of the natives by the Spanish conquerors
and others, was a collateral offensive of this European revolution on our own continent.
Through the extension of the revolutionary process, the peoples of the Stone
Age here were overcome and supplanted by the most advanced representatives of
class civilisation. This was not the only continent on which such a process took
place. What happened from the 15th to the 19th centuries in the New World had taken
place much earlier in western Europe itself; and it was to reach into the most remote
sectors of the world, as capitalism has spread over the earth from that time to our own.
The contest between the Stone Age peoples and the representatives of the
bourgeois epoch was fiercely fought. Their wars stretched over four centuries and
ended in the disintegration, dispossession, or destruction of the prehistoric cultures
and the unchallenged supremacy of class society.
With the advent of the white Europeans (as well as the enslaved coloured Africans
who were transported here by them), American history was switched onto an entirely
different set of rails, a new course marked out by the needs of a young, expanding
world capitalism.
We come now to a most crucial question: What has been the main line of American
growth since 1492? Various answers are given — the growth of national independence,
the spread of democracy, the coming into his own of the common man, or the expansion
of industry. Each of these familiar formulas taught in the schools does record some
aspect of the process, but none goes to the heart of the matter.
The correct answer to the question is that despite detours en route, the main line
of American history has consisted in the construction and consolidation of capitalist
civilisation, which has been carried to its ultimate in our own day. Any attempt to
explain the development of American society since the 16th century will be brought
up against this fact. The discovery, exploration, settlement, cultivation, exploitation,
democratisation, and industrialisation of this continent must all be seen as successive
steps in promoting the building of bourgeois society. This is the only interpretation of
the decisive events in the past 450 years in North America that makes sense, gives
continuity and coherence to our complex history, distinguishes the mainstream from
tributaries, and is validated by the development of American society. Everything in
34 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
our national history has to be referred to, and linked up with, the process of establishing
the capitalist way of life in its most pronounced and, today, its most pernicious form.
This is commonly called “The American Way of Life”. A more realistic and honest
characterisation would be the capitalist way of life because, as I shall indicate, this is
destined to be only a historically limited and passing expression of civilised life in
America.
The central importance of the formation and transformation of bourgeois society
can be demonstrated in another way. What is the most outstanding peculiarity of
American history since the coming of the Europeans? There have been many
peculiarities in the history of this country; in some ways this is a very peculiar country.
But what marks off American life from the development of the other great nations of
the world is that the growth and construction of American society falls entirely within
the epoch of the expansion of capitalism on a global scale. That is the key to
understanding American history, whether you deal with colonial history, 19th-century
history, or 20th-century history.
It is not true of other leading countries such as England, Germany, Russia, India,
Japan, or China. These countries passed through prolonged periods of slave or feudal
civilisation that left their stamp upon them to this very day. Look at MacArthur’s
preservation of that feudal relic, the emperor of Japan, or that Sunday supplement
delight, the monarchy of England.
America, on the other hand, leaped from savagery and barbarism to capitalism,
tipping its hat along the way to slavery and feudalism, which held no more than
subordinate places in building the bourgeois system. In a couple of centuries, the
American people hurried through stages of social development that took the rest of
mankind many thousands of years. But there was close interconnection between
these two processes. If the rest of mankind had not already made these acquisitions,
we Americans would not have been able to rush ahead so far and so fast. The tasks of
pioneers are invariably harder and take far longer to accomplish.
The fusion of the antifeudal revolution in Europe with the wars of extermination
against the Indians ushered in the bourgeois epoch of American history. This period
has stretched over 450 years. It falls into three distinct phases, each marked off by
revolutionary changes in American life.
However, a historical freak came along, which upset this pleasant prospect. This
freak was the result of a double revolution in technology, one which took place in
Europe, especially in English industry, and the other in American agriculture. The
establishment of factories with steam-driven machinery in English industry, notably
in textiles, its most important branch, created the demand for large supplies of cotton.
The invention of the cotton gin enabled the Southern planters to supply that demand.
Consequently, slavery, which had been withering on the vine, acquired a new
lease on life. This economic combination invested the nobles of the Southern cotton
kingdom with tremendous wealth and power. A study of American history in the first
half of the 19th century shows that its national and political life was dominated and
directed by the struggle for supremacy waged by the forces centred around the
Southern slaveholders on one side and those of the antislavery elements on the other.
The crucial social issue before the nation was not always stated bluntly. But when
every other conflict was traced to its roots, it was found to be connected with the
question: What are we Americans going to do about slavery?
(A similar situation exists today in relation to capitalism. No matter what dispute
agitates the political-economic life of this country, it sooner or later brings up the
great social-economic question: What are we Americans going to do about capitalism?)
For the first 50 years of the 19th century, the cotton aristocrats of the South
undeniably held centre stage. They became very cocky about their power and privileges,
which they thought would last indefinitely. Then, around 1850, conditions began to
change quite rapidly. A new combination of social forces appeared that was to prove
strong enough not only to challenge the slave power but to meet it in civil war,
conquer and eliminate it.
It is highly instructive to study the mentality and outlook of the American people
in 1848. That was a year of revolutions in the principal countries of western Europe.
The people in the United States, including its governing groups, viewed these outbursts
in an isolationist spirit.
The European revolutions even pleased certain sections of the ruling classes in
the United States because they were directed mainly against monarchies. There were
no monarchies here to overthrow, although there was a slave aristocracy rooted in the
South. Although most of the common people in the United States sympathised with
the European revolutions, they looked upon them as no more than a catching up with
what had already been achieved in this country. The Americans said to themselves:
“We’ve already had our revolution and don’t need any more here. The quota of
revolutions assigned to us by history is exhausted.”
They did not see even 15 years into their own future. The bourgeois-democratic
38 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
revolution still had considerable unfinished business. During the 1850s, it became
plainer that the Southern slaveholders were not only tightening their autocracy in the
Southern states but were trying to make slaves of the entire population of the United
States. This small set of rich men arrogated to themselves the right to tell the people
what they could and could not do, where the country should expand, and how the
affairs of America should and should not be managed.
So a second revolution proved necessary to complete those tasks left unsettled in
the late 18th century and to dispose of the main problems that had confronted the
American people in the meantime. There had to be 13 years of preparatory struggles,
four and a half years of civil war, 12 years of Reconstruction — about 30 years in all,
in this intense and inescapable revolutionary upheaval.
What is most important for us now are the net results of that travail. Every
schoolchild knows that the slave power was abolished and the Negro population
unshackled from chattel slavery. But the principal achievement of this revolution from
the standpoint of American and world development was that the last of the internal
impediments to the march of American capitalism were levelled, and the way cleared
for the consolidation of capitalist rule.
That period saw the conclusion of the contest that had been going on since 1492
between the procapitalist and precapitalist forces on this continent. See what had
happened to the peoples representing the diverse precapitalist ways of life. The
Indians, who embodied savagery and barbarism, had either been exterminated,
dispossessed, or herded into reservations. England, which had upheld feudalism and
colonial subjugation, had been swept aside and American industrial capital had attained
not only political supremacy but economic independence. The Southern plantation
owners, who were the final formidable precapitalist force to be pushed out of the road,
had been smashed and expropriated by the Civil War and Reconstruction.
The capitalist rulers of the industrial system were then like the Count of Monte
Cristo when he burst from prison and exclaimed, with so much wealth and newly
gained liberty at his command: “The world is mine!” And they have been acting on
that premise ever since.
hands and be exploited along such lines. The land, for example, which had been
tribally held, was cut up and appropriated by individuals or corporations from one
end of the country to the other.
After the victory of the Northern bankers, merchants, and manufacturers in the
middle of the 19th century, this process moved on to a still higher plane. The means of
production under private ownership became more and more concentrated in corporate
hands. Today an individual might be able to build a single auto or airplane, but
without many, many millions of dollars he would not be able to compete in the market
with General Motors or Ford or Lockheed or Douglas. Even so big a magnate as Henry
J. Kaiser found that out in auto.
Today there is hardly an acre of land without its title deed. In fact, the Civil War
promoted this process through the Homestead Act, which gave 160 acres to private
individuals, and through other acts of Congress that handed over millions of acres to
railroad corporations. Insofar as the land was distributed to small farmers, this was
progressive because it was the only way to hasten the development of agriculture
under the given conditions.
It is impossible to detail here the settlement and building of the Midwest and the
West, but certain consequences of capitalist expansion deserve mention. First, as a
result of this capitalist expansion, the minds of average Americans, unlike those of the
Indians, have been so moulded by the institutions of private property that its standards
can be thrown off only with difficulty. The Europeans penetrated the America of the
Indians; and their descendants are venturing into outer space. One extreme, absurd,
but for that very reason most instructive, illustration of the effects of capitalist expansion
on American consciousness appeared in a press dispatch from Illinois with the headline:
“Who Is the Owner of Outer-Space; Chicagoan Insists that He Is.” This news item
followed:
With plans for launching man-made earth satellites now in motion, the question
was inevitable [inevitable, that is, to Americans believing in the sacredness of private
ownership]: Who owns outer space?
Most experts agreed that the question was over their heads. The rocket scientists
said it was a problem for the international law experts. The lawyers said they had no
precedents to go by. Only James T. Mangan, a fast-thinking Chicago press agent, has
a firm answer to the question of space sovereignty. Mangan declares he owns outer
space. To back up his claim, he has a deed filed with the Cook County (Chicago)
Recorder. The deed, accepted after the state’s attorney’s office solemnly upheld the
claim in a four-page legal opinion, seized “all space in all directions from the earth at
midnight”, December 20, 1948.
40 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
Mangan declared that the statute of limitations for challenging the deed expires
December 20, 1955, and added: ‘The government has no legal right to space without
my permission.”
If this be madness, yet there is method in it. That method is the mainspring of the
capitalist way of life. This gentleman, Mangan, is only logically extending to the
exploration of outer space the same acquisitive creed which guided our founding
fathers in taking over the American continent. This particular fanatic of private property
thinks the same law is going to apply no matter how far into space we fly and no matter
how far we go into the future. He differs from other exponents of capitalism only in the
boldness and consistency of his private-property logic.
The second point I want to deal with is the interconnection between evolution
and revolution. These two phases of social development are often opposed to each
other as unconnected opposites, irreconcilable alternatives. What does American
history teach us about them? The American people have already passed through two
revolutionary periods in their national history, each the culmination of lengthy periods
of social progress on the basis of previous achievements.
During the interval between revolutions, relatively small changes gradually occurred
in people’s lives. They consequently took the given framework of their lives for
granted, viewed it as fixed and final, and found it hard to imagine a different way. The
idea of revolutionary change in their own lives and lifetimes seemed fantastic or at
least irrelevant. Yet it was during those very periods of evolutionary progress that
often unnoticed accumulations of changes prepared more drastic change.
The new class interests, which grew powerful but remained unsatisfied, the social
and political conflicts, which recurred but remained unresolved, the shifts in the
relations of antagonistic social forces kept asserting themselves in a series of
disturbances until they reached an acute stage. The people of this country were not
reckless. They made every attempt to find reasonable compromises between the
contending forces, and often arrived at them. But after a while, these truces turned out
to be ineffectual and short-lived. The irrepressible conflict of social forces broke out
at higher stages until the breaking point was reached.
Look at the American colonists of 1763. They had just emerged — side-by-side
with mother England — from a successful war against the French and the Indians.
They did not anticipate that within 10 years they would be fighting for their own
freedom against England and alongside the very French monarchy they had fought in
1763. That would have been considered fantastic. Yet it happened only a little more
than a decade later. Dr. Benjamin Rush, one of Pennsylvania’s signers of the Declaration
of Independence, observed in his Autobiography that:
The Long View of History 41
Not one man in a thousand contemplated or wished for the independence of our
country in 1774, and but few of those who assented to it, foresaw the immense
influence it would soon have upon the national and individual characters of the
Americans.
So, too, the majority of Northerners, who enjoyed the economic boom in America
from 1851 to 1857 — the biggest boom in the 19th century preceding the Civil War —
little reckoned that as the result of domestic processes accelerated by that very
prosperity, the country was going to be split on the slave question four years after the
depression of 1857. Instead, they reasoned: Hadn’t there been a compromise with the
slaveholders in 1850 and couldn’t others be arrived at? Indeed, there were attempts at
compromise up to the very outbreak of the Civil War, and even afterwards.
Of course, the Abolitionists at one extreme and the Southern “Fire-Eaters” at the
other prophesied a different course of development and, in their own ways, prepared
for the coming revolution. But these radical voices on the left and the right were few
and far between.
These crucial episodes in American history demonstrate that, under conditions of
class society, periods of gradual social evolution prepare forces for the revolutionary
solution of the accumulated and unfinished problems of peoples and nations. This
revolutionary cleanup in turn creates the premises for a new and higher stage of
evolutionary progress. This alternation is demonstrated with exceptional clarity by
American history in the 18th and 19th centuries.
It is important to note, as a third point in dealing with the consequences of capitalist
development in the United States, that our national revolutions stemmed directly from
native conditions. Neither was imported by “outside agitators”, although some, like
Tom Paine, played important roles. They came from the ripening of conflicts between
internal social forces. But this is only one side of the matter. The domestic struggles
in turn were connected with, conditioned, and determined by world economic and
social development.
We pointed out earlier that the impetus for the overseas migration that changed
the face of America came from the antifeudal bourgeois revolutions, which were
transforming Europe; the conquest of our continent was an offshoot of those
revolutions. The first American revolution occurred during the era of commercial
capitalism, which was the first stage in world capitalist development. Historically, it
forms part of the series of bourgeois-democratic revolutions by which the capitalist
class came to power on an international scale. The first American revolution must be
considered a child of the English bourgeois revolution of the mid-17th century and a
parent of sorts to the French bourgeois-democratic revolution of the late 18th century.
42 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
Trade in this era, not simply American but world trade, produced a powerful
merchant class in the North, which was backed up by maritime workers and artisans in
the coastal cities and by free farmers in the countryside. These became the shock
troops of the Sons of Liberty. It is no accident that the bustling seaport of Boston,
populated by rich merchants who wanted to get out from under the thumb of Great
Britain and by robust waterfront workers, longshoremen, and sailors, stood in the
forefront of the fight against Great Britain and that the revolutionary war itself was
detonated by the British efforts to gag and strangle Boston.
The second American revolution took place at the time of the greatest expansion
of industrial capitalism on both sides of the Atlantic. The years from 1848 to 1871 were
punctuated by wars and revolutions. These conflicts did not mark the disintegration
of world capital, as they do in the present century, but finally gave the capitalist class
unmitigated supremacy in America and a series of countries in Europe.
The second stage of the bourgeois-democratic revolution in the United States,
the Civil War, placed the Northern industrialists in the saddle. It was the outstanding
revolutionary event of the entire period from 1848 to 1871, which began with the
abortive French and German revolutions of 1848 and ended with the Franco-Prussian
War and the Paris Commune of 1871. The decisive event of that period in world
history was the US capitalists’ victory in this country, which heralded their ascent to
world power.
This echoes the assertion by an earlier absolute monarch, Louis XIV: “I am the
state.” The old regime of France had its funeral in 1789. Everything in this world —
and this is especially true of political regimes and social systems under class society
— includes within itself its own opposition, its own fatal opposition. This is certainly
true of the power of capitalism which breeds its own nemesis in the productive — and
political — capacities of wage labour.
The irony is that the greater the wealth of the capitalists, the stronger becomes the
social position of the exploited workers from whom this wealth is derived. The United
States has witnessed, side-by-side with the rise of monopoly capitalism, the emergence
of an ever more strongly organised, centralised, and unified labour movement. Ever
since the capitalists and wage workers came into existence together, there have been
differences, friction, outbursts of conflict, strikes, lockouts, between sections of these
two classes. They arise from the very nature of their relations, which are antagonistic.
By and large, up to now, these conflicts have never gone beyond the bounds of
the basic political and economic structure laid down by the Civil War. They have been
subdued, reconciled, or smoothed over. Despite all disturbances, the monopolist
rulers have entrenched themselves more firmly in their paramount positions. However,
a closer scrutiny of the development discloses that the working class occupies an
increasingly influential, though still subordinate, place in our national life.
The question presents itself with renewed force: Will this situation of class
stalemate — with the workers in a secondary position — continue indefinitely? The
capitalists naturally answer that it can and must be so. Furthermore, they do everything
from teaching in school the perpetual existence of the established class structure to
passing antilabour laws to insure the continuance of the status quo. The union
officialdom, for their part, go along with this general proposition.
Neither the capitalist spokesmen nor the AFL-CIO officialdom will find any
precedent in American history to reinforce their expectations of an indefinite
maintenance of the status quo. That is one lesson from our national past that the
“long view” of socialism emphasises. For many years, despite occasional tiffs, the
American colonists got along with their mother country and even cherished the tie.
Then came a very rapid and radical reversal in relations, a duel to the end. The same
held true of the long coexistence of the Northern free states and Southern slavery. For
60 years, the Northerners had to play second fiddle to the Southern slave autocracy
until the majority of people in the country came to believe that this situation would
endure indefinitely. The slaveowners, like the capitalists of today, taught that their
“American way of life” was the crown of civilisation. But once the new combination of
progressive forces was obliged to assert itself, the maturing differences broke out in
44 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
a civil war which disposed of the old order. The political collaborators of yesterday
turned into irreconcilable foes on the morrow.
The upholders of the status quo in this country can find still less support from the
main trends of world history in our own time. In 1848, at a time when the capitalist
classes on both sides of the Atlantic were toppling monarchies and feudal aristocracies,
the pioneer communists first publicly proclaimed their ideas and started the movement
of scientific socialism, which has become the guide of the world working class in its
struggle for emancipation. In 1917, 69 years later, the first working-class state was set
up in the Soviet Union. There was no other established for almost three decades.
Then came the Second World War, which extended the domain of collectivised
property throughout Eastern Europe, and afterwards the victory of the Chinese
revolution, which overturned capitalism in that major power in the East.
All this is tantamount to a colossal advance of world history. The essence of the
new stage is that the movement for the advancement of capitalism, which had dominated
world history from the 16th to the 19th centuries, has been succeeded on a world scale
in the 20th century by the anticapitalist movement of the socialist working class and
its colonial allies.
Of course it is not only the hope but the policy of the present capitalist holders of
power that the achievements, ideas, and purposes of this revolutionary movement of
the workers and colonial peoples can be contained in other parts of the world and
crushed there. At any rate, the witch-hunters make every effort to keep its influences
from these shores. Just as the British tyrants and the Southern slaveholders, each in
their day, mustered all their resources to hold back the oncoming revolutionary forces
in this land, so do the agents of the American plutocracy today. Will the monopolists
succeed where their forerunners failed? Let us consider this question.
The high point of a revolutionary process consists in the transfer of supreme
power from one class to another. What are the prevailing relationships of power in the
United States? All basic decisions on foreign and domestic policy are made by the top
capitalist circles to forward their aims and interests. Labour may be able to modify this
or that decision or policy, but its influence does no more than curb the political power
exercised by the monopolists.
However, there is a remarkable anomaly in such a relationship of forces. The now
united union movement has about 17 million members. With their families, followers,
and friends, this movement can muster enough votes to give the political representatives
of organised labour majority power in the cities, in the states, and in Washington.
This means that the capitalists continue to exercise their sway by virtue of default,
that is, a continued default of independent political action and organisation by labour,
The Long View of History 45
or more precisely by its present leaders. They are failing to use one-thousandth of the
power their movement presently and potentially possesses on behalf of the working
people.
Organised labour has within its own grasp enough political strength, not to speak
of its economic and social capacities, to be the sovereign force in this country. That is
why any movement toward the formation of an independent party of labour based on
the trade unions would have such highly revolutionising implications upon the existing
setup, regardless of the intentions or announced program of its organisers. Any such
move on a massive scale would portend a shift in the power of supreme decision in the
United States from capitalist to labour circles, just as the coming to Washington of the
Republican Party in 1860 signified the shift of power away from the slaveholders to
the Northern industrialists.
The Republican leaders of 1861 did not have revolutionary intentions. They headed
a reformist party. They wanted to restrict the power of the slaveholders. But to do this
involved upsetting the established balance of class forces. The slaveholders
recognised the threat to their supremacy far more clearly and felt it more keenly than
did the Northern Republican leaders themselves. That is why they initiated a
counterrevolutionary assault in order to retrieve the power they had previously
possessed.
The parallel with any national assumption of political power by the labour
movement, even in a reformist way, is plain to see. Is such a shift possible? A succession
of crucial shifts of power has marked the onward movement of the American people:
from Britain to the colonial merchants and planters in the 18th century; and from the
Southern slavocracy to the industrial capitalists in the 19th century. The thrust in the
present period of our national history is toward another such colossal shift, this time
from the ruling plutocracy to the rising working class and its allies among the oppressed
minorities.
The whole course of economic, social, and political development in this country
and in this century points to such a shift in power. Of course, the working class is far
from predominant yet, and even less conscious of its historical mission. But, from the
standpoint of the long view, it is most important to note the different rates of growth
in the economic, social, and political potentialities of the respective contenders for
supreme power. Reviewing this country’s history from 1876 to 1957, together with the
rate of growth of the working-class movement on a world scale, the balance of forces
has been steadily shifting, despite all oscillations, toward the side of working-class
power. Nothing whatsoever, including imperialist war, the Taft-Hartley Act, and
McCarthyism, has been able to stop the momentum of the US labour movement.
46 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
ultimate representatives of the American nation and its labour movement or enduring
shapers of the world’s destiny, or that their reactionary policies and shortsighted
outlook will prevail for decades?
The American people will bring forward in the future, as they have at critical times
in the past, more audacious men and women with a vision of a new world in the
making. These fighting leaders and leading fighters, guided by “the long view” of
Marxism, will prove in practice that the socialist prospects of humanity, and of the
American nation, are not so distant as they now appear.
48 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
I
In the third chapter of The Prophet Outcast, the final volume of his biography of
Trotsky, where he treats of “The Revolutionary as Historian”, Isaac Deutscher
discusses the role of personality in the determination of social events in a highly
instructive context. The problem is raised in connection with Trotsky’s appraisal of
Lenin’s place in the Russian Revolution.
Deutscher holds that Trotsky shuttled between two discordant positions. In the
History of the Russian Revolution, a letter to Preobrazhensky in 1928, and in his Diary
in Exile Trotsky maintained that Lenin was absolutely indispensable to the victory of
October. It would not have been achieved without him. Elsewhere, in The Revolution
Betrayed, says Deutscher, Trotsky reverted to the orthodox view of historical
materialism which subordinates the quality of the leadership to the more objective
factors in the making of history. Is this a wavering on Trotsky’s part?
Marxism does teach that no individual, however talented, strong-willed or
strategically situated, can alter the main course of historical development, which is
shaped by supra-individual circumstances and forces. Therefore, reasons Deutscher,
the revolution would have triumphed in 1917 with other leaders even if Lenin had
been removed from the arena by some accident. Trotsky himself, or a team of other
Bolshevik chiefs, might have filled his place.
Deutscher divines that Trotsky’s lapse into a subjectivism bordering on “the cult
of the individual” in regard to Lenin was motivated by a psychological need to
exaggerate the role of individual leadership as a counterweight to Stalin’s autocracy
in his mortal political combat with him. He seeks to correct Trotsky by reference to the
ideas expressed in Plekhanov’s classical essay on The Role of the Individual in
History. This was a polemic against the Narodnik school of subjective sociology
which exalted the hero as an autonomous creator of history at the expense of the
masses and other objective determinants of the class struggle. Arguing against the
thesis that the collective demand for leadership could be supplied by only one
remarkable individual, Plekhanov pointed out that the person hoisted into supreme
authority bars the way of others who might have shouldered and carried through the
same tasks, though in a different style. The eclipse of alternate candidates creates the
optical illusion of the sole irreplaceable personality. If the objective prerequisites are
ripe and the historical demand forceful enough, a range of men can fulfil the indicated
functions of command.
The Chinese and Yugoslav examples, writes Deutscher, demonstrate how rising
revolutions can utilise men of smaller stature than a Lenin or Trotsky to take power.
The class struggle can press into service whatever human material is available to fulfil
its objectives.
This theme has an importance surpassing Trotsky’s judgment on Lenin’s
significance for the Russian Revolution or Deutscher’s criticism of Trotsky’s alleged
inconsistencies on the matter. The reciprocal action of the objective and subjective
factors in the historical process is one of the key problems of social science. It is no
less a key to revolutionary practice in our own time.
Historical materialism unequivocally gives primacy, as Deutscher emphasises, to
such objective factors as the level of the productive forces and the state of class
relations in the making of history. But there is more to the matter than this.
In the first place, the social phenomena divided into opposing categories are only
relatively objective or subjective. Their status changes according to the relevant
connections. If the world environment is objective to the nation which is part of it, the
nation in turn is objective to the classes which constitute its social structure. The
ruling class is objective to the working class. The party is subjective to the class
whose interests it represents and aims it promotes while groups, tendencies, factions
and their combinations are subjective to the movement or party which contains them.
Finally, the individual has a subjective status relative to all these other factors, although
he has an objective existence in relation to other individuals.
In the second place, the multiple factors in any historical process do not, and
indeed cannot have, an equal and simultaneous growth. Not only do some mature
before others but certain of them may fail to achieve a full and adequate reality at the
decisive moment, or indeed at any point. The coming together of all the various
factors essential for the occurrence of a particular result in a great historical process
is an exceptional or “accidental” event which is necessary only in the long run.
The leadership, collective and individual, embodies the conscious element in
50 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
The conscious factor has a qualitatively different import over an entire historical
epoch than it has in a specific phase or situation within it. When antagonistic social
forces vie for supremacy on a world-historical scale, such favourable and unfavourable
circumstances as the character of the leadership tend to offset and cancel one another.
The underlying historical necessities assert themselves in and through the aggregate
struggles and override the more superficial and chance features which can decide the
upshot of any particular encounter. Moreover, an ascending class in the long run
benefits more than its opponent from the accidents of development, since the receding
class has less and less reserve strength to withstand and overcome small variations in
the relation of forces. The total assets of the one increase as those of the other
diminish.
Time is an all-important element in the conflict of contending social forces. The
indeterminate phase when events can be diverted in either direction does not last
long. The crisis in social relations must be resolved quickly one way or the other. At
that point the activity or passivity of dominant personalities, groups, parties and
masses can tip the scales on one side or the other. The individual can enter as the
ultimate factor in the total process of historical determination only when all the other
forces in play are temporarily equalised. Then his added weight can serve to tip the
balance.
Almost everyone can recall occasions where his own intervention or that of others
proved decisive in resolving an uncertain situation. What happens in the small incidents
of life applies to big events. Just as the single vote of the chairman can decide when
the forces on an issue are evenly divided, so the outstanding qualities of great figures
are manifested when history arrives at a deadlock. Their decision or decisiveness
breaks the tie and propels events along a definitely different line. This holds for
counterrevolutionary as well as revolutionary tendencies. Hitler was important because
he took Germany into fascism and war. But he did not direct German or world history
into a qualitatively new channel. He simply helped write a further horrible chapter in
the death agony of capitalism.
Lenin’s imperishable contribution was the push he gave to opening an entirely
new path for Russian and world history, redirecting it from the dead end of capitalism
onto the new beginning of socialism.
This brings us back to the specific problem Deutscher discusses. He does not
question the fact that in the actual unrolling of the 1917 revolution Lenin functioned
as the final cause in the October victory. The difference between Deutscher and
Trotsky concerns the uncertain realm of historical possibilities. Could another
revolutionist such as Trotsky, or a combination of them, have assumed Lenin’s place?
52 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
Trotsky somewhat categorically said no. Deutscher objects that if others on hand
could not have performed the same job of leadership, then the position of historical
materialism on the lawful determination of events must be abandoned. Either the
objective or the subjective factors decide; it is necessary to choose between them.
In my opinion, Deutscher here takes a too constricted and one-sided stand on
historical determinism whereas Trotsky employed a more flexible and multi-sided
interpretation based upon the interrelation of mutually opposing categories. He tested
his conception, first in practice, then in theory, in the successive stages of the Russian
Revolution where the importance of the conscious factors stood out with remarkable
clarity.
The type of leadership was very different in the two revolutions of 1917. The
February Revolution was not planned or directed from above. Trotsky points out in
the chapter of his History, “Who Led the February Revolution?” that it was led “by
conscious and tempered workers educated for the most part by the party of Lenin”.
As educator and organiser of these key workers, Lenin was to that extent necessary
to the February overturn, even though he was not on the spot in person.
Between February and October he became more and more decisive because of his
resolute and farsighted stands at a series of crucial moments, starting with the
reorienting of the Bolshevik cadres in April and culminating in his insistence on
insurrection in October. According to Trotsky, Lenin’s role could not have been
duplicated. This was not simply because of his personal gifts but even more because
of his exceptional standing in the Bolshevik party which was largely his creation.
The question of leadership in the Russian Revolution had a dual aspect. While
the Bolsheviks led the workers and peasants to victory, Lenin led the Bolshevik party.
His paramount role came from the fact that he led the leaders of the revolution.
Trotsky knew better than anyone else how Lenin could sway the higher echelons
as well as the ranks of his party. His authority was a considerable help from April to
October in getting his correct proposals adopted over the resistance of other Bolshevik
chiefs. This accumulated capital of prestige was not at the disposal of others, including
Trotsky, who had a different organisational history and relations. That was the
objective basis for his opinion that the October Revolution would most likely not
have taken place unless “Lenin was present and in command”.
To be sure, it is not possible, as Deutscher remarks and Trotsky himself recognised,
to be utterly categorical on this point. But Trotsky’s conclusion, which is to be found
in all his writings after October and before the rise of Stalin, was not based upon a
regrettable lapse into excessive subjectivity. It came from applying the Marxist dialectic
to the facts as he witnessed and assayed them. If he was wrong, it was not because of
From Lenin to Castro 53
II
Sidney Hook has entered this controversy from the opposite end. In a review of
The Prophet Outcast in the May 11, 1964, New Leader he seizes upon Deutscher’s
criticism of Trotsky’s subjectivism for his own purposes. Instead of condemning, he
compliments Trotsky for discarding the dogmas of dialectical materialism and
attributing “the most important social event in human history’ to the purely personal
and contingent circumstance of Lenin’s presence in Russia. In his eyes the October
Revolution was the accidental consequence of the work of an individual. Hook repeats
the view expressed in his book on The Hero in History, cited by Deutscher, that the
October Revolution “was not so much a product of the whole past of Russian history
as a product of one of the most event-making figures of all time”.
Whereas Deutscher in the name of Marxist orthodoxy inclines to make the objective
factors virtually self-sufficient and thus underrates the crucial importance of Lenin’s
leadership, Hook practically nullifies the other and prior determinants by making the
October victory wholly dependent upon a single individual. His approach falls below
the standards of the most enlightened liberal historians who at least placed objective
factors on a par with the ideas and intervention of great men.
Hook has to falsify Trotsky’s standpoint in order to convert him into a pragmatist
as superficial as Hook himself. Trotsky’s History is explicitly devoted to demonstrating
the necessity of the Russian Revolution and its specific outcome as the result of the
whole previous evolution of world capitalism, the backwardness of Russia
complemented by its concentrated industrial enterprises and advanced working class,
the stresses of the First World War upon a decayed tsarist autocracy, the weakness of
the bourgeoisie, the failure of the petty-bourgeois parties and the bold vision of the
Bolsheviks headed by Lenin.
Trotsky delineates the operation of this determinism in living reality by narrating
and analysing the interconnection of the salient events from the February beginning
to the October climax. The successive stages of the revolution did not unfold
haphazardly; they issued with inexorable lawfulness one from the other in a causally
conditioned sequence. The aim of his theoretical exposition was to find in the verified
facts of the actual process the effects of the objective necessities formulated in the
laws of the class struggle applied to a backward great power under 20th century
conditions. He had already anticipated and articulated these in his celebrated theory
54 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
leadership of Bolshevik-Leninist calibre. The October victory coupled with the post-
October defeats convinced the once dubious Trotsky of the decisive role of leadership
in an objectively revolutionary situation. These experiences led him to the generalisation
which was the keystone of the founding program of the Fourth International, adopted
in 1938, that “the historical crisis of mankind is reduced to the crisis of revolutionary
leadership”. That is why he dedicated the last years of his life to the task of attempting
to assemble such a leadership under the banner of the Fourth International.
Deutscher’s disagreement with Trotsky over Lenin’s part in the Russian Revolution
is directly connected with his difference with Trotsky over the latter’s role in the post-
Lenin period. Deutscher regards Trotsky’s assertion that the foundation of the Fourth
International was “the most important work of my life — more important than 1917,
more important than the period of the civil war, or any other …” as an aberration. The
energy devoted to the Trotskyist groups was largely wasted, he believes, since the
objective conditions were not suitable for constructing a new international. In his
opinion, Trotsky would have been better advised to remain an interpreter of events
instead of vainly trying to change their course by means of a rival world revolutionary
organisation.
J.B. Stuart undertook to answer Deutscher’s criticism of Trotsky’s unrealism in
connection with the Fourth International in World Outlooka and there is no point in
repeating his arguments. Here we are primarily interested in the real rationale behind
Trotsky’s positions.
Deutscher contends that Trotsky misjudged Lenin’s importance in the winning of
the Russian Revolution and his own role in the period of world reaction after Lenin’s
death for psychological reasons which ran counter to Marxist objectivity. Trotsky
actually derived his position in both cases, it seems to us, from his conception of the
needs of the revolutionary process in our time. He thought that all the major objective
ingredients for the overthrow of capitalism had in general ripened. What was missing
for new Octobers was the presence of leadership of the type supplied by Lenin and
the Bolsheviks in 1917.
Such cadres had to be created to prevent the incompetent and treacherous
bureaucracies heading the different sectors of the workers’ movement from ruining
more revolutionary opportunities. Thus world political, rather than individual
psychological, necessities accounted for his conclusions.
III
It is true, as Deutscher points out, that revolutionary power was conquered in
Yugoslavia and China with leaderships trained in the Stalinist school which do not
match the standards of Lenin’s Bolshevism. The 1963 Reunification Congress of the
Fourth International took cognisance of this development in its resolution, The
Dynamics of World Revolution Today. “The weakness of the enemy in the backward
countries has opened the possibility of coming to power even with a blunted
instrument.”
However, the document hastens to add: “The strength of the enemy in the
imperialist countries demands a tool of much greater perfection.” For the taking of
power in the capitalist strongholds as well as the administration of power in the
degenerated or deformed workers’ states, the building of new mass revolutionary
parties and their unification in a new international organisation remains the central
strategical task of the present period no less than in Lenin’s and Trotsky’s day.
This dialectical unity of the objective and subjective factors in the making of a
revolution has been both exemplified and theorised by Fidel Castro and his close
associates. If ever an historic event could be considered the work of one man, that
was — and is — the Cuban Revolution. Castro is truly its “lider maximo” [main
leader].
Castro has explained, notably in his December 21, 1961, speech on Marxism-
Leninism, how the founders of the July 26 Movement did not wait for all the objective
conditions required for revolutionary success to emerge spontaneously. They
deliberately set about to create the still missing revolutionary conditions by fighting.
Their guerrilla warfare did bring about the moral, psychological, political changes
needed to overthrow Batista’s tyranny. The general lesson of their experience for the
further struggles against Latin-American dictatorships has been formulated as follows
by Che Guevara in his handbook on guerrilla warfare: “It is not always necessary to
wait until all the conditions are ripe for the revolution; the insurrectional centre can
create them.”
The transformation of the balance of forces in favour of the progressive side by
the initiative of a small band of conscious revolutionary fighters dramatically
demonstrates how decisive the subjective factor can be in making history. Yet Castro
would be the first to caution against an adventurism which ignores objective
conditions, to disavow any cult of the individual, and to acknowledge that his intentions
would have miscarried and his combatants would have been rendered powerless
without the response they received, first from the peasants in the mountains and then
From Lenin to Castro 57
from the masses in the rural and urban areas. The sensitivity of the Cuban leaders to
the interplay of the subjective and objective factors in the development of the
revolution and its regime at all stages has brought them to a deeper understanding of
the ideas of Marx and of the need for a party like Lenin’s.
Which of these contending determinisms will prevail? The fate of mankind hangs
in the balance of this decision. To dispossess and disarm the atomaniacs headquartered
in Washington, a revolutionary movement of tremendous dimensions and
determination will have to be built. No single individual will stop them. But victory in
the life-and-death struggle for world peace against nuclear annihilation will require
the initiative and devotion of individuals who, though they may not possess the
outstanding leadership capacities of a Lenin, Trotsky or Castro, can act in their spirit.
MAJOR THEORIES OF HISTORY FROM
THE GREEKS TO MARXISM
study. The need for theorising about history or the nature of society does not arise
until civilisation is well advanced and sudden, violent, and far-reaching upheavals in
social relations take place during the lifetime of individuals or within the memories of
their elders.
When swift strides are taken from one form of social structure to another, the old
days and ways stand out in startling contrast, and even conflict, with the new. Through
trade, travel and war, the representatives of the expanding social system undergoing
construction or reconstruction come into contact with peoples of quite different
customs on lower levels of culture.
More immediately, glaring differences in the conditions of life within their own
communities and bitter conflicts between antagonistic classes induce thoughtful men
who have the means for such pursuits to speculate on the origins of such oppositions,
to compare the various kinds of societies and governments, and to try and arrange
them in an order of succession or worth.
The English historian M.I. Finley makes a similar point in reviewing three recent
books on the ancient East in the August 20, 1965, New Statesman: “The presence or
absence of a ‘historical sense’ is nothing less than an intellectual reflection of the
very wide differences in the historical process itself.”
He cites the Marxist scholar, Professor D.D. Kosambi, who attributes “the total
lack of historical sense” in ancient India to the narrow outlook of village life bound up
with its mode of agricultural production. “The succession of seasons is all important,
while there is little cumulative change to be noted in the village from year to year. This
gives the general feeling of ‘the Timeless East’ to foreign observers.”
The other civilised peoples of the ancient Near and Middle East likewise lacked a
sense of history. There is nothing, notes Professor Leo Oppenhelm, “that would
attest the awareness of the scribes of the existence of a historical continuum in the
Mesopotamian civilisation”. This is confirmed by the fact that “the longest and most
explicit Assyrian royal inscriptions … were embedded in the substructure of a temple
or a palace, safe from human eyes and only to be read by the deity to whom they were
addressed”.
The main preconditions for an historical outlook upon history in the West were
brought into being from about 1100 to 700 BC by the transition from the Bronze to the
Iron Age in the Middle East and Aegean civilisations. The comparatively self-sufficient
agricultural kingdoms and settlements were supplemented or supplanted by bustling
commercial centres, especially in the Phoenician and Ionian ports of Asia Minor.
There new classes — merchants, shipowners, manufacturers, artisans, seafarers —
came to the fore and challenged the institutions, ideas and power of the old landed
62 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
writings, and Aristotle in his Politics, collected specimens of different forms of state
rule. They named, classified and criticised them. They sought to ascertain not only
the best mode of government for the city state but also the order of their forms of
development and the causes of political variation and revolution.
Polybius, the Greek historian of the rise of the Roman empire, viewed it as the prize
example of the natural laws which regulated the cyclical transformation of one
governmental form into another. He believed, like Plato, that all states inevitably
passed through the phases of kingship, aristocracy and democracy which degenerated
into their allied forms of despotism, oligarchy and mob rule. The generation and
degeneration of these successive stages of rulership was due to natural causes.
“This is the regular cycle of constitutional revolutions, and the natural order in which
institutions change, are transformed, and return to their original stage”, he wrote.
Just as they knew and named the major kinds of political organisation from
monarchy to democracy, so did the Greek thinkers of both the idealist and materialist
schools originate the basic types of historical interpretation which have endured to
the present day.
They were the first to try to explain the evolution of society along materialist lines,
however crude and awkward were their initial efforts. The Atomists, the Sophists and
the Hippocratic school of medicine put forward the idea that the natural environment
was the decisive factor in the moulding of mankind. In its extreme expressions this
trend of thought reduced social-historical changes to the effects of the geographical
theatre and its climatic conditioning. Thus Polybius wrote: “We mortals have an
irresistible tendency to yield to climatic influences; and to this cause, and no other,
may be traced the great distinctions which prevail among us in character, physical
formation and complexion, as well as in most of our habits, varying with nationality
and wide local separation.”
These earliest sociologists taught that mankind had climbed from savagery to
civilisation by imitating nature and improving upon her operations. The finest exponent
of this materialist view in Graeco-Roman culture was Lucretius who gave a brilliant
sketch of the steps in the development of society in his poem On The Nature of
Things.
Predominant among the Greek thinkers, however, were the sorts of explanation
which have ever since been the stock in trade of the historical idealists. There were
five of these.
1. The Great God Theory. The most primitive attempts to explain the origin and
development of the world and man are the creation myths to be found among preliterate
peoples. We are best acquainted with the one in Genesis which ascribes the making of
64 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
heaven and earth with all its features and creatures to a Lord God who worked on a six-
day schedule. These fanciful stories do not have any scientific validity.
The raw materials for genuine history-writing were first collected in the annals of
the reigns and chronicles of kings in the river valley civilisations of the Near East,
India and China. The first synthetic conception of history arose from the fusion of
elements taken over from the old creation myths with a review of these records. This
was the Great God, or theological version of history which asserted that divine beings
directed human affairs together with the rest of the cosmos.
Just as the royal despots dominated the city states and their empires, so the will,
passions, plans and needs of the gods were the ultimate causes of events. The king is
the agent who maintains the world in being by means of an annual contest with the
powers of chaos. This theological theory was elaborated by the Sumerians,
Babylonians and Egyptians before it came down to the Greeks and Romans. It was
expounded in the Israelite scriptures whence it was taken over and reshaped by the
Christian and Mohammedan religions and their states.
Under the theocratic monarchies of the East the divine guidance of human affairs
was wrapped up with the godlike nature of the priest-king. In Babylon, Egypt, the
Alexandrian Empire and Rome the supreme ruling force of the universe and the forceful
ruler of the realm were regarded as equally divine. The Great God and the Great Man
were one and the same.
2. The Great Man Theory. The straightforward theological view of history is too
crude and naive, too close to primitive animism, too much in conflict with civilised
enlightenment to persist without criticism or change except among the most ignorant
and devout. It has been supplanted by more refined versions of the same type of
thinking.
The Great Man theory emerged from a dissociation of the dual components of the
Great God theory. The immense powers attributed to the gods become transferred to
and concentrated in some figure at the head of the state, the church or other key
institution or movement. This exceptionally placed personage was supposedly
endowed with the capacity for moulding events as he willed. This is the pristine
source of the tenacious belief that unusually influential and able individuals determine
the main direction of history.
Fetishistic worship of the Great Man has come down through the ages from the
god-kings of Mesopotamia to the adoration of a Hitler. It has had numerous incarnations
according to the values attached at different times by different people to the various
domains of social activity. In antiquity these ranged from the divine monarch, the
tyrant, the lawgiver (Solon), the military conqueror (Alexander), the dictator (Caesar),
Major Theories of History from the Greeks to Marxism 65
the hero-emancipator (David), and the religious leader (Christ, Buddha, Mohammed).
All these were put in the place of the Almighty as the prime mover and shaper of
human history.
The most celebrated latter-day expounder of this viewpoint was Carlyle who wrote:
“Universal history, the history of what man has accomplished in this world, is at
bottom the history of the great men who have worked here.”
3. The Great Mind Theory. A more sophisticated and philosophical variant of the
Great God-Man line of thought is the notion that history is drawn forward or driven
ahead by some ideal force in order to realise its preconceived ends. The Greek
Anaxagoras said: “Reason (Nous) governs the world.” Aristotle held that the prime
mover of the universe and thereby the ultimate animator of everything within it was
God, who was defined as pure mind engaged in thinking about itself.
Hegel was the foremost modern exponent of this theory that the progress of
mankind consisted in the working out and consummation of an idea. He wrote: “Spirit,
or Mind, is the only motive principle of history.” The underlying goal of the World
Spirit and the outcome of its laborious development was the realisation of the idea of
freedom.
The Great Mind Theory easily slides into the notion that some set of brilliant
intellects, or even one mental genius, supplies the mainspring of human advancement.
Plato taught that there are “some natures who ought to study philosophy and to be
leaders in the state; and others who are not born to be philosophers, and are meant to
be followers rather than leaders”.
Thus some 18th century rationalists who believed that “opinion governs mankind”
looked toward an enlightened monarch to introduce the necessary progressive
reconstruction of the state and society. A more widespread manifestation of this
approach contrasts to the unthinking mob some upper stratum of the population as
the exemplar of reason which alone can be entrusted with political leadership and
power.
4. The Best People Theory. All such interpretations contain infusions of the
prejudice that some elite, the Best Race, the favoured nation, the ruling class alone
make history. The Old Testament assumed that the Israelites were God’s chosen
people. The Greeks regarded themselves as the acme of culture, better in all respects
than the barbarians. Plato and Aristotle looked upon the slave-holding aristocracy as
naturally superior to the lower orders.
5. The Human Nature Theory. Most persistent is the view that history in the last
analysis has been determined by the qualities of human nature, good or bad. Human
nature, like nature itself, was regarded as rigid and unchanging from one generation to
66 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
another. The historian’s task was to demonstrate what these invariant traits of the
human constitution and character were, how the course of history exemplified them,
and how the social structure was moulded or had to be remodelled in accordance with
them. Such a definition of essential human nature was the starting point for the social
theorising of Socrates, Plato and Aristotle and other great idealists.
But it will also be found at the bottom of the social and political philosophy of the
most diverse schools. Thus the empiricist David Hume flatly asserts in An Enquiry
Concerning Human Understanding: “Mankind are so much the same, in all times and
places, that history informs us of nothing new or strange in this particular. Its chief
use is only to discover the constant and universal principles of human nature.”
Many of the 19th century pathfinders in the social sciences clung to this old
standby of “the constant and universal principles of human nature”. For example, E.B.
Tylor, the founder of British anthropology, wrote in 1889: “Human institutions, like
stratified rocks, succeed each other in series substantially uniform over the globe,
independent of what seems the comparatively superficial differences of race and
language, but shaped by similar human nature.”
Although they may have held different opinions of what the essential qualities of
humanity were, idealist and materialist thinkers alike have appealed in the last resort
to permanent principles of human nature to explain social and historical phenomena.
Thus the materialist-minded Thucydides, as M.I Finley tells us in his introduction to
The Greek Historians, believed that “human nature and human behaviour were …
essentially fixed qualities, the same in one century as another”.
For many centuries after the Greeks, scientific insight into the workings of history
made little progress. Under Christianity and feudalism the theological conception that
history was the manifestation of God’s plan monopolised social philosophy. In contrast
to the stagnation of science in Western Europe, the Moslems and Jews carried forward
the social as well as the natural sciences. The most original and unsurpassed student
of social processes between the ancients and moderns was the 14th century thinker
of the Maghreb, Ibn Khaldun who analysed the stages of development of the
Mohammedan countries and cultures and the causes of their typical institutions and
features in the most materialist manner of his epoch.
This eminent Moslem statesman was very likely the first scholar to formulate a
clear conception of sociology, the science of social development. He did so under the
name of the study of culture.
He wrote: “History is the record of human society, or world civilisation; of the
changes that take place in the nature of that society, such as savagery, sociability, and
group solidarity; of revolutions and uprisings by one set of people against another
Major Theories of History from the Greeks to Marxism 67
with the resulting kingdoms and states, with their various ranks; of the different
activities and occupations of men, whether for gaining their livelihood or in the various
sciences and crafts; and, in general, of all the transformations that society undergoes
by its very nature.”
The next big advance in scientific understanding of history came with the rise of
bourgeois society and the discovery of other regions of the globe associated with its
commercial and naval expansion. In their conflicts with the ruling feudal hierarchy and
the Church the intellectual spokesmen for progressive bourgeois forces rediscovered
and reasserted the ideas of class struggle first noted by the Greeks and instituted
historical comparisons with antiquity to bolster their claims. Their new revolutionary
views demanded not only a wider outlook upon the world but a deeper probing into
the mechanism of social change.
Such bold representatives of bourgeois thought as Machiavelli and Vico in Italy,
Hobbes, Harrington, Locke and the classical economists in England, the Scottish
school of Adam Ferguson, Voltaire, Rousseau, Montesquieu, D’Holbach and others
in France helped accumulate the materials and clear the site for a more realistic picture
of society and a more rigorous understanding of its modes and stages of development.
On a much higher level of social and scientific development, historical thought
from the 17th to the 19th centuries tended to become polarised, as in Greece, between
idealist and materialist modes of explanation. Both schools of thought were animated
by a common aim. They believed that history had an intelligible character and that the
nature and sources of its laws could be ascertained.
Theological interpreters like Bishop Bossuet continued to see God as the director
of the historical procession. While most other thinkers did not dispute that divine
providence ultimately shaped the course of events, they were far more concerned
with the mundane ways and means through which history operated.
Giambattista Vico of Naples was the great pioneer among these thinkers. He
asserted at the beginning of the 18th century that since history, or “the world of
nations”, had been created by men, it could be understood by its makers. He
emphasised that social and cultural phenomena passed through a regular sequence
of stages which was cyclical in character.
He insisted that “the order of ideas must follow the order of things” and that the
“order of human things” was “first the forests, after that the huts, thence the village,
next the cities and finally the academies”. His “new science” of history sought to
discover and apply “the universal and eternal principles … on which all nations were
founded, and still preserve themselves”. Vico brings forward the class struggle in his
interpretation of history, especially in the heroic age represented by the conflict between
68 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
thought survive today. Not one has been permanently buried, no matter how outmoded,
inadequate or scientifically incorrect it is. The oldest interpretations can be revived
and reappear in modern dress to serve some social need or stratum.
What bourgeois nation has not proclaimed in time of war that “God is on our
side”, guiding its destiny? The Great Man theory strutted about under the swastika in
the homage paid to Hitler. Spengler in Germany and Toynbee in England offer their re-
editions of the cyclical round of history. The school of geopolitics makes geographical
conditions in the shape of the heartland and the outlying regions into the paramount
determinant of modern history.
Nazi Germany, Verwoerd’s South Africa and the Southern white supremacists
exalt the master race into the dictator of history in its crudest form. The conception
that human nature must be the basis of social structure is the last-ditch defence of the
opponents of socialism as well as the point of departure for the utopian socialism of
the American psychoanalyst Erich Fromm and others.
Finally, the notion that reason is the motive force in history is shared by all sorts
of savants. The American anthropologist Alexander Goldenweiser stated in Early
Civilisation: “Thus the whole of civilisation, if followed backward step by step,
would ultimately be found resolvable, without residue, into bits of ideas in the minds
of individuals.” Here ideas and individuals are the creative factors of history.
In describing his philosophy, the Italian thinker Croce wrote: “History is the record
of the creations of the human spirit in every field, theoretical as well as practical. And
these spiritual creations are always born in the hearts and minds of men of genius,
artists, thinkers, men of action, moral and religious reformers.” This position combines
idealism with elitism, the spirit using geniuses, or the creative minority, as the agency
which redeems the masses.
These diverse elements of historical interpretation can appear in the most
incongruous combinations in a given country, school of thought or individual mind.
Stalinism has provided the most striking example of such an illogical synthesis. The
votaries of “the personality cult” sought to fuse the traditions and views of Marxism,
the most modern and scientific philosophy, with the archaic Great Man version of the
contemporary historical process.
Except in Maoist China, this odd and untenable amalgam of ideas has already
crumbled. Yet it demonstrates how generalised thought about the historical process
can retrogress after making an immense leap forward. The history of historical science
proves in its own way that progress is not even or persistent throughout history.
Thucydides, the narrator of the Peloponnesian Wars in the fourth century BC, had a
far more realistic view of history than did St. Augustine, the celebrator of the City of
Major Theories of History from the Greeks to Marxism 73
This essay aims to give a connected and comprehensive explanation of one of the
fundamental laws of human history — the law of uneven and combined development.
This is the first time, to my knowledge, that this has been undertaken. I shall try to
show what this law is, how it has worked out in the main stages of history, and also
how it can clarify some of the most puzzling social phenomena and political problems
of our age.
The text has been taken from the third US edition (Merit Publishers; New York, 1966).
76 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
tendencies.”1
What had happened? A section of the Russian nobility and landowners, the
oppositional bourgeoisie, the radical intellectuals, the insurgent workers, peasants
and soldiers, along with the Allied imperialists — these “absolutely dissimilar” social
forces — had momentarily arrayed themselves against the tsarist autocracy, each for
its own reasons. All together they besieged, isolated and overthrew the Romanov
regime. This extraordinary conjuncture of circumstances and unrepeatable combination
of forces had grown up out of the whole previous unevenness of Russian historical
development with all its long-postponed and unsolved social and political problems
exacerbated by the first imperialist world war.
The differences which had been submerged in the offensive against tsarism
immediately asserted themselves and it did not take long for this de facto alliance of
inherently opposing forces to disintegrate and break up. The allies of the February
1917 revolution became transformed into the irreconcilable foes of October 1917.
How did this hostility come about?, The overthrow of tsarisrn had in turn produced
a new and higher unevenness in the situation, which may be summarised in the
following formula. On the one hand, the objective conditions were ripe for the
assumption of power by the workers; on the other hand, the Russian working class,
and above all its leadership, had not yet correctly appraised the real situation or
tested the new relationship of forces. Consequently they were subjectively unready
to solve that supreme task. The unfolding of the class struggles from February to
October 1917 may be said to consist in the growing recognition by the working class
and its revolutionary leaders of what had to be done and in overcoming the disparity
between the objective conditions and the subjective preparation. The gap between
these was closed in action by the triumph of the Bolsheviks in the October Revolution
which combined the proletarian conquest of power with the widespread peasant
uprising.
expression.
These two contributions to the scientific understanding of social movement are in
fact intimately interlinked. Trotsky’s conception of the Permanent Revolution resulted
from his study of the peculiarities of Russian historical development in the light of the
new problems presented to world socialism in the epoch of imperialism. These problems
were especially acute and complex in backward countries where the bourgeois-
democratic revolution had not yet taken place or set about to solve many of its most
elementary tasks at a time when the proletarian revolution was already at hand. The
fruits of his thinking on these questions, confirmed by the actual developments of the
Russian Revolution, prepared and stimulated his subsequent elaboration of the law
of uneven and combined development.
Indeed, Trotsky’s theory of the Permanent Revolution represents the most fruitful
application of this very law to the key problems of the international class struggles in
our own time, the epoch of the transition from the capitalist domination of the world to
socialism, and offers the highest example of its penetrating power. However, the law
itself is not only pertinent to the revolutionary events of the present epoch but, as we
shall see, to the whole compass of social evolution. And it has even broader
applications than that.
evolved rapidly while the rest of the body was changing very little. Evolution of the
brain was much more rapid during one relatively short span than at any other time.
Evolution of the feet was practically at a standstill most of the time during horse
evolution, but three times there were relatively rapid changes in foot mechanism.
Rates of evolution also vary greatly from one lineage to another, even among
related lines. There are a number of animals living today that have changed very little
for very long periods of time: a little brachiopod called Lingula, in some 400 million
years; Limulus, the horseshoe “crab” — really more of a scorpion than a crab — in 175
million or more; Sphenodon, a lizard-like reptile now confined to New Zealand, in
about 150 million years; Didelphis, the American oppossum, in a good 75 million
years. These and the other animals for which evolution essentially stopped long ago all
have relatives that evolved at usual or even at relatively fast rates.
There are, further, characteristic differences of rates in different groups. Most land
animals have evolved faster than most sea animals — a generalisation not contradicted
by the fact that some sea animals have evolved faster than some land animals. [pp.
137-138]
The evolution of entire orders of organisms has passed through a cycle of evolution
marked by an initial phase of restricted, slow growth, followed by a shorter but intense
period of “explosive expansion”, which in turn settled down into a prolonged phase
of lesser changes.
In The Meaning of Evolution, G.G. Simpson states, “Times of rapid expansion,
high variability and beginning adaptive radiation … are periods when enlarged
opportunities are presented to groups able to pursue them” (pp. 72-73). Such an
opportunity for explosive expansion was opened to the reptiles when they evolved to
the point of independence from water as a living medium and burst into landscapes
earlier barren of vertebrate life. Then a “quieter period ensues when the basic radiation
has been completed” and the group can indulge in “the progressive enjoyment of a
completed conquest”.
The evolution of our own species has already gone through the first phase of
such a cycle and entered the second. The immediate animal forerunners of mankind
went through a prolonged period of restricted growth as a lesser breed compared to
others. Mankind arrived at its phase of “explosive expansion” only in the past million
years or so, after the primate from which we are descended acquired the necessary
social powers. However, the further development of mankind will not duplicate the
cycle of animal evolution because the growth of society proceeds on a qualitatively
different basis and is governed by its own unique laws.
The evolution of the distinctive human organism has been marked by considerable
80 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
irregularity. The skull developed its present characteristics among our ape ancestors
long before our flexible hands with the opposable thumb. It was only after our
prototypes had acquired upright posture and working hands, that the brain inside the
skull expanded to its present proportions and complexity.
What is true of entire orders and species of animals and plants holds good for its
individual specimens. If equality prevailed in biological growth, each of the various
organs in the body would develop simultaneously and to the same proportionate
extent. But such perfect symmetry is not to be found in real life. In the growth of the
human foetus some organs emerge before others and mature before others. The head
and the neck are formed before the arms and legs, the heart at the third week and the
lungs later on. As the sum of all these irregularities, we know that infants come out of
the womb in different conditions, even with deformations, and certainly at varying
intervals between conception and birth. The nine-month gestation period is no more
than a statistical average. The date of delivery of a given baby can diverge by days,
weeks or months from this average.
The frontal sinus, a late development in the primates since it is possessed only by
the great apes and men, does not occur in young humans, but emerges after puberty.
In many cases, it never develops at all.
the middle of the 19th century. The central historical task of the Americans throughout
this period was to catch up with Europe by overcoming the disparities in the social
development of the two continents. How and by whom this was done is the main
theme of American history throughout these three and a half centuries.
It required, among other things, two revolutions to complete the job. The colonial
revolution which crowned the first stage of progress gave the American people political
institutions more advanced than any in the Old World — and paved the way for rapid
economic expansion. Even after winning national independence the United States
had still to conquer its economic independence within the capitalist world. The
economic gap between this country and the nations of Western Europe was narrowed
in the first half of the 19th century and virtually closed up by the triumph of Northern
industrial capitalism over the slave power in the Civil War. It did not take long after
that for the United States to come abreast of the West European powers and outstrip
them.
savagery toward barbarism, the central areas of progress among the American Indians
changed places. “As long as the Americans remained in a hunting, food-gathering
economy, northern North America was culturally the most advanced part of the
continent. None of the pre-agricultural cultures that have been found south of the
Great Plains and Northern Woodland areas compares with those of these areas in
richness of content. With the rise of agriculture-based civilisations in Middle America,
the situation was reversed. The main line of diffusion was now from south to north,
and Middle American influences become increasingly recognisable over the whole
area east of the Rockies.”
INTERNAL INEQUALITIES
The inequality of development between continents and countries is matched by
an equally uneven growth of the various elements within each social grouping or
national organism.
In a book on the American working class written by Karl Kautsky early in this
century, the German Marxist pointed out some of the marked contrasts in the social
development of Russia and the United States at that time. “Two states exist”, he
wrote, “diametrically opposed to each other, each of which contains an element
inordinately developed in comparison with their standard of capitalist production. In
one state — America — it is the capitalist class. In Russia it is the proletariat. In no
other country but America is there so much ground for speaking of the dictatorship of
capital, while the proletariat has nowhere acquired such importance as in Russia.”
This difference in development, which Kautsky described in the bud, has since become
enormously accentuated.
Trotsky gave a superb analysis of the significance of such unevenness for
explaining the course of a nation’s history in the opening chapter of his History of the
Russian Revolution on “Peculiarities of Russia’s Development”. Tsarist Russia
contained social forces belonging to three different stages of historical development.
On top were the feudal elements: an overgrown Asiatic autocracy, a state clergy, a
servile bureaucracy, a favoured landed nobility. Below them were a weak, unpopular
bourgeoisie and a cowardly intelligentsia. These opposing phenomena were organically
interconnected. They constituted different aspects of a unified social process. The
very historical conditions which had preserved and fortified the predominance of the
feudal forces — the slow tempo of Russian development, her economic backwardness,
her primitiveness of social forms and low level of culture — had stunted the growth of
the bourgeois forces and fostered their social and political feebleness.
That was one side of the situation. On the other side, the extreme backwardness of
Uneven and Combined Development in History 85
Russian history had left the agrarian and the national problems unsolved, producing
a discontented, land-hungry peasantry and oppressed nationalities longing for freedom,
while the late appearance of capitalist industry gave birth to highly concentrated
industrial enterprises under the domination of foreign finance capital and an equally
concentrated proletariat armed with the latest ideas, organisations and methods of
struggle.
These sharp unevennesses in the social structure of tsarist Russia set the stage
for the revolutionary events which started with the overthrow of a decayed medieval
structure in 1917 and concluded in a few months with placing the proletariat and the
Bolshevik Party in power. It is only by analysing and understanding them that it is
possible to grasp why the Russian Revolution took place as it did.
IRREGULARITIES IN SOCIETY
The pronounced irregularities to be found in history have led some thinkers to
deny that there is, or can be, any causality or lawfulness in social development. The
most fashionable school of American anthropologists, headed by the late Franz Boas,
explicitly denied that there were any determinate sequence of stages to be discovered
in social evolution or that the expressions of culture are shaped by technology or
economy. According to R.H. Lowie, the foremost exponent of this viewpoint, cultural
phenomena present merely a “planless hodgepodge”, a “chaotic jumble”. The “chaotic
jumble” is all in the heads of these anti-materialists and anti-evolutionists, not in the
history or the constitution of society.
It is possible for people living under Stone Age conditions in the 20th century to
possess a radio though not to manufacture one. But it would be categorically
impossible to find such a product of contemporary electronics buried with human
remains in a Stone Age deposit of 20,000 years ago.
It does not take much penetration to see that the activities of food-gathering,
foraging, hunting, fishing and fowling existed long before food production in the
forms of gardening or stockbreeding. Or that stone tools preceded metal ones; speech
came before writing; cave-dwellings before house-building; camps before villages;
the exchange of goods before money. On a general historical scale, these sequences
are absolutely inviolable.
The main characteristics of the simple social structures of savages are determined
by their primitive methods of producing the means of life which, in turn, depend upon
the low level of their productive forces. It is estimated that food-gathering peoples
require from four to 40 square miles per capita to maintain themselves. They could
neither produce nor maintain large concentrations of population on such an economic
86 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
foundation. The groups usually numbered less than 40 persons and seldom exceeded
100. The inescapable smallness of their food supply and dispersion of their forces set
strict limits to their development.
own peculiar way and to a different degree in the expression and the expansion of
capitalism and played different roles at different stages of its development.
Capitalism rose to greater heights in Europe and North America than in Asia and
Africa. These were interdependent phenomena, opposing sides of a single process.
The capitalist underdevelopment in the colonies was a product and condition of the
overdevelopment of the metropolitan areas at their expense.
The participation of various nations in the evolution of capitalism has been no
less irregular. Holland and England took the lead in establishing capitalist forms and
forces in the 16th and 17th centuries while North America was still largely possessed
by the Indians. Yet in the final stage of capitalism in the 20th century the United States
has far outdistanced England and Holland.
As capitalism absorbed one country after another into its orbit, it increased their
dependence upon one another. But this growing interdependence did not mean that
they followed identical paths or possessed the same characteristics. As they drew
closer together economically, profound differences asserted themselves and separated
them. Their national development in many respects did not proceed along parallel
lines but at angles to each other, and sometimes even at right angles. They acquired
not identical but complementary traits.
NATIONAL PECULIARITIES
I should like to close this examination of the processes of uneven development
with a discussion of the problem of national peculiarities. Marxists are often accused
by their opponents of denying, ignoring or underestimating national peculiarities in
favour of universal historical laws. There is no truth to this criticism, although individual
Marxists are sometimes guilty of such errors.
Marxists deny neither the existence nor the importance of national peculiarities. It
would be theoretically stupid and practically reckless for them to do so, since national
differences may be decisive in shaping the policy of the labour movement, of a minority
struggle, or of a revolutionary party in a given country for a certain period. For
example, most politically active workers in Britain follow the Labour Party. This
monopoly is a prime peculiarity of Great Britain and the political development of its
working people today. Marxists who failed to take this factor into account as the
keystone of their organisational orientation would violate the spirit of their method.
Far from being indifferent to national differences, Marxism is the only historical
method and sociological theory which adequately explains them, demonstrating how
they are rooted in the material conditions of life and viewing them in their historical
origins, development, disintegration and disappearance. The schools of bourgeois
thought look upon national peculiarities in a different way, as inexplicable accidents,
god-given birthrights, or fixed and final features of a particular people. Marxism regards
them as historical products arising out of concrete combinations of worldwide forces
90 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
regimes, both arrived at the same destination. They remained subordinate to the same
fundamental laws of capitalist imperialism and could not abolish their operation or
avoid their consequences.
In the second place, national peculiarities have definite historical limits. They are
not eternally fixed and absolutely final. Historical conditions generate and sustain
them; new historical conditions can alter and eliminate them, even transform them into
their opposites.
In the 19th century, Russia was the most reactionary country in Europe and in
world politics; in the 20th century it became the most revolutionary. In the middle of
the 19th century the United States was the most revolutionary and progressive nation;
in the middle of the 20th century it has taken Russia’s place as the fortress of world
counterrevolution. But this role, too, will not be everlasting, as will be indicated in the
next section where we shall deal with the character and consequences of combined
development.
92 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
We must now examine the second aspect of the law of uneven and combined
development. This law bears in its name indications of the more general law of which
it is a special expression, viz., the law of dialectical logic called the law of interpenetration
of opposites. The two processes — unevenness and combination — which are united
in this formulation, themselves represent two different and opposing, yet integrally
connected and interpenetrating aspects or stages of reality.
The law of combined development starts from the recognition of unevenness of
the rates of development of various phenomena of historical change. The disparities
in technical and social development and the fortuitous combination of elements,
tendencies and movements belonging to different stages of social organisation provide
the basis for the emergence of something of a new and higher quality.
This law enables us to observe how the new qualities arise. If society did not
develop in a differential way, that is, through the emergence of differences which are
sometimes so acute as to be contradictory to each other, the possibility for combination
and integration of contradictory phenomena would not present itself. Therefore, the
first phase of the evolutionary process — i.e. unevenness — is the indispensable
precondition for the second phase — the combination of features belonging to
different stages of social life into distinctive social formations, deviating from abstractly
deduced standards or “normal” types.
Since combination comes about as the necessary outcome of pre-existent
unevenness, we can see why both are always found together and coupled in the
single law of combined and uneven development. Starting with the fact of disparate
levels of development which result from the uneven progression of the various aspects
of society, we will now analyse the next stage and necessary consequence of this
state of affairs — their coming together.
Uneven and Combined Development in History 93
socialist historian, wrote: “The course of evolution pursued in each colony bears a
striking resemblance to the line of development that the race has followed” (pp. 30-
31). In the beginning, he points out, there was primitive communism. Then came small
individual production and so right through to capitalism.
However, the conception that the American colonies, or any one of them,
substantially repeated the sequence of stages through which advanced societies had
travelled before them, is entirely too schematic and misses the main point about their
development and structure. The most significant peculiarity in the evolution of the
British colonies in America came from the fact that all the organisational forms and
driving forces belonging to earlier stages of social development, from savagery to
feudalism, were incorporated into, conditioned by, and in the case of chattel slavery,
even produced by the expanding system of international capitalism.
There was no mechanical serial reproduction on American soil of outmoded
historical stages. Instead, colonial life witnessed a dialectical admixture of all these
varied elements, which resulted in the emergence of combined social formations of
new and special types. The chattel slavery of the American colonies was very different
from the chattel slavery of classical Greece and Rome. American slavery was a
bourgeoisified slavery which was not only a subordinate branch of the capitalist
world market but became impregnated with capitalist features. One of the most freakish
offshoots of this fusion of slavery and capitalism was the appearance of commercial
slaveholders among the Creek Indians in the South. Could anything be more anomalous
and self-contradictory than communistic Indians, now slaveholders, selling their
products in a bourgeois market?
seen when we compare modern China and the United States of America. Today many
Chinese peasants in tiny hamlets have pictures of Marx and Lenin on their walls and
are inspired by their ideas. The average American worker, living in the most modern
cities, has, by contrast, paintings of Christ or photographs of the president on his
prefabricated walls. However, the Chinese peasants have no running water, paved
roads, cars or television sets which the American workers have.
Thus, although the United States and its working class in its basic industrial
development and its living and cultural standards have progressed far beyond China,
in certain respects the Chinese peasant has outstripped the American worker. “The
historical dialectic knows neither naked backwardness nor chemically pure
progressiveness”, as Trotsky put it.
cities on a capitalist basis. They did all this at an accelerated rate. It took the European
peoples 3000 years to climb from the upper barbarism of Homeric Greece to the England
of the triumphant bourgeois English revolution of 1649. North America covered this
same transformation in 300 years. This was a tenfold speed-up in the rate of
development. It was, however, only made possible by the fact that America was able
to profit from the previous achievements of Europe combined with the impetuous
expansion of the capitalist market to all quarters of the globe.
Alongside of this acceleration and compression of social development came an
acceleration of the tempo of revolutionary events. The British people took eight
centuries to progress from the beginnings of feudalism in the ninth century to their
victorious bourgeois revolution in the 17th century. The North American colonists
took only one and three quarter centuries to pass from their first settlements in the
17th century to their victorious revolution in the last quarter of the 18th century.
In these historical leaps, stages of development are sometimes compressed and
sometimes omitted altogether, depending upon the particular conditions and forces.
In the North American colonies, for example, feudalism, which flowered in Europe and
Asia over many centuries, hardly obtained a foothold. Feudalism’s characteristic
institutions — landed estates, serfs, the monarchy, the established church and the
medieval guilds — could find no suitable environment and were squeezed out between
commercial chattel slavery on the one hand and the budding bourgeois society on the
other. Paradoxically, at the very time that feudalism was being stunted and strangled
in the North American colonies, it was undergoing vigorous expansion on the other
side of the world in Russia.
On the other hand, slavery in the Southern colonies of North America sank deep
roots, enjoyed such an extensive growth and proved so tough and durable that it
required a separate revolution to eradicate it. There are, indeed, still, to this day,
significant anachronistic survivals in the South of chattel slavery.
HISTORICAL REVERSIONS
History has its reversions as well as its forward marches; its periods of reaction no
less than its periods of revolution. Under conditions of reaction, infantile forms and
obsolete features appropriate to bygone ages and periods of development can be
fused with advanced structures to generate extremely retrogressive formations and
hinder social advance. A prime example of such a regressive combination was chattel
slavery in America, where an obsolete mode of property and form of production
belonging to the infancy of class society sprang up in a bourgeois environment
belonging to the maturity of class society.
Uneven and Combined Development in History 99
Recent political history has made us familiar with the examples of fascism and
Stalinism, which are symmetrical, but by no means identical, historical phenomena of
the 20th century. Both represented reversions from pre-existing democratic forms of
government which had entirely different social foundations. Fascism was the destroyer
and supplanter of bourgeois democracy in the final period of imperialist domination
and decay. Stalinism was the destroyer and supplanter of the workers’ democracy of
revolutionary Russia in the initial period of the international socialist revolution.
Thus far we have singled out two stages in the dialectical movement of society.
First, some parts of mankind, and certain elements of society, move ahead faster and
develop farther than others. Later, under the shock of external forces, laggards are
prodded along, catching up with and even outstripping their forerunners on the path
of progress by combining the latest innovations with their old modes of existence.
Under certain historical conditions the introduction of new things can, for a time,
even lengthen the life of the most archaic institutions. The entrance of the great
capitalist oil concerns into the Middle East has temporarily strengthened the sheikdoms
by showering wealth upon them. But in the long run the invasion of up-to-date
techniques and ideas cannot help but undermine the old tribal regimes because they
break up the conditions upon which the old regimes rest and create new forces to
oppose and replace them.
A primitive power can fasten itself upon a higher one, gain renewed vitality, and
even appear for a time superior to its host. But the less developed power leads an
essentially parasitic existence and cannot indefinitely sustain itself at the expense of
the higher. It lacks suitable soil and atmosphere for its growth while the more developed
institutions are not only inherently superior but can count upon a favourable
environment for expansion.
bourgeoisie of the North during the American Civil War. This failure of the bourgeoisie
has ever since been a great source of embarrassment and difficulty for its
representatives. The question now posed is whether the present ultra-reactionary
capitalist rulers of the USA can now carry through to fulfilment a national task which
it failed to complete in its revolutionary heyday.
The spokesmen for the Democrats and Republicans find it necessary to say that
they can in fact do this job; the reformists of all kinds claim that the bourgeois
government can be made to do it. It is our opinion, however, that only the joint
struggle of the Negro people and the working masses against the capitalist rulers will
be able to carry through the struggle against the hangovers of slavery to its victorious
conclusion. In this way, the socialist revolution will complete what the bourgeois-
democratic revolution failed to realise.
subsequent stage or in an affiliated field. And what is backward can become the basis
for a forward leap.
It seems presumptuous to tell those peoples who are oppressed by backwardness
and are yearning to cast it off, that their archaic state has any advantages. To them
backwardness appears as an unmixed evil. But the consciousness of this “evil” emerges
in the first place only after these peoples have come into contact with superior forms
of social development. It is the contact of the two forms, backward and advanced,
which exposes the deficiencies of the backward culture. So long as civilisation is
unknown, the primitive savage remains content. It is only the juxtaposition of the two
that introduces the vision of something better and feeds the yeast of dissatisfaction.
In this way the presence and knowledge of a superior state becomes a motor force of
progress.
The resulting criticism and condemnation of the old state of affairs generate the
urge to overcome the disparity in development and drive laggards forward by arousing
in them the desire to draw abreast of the more advanced. Every individual who has
become involved in the learning process has felt this personally.
When new and imperative demands are made upon backward peoples, the absence
of accumulated, intermediate institutions can be of positive value, because then fewer
obstacles are present to obstruct the advance and the assimilation of what is new. If
the social forces exist and exert themselves effectively, intelligently and in time, what
had been a penalty can be turned to advantage.
easier for this energetic young class, which had so little to unlearn and so much to
learn so quickly, to adopt the most advanced theory, the boldest and clearest program
of action and the highest type of party organisation. The peasant revolt against
medievalism, a movement which in Western Europe had been characteristic of the
dawn of the bourgeois democratic revolutions, intermeshed with the proletarian
revolution against capitalism, which belonged to the 20th century. As Trotsky explained
in The History of the Russian Revolution, it was the conjunction of these two different
revolutions which gave an expansive power to the upheaval of the Russian people
and accounted for the extraordinary sweep and momentum of its achievements.
But the privileges of backwardness are not inexhaustible; they are limited by
historical and material conditions. Accordingly, in the next stage of its development,
the backwardness inherited from the Russia of the tsars reasserted itself under new
historical conditions and on an entirely new social basis. The previous privileges had
to be paid for in the next decades by the bitter suffering, the economic privations and
the loss of liberties which the Russian people endured under the Stalinist dictatorship.
The very backwardness which had previously strengthened the revolution and which
had propelled the Russian masses far ahead of the rest of the world, now became the
starting point of the political reaction and bureaucratic counterrevolution, a
consequence of the fact that the international revolution failed to conquer in the
industrially more advanced countries. The economic and cultural backwardness of
Russia, combined with the retarded development of the international revolution, were
the basic conditions which enabled the Stalinist clique to choke the Bolshevik Party
and permitted the bureaucracy to usurp political power.
For these reasons, the Stalinist regime became the most self-contradictory in
modern history, a coagulation of the most advanced property forms and social
conquests emanating from the revolution with a resurrection of the most repulsive
features of class rule. Giant factories with the most up-to-date machinery were operated
by workers who, serf-like, were not permitted to leave their places of employment;
airplanes sped above impassable dirt tracks; planned economy functioned side by
side with “slave labour” camps; tremendous industrial advances went hand in hand
with political retrogression; the prodigious growth of Russia as a world power was
accompanied by an inner decay of the regime.
However, the dialectical development of the Russian Revolution did not stop at
this point. The extension of the revolution to Eastern Europe and Asia after the
Second World War, the expansion of Soviet industry, and the rise in the numbers and
cultural level of the Soviet workers, prepared conditions for a modified reversal of the
old trends, the revival of the revolution on a higher stage, and the undermining and
Uneven and Combined Development in History 105
partial overcoming of the scourge of Stalinism. The first manifestations of this forward
movement of the masses in Russia and in its satellites, with the working class in the
lead, have already been announced to the world.
From the Khrushchev speech to the Hungarian Revolution there has been a
continuous series of events demonstrating the dialectics of revolutionary development.
At every stage of the Russian Revolution since 1905, we can see the interaction of its
backwardness and progressiveness with their conversion one into the other according
to the concrete circumstances of national and international development. Only an
understanding of the dialectics of these changes can provide an accurate picture of
the extremely complex and contradictory development of the USSR throughout the 40
years of its existence. The dozens of oversimplified characterisations of the nature of
modern Russian society, which serve only to confuse the revolutionary movement,
derive directly from a lack of understanding of the laws of dialectics and the use of
metaphysical methods in analysing historical processes.
The law of uneven and combined development is an indispensable tool for
analysing the Russian Revolution and for charting its growth and decay through all
its complex phases, its triumphs, its degeneration and its prospective regeneration as
the process of de-Stalinisation is carried through to the end by the Soviet people.
106 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
3. DISPROPORTIONS OF AMERICAN
DEVELOPMENT
The previous section showed how the law of uneven and combined development
enables the Marxist to unravel the twisted course of the Russian Revolution. Every
socialist today recognises the supreme importance of arriving at a satisfactory
explanation of the degeneration of the Soviet Union and so of reliably estimating the
significance of the conflict between the progressive character of nationalised property
in the USSR and the reactionary bureaucracy which rules that country. Equal in
importance to the Russian question for the international socialist movement is an
understanding of the dialectics of the development of the socialist movement in the
United States of America, the most highly developed and most powerful capitalist
country in the world. How, in essence, has the law of uneven and combined development
shown itself in the principal stages in the history of the USA? How does an
understanding of this law help us to forecast the possible future course of the class
struggle in America?
been worked out in England and brought over by the colonists. To justify their demands,
the colonists found ready-made theories of natural law in the writings of ideologists
of the English revolution of the 17th century like Milton, Harrington and John Locke.
In addition the colonists created a new technique of warfare, uniting their experiences
of hunting in the wilds of the North American plains and mountains with the
potentialities of the musket. These new tactical methods were important in helping the
colonists to defeat the British Redcoats of George III. As a result of its victory America
not only caught up with the Old World but, politically, surpassed it. This was the first
victorious colonial revolution of modern times and it established what was then the
most progressive democracy in the world.
However the American revolution of the 18th century, like the Russian revolution
of the 20th century, could not draw upon unlimited resources. The political
progressiveness of the Yankee republic became combined with economic
backwardness. For example, the War of Independence did not, and could not, uproot
slavery or curb the power of the slaveowners. The backwardness of the USA in this
decisive sphere took its revenge upon the Americans of the 19th century.
The American people had for some time to endure the rule of the Southern
slaveowners, who later became so reactionary and insolent that they not only
prevented further progress of the country but even endangered the democracy and
unity achieved by the first revolution. Fortunately a new combination of social forces
had been created in the meantime, and this new combined formation proved strong
enough to meet and overthrow the slaveholders’ counterrevolution.
Historically considered, this second American revolution — i.e., the Civil War —
represented, on the one hand, the price paid by the American nation for the economic
backwardness which it had inherited from its colonial youth. On the other hand, the
impetus provided by the Yankee victory in the Civil War jet-propelled the USA once
again into becoming the leading nation of the world. After all the precapitalist forces
and formations, from the barbarism of the Red Indian tribes to the slavery of the
Southern states, had been disposed of, American capitalism was able to leap forward
with mighty strides, so making the USA today the model and most advanced capitalist
nation and the paramount world power.
However, this dominant position was not achieved all at once but in two
revolutionary leaps separated by an interval of gradual progress and political reaction.
most advanced and American industry and agriculture the most productive in the
world. This not only enriches the capitalist monopolists but showers many benefits
upon the American people — ranging from an abundance and wide variety of foodstuffs
to a plethora of television sets, refrigerators, motorcars and other “luxuries”. This is
one side of the picture. On the other side, the American monopolists are the most
efficient of all the capitalists in the world in exploiting both their own working people
and the rest of the toilers of the world. While the American worker enjoys the highest
standard of living of any worker in the world, he is also the most heavily exploited.
This tremendously productive working class gets back for its own consumption a
smaller part of its output and hands over in the form of profit to the capitalist owners
of the instruments of production a greater part of its output than does either the
English or the French working class.
The greatest unevenness of America’s social development is this: its economy is
so advanced that it is fully ripe for collective ownership and planned production (that
is, it is ripe for socialism) and yet this economy remains encased in a straitjacket of
capitalist and nationalist restrictions. This contradiction is the main source of the
social insecurity of our age and of the main social evil of our time, not only in the USA
but also throughout the whole world.
The high productivity of the American economy, along with the privileges of the
dominating position of American capitalism in world economy, is primarily responsible
for another phenomenon of American life, and one which always impresses foreign
observers — the extraordinary backwardness of American politics in general and the
backwardness of the political ideology of organised labour in particular. In this field,
it may be said, a colonial cottage is standing upon foundations suitable for skyscrapers.
The workers and even the farmers of Britain, or even for that matter the peasants of
China, are today influenced and, to some extent, guided by socialist ideas while the
working people of America remain captive to the crudest bourgeois ideas and
organisations.
This is the second outstanding feature of unevenness in the social structure of
the USA. The political life of America lags far behind that of most of the rest of the
world and even further behind the economic and social development of the country
itself. This lag is, ironically enough, part of the price America is paying for the successes
of its two previous revolutions and for its resulting outstanding achievements in
industry and agriculture. The third American revolution, the socialist revolution, is
being retarded precisely because its forerunners accomplished so much.
Unevenness also prevails in other sections of the American social consciousness.
The ideology of the American ruling class is one of the most highly developed in
Uneven and Combined Development in History 109
capitalist history. This ruling class not only has a militant, positive philosophy to
justify its privileges, a philosophy which it assiduously disseminates inside the USA
and internationally, but also it is simultaneously engaged in an unceasing offensive
against the ideas of communism and socialism, even though Marxist ideas have spread
amongst the people of America to the most limited degree. This anti-communist, anti-
socialist crusading zeal, together with its acute class sensitivity and consciousness
of the class struggle, expresses the American ruling class’s forebodings about its
own future. But in contrast to this class consciousness of the capitalists the American
working class has not yet reached the level of generalising its own particular class
interests even in the form of the most elementary social-reformist notions. This
indifference to socialist ideology is one of the most pronounced peculiarities of the
American worker. This is not to say that the American worker is devoid of class
feeling and initiative. On the contrary, he has asserted himself time and time again as
an independent fighting force, especially in the industrial field — often with brilliant
results. But these experiences have not led to the establishment of a conscious and
permanent challenge to the capitalist order, i.e., to a mass socialist movement.
The hyper-development in America of bourgeois ideology and the corresponding
underdevelopment of working-class consciousness are the inseparable products of
the same historical conditions. They are interdependent aspects of the present stage
of social and political development in the USA.
Today the political complexion of the whole world reflects the major unevennesses
of American society — one in the domain of production, another in political
organisation and a third in social consciousness. The gap between the economy’s
ripeness for socialisation and its capitalist-monopolist ownership and administration,
and the gap between the high level of labour’s trade union organisation and its
political and ideological immaturity, are the most striking peculiarities of American life.
This situation sets the most difficult theoretical and practical problems to all socialists,
especially to those who have to operate in such an environment. To the whole world
of labour these gaps in American social life sometimes look like bottomless pits into
which the peoples of the whole world must be dragged to their nuclear destruction.
Sometimes it seems impossible to imagine that forces could ever come into existence
to fill up or bridge the abyss.
and the forms of ownership, between the present weakness and the potential power
of the American working class, remain as they are today? The capitalists, the reformists,
the liberals, the pragmatists and pseudo-Marxists of all kinds not only think they will
but try also to induce everyone else to share their convictions.
But all these people reckon without the movement of world history, a movement
which has been considerably speeded up in our time. They reckon without the
contradictions of the capitalist system on a world scale. These contradictions will, in
time, generate new and more devastating crises. They reckon without the development
of the class conflicts in our own time and above all they underestimate the creative
capacities of the American working class. Again, not being Marxists, they leave out
of their calculations the operation and effects of the law of uneven and combined
development.
Let us see how the law of uneven and combined development can help us to
penetrate below the surface and to expose the kernel of present realities. As we have
seen, this is certainly not the first time in the history of America, nor is America the
only place in the world in the 20th century, where economic relations, political structures
and social ideas have lagged far behind the development of the forces of production.
The undeniable facts of history are that, in the past, the only way in which similar
disparities have been resolved, and unevenness eliminated, has been through
revolutionary upheavals whose function, on each occasion, has been to place new
progressive forces at the head of the nation. In our time only the working class can
perform once more this historically necessary function. There is no adequate reason
for believing that, whatever else intervenes, the extreme contradictions in American
life can be resolved in any other way.
At this point an astute critic may object: “According to the law of uneven and
combined development, and this exposition of it, events do not necessarily reproduce
themselves in the same way even within the same social system, but, under a different
set of circumstances, the course of events may take a different line of development.
Why then does the USA have to follow the same revolutionary path in the 20th
century as it did in the 18th and 19th centuries? Why must the USA necessarily follow
the course taken by the backward countries like Russia and China in our own time? Is
it not possible for America to make a detour around the socialist revolution and by
easy and gradual stages arrive at a higher form of social organisation and a better
life?”
Now it is certainly true that no historical precedent, however superficially apposite,
can properly replace the direct analysis of the real concrete situation; precedents can
only guide and supplement the specific investigation. Of course, it would be more
Uneven and Combined Development in History 111
advantageous for the peoples of the whole world if the transition from capitalism to
socialism in America (or, indeed, in Britain or anywhere else) could be effected by
mutual agreement between the classes. Marxists have never denied this nor desired
otherwise. But this pious wish, unfortunately, does not dispose of the problem. The
question then arises: is this ideal and desirable prospect a realistic one? Should it be
made the basis for practical socialist politics in Britain or in the USA? This same
question has once more been raised in the British and American Communist Parties in
the “great debate” which has followed the 20th Congress of the Soviet Communist
Party.
The “peaceful” road of development to socialism in America presupposes that
American capitalism can proceed without further devastating economic convulsions,
social crises and world wars, and that if these do occur the rulers, discredited by these
catastrophes, would step aside and voluntarily relinquish their power, property and
privileges, in answer to the demands (and perhaps votes) of an aroused people.
Can it be realistically expected that the most profound social conflict in all history,
the conflict which involves the final abolition of exploitation of man by man, will, in
the advanced capitalist countries of “Western democracy”, be resolved through
diplomatic negotiations between the classes backed up by peaceful forms of mass
pressure and by the counting of votes? Incidentally, there are no precedents for such
“revolutions” in British, French, German or American history. It can, however, be
easily shown that the most powerful reasons exist indicating why the capitalist
monopolists of today, in the USA and elsewhere, are even less likely to relinquish
voluntarily their ruling position, to act against their basic material interests and to
commit “social suicide” than were the courts of Charles I, George III and Louis XVI,
the slaveholders of the Southern states of the USA and, for that matter, the court of
Tsar Nicholas II, in their day.
The powerful financial and industrial magnates who rule America today have long
been accustomed not only to rule but to believe in the rightness and eternity of their
rule. Moreover they realise that they would not merely be relinquishing their own
supremacy but also that of capitalism on a world scale. For should the American
workers assume state power, this would not be just a minor shift of power within a
single social system. It would represent the decisive act in the most fundamental and
far-reaching of all the transformations of society. Nothing less would be involved
than the worldwide historical coup de grace of capitalism and the passing of decisive
sections of mankind to a higher social system, to socialism. Fundamentally the fate of
two world historical systems, capitalism and socialism, are at issue in the struggle
between the American capitalists and the American working class. The recognition of
112 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
this key position of the American working class is of fundamental importance for the
socialist movement in every country of the world.
With so much at stake, the reflex action of the American capitalists to the threat of
displacement by the working class would most likely be, as McCarthyism indicated, a
sharp turn towards military dictatorship or fascism. In any event, it would be unrealistic
and irresponsible for a serious Marxist to count only upon the most favourable line of
development and to ignore the probability that, instead of facilitating the transition to
socialism, the representatives of capitalism will try to throw up new barriers against
socialist advance and to fight to retain their sovereignty, however illegal and
“undemocratic” their resistance might be.
However, if this last stronghold of world capitalism, the USA, is the least likely of
all countries to escape the necessity for revolutionary struggle on its road to socialism,
this certainly does not mean that the pattern of this struggle will duplicate precisely
the path taken in other countries, say, for example, Russia. It is an elementary
proposition of Marxism, which to suit their own temporary aims the Stalinists are now
busy “rediscovering”, that the revolutionary class in each country will proceed in its
own peculiar way in achieving state power and in building socialism.
After decades of the most discouraging and demoralising delay, the American
workers obtained their industrial organisation in one mighty leap during the thirties
through the CIO. They compressed several stages of development in this leap. The
American auto workers did not proceed through craft unionism to industrial unionism,
but went at one bound from a state of non-organisation to the highest form of industrial
organisation, skipping the intervening craft stage which industrial workers in Britain
found it necessary to pass through.
How are the American working masses likely to respond to radical changes in
their economic and political conditions? Can they be expected to follow in the footsteps
of the British workers? A Marxist, dialectical thinker can only answer this question
thus — yes and no. The American worker will follow the British worker but only in the
most general way. He will certainly find it imperative to cut loose from the capitalist
parties and to create an independent class outlook and organisation, just as the
workers of Britain have done. But the specific forms, the special features and the rate
of political development of the American workers not only need not, but most certainly
will not, simply duplicate the features of British development, because the world
historical conditions under which they will set up their class political party will be
vastly different from those under which the British Labour Party was created.
When the British working class launched itself into independent politics at the
turn of the century world capitalism was still ascending and no country had yet
overthrown capitalist rule. Today capitalism on a world scale is on the defensive,
while the anticapitalist powers and the socialist and colonial movements have become
a mighty reality.
Nor is the America of today, internally, anything like the Britain of the first half of
the 20th century. Today America is the last stronghold of capitalism and, unlike the
British capitalists of Edwardian days, the US capitalists have little room for strategic
retreat. These differences will ensure that there will be great differences between the
British Labour Party and the American Party of Labour which still remains to be
created. Accordingly, the American working class will enter this new chapter of
American political events in a mood very different from that of their British predecessors
In the USA it will take a very acute crisis to jerk labour loose from the old moorings,
rather than the sort of chronic long-drawn-out crisis which was the case in Britain.
The impact of these social shocks will run up against the stunted political development
of the US working class at a time when capitalism is on the defensive and the
anticapitalist forces on the offensive in the rest of the world. The offensive of the
working class will not only collide with intensified resistance from the capitalists, but
also with the inertia and short-sightedness of the trade union bureaucracies — as it
has already done in Britain. But the American reactionary trade union bureaucracies
will also have to operate under far different conditions from those which obtain in
Britain. The critical situation will, on the one hand, dictate the most radical measures.
On the other hand, the bureaucrats will be challenged for the leadership of the militant
workers by a strong and solid revolutionary socialist grouping.
114 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
‘EXPLOSIVE EXPANSION’
Such a combination of a strongly organised, highly cultured and newly radicalised
working class with a leadership equipped with the most advanced theory and farseeing
policies, as is in the process of gestation in the USA today, will have extraordinary
explosive power.
At such a juncture in world history, the penalties of backwardness from which the
American socialist movement now suffers will be certain to show their other, more
hopeful side. The American workers will be receptive to the boldest revolutionary
prospects and will be prepared to assimilate them readily and to act upon them.
New species, it was noted earlier, have experienced “explosive expansion” when
they have broken into virgin territories under favourable conditions. An analogous
acceleration in development can be expected when the American workers enter the
field of independent class political action and take possession of the ideas of scientific
socialism and the methods of Marxism. In such days of grave social crisis this
amalgamation of a previously politically backward but potentially powerful working
class with the science of society and of political action, i.e., with Marxism, can effect
the greatest leap forward any society has yet achieved — greater than any leap
forward in American history — and, by this single act, raise the whole of humanity by
a head.
4. APPENDIX: HOW TO APPLY A LAW OF
SOCIOLOGY
be cleared up, then other fruitful controversial problems can be raised later.
C.S.
I do not clearly see why C.S. hesitates to accord the law of uneven and combined
development the status of a law. Lawfulness is derived from ascertaining materially
conditioned, necessary connections among phenomena. Laws formulate such
necessary relations among the factors in a certain sector of reality in a generalised
way. In natural science, for example, the early physicists Boyle, Charles, Gay-Lussac
and Avagadro established simple relationships connecting the volume, temperature
and pressure of gases which they formulated in elementary empirical laws.
Since different aspects of reality have their own laws, different laws do not operate
on the same level of generality nor do they have the same degree of necessity. The
broadest laws are formulated in the materialist dialectic of being and becoming, which
embraces universal processes and modes of development. The law of the
interpenetration of opposites belongs in this class. On the other hand there are
particular laws which apply only within the limits of specific social-economic formations
— as, for instance, the law of the growing concentration of capital which pertains
exclusively to the capitalist system.
The law of uneven and combined development stands midway between these two
types in its scope of operation. It belongs not to philosophy or to political economy
but primarily to the science of sociology which seeks to discover the general laws of
human evolution. It formulates certain important aspects of the historical tendencies
of social development. It is more concrete than the law of the interpenetration of
opposites, of which it is a specific expression, and less limited than the law of the
concentration of capital.
RUSSIAN DEVELOPMENT
Consider in this light the evolution of the Soviet Union since 1917, as Trotsky
explained it in The Revolution Betrayed with the aid of the law of uneven and combined
development. Trotsky pointed out how, in the first place, “the law of uneven
development brought it about that the contradiction between the technique and
Uneven and Combined Development in History 119
property relations of capitalism (a universal feature in its death agony) shattered the
weakest link in the world chain.”5 The Russian Revolution was, as he stated elsewhere,
a national avalanche in a universal social formation. “Backward Russian capitalism
was the first to pay for the bankruptcy of world capitalism.”
Trotsky then observes that in general “the law of uneven development is
supplemented throughout the whole course of history by the law of combined
development”.6
What was its specific result in Russia? “The collapse of the bourgeoisie in Russia
led to the proletarian dictatorship — that is, to a backward country’s leaping ahead of
the advanced countries.” As we know, this caused a lot of grief to the schematic
theorists in Russia and Western Europe who insisted that the workers could not and
should not take power until capitalism had elevated the national economy to an
advanced height.
But it also brought much genuine grief to the Russian people, as Trotsky goes
onto explain. “However, the establishment of socialist forms of property in a backward
country came up against the inadequate level of technique and culture.” That is, new
types of unevenness emerged on the basis of the preceding achievements and on a
higher historical level. “Itself born of the contradictions between high world productive
forces and capitalist form of property, the October Revolution produced in its turn a
contradiction between low national productive forces and socialist forms of property.”
While the achievements of the revolution — the nationalised property and planned
economy — exercised a highly progressive action upon the Soviet Union, they were
themselves subjected to the degrading influence of the low level of production in the
isolated workers’ state. From this fundamental condition flowed all the degenerative
effects witnessed in the Soviet state under the Stalinist regime, including that regime
itself. The most advanced ideas and progressive productive relations could not prevail
against the inadequacy of their economic substructure and suffered debasement as a
result.
Thus unevenness prevents any simple, single straight line of direction in social
development, and what we have instead is a complex, devious and contradictory
route. The theoretical task is to analyse the dialectical interplay of action and reaction
of the contending forces in their connection with the historical environment.
In this now the progressive tendencies and now the reactionary counterforces
assert themselves and come to the fore.
120 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
both countries. In Japan, the imperialist regime — product of the highest stage of
world and national evolution — was headed by an Emperor cult carried over from pre-
feudal times. Its capitalist structure bulged with bizarre combinations and extreme
disproportions. Modern factories and workshops sprang up in the cities while feudal
relations in the countryside remained unaltered. Light industry was overdeveloped,
while the heavy industry from which contemporary mastery is derived remained
underdeveloped. The military, equipped with the latest weapons, remained animated
by feudal traditions. Because of its reformation from above instead of revolutionisation
from below, democracy was feeble and parliamentary life flimsy. This incomplete
modernisation of Japan’s social structure culminated in a supreme disproportion: the
imperialist program imposed upon that latecomer by the needs of national capitalist
expansion and world competition were beyond the capacities of its forces and
resources. The result was the debacle suffered by Japanese militarism in the Second
World War.
chemistry will illustrate. A beach is defined both by water and by land. Each of these
opposing physical entities are essential components of its makeup. Take away one or
the other and the beach no longer exists.
But transitional formations are distinguished from ordinary things by the
heightened character of their dual constitution. They belong to a special kind of
processes, events and forms in nature, society, and individual experience which have
exceptionally pronounced, almost outrageously, contradictory traits. They carry the
coexistence of opposites in a single whole to the most extreme and anomalous lengths.
These phenomena are so self-contradictory that they can embody the passage
from one stage or form of existence to another. Since the major features of transitional
formations belong to consecutive but qualitatively different stages of development,
they must represent a combination of the old and the new.
In the life process, the first products of development are necessarily inadequately
realised on their own terms. What is new makes its first appearance in and through
underdeveloped forms and asserts its emerging existence within the shell of the old.
The new becoming is struggling to go beyond its previous mode of existence. It is
passing over from one stage to the next but is not yet mature, powerful or predominant
enough to destroy and throw off the afterbirth of its natal state and stand fully and
firmly on its own feet. Like a foetus, it is still dependent on the conditions of its birth
or, like an infant, dependent on its parents.
In a full and normal development, transitional formations go through three phases.
1. A prenatal or embryonic stage when the functions, structures and features of the
nascent entity are growing and stirring within the framework of the already established
form. 2. The qualitative breakthrough of its birth period, when the aggregate of the
novel powers and features succeeds in shattering the old form and stepping forth on
its own account. At this point the fresh creation continues to retain many residues
belonging to its preceding state. 3. The period of maturation when the vestigial
characteristics unsuited to its proper mode of existence are largely sloughed off and
the new entity is unmistakably, firmly, strongly developing on its distinctive
foundations.
It takes time for the unique features and functions of something novel to manifest
their potential, engender the most appropriate type of expression, and become stabilised
in normal or perfected shape. At the beginning of their career they are trammeled,
often even disfigured, by the heritage of the past.
These borderline phenomena are so significant — and puzzling — because they
form the bridge between successive stages of evolution. Their hybrid nature,
embodying characteristics belonging to antithetical phases of growth, casts light
126 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
upon both the old and the new, the past and the future. Through them it is possible to
see how and where the carapace of the old is being broken through by antagonistic
forces striving to establish the groundwork, the basic conditions, for higher forms of
existence.
Each turning point in the evolution of life has produced species with contradictory
features belonging to different sequential forms. These betoken their status as links
between two separate and successive species.
PROBLEMS OF CLASSIFICATION
The most momentous turning point in organic evolution was the changeover from
the ape to man. Here scientists have found once living fossils with opposite
characteristics. Structurally the South African Australopithecus is not altogether an
ape nor altogether a man; it is something in between. He habitually stood and walked
erect as ably as man and his brain volume comes close to that of man. The fact that
these beings used tools, and thereby engaged in labour activity to get their means of
existence, proves that they had crossed the boundary separating the ape from man
and had embarked on a new mode of existence, despite the heavy vestiges of the
primate past they bore with them.
Precisely because of their highly self-contradictory and unfinished traits,
transitional forms present exceedingly vexing problems of precise definition and
classification to scientists and scholars. They are the most enigmatic of phenomena.
It is often difficult, and sometimes impossible, to tell on which side of a frontier they
definitely belong.
The task is to discriminate the genuinely new from what is rooted in the preceding
conditions of existence and then to assay the relative weights of the conflicting traits
and tendencies of development incorporated in the specimen. Taxonomists among
biologists, botanists and physical anthropologists have engaged in prolonged, bitter
and sometimes inconclusive controversies over whether a given specimen properly
belongs to one category or another.
What settles the locus of classification? The mere possession of one or another
trait of a higher or lower type is not considered conclusive evidence. The question is
decided one way or the other by the totality of characteristics in relation to what went
before and what came out of it.
For example, the fossil remains of Archaeopteryx show many characteristics now
found only in reptiles or in bird embryos: reptilian tail, jaws with teeth, and clawed
wings. Yet it is a true bird. This superior classification is warranted by the presence of
feathers and the structure of the legs and wings which fitted it for flight. Archaeopteryx
The Problem of Transitional Formations 127
had broken through the confines of the reptile state to become the first incarnation of
a higher form of living creature.
The difficulties of classification arising from the contradictory characteristics of
transitional phenomena are well illustrated by the current controversy among
authorities on early man over the new fossil finds at Olduvai Gorge in Tanganyika.
(See Current Anthropology, October 1965.) This famous site has yielded evidences
of tool-using and tool-making hominoids at levels which are dated as far back as over
two million years ago — the oldest yet discovered.
The problem posed by the latest finds concerns a group of fossil remains named
Homo habilis. The International Code of Zoological Nomenclature (1961) insisted
on dividing the Hominidae into two genera: Australopithecus and Homo. It did not
permit any intergeneric or ambigeneric groups.
However, Homo habilis did not fit into either one of these counterposed categories.
It diverged from Australopithecus in its more humanised morphological pattern
(biological traits), but even more significantly because it had taken the decisive step
of making stone tools according to a regular and evolving pattern. While
Australopithecus used and modified tools and may even have improvised them for
immediate purposes, he did not fabricate implements according to a set pattern. On
the other hand, the biological and cultural traits of Homo habilis fell short of the
status of Homo.
The dilemma facing the classifiers was formulated as follows by Phillip V. Tobias,
professor of anatomy at the University of Witwatersrand: “… the habilis group was
in so many respects intermediate between Australopithecus and Homo. Were we to
regard it as the most advanced species of Australopithecus or the most primitive
species of Homo?” Neither of these solutions was satisfactory. ‘We had come face to
face with a fundamental weakness in classical taxonomic procedure: Our systems of
classification make inadequate allowance for intermediate or transitional forms.”
How was the issue resolved? Tobias and L.B.J. Leakey concluded that, on the
basis of the evidence regarding these hominid remains, it was necessary to recognise
a new species of early man which they designated as Homo habilis. This species of
hominid was younger and more advanced then Australopithecus yet older and less
matured than Homo.
The great significance of Homo habilis as a bridge between Australopithecus
and Homo is that it closes the last remaining gap in the sequence of Pleistocene
hominid phylogeny. The lineage of human evolution now comprises three distinct
stages: partially humanised (Australopithecus); markedly humanised (Homo habilis);
and fully humanised (Homo).
128 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
Professor Tobias concludes: “There will always be arguments about the names to
be given to transitional forms (like Homo habilis); but the recognition of their crucial
intermediate status is of more importance than the name given to the taxon. It seems
that our nomenclatural procedure is not equal to the naming of ‘missing links’ when
the gaps have narrowed to such fine gradations as now exist in the hominid sequence
of the Pleistocene.”
As Tobias remarks in answer to objections from his critics: “Intermediate forms
(‘missing links’) always cause taxonomic headaches, although they make good
phylogenetic sense.” Once it had been established that Homo habilis did not properly
belong to either group, it had to be accorded a separate status. What that should be
was determined by its specific place in the evolutionary ascent of man.
It was not an Australopithecus because it had attained the capacity to make tools
with the aid of other tools. Yet it had not progressed sufficiently along the road of
humanisation to justify inclusion with Homo. There was no alternative except to
recognise it as a new and distinct species of the genus Homo.
Tobias suggests that the new group of hominids might have been designated
Australopithecus-Homo habilis. The compromise of making it a subcategory would
have brought out its emergent position but not its distinctive nature or subsequent
destiny. It evidently has enough important attributes of its own to deserve independent
status.
Like all transitional formations, the qualitative difference of Homo habilis consisted
in its peculiar combination of features, one set resembling its predecessor, the other
anticipating its successor. The relative weight of these contradictory features changed
in the course of its development. It moved away from and beyond the antecedent
genus as it more closely approached the earliest members of the next higher stage.
Hegel supplied a key to comprehending transitional formations by the concepts
of determinate being and limit analysed in the first section of The Logic. Anything is
what it is by virtue of the negations which set its qualitative limits. Both what it comes
out of and what it passes into are essential elements of its being. This being is a
perpetual process of becoming, of continual determination and redetermination through
the interaction of the conflicting forces within itself. These drive it forward to becoming
something other than it has been or is.
Thus Homo habilis is to be designated as a determinate being, that is, a qualitatively
distinct grouping bounded on one side by Australopithecus and on the other side by
Homo. This transitional species is delimited through its organic connections with
both the anterior and posterior stages of human evolution. Its special standing depends
on its qualitative differences from these opposing determinants. To the extent that
The Problem of Transitional Formations 129
these differences are effaced it passes over into and merges with one or the other.
living to open-air encampments around 9000 BC, the inhabitants, who had formerly
hunted many wild goats and occasionally wild sheep, had tamed sheep.
The type of tools at similar open sites in northern Palestine and in Iraq and Iran
showed that the people who lived in these camps, while hunting and collecting most
of their food, possessed sickles and mortars. Taken together with the many bones of
animals capable of domestication, this suggested that they may have already become
regular food producers.
The oldest site yet excavated of a community on the boundary line between the
Old and New Stone Age is at Jericho in Palestine, Nine thousand years ago the
inhabitants of this oasis in the desert grew cereals and bred sheep and goats, in
addition to hunting and collecting. However, they did not yet make pottery or use
ground stone axes.
It is therefore difficult to ascertain whether the villagers of Jericho I, the most
ancient settlement, simply supplemented their diet through food production, or whether
they had gone so far as to make food production the foundation of their economy. In
that case they would have passed beyond the borders of savagery and entered
barbarism.
The situation is clearer, though not yet unmistakable, in the case of the next oldest
village, Jarmo in Kurdistan, a settlement of about 30 houses which was rebuilt 15 times
after its founding. Its deepest layers date back to about 6750 BC. The inhabitants had
domesticated goats and sheep. They not only raised grains as cultivated plants,
which implies a considerable previous history, but they possessed most of the
equipment used by later neolithic farmers to make grain into bread. They had flint
sickle blades, mortars or querns to crack the grain, ovens to parch it, and stone bowls
out of which to eat their porridge. In the upper levels pottery had begun to replace
some of the stone vessels.
All this implies that Jarmo’s residents had left food gathering behind and subsisted
on what they themselves produced. They had become full-fledged food producers,
genuine villagers and farmers.
An interesting sidelight on the botanical aspect of this process of transformation
has been provided by the data accumulated by the archaeological botanist Hans
Helbaek of the Danish National Museum. The successive changes in the details of
carbonised grain and of the imprints of plant parts can tell a sharp-eyed botanist just
as much as successive changes in tools and artifacts can tell an archaeologist.
Domesticated plants and animals are living artifacts, products of man’s modifications
and manipulations.
The Danish botanist concluded that the Jarmo wheat and barley were early
The Problem of Transitional Formations 131
cultivated varieties which had been grown for a number of generations. Their growers
were several steps removed from the first farmers who would have taken the seeds
from plants in their wild state. Who, then, were these pioneers? Diggers have recently
come across caches of wild cereal grain in villages of hunters and seed collectors.
They may possibly have started to reap wild grain before purposively planting the
first wheat and barley.
Thus a hunters’ village of about 200 small stone houses excavated at Mureybat in
northern Syria contained bones of wild animals at all 17 levels. Seeds of wild barley
and wheat showed up at the fifth level from the bottom, along with sickle blades,
mortars, flat stone slabs, and small raised fire pits filled with big pebbles and ashes.
Mauritz Van Loon of the Oriental Institute of Chicago believes the pebbles were
heated and used to crack the wild seeds.
It took about 2500 years to make the changeover from hunting to farming and
arrive at the earliest farming villages. According to present indications, the sequence
of steps in this food-producing revolution began with animal domestication about
10,000 BC, proceeded through hamlets of seed collectors, and culminated with the
emergence of farming communities by 7500 BC.
This record shows that, before they could shake off dependence upon food
gathering, the first domesticators of plants and animals had to pass through
intermediate steps in which the primitive mode of procuring the means of subsistence
was combined with either food or stock raising, or even both. In the first phase, food
production remained subordinate and supplementary to hunting and foraging pursuits
until the new techniques and forces of production gained predominance. Just before
this crucial turning point, a period must have come when the total activities and
output of communal labour were about equally divided between the two, and it would
have been difficult to tell whether the group belonged to one category or the other.
This internal contradiction would be resolved by the further development of the
more dynamic new productive forces. Thus, when food and stock raising were
introduced into the less advanced Old Stone Age culture of Europe some thousands
of years later, the Starcevo folk who lived in the Balkan peninsula learned to practice
a system of rotating crops and pasture that made hunting and fishing less and less
vital to their economy.
The insuperable ambiguities of the boundary separating food gatherers from food
producers have been underscored in a recent account of the rise of Mesopotamian
civilisation. “We cannot with the material at our disposal pinpoint the crucial passage
from a food-gathering to a food-producing economy. It can be argued that hoes could
be used for uprooting as well as for tilling, sickles for reaping naturally growing or
132 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
cultivated wheat, querns and mortars for grinding and pounding wild seeds or even
mineral pigments; and it is not always easy to decide whether bones of sheep or cattle
belonged to wild or to domesticated animals. All considered, our best criterion is
perhaps the presence on a site of permanent habitations, for agriculture ties man to
the land. But here again, it is sometimes difficult to draw a firm line between the stone
huts of hunters, for whom agriculture was an occasional activity, and the farms of
fully settled peasants.” (Ancient Iraq, Georges Roux, 1964. p. 54.)
society based on the division between cultivators of the soil who provide the
sustenance and those layers of consumers who produce other goods and the
administrators of various kinds who serve higher social functions. The city comes to
dominate the country and is the force that civilises the barbarians.
The town is an overgrown village at one end of its growth and an embryonic city
at the other. It displays characteristics common to both types of settlement without
being either. Unlike the village, it is not completely rural but is larger and more complex.
At the same time it is smaller, less diversified, less developed, less centralised and less
powerful than the city.
Neither rural nor urban, the town has an indeterminate character and an imprecise
and fluctuating connotation. It is not easy to single out the ensemble of positive
features which distinguish the town from the village it has come out of or from the city
status it may be heading toward. This ambiguity is built into its constitution as an
intermediate form of permanent settlement.
Thus the town exemplifies the congenital fluidity of a transitional form. Its structure
is amorphous; its boundaries are blurred. This indefiniteness, which is inherent in its
very nature, is reflected in the concept “town”, which is likewise clouded with an
insurmountable fuzziness.
transition from Roman slavery to the feudal age invalidates any rigid scheme of
historical evolution predicated on an undeviating line of succession from one form of
production to the next. The native population of the Romano-Germanic world sank to
a lower level of production and culture before it went on to assemble the conditions
for a higher mode of existence. This discontinuity in economic growth illustrates the
dialectical nature of the concrete processes of social evolution. Far from following
prescribed paths in a mechanical manner, the peoples of the past have often fallen
backward before taking the next step in historical progress.
through and overcome with the introduction of steamdriven machinery into industry
and transportation. Mechanical industry fashioned the modern proletariat; it enabled
the capitalists to exploit wage labour to maximum advantage by reducing the value of
commodities and thereby increasing the surplus value which the workers produced
and the capitalists appropriated. On this technical basis the capitalist mode of
production stood squarely on its own feet for the first time and went forward to
conquer the globe. But it could not have embarked on that career unless manufacture
had left the guild system behind and prepared the advent of that technology best
adapted to the needs of capital accumulation.
movement toward workers’ democracy in the postcapitalist countries and the adoption
of revolutionary socialist policies and perspectives which can lessen the birth pangs
of the new society and shorten the interval between the abolition of capitalist power
and private property and the creation of harmonious and equal relations for all mankind.
Although postcapitalist economic relations and their superstructures have existed
for half a century, they are only in the elementary stage of their historical process of
formation and remain subject to all the infirmities of infancy. Furthermore, they have
yet to be installed in the habitat most propitious for their growth.
When bourgeois society came forth from feudal Western Europe, capitalist relations
did not all at once take possession of the whole of social life. They first preempted the
field of commerce where monetary wealth was accumulated. Meanwhile, the production
of material wealth either continued in the old ways or else, as with industry, passed
over into manufacture which retained the old handicraft techniques. The new laws of
capitalist development did not break through all limitations, take full command of
economic and social life, and unfold their immense potency until the industrial
revolution of the early 19th century, based on the steam engine, large-scale industry
and the factory system, thoroughly transformed the methods of production.
A comparable incompleteness has characterised, and even disfigured, the first
period of the transition from capitalism to socialism. Since 1917 the laws of
socioeconomic development bound up with the new system of production have had
to function under the least favourable and most restrictive conditions. Whereas they
required the most advanced productive forces for effective operation, they were
confined to the poorest and most backward countries, where they had to contend
with incompetent and bureaucratised regimes at home and imperialist encirclement
and hostility on a world scale.
Even under such adverse historical circumstances the new mode of production
based on nationalised property and the planning principle disclosed its effectiveness
and registered colossal achievements.
Despite these successes, the methods of socialist development have not yet been
given the chance to manifest their real potential. Implanted in poor soil, they have not
had the right nutriment or atmosphere for their flowering. As Marx long ago pointed
out, socialism needs a preponderant and highly cultivated working class, a powerful
industry, a well-rounded economy and an international basis. None of these
prerequisites for socialism prevailed in the first half-century of the international
anticapitalist revolution. They have had to be created largely from scratch under
forced draft and with intolerably heavy sacrifices by the working masses.
Consequently, the laws of the transition from capitalism to socialism have thus far
142 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
developed continuously from its origins to the present. Each stage of human history
and its social organisation has had an integrated constitution depending upon its
mode of production and its appropriate place in the sequence of the historical process.
Sociology is that branch of scientific knowledge which investigates the evolution
of society in its entirety and the content of social life in its fullness. It endeavours to
discover the laws governing the progress of social life from the most primitive and
simple form of social organisation to its most complex and mature structures.
Both the laws of nature and the laws of society are historical in character since
they are drawn from phenomena engaged in constant change. But social phenomena
are qualitatively different from the purely natural events out of which they have
grown and in which they remain rooted. Social facts are produced by our species,
which obtains its means of existence in a unique manner through cooperative labour.
Man’s activities of production and their results invest the laws of social development
with characteristics distinctively different from those governing other living creatures.
The laws of social evolution have retained certain traits in common with the laws
of organic evolution, since up to now these have operated without conscious collective
direction or control. That is why Marx regarded “the evolution of the economic
formation of society …as a process of natural history”, as he wrote in the preface to
the first edition of Volume 1 of Capital. But the dominant features of the social-
historical process are fundamentally different from those prevailing in the rest of
reality.
The broad scope and aims of sociology make it the most general of the social
sciences. It seeks to synthesise the findings of the rest of the social sciences into a
comprehensive conception of the dynamics of the historical process.
Sociology plays a role in regard to the social sciences comparable to scientific
cosmology, which comprehensively explains the evolution of the physical universe,
or synthetic biology, which aims to provide a coherent picture of the whole realm of
living matter.
To the degree that sociology succeeds in comprehending the laws of human
development, it provides the other social sciences with a general method of
investigation which can serve as a guide to their more specialised studies. There is an
unbreakable interdependence and constant interaction between sociology and the
more specialised departments of social science, each of which has its relative autonomy.
The data provided by these in turn enrich and extend the ideas and method of sociology
as it grows.
Sociology seeks to answer such questions as: What is society and in what respects
does it differ from nature? How did social life originate? How and why does it change?
Sociology and Historical Materialism 145
What are the most powerful driving forces in its development? Through what stages
has social evolution passed? What forms of organisation has society acquired? What
are the standards of social progress? What relations do the various aspects of the
social structure have to one another? What laws regulate the replacement of one
grade of social development by the next and the transformation of one type of social
organisation into another?
was emphasised by the 18th century French thinker Montesquieu, who picked out
geography and government as the main determinants of social phenomena. The
influence of the first factor prevailed in the earlier stages of human development; the
second came forward as civilisation progressed. But both continue to work together
upon the mental life of man and generate his predominant characteristics. Thus heat
and despotism made certain Asiatic peoples placid and docile while cold and
democracy made some Europeans active in mind and body.
Besides such efforts to apply either idealist or materialist procedures in a more or
less consistent and clear-cut manner, we find an array of thinkers who shuttle between
these opposing modes of reasoning and arrive at the most incongruous conclusions
in their works. The literature of the social sciences is saturated with such eclecticism
in theory and method; it is the habitual, normative viewpoint of contemporary Western
scholarship.
A characteristic expression of this dualism was provided by Charles Beard, the
American liberal historian. His last word on historical philosophy was that ideas and
interests were the twin motive forces of civilisation. If it be asked which is predominant
as a rule and in the long run, he answered that this cannot be ascertained in advance.
All depends upon the concrete circumstances of the given case. The door was thus
flung open for ideological considerations to prevail over material conditions both in
particular and in general.
Although the idealist approach to history is false in principle, it is not all wrong. It
takes into account certain features of the development of society. Ideas, opinions,
religions, individual action, are all parts of history and contribute to its making. The
point is that they are not the decisive factors in social life and therefore cannot serve
to explain the rest They are secondary and derivative elements which themselves
stand in need of explanation. The idealistic conception is misleading because it is
shallow; it does not get to the inner core, the essential causes, of social phenomena.
Every materialist school of historical explanation has had erroneous and inadequate
notions. But their procedure was valid in essence because it oriented social
investigation in the right direction. The materialists looked for the motive forces and
root causes of social evolution in the influence and changes of the material conditions
of human existence and kept digging deeper and deeper into these. With Marx and
Engels they succeeded in reaching bedrock: They located the basis of society in the
mode of production which arises out of the given state of man’s struggle with nature
for the means of life and further development.
Sociology and Historical Materialism 149
HISTORICAL MATERIALISM
Historical materialism is a particular type of sociological theory. It is the sociological
method of Marxism. It investigates the same phenomena as rival schools of sociology
but in a more probing, many-sided, rigorously scientific way that gives more insight
into the total life of society and more foresight about its trends of development.
Historical materialism is not the whole of Marxist theory. It forms a special branch
arising from the application of its dialectical and materialist principles to the evolution
of society. This is disputed by certain revisionist interpreters of Marxism, like Sidney
Hook and Jean-Paul Sartre, who contend that the Marxist domain is restricted to
social phenomena, to the life of man, and cannot be extended to nature. The Russian
Marxist Plekhanov, more correctly stated that it had an all-embracing universal
jurisdiction.
Plekhanov divided the unified and systematic structure of Marxist thought into
three parts: 1. Dialectical materialism, the most general approach to reality, which
covers nature, society and the mind and which aims to discover the general laws
governing the modes of motion in all three interacting sectors of existence; 2. Historical
Materialism, the application of these laws to the development of mankind and the
discovery of the specific laws involved in social existence; 3. Scientific socialism, the
application of the laws of historical materialism to that particular stage of social evolution
in which capitalism takes shape, fulfils and exhausts its potential, and passes over to
the higher formation of socialism. Thus dialectical materialism is a school of philosophy,
logic and theory of knowledge; historical materialism, of sociology; and scientific
socialism, of political economy and revolutionary practice.
Historical materialism is accurately named. It did not acquire either element of its
designation by chance. Its title formulates the essential features which demarcate this
method from other ways of interpreting social phenomena: On the one hand, its
derivation of all the higher manifestations of culture from their economic foundations
opposes it to the historical idealisms which have been the chief adversary of materialist
thought in history and sociology. On the other hand, there have been tendencies
which analysed social processes and structures materialistically but disregarded or
minimised their evolutionary aspects. These unhistorical materialisms attributed the
basic elements of social formations either to an unchangeable nature or to some fixed
traits of human nature.
The distinctiveness of Marxist sociology comes from its fusion of the materialist
approach to society with a thoroughgoing evolutionary outlook. It teaches that
everything in social life is subject to modification and transformation in accord with
150 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
monarchical and theocratic views. Their critical and creative thought introduced lasting
enlightenment into these fields of social science.
As one type of social regime has supplanted another in the onward march of
civilisation, there has been a cumulative growth of knowledge about society. The
comprehension of social relations and their modes of transformation arrived at by the
most penetrating theorists of one stage of social and scientific development and its
dominant class has been reevaluated, sifted and corrected by the leading ideologists
of the next higher social formation. Thus the political economy of the working class
took off from a critical reworking of the doctrines of the classical bourgeois economists,
just as its philosophy combined the principles of previous materialists with the logical
method of the German philosophers from Kant to Hegel. In this way the deficiencies
and inherent limitations of the outmoded stage were reduced and removed while the
store of genuine knowledge was amplified and improved by the fresh findings of the
representatives of the more progressive class forces.
The incentives for objective research and judgment in sociology are lessened and
the advance of the science slowed down when the major efforts of a class become
dedicated to preserving an obsolete system of production and a reactionary political
structure. The statesmen and economists of Southern slavery added very little to the
sum of knowledge even about the laws regulating their own peculiar social regime.
This blindness to the real forces stirring within society and their trends of development
has afflicted all decadent and outdated ruling classes. Because they had acted as the
dominant power in national politics for decades, the representatives of the slavocracy
believed they could continue to hold sway after the economic, social and political
balance of forces in the country had decisively shifted against them. The test of the
Civil War burst this illusion.
Today the statesmen and ideologists of the major capitalist power expect the
United States to exercise the same prolonged supremacy over world affairs that England
did 100 years ago, regardless of the growing weight of the anticapitalist states and
forces in this century. Their vision and prevision of world history is impaired, not
sharpened, by their class position and prejudices.
The best understanding of society at the disposal of the world working class is
contained and codified in the tenets of historical materialism. This is the most
comprehensive and integrated system of sociological laws and the most profound
interpretation of historical development. It incorporates the verified knowledge of
history and society bequeathed from the past with the contributions made by the
masters of Marxism.
The needs of the working class in its struggle for emancipation impose exacting
154 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
demands and a severe objectivity upon its ideologists. As two world wars and fascism
have demonstrated, the working class has to pay heavily for every failure of cognition
about the dynamics of contemporary society. It suffers from every instance of
ignorance, subjectivity and shortsightedness in the socioeconomic analyses of its
leaders and scholars.
This puts a premium on finding out the reality of social and political conditions
and ascertaining the precise movements of the diverse social forces. False ideas have
to be constantly corrected by the results of actual experience in the arena of struggle
on a world scale; a more objective and rounded picture of the concrete situation in all
its interacting aspects has to be worked out if the historical aims of the socialist
movement are to be fulfilled.
These vital stimuli emanating from the movement for liberation from bondage to
class society are the lifeblood of the progress of historical materialism. This method
teaches that theory and practice, science and experience go hand in hand throughout
history. But the two do not evolve symmetrically; their progress is extremely uneven.
The understanding of peoples and classes about their situation and tasks has usually
lagged far behind their actual relations and the possibilities of changing them.
This gap has never been greater than in the atomic age. Although the world is
ready to receive socialism, a considerable section of the working class in the West is
not ready to achieve it. Yet the very salvation of humanity depends upon its capacity
to intervene as the dominant and decisive force in redirecting the history of our time.
The enlightenment and guidance provided by historical materialism can do much to
alter the gross imbalance between the immense untapped revolutionary potential of
the working people and their present inadequate level of consciousness.
From the 1840s to the 1960s the victories and defeats, advances and setbacks of
the masses in their strivings to change the course of history and reconstruct society
on new foundations has amplified the method and enriched the content of historical
materialism. The greatest value of all science comes from its usefulness in practice.
The science of the social process formulated in historical materialism must also meet
and pass this supreme test.
The history of the past century has given many proofs of its superior capacities to
decipher the past, analyse current events, and forecast the variants of social and
political development Its truth and potency will be irrefutably vindicated as the
application of its ideas enables the revolutionary forces to forge a policy which can
bring about with the greatest speed and efficiency the abolition of the old order and
the building of a better world.
POSITIVISM AND MARXISM IN
SOCIOLOGY
APROPOS OF PROFESSOR POPPER AND HIS METHODS
Does history have any regularities that can be scientifically known and used to
foresee and shape the future? Marxism says yes, positivism says no, to this cardinal
question of sociology.
Both the positivists and their ideological cousins, the pragmatists, are extremely
dubious about the existence of sociological laws and the possibilities of ascertaining
the direction of social developments. They disavow historical determinism, especially
in connection with the prospects of capitalism, and are intent upon disqualifying the
claims of Marxism to be scientific.
Their case is most vigorously argued nowadays by Professor Karl Popper of the
University of London, author of The Open Society and its Enemies, The Logic of
Scientific Discovery and The Poverty of Historicism. This influential theorist of
positivist method in the social sciences is a proponent of “piecemeal social
engineering”. He is also a pioneer of cold-war liberalism whose reputation in the West
has been enhanced by the political consequences of his views. As early as 1945 he
expounded the thesis that the central issue of our time was the world conflict between
capitalist democracy and communist totalitarianism, the first safeguarding the values
of reason, freedom, democracy, individualism and liberalism in “an open society”, the
other promoting collectivism, servitude and authoritarianism in “a closed society”.
The contending camps had their respective philosophies in a flexible empiricism versus
a dogmatic dialectical materialism.
Professor Popper is not conservative but progressive in his social outlook. He
expresses agreement with Marx that philosophers should not simply interpret the
world but help change it. He contends, however, that Marxist historical method is not
suited for that purpose; its pretensions to scientific knowledge of the laws of social
development are spurious.
Although Professor Popper believes in a kind of physical necessity, he does not
extend any determinism to social phenomena. In an address on “Prediction and
Prophecy in the Social Sciences”, delivered at the 10th International Congress of
Philosophy at Amsterdam, 1948, and printed in Theories of History, edited by Patrick
Gardiner, he asserts that “there exists no law of evolution” either for plants and
animals or for man. Consequently there is no factual basis for forecasting economic,
political or historical developments. He labels the irrepressible fondness for prediction
shared by diverse schools of sociology as “historicism” and focuses his attack upon
Marxism as the worst offender in the practice of “futurism”.
Scientific socialism maintains that the purpose of both natural and social science
is to know in order to foresee correctly and act most effectively. That is its practical
value, the reason why so many people devote so much time to scientific work and
governments today subsidise it so heavily.
Professor Popper dismisses this aim in sociology as wishful thinking. It is the
modern secular version of an age-old dream of prophecy — “the idea that we can
know what the future has in store for us, and that we can profit from such knowledge
by adjusting our policy to it”. The kind of predictability pursued by historical
materialists, who believe that human affairs are causally determined and lawful, is a
chimera because history exhibits no regularities, he says. It is largely made up of
singular cases. “Non-repetitive events are the most striking aspects of historical
development”, he writes.
Obviously, no general laws can be derived from an endless series of purely unique
events. If every occurrence in social life and the procession of history was as
unprecedented as he proclaims, scientific analysis would indeed be impossible. So
would any reasonable orientation and effective action.
Positivism claims to be superior to dialectical materialism because it is not dogmatic
but faithful to the facts. The rival theories may therefore be tested by reference to the
basic facts about the regularities and irregularities of social existence and historical
development.
The society around the professor does undergo minor modifications from day to
day but, barring overnight revolutions, he can count on meeting substantially the
same institutions and customs in the morning as when he fell asleep on the previous
evening. But he has not awakened to the philosophical import of this simple fact.
It is grossly unfactual to assert that history has no regularities or that nonrepetitive
events are its decisive characteristics. Social relations themselves refute such a
Positivism and Marxism in Sociology 157
contention; they are definite types of perennially repeated mutual interactions among
men arising from continuous activities of a definite kind. The regularities of society
are primarily expressed in the productive activities and economic relations of its
members. Since our species emerged from the primate stage, men have acquired and
produced the means of satisfying their needs in routine ways through repetitive
labour processes. The tools they made for that purpose were fashioned according to
traditional techniques and previous models.
Our prime source of knowledge about preliterate times comes from archaeology,
that science of society which deals with the earliest human activities incorporated in
artifacts. Although each of these products and instruments of labour has individual
characteristics, almost all belong to specific types. These constitute the data of
archaeology. “If the implement be unique, it is not a datum for archaeology at all; it
remains just a curio, until a similar implement, that is, one of the same type, be observed
in a significant archaeological context … Archaeologists must ignore the small
individual peculiarities of any given knife and treat it as an instance of one or another
of the standard types, as a member of that class of knives”, observes V. Gordon Childe
in A Short Introduction to Archaeology (pp. 13-14). Jacquetta Hawkes tells us that
“in the Lower Palaeolithic period the hard-axe, although it was gradually improved,
remained in use as the dominant tool form for over a quarter of a million years”
(Prehistory, p. 172).
The social relations of the most primitive peoples were as simple and standardised
as their instruments of production. The small bands or tribes of Stone Age food-
gatherers, hunters or fisherman, had collectivist institutions and customs. The scope
of variations in their social organisation were held within the narrow limits prescribed
by their mode of production. They might live in caves or camps but had, as a rule, no
permanent settlements.
The innovation of food production which gave rise to barbarism introduced the
first epoch-making changes and extensive diversifications into primitive social
structures. But the barbaric communities and kingdoms were based upon agriculture.
What could be more repetitive than this kind of economy rooted in the natural processes
of plant growth and reproduction, regulated by the round of the seasons and carried
on by traditional techniques and rituals?
Mankind took more than a million years to go from savagery through barbarism to
civilisation. This crawling pace indicates how greatly recurrences outweighed novelties
in daily life. Even after the most advanced sections of humanity became civilised, the
fixity of social relations and the slow and intermittent rate of change in the agricultural
societies culminating in feudalism betokened the predominance of repetition in the
158 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
conditions for its survival and revival are no longer at hand. Popular sovereignty, on
the other hand, which was absent in the first civilisations, is today regarded as the
normal and most desirable form of government to which even antidemocratic regimes
pay lipservice. What was once constant has become variable and vanishing; what
was nonexistent is on the rise and constantly growing.
The second case, taken from technology, deals with an analogous transformation
in the relations between the two major consecutive types of means of labour. Until 200
years ago men used nothing but hand-tools in production; machines were an
insignificant exception. This historical constant was set aside by the large-scale
introduction of machinery, an innovation which came about lawfully and
comprehensibly by transferring the function of handling the working tool from a
human being to a mechanism. The more complex and efficient means of production
displaced the more primitive and less productive implements as the capitalists
recognised their greater profitability. In factory industry the use of hand-tools is
exceptional while machine production is its basis; their roles have become reversed.
This fundamental change in technology generated a host of others which together
constitute industrial capitalism. Under this system tens of millions of people get up
five to six days a week and go to work for eight hours or more for wages in enterprises
operated by capitalist owners for their private profit. Whatever their individual
differences and personal preferences, the wageworkers must submit to this standard
type of labour relation in order to get their daily bread, pay the landlord monthly and
meet installment loans regularly. This is not an accident but a necessity of capitalism,
its fundamental law, the source of its exploitation.
Professor Popper denies that there are any such essential necessities in economic
activities and social relations or that the aim of sociology is to discover and explain
them in order to foresee their development. He even contends that social systems or
“wholes” do not exist as “empirical objects”; they are only “ideal objects”. What
really exists are “individuals and their actions and reactions”, which presumably
never acquire a definitely organised or systematised character.
He therefore assigns an entirely different task to the social sciences. Their main
task, he tells us, “is to trace the unintended social repercussions of intentional human
actions”. That is to say, sociology must revolve around an explanation of the accidents
rather than the necessities of history.
This is a legitimate subject of social science, although it is not central to it. Sociology
should be more concerned with demonstrating the interplay of accident and necessity
in history and the conversion of the one into the other as it develops. Nevertheless,
the discrepancies between the conscious purposes of human beings and the real
Positivism and Marxism in Sociology 161
results of their activities, which Hegel called “the cunning of reason”, that is to say,
the irony of history, does pose an important problem for social science.
In order to clarify why this anomaly has been such a pronounced and persistent
trait of human affairs to date, it is essential to find out the social and historical
circumstances that have prevented the outcome of man’s collective activities from
coinciding with their avowed aims or will. Professor Popper apparently believes that
this is an eternal law and irremediable flaw of history. Actually, this prime feature of
past and present history originated in the exchange of commodities and man’s
consequent loss of control over his social relations issuing from the expansion of
exchange relations. This lack of control is most accentuated in the capitalist phase of
commodity production. The phenomenon so overwhelms Professor Popper because
capitalism is an inherently anarchic system, beyond regulation by its most powerful
agencies and privileged beneficiaries.
The conflicting private interests of its constituent parts make it impossible for the
plans of an individual, a corporation or a state to be assured of realisation. The main
objective of the socialist movement is to do away with the economic sources of this
social disorder and establish the material preconditions for bringing man’s aims into
consonance with his results, by eliminating the private ownership of the means of
production, and planning economic development.
This is abhorrent to Professor Popper, who is a partisan of individualism and free
enterprise. The last sentence of his liberal polemic against Marxism reads: “The fight
against avoidable misery should be a recognised aim of public policy, while the increase
of happiness should be left, in the main, to private initiative.”
The theoretical justification for his program is that social science in general, and
Marxism in particular, possesses no predictive power that could contribute to effective
social control over the next stage of human progress. He would have us believe that
our contemporaries, who have proved capable of the intricate computations and
constructions required to send spacecraft and their instruments to the moon and to
Mars, are unable to discern the forces at work around them on earth and figure out the
main lines of their evolution. Or, having analysed and ascertained these trends, they
cannot act consciously and collectively to realise the best alternative.
Fortunately, even pre-Marxist revolutionaries have not been as myopic as the
positivist scholar. They have grasped historical necessities before these became
actualities. Indeed, a clear and conscious recognition of these was a prerequisite for
their realisation. In the Declaration of Independence the colonial patriots proclaimed
that it was imperative to break loose from English crown rule at least seven years
before they succeeded in doing so. Sam Adams saw its urgency much sooner. The
162 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
prognoses, which should flow from an all-sided diagnosis of the given situation, are
not presented with such absoluteness. Where there are opposing necessities at work,
the outcome must be conditional on their further interaction and relative weight.
Proceeding from a knowledge of the laws of the class struggle and their specific
refraction in the Germany of the Weimar Republic, Trotsky concluded that the rickety
bourgeois democracy could not be saved and only two opposing roads were open
under the given circumstances: fascism or socialism. He stated that all the objective
conditions for another October 1917 were present but that the subjective factors of
correct leadership would have to be brought to bear for the favourable variant to be
achieved. If the divided leadership of the working masses failed to apply the right
policies in time, Hitler would win. The perspectives which guided his recommendations
for action were conditional, although the possible outcomes were categorical.
The same conditionality applies to judgments on the prospects of the conflict
between capitalism and socialism on a world-historical scale. The triumph of the
socialist cause is not predetermined in the same way as an astronomical eclipse, since
the factor of human consciousness and timely action is involved and decisive. If a
cosmic catastrophe or a nuclear war should blow up the planet, that would end human
history and dispose, among other things, of the controversy between positivism and
Marxism.
Assuming, however, as one must, that mankind will have a future and a better one,
victory for the international working class depends upon many factors: the course of
development and degree of disintegration of monopoly capitalism, the growth in
power of the workers’ states, the advances of the colonial revolution, the actions and
consciousness of the industrial workers in the imperialist strongholds, the kind of
political organisation and leadership they get.
It is possible for all the conditions required for a successful socialist revolution to
be met. The overthrow of capitalism is no longer the wholly conditional or conjectural
prospect it was when Marx and Engels predicted its advent in the Communist
Manifesto. It is already an accomplished fact in countries on three continents.
As an empiricist, Professor Popper would maintain that no amount of precedents
establishes a rule. He does not understand that what has been more or less possible
becomes more and more probable, and eventually necessary, as the conditions for its
occurrence and recurrence pile up and come together. What has hitherto been
conditional, at a certain critical turning point in the processes of development, becomes
necessary.
His death is conditional and avoidable at any time of his life; it is more and more
probable as he ages and is inevitable in the long run because of the laws of his
164 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
biological constitution. Social systems are no more immortal than the human beings
whose activities sustain them. Like capitalism, they can perish piecemeal before they
are abolished in toto.
Let us consider a fresh historical instance which is most favourable to his
viewpoint. The Cuban revolution developed in an unexpected fashion which surprised
not only the Cuban property owners and the corporations and government of the
United States but also the July 26th leaders and the entire world socialist movement.
Yet, even if it was not specifically predicted before the fact, its line of development can
be explained after the fact.
Political analysts should first ask: Why did the Cuban revolution follow a different
path and have an outcome different from its Latin American predecessors in Mexico,
Bolivia and Guatemala? There were numerous reasons for its unprecedented turn.
Among these was the fact that Castro and his associates learned from the military
coup in Guatemala in 1954 that, if colonialism was to be stamped out and popular
power preserved, the officer corps and the old army had to be destroyed and replaced
by a revolutionary armed force. In addition, they learned how to expropriate the
capitalists and start building a planned economy from Russia, Yugoslavia and China.
The whole experience of 20th century history since 1917, plus the international balance
of forces issuing from it, were indispensable preconditions for the unanticipated
course taken by the Fidelistas.
The transformation of the armed insurrection against Batista’s capitalist
dictatorship into a proletarian-peasant revolution is a spectacular example of the law
governing the present stage of world history that the fundamental problems of
backward countries cannot be solved except by a revolutionary struggle directed
along socialist lines.
This theorem of the permanent revolution formulates an irrepressible and growing
tendency inherent in all the insurgent colonial movements of our time.
The positivist professor must protest against this logic of contemporary history.
The Cuban experience, he will expostulate, was unique; it cannot be taken as a sample
of a law. “Society is changing, developing. Its development is not, in the main, a
repetitive one.” Contrary to his shortsighted philosophy, the Cuban revolution is not
regarded as unique either by its leaders or its enemies. Its general import and impact
is what makes it such a touchy issue in American and world politics.
Official Washington does not view Cuba as an isolated incident that can have no
sequel, although it would like to have it that way. That was demonstrated by its armed
intervention in the Dominican Republic in 1965 and declared intention to dispatch
troops elsewhere in Latin America if a comparable threat arises. Both sides recognise
Positivism and Marxism in Sociology 165
the potential for further Cubas in the Western hemisphere and are taking appropriate
measures to promote or prevent them.
The policies of Washington to contain and crush, and of Havana to aid and
extend, the socialist revolution have a lawful character. They correspond to the logic
and dynamics of current history, which is determined and directed by the necessities
of the mortal combat between capitalism and socialism.
Standing helplessly between the class adversaries, Professor Popper would advise
them that no such necessities exist. Since both sides know better, his advice would
fall on deaf ears.
Professor Popper is acclaimed in scholarly circles for his special definition of the
nature of scientific method. He teaches that the essence of science consists, not so
much in the verification of hypotheses, as in their falsification. The greatest scientific
progress is registered when it is disclosed, not what theories and laws can tell us
about what exists and what can be done, but when they advise us what does not exist
and what cannot be done. Laws above all set limits to the possible.
The timidity of his sceptical epistemology is evident in this lopsided conception
of scientific lawfulness. To be sure, the clarification of the conditional limits,
inadequacies and errors of existing theories are an indispensable and fruitful function
of scientific activity, a prime source of its growth, the starting point for fresh advances
and breakthroughs. That happened in the 19th century and early 20th century with
Euclidean geometry, Newtonian physics and classical political economy.
But exposures of this kind, which have stimulated progressive crises in science,
represent only one phase, one step in the totality of scientific investigation and
advancement. It is the negative side of the unending process of acquiring more precise
and deep-going understanding of the phenomena in question. Such revisions in the
light of further experimental facts pave the way for the elaboration and verification of
more comprehensive, complex and correct theories. Darwin banished incorrect
doctrines from biology as part of his positive demonstration of the evolutionary
mechanism and unity of living beings. The eventual outcome, the net result, is a
steady accumulation of more ample and dependable information with which to foresee
and control natural and social processes.
Ironically, positivism shies away from acknowledging this growth of positive
knowledge about the world, does not properly assess its significance and its role and
relevance in providing foresight and facilitating action. It is badly named and should
be more precisely termed “negativism”.
Finally, Professor Popper, who insists that the social sciences cannot and should
not forecast historical developments and that unconditional laws are taboo, fails to
166 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
abide by these two precepts of his own position. Despite his contention that the
future is opaque, this liberal does not hesitate to affirm most categorically that revolution
in general, and above all the socialist revolution heralded by Marxism, is bound to be
ruinous. “I am convinced that revolutionary methods can only make things worse —
that they will increase unnecessary suffering; that they will lead to more and more
violence; and that they must destroy freedom.”
On what scientific grounds, empirical or rational, can such an unconditional
assertion be justified? Many past revolutions have benefited mankind and enlarged
freedom for the masses. The very bourgeois democracy he defends and cherishes
was the offspring of revolutionary struggles. The American people have had two
revolutions which made things much better rather than worse for them. Is it then only
contemporary proletarian, and not previous bourgeois revolutions, that are full of
evils? He will not convince the peoples of the Soviet Union, Yugoslavia, China and
Cuba that their revolutions brought no good, whatever their shortcomings. Nor will
his timid admonitions prevent other peoples from seeking and finding the
revolutionary socialist method of solving their otherwise insoluble problems. This
empiricist turns rigidly dogmatic when he confronts the prospect of socialist revolution.
In order to uphold gradualism and piecemeal reform at all costs, he is compelled to
throw overboard the principles of his own method and relapse into “ahistoricism”, an
absolute rule that revolutions always and everywhere have baneful results.
Such inconsistency is a congenital vice of positivist epistemology. It is engendered
in the last analysis by the predicament of the middle-class liberal under monopoly
capitalism who wishes to work toward a better society but fears to overstep the
framework of the established order in his views, perspectives, and actions. Others,
who refuse to be hemmed in by these arbitrary and essentially reactionary standards,
are told that they are “unscientific”. This demonstrates how different conceptions of
science and its methods, which appear so remote and detached from everyday life,
have their social implications, class affiliations, and political uses.
MARXISM VERSUS EXISTENTIALISM
Existentialism and Marxism are the most widely discussed and widely held
philosophies of our time. The first is dominant in Western Europe and gaining
increasing popularity in the United States. The second is not only the official doctrine
of all communist countries but, in one form or another, is accepted as a guide by many
movements and parties throughout the world.
Over the past 20 years the proponents of these two schools of thought have
engaged in continual debate with one another. The centre of this controversy has
been France. There existentialism has found its most talented spokesmen in Nobel
Prize winner Jean-Paul Sartre and his associates, who have developed their positions
in direct contact and contest with Marxism. They live on a continent where, unlike the
United States, socialism has influenced public life for almost a century, and in a
country where the Communist Party gets a quarter of the vote, is followed by most of
the working class, and exerts heavy pressure upon radical intellectuals. These
circumstances have compelled the so-called mandarins of the left to make clear their
attitude toward Marxism at every stage in the evolution of their views.
The development of Sartre has been especially paradoxical. He worked out his
original existentialist ideas under the sway of nonmaterialist thinkers such as Edmund
Husserl and Martin Heidegger as a deliberate challenge to Marxism. In Being and
Nothingness (1943) and Materialism and Revolution (1947) Sartre presented his
philosophy as an alternative to dialectical materialism. Then in the late 1950s he made
a turnabout and embraced Marxism, at least in words — which for him, as he explains
in the first volume of his recent autobiography, have had a reality greater than the
objective world.
In his latest philosophical treatise, The Critique of Dialectical Reason (1960), the
first section of which has been published in English as Search for a Method, he
declares that existentialism has become a subordinate branch of Marxism which aspires
to renew and enrich it. Thus the phenomenologist of existence who condemned
dialectical materialism as false and a foe to human freedom in the 1940s now proposes
to marry Marxism and existentialism.
To what extent, if any, can these philosophies be conjoined? Can a synthesis of
the two be viable? This article intends to show that the contending world outlooks
cannot be harmonised or integrated into one containing “the best features” of both.
A legendary alchemist thought that by putting together fire and water he would
concoct that most desirable of delights, “fire-water”. Actually, the one nullifies or
extinguishes the other when they come into contact. It is the same with Marxism and
existentialism. Their fundamental positions over a broad spectrum of problems
extending from philosophy and sociology to morality and politics are so divergent
that they cannot really be reconciled.
This piece can do no more than indicate the main lines of their disagreement on
the most important issues. Let us first consider their opposing conceptions on the
nature of reality and then on science, which is the highest expression of our endeavours
to investigate and know the world.
hopeless, he asserted, to try to give rational form to the irrational. The absurdity of
existence must be lived through, suffered, defied; it cannot be satisfactorily explained.
However, the professional thinkers of this school do not choose to commit
philosophical suicide. They have proceeded, each in their own way, to elaborate a
philosophy of “being in an absurd world”. There is logic to their illogicality. If
everything is hopelessly contradictory, why should the enterprise of philosophy be
an exception? The human mission, they say, is to find out the meaning of
meaninglessness — or at least give some meaning through our words and deeds to an
otherwise inscrutable universe.
For dialectical materialism, reality has developed in a lawful manner and is rationally
explicable. The rationality of nature and human history is bound up with matter in
motion. The concatenation of cosmic events gives rise to cause-and-effect relations
that determine the qualities and evolution of things. The physical preceded and
produced the biological, the biological the social, and the social the psychological in
a historical series of mutually conditioned stages. The aim of science is to disclose
their essential linkages and formulate these into laws that can help pilot human activity.
The rationality, determinism, and causality of the universal process of material
development do not exclude but embrace the objective existence and significance of
absurdity, indeterminism, and accident.
However, these random features of reality are no more fundamental than regularity.
They are not immutable and irremovable aspects of nature and history but relative
phenomena which in the course of development can change to the extent of becoming
their own opposites. Chance, for example, is the antithesis of necessity. Yet chance
has its own laws, which are lodged in the occurrence of statistical regularities. Quantum
mechanics and the life insurance business exemplify how individual accidents are
convertible into aggregate necessities.
Exceptions are nothing but the least frequent alternatives, and when enough
exceptions pile up they give rise to a new rule of operation which supersedes the
formerly dominant one. The interplay of chance and necessity through the conversion
of the exception into the rule can be seen in the economic development of society.
Under tribal life, production for immediate personal consumption is the norm whereas
production for exchange is a rare and casual event. Under capitalism, production for
sale is the general law; production for one’s own use is uncommon. What was
categorically necessary in the first economic system is fortuitous in the second.
Moreover, in the transition from one economy to the other the bearers of chance and
necessity have changed places, have become transformed into each other.
Social structures that are rational and necessary under certain historical
170 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
stagnation, and oddities. Despite its zigzags, however, history has moved onward
and upward from one stage to the next, from savagery to civilisation, for ascertainable
reasons. It exhibits necessities as well as ironic contingencies, final settlements as
well as unresolved issues. The French feudalists, the colonial Loyalists, the Southern
slaveholders, the German Nazis, and the Russian capitalists can attest to that.
it. Nature, society, and the individual coexist in the closest reciprocal relationship,
which is characterised by the action of human beings in changing the world. In the
process of subduing objective reality for their own ends they change themselves.
The subjective comes out of the objective, is in constant interaction and unbreakable
communion with it, and is ultimately controlled by it.
These opposing conceptions of the object-subject relationship are reflected in
the conflict between the two philosophies on the nature of the individual and the
individual’s connections with the surrounding world. The category of the isolated
individual is central in existentialism. The true existence of a person, it asserts, is
thwarted by things and other people. These external forces crush the personality and
drag it down to their own impersonal and commonplace level.
The individual can attain genuine value only in contest with these external
relationships. We must turn inward and explore the recesses of our being in order to
arrive at our real selves and real freedom. Only at the bottom of the abyss where the
naked spirit grapples with the fearful foreknowledge of death are both the senselessness
and the significance of existence revealed to us.
Thus existentialism pictures the individual as essentially divorced from other
humans, at loggerheads with an inert and hostile environment, and pitted against a
coercive society. This desolation of the individual is the wellspring of inconsolable
tragedy. Having cut off the individual from organic unity with the rest of reality, from
the regular operation of natural processes and the play of historical forces, existentialism
is thereafter unable to fit the subjective reactions and reflections of the personality to
the environing conditions of life. Indeed, says Sartre, our attempts to make
consciousness coincide with “facticity”, the world of things, are a futile business.
By a grim paradox, the solitary human mind is completely sovereign in shaping its
real existence. With nothing but its own forces to lean on and its own judgment as a
guide, it must confront and solve all the problems of life.
Existentialism is the most thoroughgoing philosophy of individualism in our time.
“Be yourself at all costs!” is its first commandment. It champions the spontaneity of
the individual menaced by the mass, the class, the state. It seeks to safeguard the
dignity, rights, initiatives, even the vagaries of the autonomous personality against
any oppressive authority, organised movement, or established institution.
With individual liberty as its watchword and supreme good, existentialism is a
creed of nonconformism. “I came to regard it as my task to create difficulties
everywhere”, wrote Kierkegaard in describing how he turned to an existentialist view
of life. The existentialists are averse to routine, externally imposed ideas, or disciplined
modes of behaviour, and whatever is uncongenial to the desires of the ego. All
Marxism Versus Existentialism 175
submission to projects not freely chosen is evidence of bad faith, says Sartre.
The targets of existentialism’s protest are as diversified as the interests and
inclinations of its exponents. These have ranged from religious orthodoxies to
philosophical systematising, from capitalist exploitation to Stalinist regimentation,
from bourgeois morality to workers’ bureaucratism. Kierkegaard set about to disturb
the peace of mind of the hypocritical Danish middle class. Nietzsche heralded the
superman who was to rise above the herdlike crowd and transcend good and evil. The
favoured heroes of Camus and Sartre are rebels and outsiders. Simone de Beauvoir
and Sartre analyse writers such as the Marquis de Sade and Jean Genet, whose ideas
and lives have outrageously flouted the ordinary canons of moral conduct.
It must be said that the heresies of the existentialists do not always succeed in
shedding completely the values of the society they rebel against. Kierkegaard assailed
the sluggishness and self-deception of the smug citizens around him only to embrace
the Christian God with more passionate intensity. And Sartre, who attacks stuffed
shirts and stinkers for their egotism, clings to the concept of the totally free person
beholden solely to himself as the pivot of his philosophy and moral theory.
Existentialism proclaims the urge of the individual to develop without hindrance.
But its constitutional aversion to the organised action of mass movements determined
by historically given circumstances renders it incapable of finding an effective solution
of this problem for the bulk of humanity. That is why it is nonconformist rather than
revolutionary.
Historical materialism takes an entirely different approach to the relationship
between individual and environment. We are essentially social beings; we develop
into individuals only in and through society. For Marxists, the isolated individual is
an abstraction. All distinctive things about humans, from toolmaking, speech, and
thought to the latest triumphs of art and technology, are products of our collective
activity over the past million years or so.
Take away from the person all the socially conditioned and historically acquired
attributes derived from the culture of the collectivity and little would be left but the
biological animal. The specific nature of the individual is determined by the social
content of the surrounding world. This shapes not only our relations with other
people but our innermost emotions, imagination, and ideas.
Even the special kind of solitude felt by people today is an outgrowth of the social
system. One of the major contradictions of capitalism is that it has brought humans
into the closest “togetherness” while accentuating conditions that pull them apart.
Capitalism socialises the labour process and knits the whole world into a unit while
separating people from one another through the divisive interests of private property
176 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
and competition. Frederick Engels noted this when he described the crowds in the
London streets in his first work, The Condition of the Working Class in England in
1844: “This isolation of the individual, this narrow self-seeking, is the fundamental
principle of our society everywhere … The dissolution of mankind into monads, of
which each has a separate principle, the world of atoms, is here carried out to its
utmost extreme.” The “barbarous indifference, hard egotism and nameless misery”
which he observed over a century ago still strongly permeate our acquisitive society.
Like the existentialists, the socialist movement has made one of its chief aims and
persistent concerns the defence and expansion of individuality — however much this
has been violated in practice by bureaucratic powers speaking in the name of socialism.
But Marxism differs from existentialism by denying that individualism as a philosophy
can provide an adequate method of social change and political action. Since the social
structure shapes and dominates the lives of individuals, it has to be transformed by
the collective struggle of the working people in order to eliminate the conditions that
repress individuality and create an environment suited to the unhampered cultivation
of the capacities of each living human being.
the extent that verified scientific knowledge enables us to control and change the
world around us. The existentialist demand for absolute personal freedom does not
correspond to anything real or realisable. People must act under the constraint of their
conditions of life and cannot cast off their causal weight.
Human activity is an unequal synthesis of extrinsic determination and self-
determination. People react consciously and vigorously to their environment and
take initiatives to alter certain aspects of it. The measure of control exercised by the
objective and subjective components of the causal process changes and develops in
the course of time according to the growth of our mastery over nature and society.
History has proceeded, by and large, toward greater freedom, toward a growth in our
ability to decide and direct an increasing number of activities.
The existentialists regard determinism as an inveterate foe of human aims and
aspirations. In reality, determinism can display either a hostile or friendly face to us,
depending upon the given circumstances. Humans became free in this century to
travel through the atmosphere for the first time and even to leave this planet. This was
achieved by finding out the principles of aerodynamics and propulsion and then
utilising them to construct the instruments to realise the aim of flight. In making
aircraft we have succeeded in putting the determinism of the material world to work for
us, rather than against us.
The same is true of social determinism. People have been enabled to enlarge their
freedom not by ignoring and rejecting the determinants of history but by recognising
them and acting in accord with their requirements. The American people acquired and
extended their liberties by seeing the need for abolishing British domination and
Southern slaveholding when national progress demanded such revolutionary deeds.
Far from being incompatible with freedom, as the existentialist thinks, natural and
social necessities are the indispensable foundation of all the freedoms we have.
The existentialists, however, are more concerned about the narrower dilemmas of
personal responsibility than with the broader problem of the interaction of freedom
and necessity in social and historical evolution. Both existentialism and Marxism
agree that our conduct has to be regulated and judged by relative human standards.
We are accountable only to ourselves and for ourselves, and have no right to sanctify
or justify our decisions by reference to any supernatural source.
What, then, is the basis of morality? Where do our standards of right and wrong
come from? The ethics of existentialism is uncompromisingly libertarian. We create
both ourselves and our morality through our utterly uncurbed choices. Authentic
freedom manifests itself in the causeless selection among alternative possibilities and
fulfils itself in the deliberate adoption of one’s own set of values.
178 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
The Marxist theory of morality does not rest upon an inborn capacity of the
individual to make unconditioned and unmotivated choices but upon historical and
social considerations. Its position can be summarised as follows: 1. Morality has an
objective basis in the conditions, relations, needs, and development of society. Its
rational character is derived from a correspondence with given historical realities and
an understanding of specific social necessities. 2. Morality has a variable content and
a relative character, depending upon changes, in social circumstances. 3. Under
civilisation to date, morality inescapably takes on a class character. 4. There are no
absolute standards of moral behaviour and judgment. Human acts are not good or
had, praiseworthy or iniquitous, in themselves. All moral codes and conduct must be
evaluated by reference to the prevailing conditions and the concrete social needs,
class interests, and historical aims they serve.
The rival theories of morality are put to a test in cases which pose conflicting lines
of action. The philosophical and literary works of the existentialists concentrate upon
such “either-or” situations. To accept God or reject Him. To join one side rather than
the other. To turn traitor or remain loyal to one’s comrades. To live or die.
Existentialism insists that there cannot be any sufficient and compelling grounds
within the situation itself, the individual’s connections with it, or the person’s own
character to warrant choosing one rather than the other of mutually exclusive
alternatives. Humans, says Sartre, are the beings through whom nothingness enters
the world. This power of negation is most forcefully expressed in our perfect liberty to
do what we please in defiance of all external circumstances. The exercise of fully
conscious, uninhibited preference distinguishes people from animals and one person
from another. “By their choices shall ye know them.”
The historical materialists reply that, while we can make choices in situations
permitting real alternatives — that is the crux of personal morality — these decisions
are not made in a void. Making up one’s mind about the possibilities of a confusing or
conflicting situation is only a part of the total process of moral action.
Voluntary acts are links in a chain of events beginning with objective circumstances
and ending with objective consequences. The given situation, personal character,
motivation, decision, action and results form a continuity of phases which are lawfully
connected and feed back upon one another. The uniqueness of individual choice
does not consist in its self-sufficiency or release from essential relations with other
facts, but in contributing its special quality of approval or dissent, collaboration or
resistance, to them.
The existentialists deny any causal ties between the psychological act of choice
and the circumstances in which it takes place.
Marxism Versus Existentialism 179
They sheer away the moment of personal decision from all that precedes and
follows it, from the environing conditions, motivations, and consequences of human
action. However, there is no empirical evidence that choice occurs apart from and
unaffected by the totality of concurrent conditions; this is a purely metaphysical
assumption.
In fact, the power of choice is far from unlimited. A multitude of social, historical,
and biographical factors enter into the process of moral determination. The real
opportunities open to the individual are restricted by natural and social history, by
the forces operating in a particular situation and the trends of their development.
These provide objective criteria which make it possible to ascertain beforehand whether
one alternative is preferable to another, or, after the fact, whether one was better than
another. Moreover, the individual is predisposed, though not predestined, by previous
experiences and existing connections to take one path rather than another. Otherwise
human behaviour would be completely unpredictable.
The highest good in the existentialist scale of values is personal sincerity, which
is certified by devotion to a freely chosen object of faith. This psychological quality,
which is considered the most powerful manifestation of freedom, is the sole principle
of moral worth. The feelings of the autonomous individual determine what is right or
wrong in any given case.
Marxists judge actions to be good or bad not according to the intentions or
emotions of the agents, but by their correspondence with social and class needs and
their service to historical aims. They are considered justified or unjustified to the
extent that they help or hinder progress toward the goals of socialism. Good deeds
must be judged by their consequences. They must actually lead to increasing our
command over nature and to diminishing social evils.
succeeded through its own titanic efforts in elevating itself from animality to the
atomic age — and is just on the threshold of its authentically human career.
This belief in the rationality of social evolution and in the necessity of the socialist
revolution to usher in the next stage of human progress is the theoretical source of the
optimism which suffuses scientific socialism. Marxism points to the historical
achievements recorded in humanity’s rise over the past million years and incorporated
in the accumulated knowledge, skills, and acquisitions of world culture as tangible
proofs of the worth of human work and as a pledge of the future.
The indomitable struggles for a better life among the downtrodden, the “wretched
of the earth”, the key role of the industrial workers in modern economy, the successes
of the first experiments in nationalised property and planned economy even under
extremely adverse conditions, give confidence to Marxists that the most difficult
problems of our age are susceptible of solution through the methods of proletarian-
peasant revolution and socialist reconstruction.
As in the past, many surprises, setbacks, disappointments, and detours will be
encountered en route. These are part of the price exacted by the fact that we have to
climb and sometimes crawl upward unaided by anything but our own collective efforts.
Yet every great social and political revolution has added new stature and power to
humankind despite the pains and even disenchantments attending it. The offspring
of history have been worth the agonies of birth and the difficulties of their upbringing.
the masses of direct producers lose control over their lives, their liberties, and their
means of development, which are at the mercy of hostile social forces. This is obvious
under slavery, which was the first organised system of alienated labour. The alienation
of labour is far more complex and refined under capitalism, where it attains ultimate
expression.
The wage workers are subjected to uncontrollable external forces at every step of
capitalist economy. Having none of the material prerequisites of production, they
must go to work for their owners. Even before physically participating in production,
they surrender their labour power to the entrepreneur in return for the payment of the
prevailing wage. While at work, the conditions and duration of the job are determined
by the capitalist and his foremen. As men and women on the assembly line can testify,
workers become degraded into mere physical accessory factors of production. Instead
of intelligently exercising their capacities, they are constrained to perform monotonous,
repetitious tasks which strain their endurance. The plan, process, and aim of production
all confront them as hostile and hurtful powers.
At the end of the industrial process the product does not belong to the workers
who made it but to the capitalist who bought their labour power. It goes into the
market to be sold. There the masses of commodities and money function like an
untameable force which even the biggest groups of capitalists cannot control, as the
fluctuations of the business cycle and periodic crises demonstrate.
On top of this, the competitiveness of capitalism pits the members of all classes
against one another and generates unbridled egotism and self-seeking. The members
of bourgeois society, whatever their status, are immersed in an atmosphere of rivalry
rather than communal solidarity.
Thus the alienations within capitalism come from the contradictory relations of its
mode of production and the class antagonisms and competitive conditions engendered
by them. The divisions rooted in the economic foundations of capitalism branch out
into all aspects of social life. They appear in the collisions of class interests and
outlooks on a national and international scale, in the opposition of monopolist-
dominated governments to the mass of the people, in the struggle of the creative artist
against commercialism, in the contrast between metropolitan slums and ghettos and
luxury apartments and hotels, in the subordination of science to militarism, and in
myriad other ways. Its cruelest and sharpest large-scale expression today in the United
States is the deep-going estrangement between the Black people and the whites.
These stigmata mangle human personalities, injure health, stamp out the chance
of happiness. They produce many of the mental and emotional disturbances which
make up the psychopathology of everyday life in the acquisitive society.
184 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
aims and activities, but only when one awakens to the full implications of one’s doom.
Most people try to shut out this awful awareness by cowardly evasion. The ordinary
citizen becomes immersed in everyday activities and distracting pleasures, the artist
in creative work, the philosopher in spinning cobwebs of thought. These are nothing
but diversions and illusions so long as the individual refuses to confront the realisation
of eventual annihilation with unflinching and complete consciousness.
Death is the foundation of morality and liberation because it compels each of us to
decide whether life is worthwhile and what to do with it. Every act of moral choice is
literally a life-and-death matter. All the freely created values of life are stacked up
against the overwhelming prospect of death.
Heidegger declares that death is the only thing nobody else can do for me. If we
embrace our finitude, our being-for-death, we internalise it and integrate it into the
totality of our existence and thus give it meaning. To Sartre, on the other hand, death
is a meaningless external fact, a limit that cannot be interiorised in the sum total of our
lives. The consciousness of death does not make us human. It merely heightens our
individuality by prodding us to decide in defiance of conventional values. “The
choice that each of us has made of his life was an authentic choice because it was
made face to face with death”, he says.
For Heidegger death gives life all meaning; for Sartre it removes all meaning from
life. These opposing evaluations show how difficult it is to extract a common position
from the existentialists. But, despite the extreme variations in their answers to this
problem, the terrifying shock of the recognition of death overshadows their reflections
on the meaning and worth of life.
The Marxist approach is more in accord with the humanist mainstream. It is the
first law of nature — as well as dialectical materialism — that everything has its day
and then must perish. Nothing and no one is immune from this law. The processes of
life and death emerged on this planet as the result of new biochemical reactions
several billion years ago. Humankind is the highest product of this development.
Is life worth living? And if so, how should the inevitable approach and advent of
death be met? Marxism replies to the first question with a ringing affirmative. No
matter what the toil, turmoil, and pain of personal and social experience, life is the
supreme value for humankind. Not life as it is but life as liberated humanity will make
and remake it. The paramount practical-moral aim of socialism is to improve the quality
of life without limit. By increasing humanity’s power over nature, and decreasing the
power of one person over another, a boundless potential of happiness and creative
achievement can be released from generation to generation.
The prospect of our own death and the death of others we love and admire often
186 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
causes anguish and sorrow. Such grief is a normal sentiment among civilised people
and is morbid only when it becomes obsessive. The dread of death is not the primal
and central fact of human existence, an eternal attendant of the human condition, as
the existential metaphysicians contend. It is a historically conditioned psychological
reaction. Many primitive peoples do not experience it.
Excessive preoccupation with death belongs to the psychopathology of
civilisation. The malfunctioning and disproportionate wearing out of our bodies, the
multiple insecurities, disorders, stresses, sufferings, and alienations of a crisis-ridden,
class-divided society make life difficult and burdensome. Paradoxically, for all their
hysterical fear of death many people desperately welcome and even hasten the ending
of a too hard life.
The socialist movement aspires to transform and eventually eradicate such
attitudes and feelings by changing the conditions of life and labour for all. The
remodelling of humanity must begin with the transformation of social relations from
antagonism into cooperation, with its ever-enlarging possibilities of satisfying human
desires. But it will not stop there. The scientists of the future, in teamwork with highly
conscious individuals, will plan to reshape the physiological side of life and
subordinate that to the control of reason and will. Biology and medicine will ease the
processes of birth and postpone the incidence of death. The coming biological-social
type of human will manifest a new psychology in which, among other things, people
will no longer have reason to dread death. So long as it cannot be indefinitely put off
or averted, the end of living will be greeted not as a frightful calamity, but as the
ransom of time.
The existentialist displacement of the seat of value from life to death reflects both
the ordeals of our age and a loss of vitality among sensitive souls who despair of
triumphing over the dark and destructive forces of a sick social order. On the other
hand, a lust for life, conscious participation in the collective struggle for a better
world, and an indestructible confidence in the real possibilities of unbounded progress
characterise the working class humanism projected by Marxism. It is intent on making
life what it could and should be — a serene and splendid adventure for all members of
the human family.
fails to recognise what to them is the most meaningful aspect of being: the sovereign
subjectivity and dignity of the individual. They maintain that materialist theory debases
people to mere objects while socialist practice stamps out personal freedom.
Orthodox Marxists no less firmly insist that the contending philosophies have far
too many principled differences to be welded into one.
In between stand a variegated group who agree with Sartre that the two can be
fused into a single alloy that will reinforce both. In the United States the noted
psychoanalytical sociologist Erich Fromm is the most ardent champion of the thesis
that existentialism and Marxism are substantially identical. In Marx’s Concept of Man
(1961), which presents Fromm’s concept of Marx, he asserts that Marx’s thinking is
humanist existentialism. The doctrines appear alike to him since both protest against
the alienation in modern society and seek ways to overcome it. “Marx’s philosophy”,
he writes, “constitutes a spiritual existentialism in secular language and because of
this spiritual quality is opposed to the materialistic practice and thinly disguised
materialistic philosophy of our age. Marx’s aim, socialism, based on his theory of man,
is essentially prophetic Messianism in the language of the 19th century.”
This transmutation of the materialist Marx into a precursor and preacher of
existentialism is typical of radical humanists of very different backgrounds and beliefs;
Fromm is their chief American representative They locate the “true” Marx in the early
Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, which mark transitional stages of
his development, instead of in the ripe conclusions of his mature thoughts. They
contend that Marx has been misrepresented as a crude dialectical materialist by his
orthodox disciples from Engels to Lenin — until the radical humanists revealed that
he really was an ethical existentialist.
Fromm’s equation of dialectical materialism with existentialism is as ill-founded as
his astonishing statement that “Marx’s atheism is the most advanced form of rational
mysticism”. The atheistic Marx is no more a mystic than the Marx of scientific socialism
is an existentialist.
Ever since socialism became a powerful movement and Marxism its dominant
ideology, attempts have been made to disqualify the dialectical and materialist
principles of its method in favour of a different theoretical basis. At various times and
places Kantianism, ethical idealism, positivism, pragmatism and even Thomism have
been nominated as replacements. None of these proposed supplements and substitutes
(or their eclectic combinations) have proved convincing or viable. The Marxist system
has such an integrated structure, from its philosophical and logical premises to its
political economy and historical outlook, that it cannot easily be chopped up and
recombined with other theories.
188 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
Sartrean existentialism is the latest and most popular candidate for the office of
eking out the real or alleged deficiencies of Marxist thought. It is unlikely to be more
successful than its predecessors.
The existentialists aver that the individual’s sincerest act and tragic responsibility
is the necessity to choose between anguishing alternatives and take the consequences.
Sartre shrinks from doing this in philosophy. The confrontation of existentialism with
dialectical materialism is a genuine case of “either-or.” But Sartre wants to embrace
both Kierkegaard and Marx without choosing between them.
“To the marriage of true minds, let us admit no impediment”, Shakespeare said.
The trouble is that dialectical materialism and existentialism are contrary-minded and
oriented along diametrically different lines. They clash at almost every point on the
major issues of philosophy, sociology, morality, and politics. It is a pointless task to
try to mate these opposites.
This has not — and will not — deter either radical-minded existentialists or socialist
eclectics from trying to coalesce the one with the other. The controversy between the
philosophers of existence and the dialectical materialists, as well as those who mix the
two, has steadily expanded its area over the last two decades. It is still in full swing
and far from concluded.
The first commandment of existentialism is, as has been said: “Be yourself!” This
is not a bad maxim, and it ought to be applied as strictly to philosophies as to
personalities. Let existentialism be what it really is — the ideological end product of
liberalism and individualism — and not pretend to be something else. Let Marxism
likewise be what it should be: that dialectical materialism which is the scientific
expression and practical guide of the world socialist revolution of the working masses.
But let not the two be intermixed and confused. Their mismating can produce only
stillborn offspring, whether in philosophy or in politics.
IS NATURE DIALECTICAL?
consistent materialism. This position has been put forward by quite a number of
Marxists and semi-Marxists. Such is the view taken by the existentialists Sartre and
Hyppolite.
The third position is that dialectical materialism deals with the entire universe and
its logic holds good for all the constituent sectors of reality which enter into human
experience: nature, society, and thought. The laws of dialectics, which have arisen out
of the investigation of universal processes of becoming and modes of being, apply to
all phenomena. Although each level of being has its own specific laws, these merge
with general laws covering all spheres of existence and development, which constitute
the content and shape the method of materialist dialectics. This view, held by the
creators of scientific socialism and their authentic disciples, was defended in the
debate by Garaudy, Vigier, and the chairman, Jean Orcel, professor of mineralogy at
the National Museum of Natural History.
An American would consider it strange that the controversy on the question
should take place only between two schools of dialecticians, one piecemeal, the other
thoroughgoing. Very few people in the United States today are convinced that
dialectical logic of any kind is worth serious consideration.
A broad spectrum of attitudes toward Marxism is exhibited in the Soviet Union,
the United States, and France. In the US, where capitalism reigns supreme, anything
associated with socialism and communism is depreciated, if not tabooed. Marxism is
regarded as obsolete, its philosophy false.
In the Soviet Union, where the socialist revolution abolished capitalism decades
ago, dialectical materialism is the state philosophy. Under Stalin, in fact, it became
scholasticised and ossified, as Vigier admits and Hyppolite testifies. The latter tells
how during a recent visit the Soviet Academy of Sciences contrived to have him talk
to the students about mechanism instead of existentialism, as he wished. However, all
the questions after his lecture related to existentialism. “It seems to me that the youth
were strongly interested in Sartre’s existential philosophy”, he dryly observes.
The intellectual and political climate of France stands between those of the major
cold war antagonists. There is lively tension and continual intercourse between Marxist
and non-Marxist currents of thought, and especially between the politically oriented
atheistic existentialists such as Sartre, and various exponents of Marxism. Sartre and
C. Wright Mills reflect the ideological differences between their two countries. Mills
held a place among radical intellectuals in the English-speaking world like that of
Sartre in Europe. Yet in his last work, The Marxists, Mills dismissed the laws of
dialectics as something “mysterious, which Marx never explains clearly but which his
disciples claim to use”. Indeed, even this footnote reference was an afterthought
Is Nature Dialectical? 191
movement.
3. We can know society and history from the inside, as they really are, because
they are the work of humanity, the result of our decision and action. Their dialectical
linkages are disclosed through the contradictory interplay of subject and situation.
But physical phenomena remain external to us and to other objects. They are opaque
to our insight. We cannot penetrate to their real inner nature and grasp their essence.
In sum, nature must be nondialectical because of its disunity, its lack of
contradiction, its insurmountable externality and inertia. The only possible dialectical
materialism is historical materialism, which views our establishment of relations with
the rest of reality from the standpoint of our action upon it.
Orthodox Marxists revert to theology and metaphysics, says Sartre, by extending
dialectical laws over nature on purely philosophical or methodological grounds. He
does, however, concede that dialectical laws may at some point be found applicable to
nature. But only by way of analogy. This presently involves a risky extrapolation,
which must await verification through further findings by the natural scientists. And
even if they should discover that physical processes resemble the dialectical type
and start to use dialectical models in their research, this would provide no insight into
the nature of nature, no true knowledge of its essential features.
Thus the existentialist Sartre turns out to be a positivist in his last word on the
possible relations of dialectics to the physical world. For him the ideas of this logic
can be no more than handy hypotheses in metaphorical dress that may help scientists
order and clarify their data but cannot reflect the content of nature.
Sartre is not consistent in his effort to imprison dialectics in the social world and
strike it out of prehuman and nonhuman phenomena. His arguments against the
dialectics of nature are more fully set forth in his 1960 philosophical work of 755
pages, Critique of Dialectical Reason, of which the first part was published here in
1963 under the title Search for a Method. There he admits that living matter, at least,
may develop dialectically. Sartre writes: “The organism engenders the negative as
that which disrupts its unity; disassimilation and excretion are still opaque and biological
forms of negation in so far as they are a movement oriented toward rejection.” This
exception opens a breach in his position. Garaudy correctly observes that once Sartre
has recognised that negation and totalisation exist in the prehuman state, it will be
difficult to stop halfway and keep dialectics confined to biology without extending its
jurisdiction to the rest of nature.
In his rejoinder to Sartre, who wishes to see only partial unities or specific totalities
in nature, Vigier points out that nature is a whole made up of myriad parts. The reality
of the universe we inhabit is both material and dialectical. Its unity is expressed in an
Is Nature Dialectical? 193
infinite series of levels of existence. Each of the specific realms of being which
collectively constitute the material universe is finite, partial; it incorporates only a
limited aspect of the whole.
In itself nature is endless and inexhaustible. It forever generates new properties,
modes, and fields of existence. There are no limits to what it has been, to what it now
is, to what it may become. One of the major errors of mechanical and metaphysical
thought about nature, Vigier says, is the notion that it is based upon ultimate elements
from which everything else issues and with which the rest of reality can be built up.
This conception, which goes back to the Greek atomists, has been carried forward by
the natural scientists who believed that molecules, atoms, and then “elementary”
particles were the basic building blocks of the entire universe.
Actually science has been developing along different lines, both in regard to the
universe at large (the macrocosm) and to the subatomic domain (the microcosm).
There is no foreseeable end to astronomical phenomena or our discovery of them, as
the recently discovered “black holes” indicate. What appears immobile on one level is
really in flux at another level. There are in principle no irreducible or immutable elements
in nature. This has just been reconfirmed by the acknowledgment that so-called
elementary particles can no longer be considered the ultimate objects of microphysics.
New microparticles keep turning up which reveal more profound movements and
antagonisms.
The history and practice of the sciences demonstrate that various totalities exist
in nature as well as in human history. Vigier points out that living organisms are
totalities which can be decomposed into finer totalities such as the giant molecules.
Farther afield, the earth, the solar system, our galaxy, and all galactic systems taken
together can be approached and analysed as totalities with a disregard for their detailed
fluctuations. The distinct totalities which are found all around us in nature are relative,
partial, and limited. Yet, far from negating the unity of nature, they constitute and
confirm it.
Experiments show that however complicated the biochemistry of life, its processes
are fundamentally the same from the algae to the human organism. We ourselves are
made of star-stuff. It has been ascertained that the universe has a common chemistry,
just as all the diverse forms of life on earth share similar biological laws. The same
elements that make up the earth and its inhabitants are present in the most remote
stellar regions.
The substantial unity of nature is asserted not only in its structural components,
but in its stages and modes of development. Science is rapidly filling in a vast panorama
of cosmic advancement. It is uncertain how the observable universe originated, if it
194 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
did at all. But it has certainly evolved — from the creation of the elements, the
constitution of the stellar galaxies, and other celestial phenomena to the birth of our
solar system and the formation of the earth’s crust and atmosphere. Then it proceeded
to the chemical conditions required for the primary reactions leading to the first forms
of life, on through the transformations of organic species, up to the advent of humanity.
All this has been climaxed by the birth and forward movement of society over the past
million-odd years.
This unified process of development is the real basis for the universality of the
dialectic, which maintains that everything is linked together and interactive, in
continuous motion and change, and that this change is the outcome of the conflicts
of opposing forces within nature as well as everything to be found in it.
To assert that everything is in the last analysis connected with everything else
does not nullify the relative autonomy of specific formations and singular things. But
the separation of one thing from another, its qualitative distinctions from everything
else, breaks down at a certain point in time and in space. So long as the opposing
forces are in balance the totality appears stable, harmonious, at rest — and is really
so. But this is a transient condition. Sooner or later, alterations in the inner relation of
forces, and interactions with other processes in the environment, upset the achieved
equilibrium, generate instability, and can eventuate in the disruption and destruction
of the most hard-and-fast formations. Dialectics is fundamentally the most consistent
way of thinking about the universal interconnections of things in the full range of
their development.
the unbreakable unity of the diverse levels of being. The farmer furrowing the soil
with an animal-drawn plough and seeding it brings together mineral, botanical,
zoological, and human forces in the unified process of producing food.
The inanimate, the animate, and the social belong to a single stream of material
existence and evolution with endless currents.
Are the oppositions in nature so radically different from contradictions in the life
of humanity as Sartre contends? Contradictions on every level of existence have their
peculiar characteristics, which must be found out in the course of practical experience
and formulated in scientific inquiry. The sociological law that as technology expands,
the productive forces of humankind tend to grow beyond and conflict with the relations
of production and the property forms in which they have been encased is very different
from Isaac Newton’s laws of motion.
Does this mean that physical and social processes have no common denominators?
Marxism maintains that general laws of being and becoming exist which allow both for
the identities and differences, the persistent and the changing, in the real world. They
embrace both nature and human life and are capable of expression as laws of logical
thought. Included in the inventory of the laws of dialectics are the interpenetration of
opposites, the passage of quantity into quality, the negation of the negation, the
conflict of form and content, and many others. They are as relevant to nature as to
society because they are rooted in the objective world.
Vigier observes that “internal antagonisms (that is to say, the assemblage of
forces which necessarily evolve in contrary directions) illustrate the nature of
contradiction … The unity of opposites is understood as the unity of elements on one
level which engenders the phenomena of a higher level. The transformation of quantity
into quality is interpreted as the sudden rupture of equilibrium within a system (for
example, the destruction of one of the antagonistic forces), which modifies the
equilibrium and gives rise to a qualitatively new phenomenon in the midst of which
new contradictions appear.”
Vigier cites the advances of modern physics as evidence of the intrinsically
contradictory properties of analysed systems, which contain simplicity and complexity,
inertia and violent motion at one and the same time. “The material elements considered
inert at one level, for example the macroscopic bodies described by classical physics,
are revealed upon analysis to be prodigiously complex and mobile as scientific
knowledge progresses. On our scale this table can appear to me inert, but we know it
is composed of molecules in extremely complex and violent motion. These molecules
themselves can be decomposed into mobile atoms when I push analysis much further.
Finally, the atoms themselves split into so-called ‘elementary particles’ which in their
196 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
forever incomplete.
This is true of the dialectics of nature as well. It is not imposed a priori or wilfully
upon nature, as Sartre charges. It represents the verified conclusions, the systematic
formulations of practical experience, scientific investigation, and critical thought
extending from Heraclitus to Hegel. Like other theoretical acquisitions, it is projected
into the future as a guide to further inquiry into concrete reality.
But if Marxism has discarded the passive, oversimplified, and nonevolutionary
versions of the thought process held by previous schools of materialism from Epicurus
to the 18th-century sensationalists, it asserts with them that conceptual reflection
does bring out and define the essential qualities and relations of things. Nature is
prior to consciousness. There is an internal bond between what exists and what is
known — and even how it is known. The order of ideas, as Benedict Spinoza said,
does correspond with the order of things.
Hyppolite makes two charges against the Marxist interpretation of dialectics. On
the one hand it aims to make nature historical by importing dialectical laws into it, and
on the other it tries to “naturise” history by subjecting it to the same laws as the
physical world. He wishes to keep history and nature in totally separate compartments.
This is alien to reality. Nature is through and through historical. Vigier emphasises
how, “proceeding from the history of biology and the human sciences, the idea of
evolution has step by step invaded the whole of the sciences: after astronomy it is
today breaking through into chemistry and physics … This idea of history, of evolution,
of analysis in terms of development is for us precisely the profound logical root of the
dialectics of nature. It can even be said that in a sense all scientific progress is being
achieved along the line of abandoning static descriptions for the sake of dynamic
analyses combining the intrinsic properties of the analysed phenomena. For us, science
progresses from Cuvier to Darwin, from the static to the dynamic, from formal logic to
dialectical logic.”
Nature and society form two parts of a single historical process. But they are
basically different, contradictory parts. Other living beings have history made for
them; we make our own history.
Animals depend upon the available food and other features of their environment
for survival; they cannot alter or discard their specialised organs and ways of life to
cope with sudden changes. Entire species can perish when their habitats change too
rapidly and radically. Humans, on the other hand, are not subjected to any particular
environment or mode of adaptation. We can adjust to new conditions, meet changes,
and even institute them by inventing new tools and techniques and producing what
we need.
Is Nature Dialectical? 199
Up to now social development has carried over certain traits of natural development
because by and large it has proceeded in an unconscious and uncontrolled manner.
The course of society has been determined not by human purposes, but by the
unintended results of the operation of the productive forces. But human history has
reached the point where it can discard its blind automatism and enter an entirely
different type of development. By discovering the laws of social development and
collectively acting upon them, we can take control of society and consciously plan its
further growth.
work of the group, first in the struggle against nature, then in the conflict of classes.
Subjective components of the whole — such as individual psychology — which so
preoccupy the existentialists, are integral and subordinate elements of this objective
historical process and derive their validity and significance from it.
In the reciprocal relationship whereby human practice transforms and masters the
environment, nature retains existential priority, however much this offends the
subjectivity of the existentialist philosopher.
The origin of human practice itself requires explanation. The distinctive activities
that have separated humanity from the animal condition originated with the using and
making of tools and weapons to obtain the means of subsistence. But this new kind of
activity, which is at the foundation of society, grew out of natural processes which
antedate human practice by billions of years.
In the evolutionary scale, animal activity preceded human practice, which was a
qualitatively new offshoot of it. When the first fish developed lungs, came to live on
dry land, and converted themselves into amphibians, that was a dialectical change in
organic nature. Through the natural mechanisms of the evolution of species, the fish,
to use Sartre’s language, “objectified himself” into something else.
The dialectics of human history grew out of this dialectics of nature. It originated
in the conversion of the early primate into the human, the most meaningful of all the
contradictory developments of matter. The elevation of humanity above animality
was the greatest rupture in the continuity of nature’s evolution. The qualitative
disjunction between us and other species is so deepgoing that Sartre takes it as the
ground for excluding dialectics from nature.
He is here baffled by a genuine contradiction. Human beings are both creatures of
nature and a departure from it. When the human is low-rated as nothing but a high-
grade animal, different in degree but not in kind from other living beings, the essential
and distinctive nature of humanity is obliterated. Human life, which stems from the
production of the means of subsistence by tools and weapons, is something radically
new compared with the animal foraging for food. The labour process is the beginning
of society and provides the platform for the dialectical movement of history.
Fundamental changes in the organisation of this labour process are the decisive
steps in the further advancement of humanity.
But the processes which humanised our primate ancestors were both a prolongation
of brute nature and a level above and beyond it. Just as there is both continuity and
discontinuity in the transition from ape to human, so there is comparable continuity
and discontinuity between the dialectics of nature and that of history. The dialectics
of nature has different forms and proceeds according to different laws than the
Is Nature Dialectical? 201
This ringing affirmation will appear bizarre to Anglo-American scientists who may
respect Vigier for his work as a physicist. They summarily disqualify dialectical logic
on the ground that, whatever its philosophical or political interest, it has no value in
promoting any endeavour in natural science. If the method is valid, the antidialecticians
say, then purposeful application by its proponents should prove capable of producing
important new theories and practical results in other fields than the social. Marxists
are challenged to cite instances where the dialectical method has actually led to new
discoveries and not simply demonstrated after the fact that specific scientific findings
conform to the generalisations of dialectical logic.
The most splendid contribution of this kind in recent decades has been Oparin’s
theories on the origin of life, which are widely accepted and have stimulated fruitful
work on the problems of biogenesis and genetics. The Soviet scientist’s theory is
based on the hypothesis that the random formation and interaction of increasingly
complex molecules gave rise to the simplest forms of living matter, which then began
to reproduce at the expense of the surrounding organic material.
Oparin consciously employed such principles of materialist dialectics as the
transformation of quantity into quality, the interruption of continuity (evolution by
leaps), and the conversion of chance fluctuations into regular processes and definite
properties of matter, to initiate an effective new line of approach to one of the central
problems of science: How did inanimate nature generate life on earth? Such cases
would undoubtedly multiply if more practicing scientists were better informed about
the Marxist method of thought.
The imperative political conclusion is that the representatives of the money power
in the United States must be prevented from pressing the button which can doom us
all, as was nearly done in the 1962 missile crisis over Cuba. Capitalism is the last form
of socioeconomic organisation dominated by laws which operate in an ungovernable
way, like laws of nature. The aim of scientific socialism, the task of the proletarian
world revolution, is to subdue all the anarchic forces tied up with capitalism which
generate insecurity and havoc in our society. The blind drives of class society have
pushed humanity to the brink of extinction. Conscious understanding and application
of the dialectical laws of evolution — and revolution — can help save us.
Only through public ownership and operation of the economy and democratic
direction of state policy can the working people introduce scientific enlightenment
into the material foundations of life, overthrow the last entrenchment of automatism in
social evolution, and clear the way for the rule of reason in all human affairs.
the world, and would destroy the objectivity of our knowledge and thus our ability to
act. Sartre’s position, as described in your article — that humans can never attain to the
“reality” of things, that our knowledge and the laws of our (dialectical) logic apply
only to humanity and society, etc. — sounds like that of a resuscitated Kant.
It can only lead to a divided world-view, a denial of the possibility of true knowledge
and, ultimately, to excesses of subjectivity rather than creative activity. The
existentialists may begin their philosophic inquiry from the standpoint of the individual,
but that does not mean that they can stop there without losing sight of the essential
thing — that we are in and of the world.
The points made by Vigier and Garaudy were, I felt, an excellent rebuttal to Sartre
and Hyppolite. There is one point in your article, however, with which I would take
some exception. That is when you argue against the antidialecticians by pointing out
the advances made in science, especially by Oparin, through the use of dialectical
method. Dialectical logic may help the scientist reach some useful hypotheses for later
investigation, but this is not the essential point here.
It seems to me that the method or means by which scientific discoveries are made
is secondary in this argument. What is really vital is the fact that only a dialectical view
of nature can provide an adequate framework in which these new discoveries can be
seen in their total relationship. That is, how one gets to the discovery is not so
important as the realisation that this new “fact” can only be thoroughly explained and
related to the rest of our knowledge through a dialectical viewpoint.
There is one other point that seems appropriate to this discussion: I read recently
that Roger Garaudy was to write an introduction to a Russian translation of Pierre
Teilhard de Chardin’s Phenomenon of Man. Now Teilhard certainly is not a dialectical
materialist in any sense of the word. However, beneath the theological portion of his
thought, one finds a view of evolution that is certainly dialectical — in a Hegelian, if
not a Marxist, sense. And Teilhard’s work seems to have been a little too “materialistic”
for the Roman Catholic church.
Teilhard’s work in itself deserves study, but simply in connection with the question
of the dialectics of nature, it seems to me that it may be a sign that we are approaching
a higher synthesis of thought. The static conceptions of “idealism” and “materialism”
may give way to a newer, more adequate realisation of their interdependence throughout
the whole sphere of nature. That can only be achieved if we recognise the objective
character of dialectics — that it applies to nature as well as to history. The perpetuation
of alienation between “mind” and “matter”, humanity and the world, nature and history,
can serve no good purpose, but only leads to fragmentation and confusion in philosophy
and action.
Is Nature Dialectical? 205
Dialectics by its nature has to be an “open” system which not only allows for the
addition of new knowledge but also admits our freedom and ability to shape history.
The recognition of nature as dialectical is the only way to a whole world-view that
includes humanity in the world while recognising our unique position and frees us to
control our own future. Your article is an excellent statement of the issues and their
importance, and I hope it will precipitate in this country a greater appreciation of the
problem and wide discussion of it.
Yvonne Groseil
Here are some comments on the main questions of theoretical interest raised by
this friendly comment.
1. Would knowledge of the method of the materialist dialectic, which is based on
the most general laws of being and becoming, assist physical scientists in their
investigations of nature?
Up to now almost all scientists have carried on their work without conscious
understanding of the dialectical laws of universal development, just as most people
speak very well without knowing the history or grammar of their language, breathe
without awareness of the physiological processes of respiration, and acquire the
necessities of life without comprehending the principles of political economy.
Western philosophers and scientists almost unanimously believe that the dialectical
view of nature is false, irrelevant, and even positively harmful in the theory and
practice of science. This prejudice, rooted in our predominantly empirical and positivist
intellectual traditions, has been reinforced by the arbitrary and ignorant interference
of the Stalinist bureaucrats with scientific theory, along with their narrowly schematic,
distorted, and dogmatic interpretation of Marxist method.
This correspondent has a more favourable attitude toward the dialectical
conception of nature. But she suggests that it may be far less important in facilitating
progress in physical science than it is for explaining and correlating its discoveries
after they have been made.
Such a one-sided emphasis runs the risk of lapsing into the very Kantian dualism
which she correctly criticises in the case of the existentialists. What are here involved
are the organic connections between the unity of reality, the sum total of our knowledge,
and the scientific inquiry which shuttles from one to the other. If the dialectical method
can be useful in clarifying the relationships of the knowledge of nature once it has
been acquired, why cannot it be equally valuable in helping scientists to arrive at
verified results? After all, the dialectical characteristics which are disclosed in the
body of known facts must already have existed and been effective in the objective
realities from which they have been derived.
206 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
If scientists should approach the problems for which they seek solutions in their
particular fields with an informed understanding of the fundamental traits of
development formulated in the laws of dialectical logic, why couldn’t these serve as a
general methodological guide in their concrete inquiries?
In fact, the most creative scientists have assumed the truth of this or that rule of
dialectical logic in conducting their work, although they have done so in a piecemeal,
haphazard, semiconscious manner. Without referring to past examples, let’s take the
many non-Marxist scientists around the world who are cooperating with Oparin in
studying the specific steps by which the most elementary processes and mechanisms
of life have emerged from inanimate matter. Unlike him, they pay no heed to the fact
that the transition of the lifeless into the living exemplifies at least two laws of dialectical
logic.
One is the unity of opposites, which states that A equals non-A; the other is the
transformation of quantity into quality. That is to say, a sufficient aggregate of chemical
reactions of a special type gave rise to new properties appropriate to a new and higher
state of material existence on this planet, the biochemical level, of which humans are
the most complex and advanced embodiment.
Just as Teilhard de Chardin’s religious views did not prevent him from participating
in the discovery of Peking Man in 1929 and thus adding to our knowledge of human
origins, so practicing physicists, chemists, and biologists can and do promote their
sciences without any clear notions of the logic underlying their investigations, or
even with erroneous ideas of the world. But would not the work of individual scientists
benefit — as much as science as a whole — if they could rid their minds of errors and
inconsistencies which run counter to a scientific outlook, and thus bring their general
ideas about the universe and their logical theory into closer accord with their
experimental practice and the requirements of science itself?
That is why Marxists contend that a comprehensive grasp of the logic of dialectical
materialism would not only clarify what science has already achieved but enable
contemporary scientists to promote and improve their work. Science is still in its
infancy and is only now being applied on a grand scale. There are more scientists in
the world today than in all previous history. This sudden and sharp jump in the
number of scientists and the facilities at their disposal demands a corresponding
expansion in their understanding of the logic of evolution, which so far has been best
provided by the school of dialectical materialism.
2. The works of Father Teilhard de Chardin can throw light on this matter, although
not entirely in the way intended by our correspondent. While Chardin is an inconsistent
dialectician, he is not at all a materialist in his philosophy and procedure. One of the
Is Nature Dialectical? 207
world’s most eminent biologists, George Gaylord Simpson, who was a friend of
Chardin’s and has read both his published and unpublished manuscripts, concurs
with this judgment in his book This View of Life. There, in a chapter entitled
“Evolutionary Theology: the New Mysticism”, Simpson states that Chardin’s ideas
are mystical and nonscientific in two major respects. First, he divides all energy into
two distinct kinds which cannot be verified: a “tangential” material energy and a
“radial” spiritual energy. Second, he advocates orthogenesis as the principal mechanism
of evolution. Unlike natural selection, which is based upon random and multidirectional
trends of evolution, orthogenesis holds that evolution proceeds in a unidirectional,
predetermined, and even purposive manner.
Simpson severely censures Chardin for his spiritualistic “doubletalk”, which really
has nothing to do with science. He writes that “Teilhard was primarily a Christian
mystic and only secondarily a scientist”.
Roger Garaudy likewise deals with Chardin in his book Perspectives of Man.
Ironically, this foremost French communist philosopher is far more conciliatory toward
the views of the Jesuit father than is the American biologist Simpson. Garaudy’s book
undertakes a critical analysis of the main currents of contemporary French thought:
existentialism, Catholicism, and Marxism. He claims that all three are engaged in a
common effort to grasp “man in his totality”, and he seeks to emphasise their “possible
convergences”. He concludes that radical existentialists, liberal Catholics, and
communists can cooperate “not as adversaries but as explorers in a common venture”
which proceeds by different paths toward the same goal.
This theoretical position is the reverse of that taken by Garaudy in the days of
Stalin-Zhdanov. It is motivated by the desire for a philosophical rapprochement among
these incompatible schools of thought to accompany the CP’s quest for a political
alliance of all “democratic, progressive, peace-loving” forces as prescribed by the
policy of “peaceful coexistence”.
Those unorthodox features of Chardin’s thought, which scandalise his superiors
in the Jesuit order and the church but attract liberal Catholics, lend themselves to this
purpose. It is true, as Garaudy points out, that Chardin recognised certain dialectical
characteristics in the process of evolution, such as the universal interconnection and
reciprocal action of all things, the transformation of quantity into quality in connection
with biogenesis (though not in the transition from biological to social life), and the
transmutation of matter in an ascending series of higher forms.
But the “finalism” and “vitalism” which permeate his thought — based on the
supposition that evolution heads in only one direction, toward greater “centro-
complexity”, toward the Omega point where humanity will merge with God — are
208 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
irreconcilable not only with dialectical materialism but, as Simpson insists, with any
acceptable scientific approach to universal evolution.
3. Somewhat in the spirit of Chardin, Yvonne Groseil intimates that “the static
conceptions of ‘idealism’ and ‘materialism’ may give way to a newer, more adequate
realisation of their interdependence throughout the whole sphere of nature.” A Marxist
cannot agree with this for numerous reasons.
First, there is nothing “static” about a consistently dialectical and materialist view
of nature, which is based upon the proposition that everything is in flux because of
the opposing forces at work within it and in the universe. Materialist dialectics is
dynamic, mobile, evolutionary through and through.
Second, the valid and valuable contributions made to the store of human knowledge
by the great idealists of the past (like dialectical logic itself) have been — or ought to
be — incorporated into the structure of dialectical materialism without surrendering
or compromising its fundamental positions: that reality consists of matter in motion,
and that social life and intellectuality are the highest manifestations of the development
of matter.
Idealism, on the other hand, makes spiritual, supernatural, ideological, or personal
forces the essence of reality. Such a fundamentally false philosophy has to be rejected
in toto.
Nor can these two opposing conceptions of the world and its evolution be
amalgamated into some superior synthesis eclectically combining the “best features
of both”, as Sartre tries to do with his neo-Marxist existentialism and Father de Chardin
in his blend of religious mysticism and evolutionism.
Modern thought and science can be most effectively advanced through a firm
repudiation of all religious, mystical, and idealistic notions and the conscious adoption,
application, and development of dialectical materialism. Working in equal partnership,
Marxist logic and the sciences can enable us to penetrate more surely and deeply into
the nature of the world we live in.
logical thinking he was applying, just as another naturalist of lesser stature might explore
a novel type of adaptation of a group of organisms without concerning himself about a
general explanation of evolutionary novelty as Mayr had done.
Mayr’s acknowledgment of the indispensability of this law of dialectics in solving
the problem of the emergence of evolutionary novelties provides involuntary and
forceful testimony to its value for the natural scientist.
TROTSKY’S VIEWS ON DIALECTICAL
MATERIALISM
January 10, 1937 — the day after Leon Trotsky and his wife, Natalia Sedova, had
landed in Mexico. His party was on the troop-guarded private train sent by the minister
of communications to ensure their safe conduct from Tampico to Mexico City. That
sunny morning Max Shachtman and I sat with Trotsky in one of the compartments,
bringing the exile up to date on what had happened during his enforced voyage from
Norway.
Our conversation was animated; there was so much to tell, especially about
developments around the Moscow trials. (This was in the interval between the first
and second of Stalin’s stage-managed judicial frame-ups.) At one point Trotsky asked
about the philosopher John Dewey, who had joined the American committee set up to
obtain asylum for him and hear his case.
From there our discussion glided into the subject of philosophy, in which, he was
informed, I had a special interest. We talked about the best ways of studying dialectical
materialism, about Lenin’s Materialism and Empirio-Criticism, and about the
theoretical backwardness of American radicalism. Trotsky brought forward the name
of Max Eastman, who in various works had polemicised against dialectics as a worthless
idealist hangover from the Hegelian heritage of Marxism.
He became tense, agitated. “Upon going back to the States”, he urged, “you
comrades must at once take up the struggle against Eastman’s distortion and
repudiation of dialectical materialism. There is nothing more important than this.
Pragmatism, empiricism, is the greatest curse of American thought. You must inoculate
younger comrades against its infection.”
I was somewhat surprised at the vehemence of his argumentation on this matter at
such a moment. As the principal defendant in absentia in the Moscow trials, and
because of the dramatic circumstances of his voyage in exile, Trotsky then stood in
the centre of international attention. He was fighting for his reputation, liberty, and life
against the powerful government of Stalin, bent on his defamation and death. After
having been imprisoned and gagged for months by the Norwegian authorities, he had
been kept incommunicado for weeks aboard their tanker.
Yet on the first day after reunion with his cothinkers, he spent more than an hour
explaining how important it was for a Marxist movement to have a correct philosophical
method and to defend dialectical materialism against its opponents!
He proved how serious he was about this question three years later by the manner
of his intervention in the struggle which convulsed the Socialist Workers Party at the
beginning of the Second World War.1 By this time Shachtman had switched
philosophical and political fronts. He was aligned directly with James Burnham and
indirectly with Eastman and others against Trotsky, breaking away from the traditional
positions of Marxism and the Fourth International on issues extending from the role
of philosophy to the class nature of the Soviet Union and its defence against imperialist
attack.
The Burnham-Shachtman opposition sought to separate philosophy from politics
in general, and the principled politics of the revolutionary working class movement
from Marxist theory in particular. In the spirit of pragmatism, Burnham demanded that
the issues in dispute be confined to “concrete questions”. “There is no sense at all”,
he declared in “Science and Style”, “in which dialectics (even if dialectics were not, as
it is, scientifically meaningless) is fundamental in politics, none at all.”2
In “An Open Letter to Comrade Burnham” Trotsky had pointed out that the
experience of the labour movement demonstrated how false and unscientific it was to
divorce politics from Marxist sociology and the dialectical method.
You seem to consider apparently that by refusing to discuss dialectic materialism
and the class nature of the Soviet state and by sticking to “concrete” questions you are
acting the part of a realistic politician. This self-deception is a result of your inadequate
acquaintance with the history of the past 50 years of factional struggles in the labour
movement. In every principled conflict, without a single exception, the Marxists
sought to face the party squarely with the fundamental problems of doctrine and
program, considering that only under this condition could the “concrete” questions
find their proper place and proportion.3
On the other hand, opportunists and revisionists of every shade avoided
discussion of principles and counterposed superficial and misleading episodic
appraisals of events to the revolutionary class analysis of the scientific socialists.
Trotsky cited examples from the history of the German social-democracy and from the
Trotsky’s Views on Dialectical Materialism 213
disputes of the Russian Marxists with the “Economists”, the Social Revolutionaries
and the Mensheviks. The Narodnik terrorists, bomb in hand, used to argue: “Iskra
[Lenin’s paper] wants to found a school of dialectic materialism while we want to
overthrow tsarist autocracy … It is historical experience”, Trotsky observed with
characteristic irony, “that the greatest revolution in all history was not led by the
party which started out with bombs but by the party which started out with dialectic
materialism.”4
Trotsky attached such great importance to the generalised theory incorporated in
Marxist philosophy because of its utility in political practice. “The question of a
correct philosophical doctrine, that is, a correct method of thought, is of decisive
significance to a revolutionary party just as a good machine shop is of decisive
significance to production”, he wrote.5 Many of the now indispensable tools of thought
for investigating and analysing reality were fabricated by the great philosophers
before entering into common use. In dialectical materialism, he asserted, Marx and
Engels forged the theoretical tools and weapons required by the workers in their
struggle to get rid of the old order and build a new one.
including dialectical thought, is only one of the forms of the expression of changing
matter. There is place within this system for neither God, nor Devil, nor immortal soul,
nor eternal norms of laws and morals. The dialectic of thinking, having grown out of the
dialectic of nature, possesses consequently a thoroughly materialist character.6
To clarify the operation of dialectical laws in nature he cited two examples from
19th-century science — one from biology, the other from chemistry. “Darwinism,
which explained the evolution of species through quantitative transformations passing
into qualitative, was the highest triumph of the dialectic in the whole field of organic
matter. Another great triumph was the discovery of the table of atomic weights of
chemical elements and further the transformation of one element into another.”7
Materialism provided the only solid theoretical foundation for progress in the
sciences, even though many natural scientists might be unaware of this truth or even
deny it.
It is the task of science and technology [Trotsky said in a 1926 speech] to make
matter subject to man, together with space and time, which are inseparable from
matter. True, there are certain idealist books — not of a clerical character, but
philosophical ones — wherein you can read that time and space are categories of our
minds, that they result from the requirements of our thinking, and that nothing actually
corresponds to them in reality. But it is difficult to agree with this view. If any idealist
philosopher, instead of arriving in time to catch the 9pm train, should turn up two
minutes late, he would see the tail of the departing train and would be convinced by his
own eyes that time and space are inseparable from material reality. The task is to
diminish this space, to overcome it, to economise time, to prolong human life, to
register past time, to raise life to a higher level and enrich it. This is the reason for the
struggle with space and time, at the basis of which lies the struggle to subject matter to
man — matter, which constitutes the foundation not only of everything that really
exists, but also of all imagination …
Every science is an accumulation of knowledge, based on experience relating to
matter, to its properties; an accumulation of generalised understanding of how to
subject this matter to the interests and needs of man.8
conception of history at the early age of 18, when he was already involved in the
illegal workers’ movement of South Russia. From that time on these two sides of his
activity — the theoretical investigation of social reality and the practical urge to
transform it with the masses along revolutionary lines — went hand in hand.
Trotsky tells in My Life how he at first resisted the unified outlook of historical
materialism. He adopted in its stead the theory of “the multiplicity of historical factors”,
which even today is the most widely accepted theory in social science. (Compare the
school of Max Weber in Europe or C. Wright Mills in the United States.) His reading
of two essays by the Italian Hegelian-Marxist Antonio Labriola convinced him of the
correctness of the views of the historical materialists. They conceived of the various
aspects of social activity as an integrated whole, historically evolving in accord with
the development of the productive forces and interacting with one another in a living
process where the material conditions of life were ultimately decisive. The eclectics of
the liberal school, on the other hand, split the diverse aspects of social life into many
independent factors, endowed these with superhistorical character, and then
“superstitiously interpreted their own activity as the result of the interaction of these
independent forces”.
During his first prison sentence Trotsky wrote a study of Freemasonry, which was
later lost, as an exercise in the materialist conception of history. “In the writings of
Marx, Engels, Plekhanov and Mehring, I later found confirmation for what in prison
seemed to me only a guess needing verification and theoretical justification. I did not
absorb historical materialism at once, dogmatically. The dialectic method revealed
itself to me for the first time not as abstract definitions but as a living spring which I
had found in the historical process as I tried to understand it.”9
Trotsky employed the newly acquired method to uncover the “living springs” of
the class struggle in modern society and, first of all, in tsarist Russia at the turn of the
20th century, where a revolution was being prepared. The development of his celebrated
theory of the permanent revolution was the first result of his researches. This was one
of the outstanding triumphs of dialectical analysis applied to the social tendencies
and political prospects of prerevolutionary Russia and, in its further elaboration, to
the problems confronting backward countries in the imperialist epoch.
Marxists are often accused by their critics of dogmatism, of obsession with abstract
schemes of historical development. Some would-be Marxists have been guilty of this
fault. Not so Trotsky. He was a consistent practitioner of historical materialism, but
within those principled boundaries he was the least formalistic and the most flexible of
thinkers.
The materialist dialectic is based upon the existence of conflicting movements,
216 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
forces, and relations in history, whose contradictions as they develop expose the
shortcomings of all fixed formulas. As Trotsky wrote in 1906 in Results and Prospects:
“Marxism is above all a method of analysis — not analysis of texts, but analysis of
social relations.”10
Trotsky undertook to apply the Marxist method in this materialist manner to the
specific conditions of tsarist Russia. He pointed out that the social structure of Russia
at the beginning of the 20th century was a peculiar blend of extremely backward and
advanced features. The predominant political and religious backwardness embodied
in the Asiatic despotism of the all-powerful monarchy and its servile state church was
rooted in the historical and economic backwardness of the country. In Russia there
had been no Reformation, no successful bourgeois revolutions, no strong third estate
(bourgeoisie) as in Western Europe. The boundless spaces and windswept climate
had given rise to nomadic existence and an extensive agriculture, a thin population, a
belated and meagre feudal development, and an absence of commercial and craft
centres. The prevalence of peasant agriculture and home industry self-contained in
small villages, of large landed estates, and of administrative-military consuming cities
restricted the domestic market and led to dependence upon foreign capital and culture.
However, with the entry of modern industry, this Asiatic backwardness became
complemented and combined with the most up-to-date products of Western European
development. Large-scale industry led not only to the fusion of industrial with banking
capital and domination of the Russian economy by foreign finance, but ultimately to
a proletariat in the major industrial centres, a modern labour movement engaging in
political strikes and mass demonstrations, and scientific socialism. These exceptional
conditions set the stage for the revolutionary events which were to explode in 1905
and culminate in 1917.
The schematic thinkers among the Russian social-democrats, who had learned
the letter but not the essence of Marx’s method and were more or less under bourgeois
influence, asserted that Russia would have to follow the trail blazed by Western
Europe.
The older capitalist nations had passed from feudalism through a prolonged period
of capitalist evolution toward socialism; in politics they had proceeded from rule by
the monarchy and landed aristocracy to bourgeois parliamentarism before the workers
could bid for supremacy. From this the Mensheviks concluded that the rulership of
the bourgeoisie in a democratic republic on a capitalist basis was the logical successor
to feudalised absolutism; the workers would have to wait a long while for their turn.
The attempt to impose such a prefabricated sequence upon 20th-century Russia
was arbitrary and false, according to Trotsky. The powerful peculiarities of Russia’s
Trotsky’s Views on Dialectical Materialism 217
past and present made possible, and even inevitable, an unprecedented path of
development which opened up immense new prospects for the labour movement. The
rottenness of tsarism, the weakness of the bourgeoisie and its institutions, the strategic
position of the industrial workers, and the revolutionary potential in the peasantry
springing from the unsolved, but urgent, problems of the land question would enable
the pending revolution to compress and leap over stages. The workers could place
themselves at the head of the insurgent people; they could lead the peasantry in
overthrowing the old order and establishing democracy in a higher form under the
government of the working class, which would quickly pass over from bourgeois
democratic to revolutionary socialist measures. Thus the belated bourgeois democratic
revolution would clear the way for and be a direct introduction to the first steps of the
socialist revolution.
The political force of the working class could not be viewed in isolation but had to
be judged in its relation with all the other factors at work within the country and the
world. Although “the productive forces of the United States are 10 times as great as
those of Russia, nevertheless the political role of the Russian proletariat, its influence
on the politics of its own country and the possibility of its influencing the politics of
the world in the near future are incomparably greater than in the case of the proletariat
of the United States”.11 From all these considerations he drew the conclusion that
“the Russian revolution will create conditions in which power can pass into the hands
of the workers — and in the event of the victory of the revolution it must do so —
before the politicians of bourgeois liberalism get the chance to display to the full their
talent for governing”.12
This was the first form of his theory of the permanent revolution. Upon the basis
of Russian experience he subsequently extended it to cover the problems and prospects
of the revolution in other underdeveloped countries where the workers and peasants
must struggle against imperialism and its native agents to extricate themselves from
precapitalist barbarism and acquire the benefits of modern economy and culture.
From 1904 to 1917 Trotskyism was identified with the conception that the Russian
revolution could end only in the dictatorship of the proletariat, which in its turn must
lead to the socialist transformation of society, given the victorious development of
the world revolution. This outlook was opposed by the Mensheviks, who could not
see beyond the bourgeois democratic republic, and was even unacceptable to the
Bolsheviks. However, the young Trotsky was able to see farther than all the others
among the brilliant constellation of Russian Marxists thanks to his precocious mastery
of the materialistic and dialectical sides of Marx’s method and his exceptional boldness
and keenness of thought. He was the Columbus of the most extraordinary event in
218 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
modem history: the first successful proletarian revolution, in the most backward country
of Europe.
In working out his prognosis of the Russian revolution, Trotsky utilised the law of
uneven and combined development, which he was later to formulate in general terms.
This generalisation of the dialectical intertwining of the backward and advanced
features of the historical process is one of the most valuable instruments for deciphering
the complex relations and contradictory trends of civilised society.
Each society forms an organic whole. The bones of the social organism consist of
its productive forces; its muscles are its class (property) relations. The functions and
reflexes of all other social organs can be understood only in their connections with
the skeletal and muscular systems (the productive forces and property forms) which
make up the general structure of the social organism. Since civilised society is split up
into classes, the critical point of analysis in scientific sociology has to be “the class
definition of a given phenomenon, e.g., state, party, philosophic trend, literary school,
etc. In most cases, however, the mere class definition is inadequate, for a class consists
of different strata, passes through different stages of development, comes under
different conditions, is subjected to the influence of other classes. It becomes necessary
to bring up these second and third rate factors in order to round out the analysis, and
they are taken either partially or completely, depending upon the specific aim. But for
a Marxist, analysis is impossible without a class characterisation of the phenomenon
under consideration.”15
In order to ascertain the decisive tendencies and the main course of development
of any given social formation or nation, the scientific sociologist, according to Trotsky,
has to examine its structure and the dynamics of its social forces in their connections
with world historical conditions. We must find specific answers to the following
questions: What classes are struggling in a country? What are their interrelations?
How, and in what direction, are their relations being transformed? What are the objective
tasks dictated by historical necessity? On the shoulders of what classes does the
solution of these tasks rest? With what methods can they be solved?
During his revolutionary career Trotsky analysed the situations in many major
countries at critical turning points in their evolution, according to this procedure.
These included Russia, Germany, France, England, Austria, and Spain in Europe;
China and India in Asia; and the United States. The results of his inquiries are contained
in a series of works which are models for any aspiring scientific historian or sociologist.
Ever since Marxism stirred up the academicians, much dust has been raised about
its conception of the relations between the economic foundations and the rest of the
social structure in the process of historical evolution. Trotsky tried not only to clear
up the misunderstandings around this question in general, but also to show by example
how the material substructure of society, crystallised in the relations of production
and its property forms, reacted with other social and cultural phenomena.
“The opinion that economics presumably determines directly and immediately the
creativeness of a composer or even the verdict of a judge, represents a hoary caricature
of Marxism which the bourgeois professordom of all countries has circulated time out
of end to mask their intellectual impotence”, he declared.16 The dialectical approach
220 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
of Marxism has nothing in common with this crude “economic determinism”, so often
practiced by the Stalinist school.
The economic foundation of a given society is organically interrelated and
continuously interactive with its political-cultural superstructure. But the relations
between them can be harmonious or inharmonious, depending upon the given
conditions of historical development and the specific combinations of historical factors.
In some cases the political regime can be in stark contradiction with its economic
basis. Indeed, this is the source of the deepening class antagonisms which generate
the need for revolutions. This can hold true not only for capitalist states but for
postcapitalist political structures in the period of transition to socialism. In the Soviet
Union under Stalin and his heirs, for example, the economic basis of nationalised
property and planned production has been increasingly at odds with the autocratic
system of bureaucratic rule.
In the long run, economics takes precedence over politics Political regimes,
institutions, parties, and leaders are defined by the roles they play in upholding or
changing the existing relations of production. “[A]lthough economics determines
politics not directly or immediately, but only in the last analysis, nevertheless economics
does determine politics”, Trotsky affirmed.17 Capitalist property relations determine
the nature of the bourgeois state and the conduct of its representatives; nationalised
property determines the nature of the workers’ states, however deformed and
bureaucratic they may be.
The controversy around “the cult of the individual” provoked by the de-
Stalinisation campaign in the Soviet bloc has raised again for consideration the
question of the role of the individual in history. This much-debated issue has long
divided one tendency from another in the social sciences.
Nonmaterialists make one or another of the subjective factors in social life, from
ideas to the actions of individuals, paramount in the determination of events. For a
historical materialist like Trotsky, the social takes precedence over the individual, the
general over the particular, the whole over the part, the material over the intellectual.
The individual is important in history. But the extent of his influence depends upon
broader historical factors. The strictly personal elements are subordinate to objective
historical conditions and the major social forces of which they are a product, a part,
and an exemplar.
The Russian Marxists from Plekhanov to Lenin gave considerable attention to
this question. In arguing against the Narodnik school of subjective sociology, which
in its most extreme expression upheld terrorism as a political means of struggle, the
Marxists pointed out that social and political power was not simply an individual
Trotsky’s Views on Dialectical Materialism 221
attribute; it was at bottom a function of the relations between people and, in the last
analysis, between classes. The most prominent personages wield power not solely on
their own account, but on behalf of social forces greater than themselves. Even kings,
tyrants, dictators represent the material interests of a specific class or combination of
classes.
No political institution, for example, fuses the superpersonal forces in history with
the personal more than the monarchy. “Monarchy by its very principle is bound up
with the personal”, wrote Trotsky in The History of the Russian Revolution.18
Under tsarism the royal family appeared to count as everything, the rest of the
nation as nothing. Yet this was only the outward semblance of things.
“The king is king only because the interests and prejudices of millions of people
are refracted through his person.”19 The king cannot rule without the tacit consent of
nobles, landlords, and other class forces which he serves, or even in the end without
the acquiescence of the mass of his subjects. When these refuse any longer to
recognise or abide by the royal authority, it is in danger or done for. The first act of the
Russian revolution, the overthrow of the monarchy, verified this social basis of personal
power.
The Russian revolution, led by the Bolshevik Party of Lenin and Trotsky, abolished
both tsarism and capitalism and instituted a workers’ and peasants’ democracy under
the Soviets. This was smashed, and a new despotism came to flourish under Stalin.
What was the social basis for Stalin’s absolute one-man rule?
Trotsky is often severely condemned for “permitting” Stalin to outwit him in the
contest for supremacy after Lenin’s death. Critics of this superficial stamp do not
understand that the most intelligent individuals with the most correct ideas and strategy
are necessarily subordinated to the historical tides of their time and to the prevailing
relations of class forces. Power is not a personal possession which can be transported
at will like any commodity from one owner to another.
The fundamental factors at work in the world that decide the turn and outcome of
great events were then ranged against the cause for which Trotsky fought; they
favoured and facilitated the advance of Stalin. On the basis of the defeats of the
working class in Europe, the isolation of the Soviet Union, and the weariness of the
Soviet masses, Stalin was being lifted up and pushed to the fore during the 1920s by
the increasingly powerful Soviet bureaucrats and labour aristocrats, backed up and
egged on by an acquisitive upper layer of the peasantry. The Left Opposition, headed
by Trotsky, which spoke for the revolutionary movement of the world working class
and fought for the interests of the Soviet poor, was being pushed aside.
Trotsky explained over and over again that Stalin’s triumph and his own defeat
222 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
did not signify the mere displacement of one individual by another, or even of one
faction by another, but the definitive transfer of political power from the socialist
working class to the privileged Soviet bureaucracy. He consciously tied his own fate
and the fortunes of the Communist Left Opposition to the situation of the world
revolution and the Russian working class.
Trotsky had thought profoundly on the dialectical interplay between the individual
and the great impersonal driving forces of history. The purely personal characteristics
of individuals, he stated, have narrow limits and very quickly merge into the social
conditions of their development and collectivity to which they belong. “The
‘distinguishing traits’ of a person are merely individual scratches made by a higher
law of development.”20
We do not at all pretend to deny the significance of the personal in the mechanics
of the historic process, nor the significance in the personal of the accidental. We only
demand that a historic personality, with all its peculiarities, should not be taken as a
bare list of psychological traits, but as a living reality grown out of definite social
conditions and reacting upon them. As a rose does not lose its fragrance because the
natural scientist points out upon what ingredients of soil and atmosphere it is nourished,
so an exposure of the social roots of a personality does not remove from it either its
aroma or its foul smell.21
The tsar, as the head of his dynastic caste resting upon the Russian bureaucracy
and aristocracy, was a product of its whole historical development and had to share
its destiny. The same law held good for his successors at the helm of the Russian state
after February 1917. Each of the leading individuals, from Kerensky through Lenin
and Trotsky to Stalin, represented and incarnated a different correlation of social
forces both national and international, a different degree of determination by the
working class, a different stage in the development of the Russian revolution and the
state and society which issued from it.
Trotsky was as thoroughgoing a materialist in his psychological observations as
in his sociological and political analyser. Stalin as a man, he explained, acquired his
definitive historical personality as the chosen leader of the Soviet aristocratic caste.
“One can understand the acts of Stalin only by starting from the conditions of existence
of the new privileged stratum, greedy for power, greedy for material comforts,
apprehensive for its positions, fearing the masses, and mortally hating all opposition”,
Trotsky told the Dewey Commission in 1937.22 Stalin’s depravity, confirmed two
decades afterward by Khrushchev, was not uniquely his own.
The more precipitate the jump from the October overturn — which laid bare all
social falsehood — to the present situation, in which a caste of upstarts is forced to
Trotsky’s Views on Dialectical Materialism 223
cover up its social ulcers, the cruder the Thermidorian lies. It is, consequently, a
question not simply of the individual depravity of this or that person, but of the
corruption lodged in the position of a whole social group for whom lying has become
a vital political necessity. In the struggle for its newly gained positions, this caste has
reeducated itself and simultaneously reeducated — or rather, demoralised — its leaders.
It raised upon its shoulders the man who best, most resolutely and most ruthlessly
expresses its interests. Thus Stalin, who was once a revolutionist, became the leader
of the Thermidorian caste.
Conversely, the revolutionary essence of the principles, positions, and social
interests that Trotsky consistently embodied and expressed throughout his lifetime
made him what he was and placed him where he had to be at each stage. He worked at
the side of the Russian working class while it was preparing its first revolution; he
rose to its head in the Soviet of 1905. He remained with its active vanguard during the
subsequent reaction. When the revolution surged up to the heights he organised the
October insurrection, and then led the Red Army until after the Civil War.
Later, when the workers again became politically passive and prostrate under
Stalin’s regime, he still stood firmly with them. Throughout this period of reaction he
did his utmost to stem the decline of the revolution, rally and educate its forces, and
prepare the best conditions for its revival. Trotsky was too much the Marxist to desire
or exercise power for any purpose other than to promote socialist aims.
Bolshevik Party had distinguished themselves in battle by their ideas and their program,
showing their readiness to sacrifice everything for the cause of socialism.
And yet the viruses of bureaucratism and privilege — “the professional dangers
of power”, as Christian Rakovsky designated them — had attacked the new rulers of
Russia and weakened their resistance to alien class influences. The inroads of infection
had been manifest during Lenin’s last years, and he had asked Trotsky to join him in
combating their spread.
For someone like Trotsky, who had been so wholly and intimately identified with
the revolution and its leadership, it required the utmost objectivity to detach his
personal fate from this situation and cope with the problems it presented. He was like
a medical scientist who, having detected the presence of a wasting disease in a dear
companion, notes its symptoms and makes a diagnosis and prognosis, understanding
all the while that the disease may not be arrested and can prove fatal. He followed the
unfolding of the bureaucratic reaction step by step, analysing its causes, pinpointing
its results — while prescribing the necessary therapeutic measures to alleviate and
cure the disease.
The basic conditions for the growth of bureaucratism, he said, were first of all
lodged in the world situation. The failure of the Russian revolution to be matched by
the workers in the more advanced industrialised countries of the West, and the
temporary stabilisation of international capitalism, left the first workers’ state in an
exposed and weakened position. In the Soviet Union a small working class, exhausted
after enormous and sustained exertions, surrounded by a sea of peasantry and poverty,
lacking culture, an adequate economic basis, even the elementary necessities of life,
had to relinquish the powers and positions it had won to a layer of bureaucratic
specialists in administration who wanted rest and the enjoyment of the fruits of the
previous revolutionary efforts. The material privileges and narrow political views of
this upstart caste came into ever greater conflict with the interests of the masses.
This was the source of the factional conflicts which tore apart the Russian
Communist Party and were extended into the Communist International. With the
deepening and strengthening of world reaction during the 1930s this process reached
its climax in the consolidation of the Stalinist autocracy and the total erasure of Soviet
democracy. The ascendancy of Stalinism in the Soviet Union and of fascism in Western
Europe were symmetrical historical phenomena. The destruction of bourgeois
democracy under the decadence of capitalist imperialism and the destruction of
workers’ democracy in the Soviet Republic were parallel products of the defeats of the
working masses by reaction.
These totalitarian states had, however, completely opposite and historically
Trotsky’s Views on Dialectical Materialism 225
different economic bases. The fascist dictators Adolf Hitler, Benito Mussolini, and
Francisco Franco ruled over states which defended capitalist property relations.
Stalin’s government, the uncontrolled agent of Soviet bureaucratism, rested upon
nationalised property.
Trotsky gave a dialectical, historical, and materialist definition of the Soviet Union.
By virtue of its nationalised property, its planned economy, its monopoly of foreign
trade, and the socialist consciousness and traditions in the working class, it remained
a workers’ state. But it was a special type of workers’ state in which the political
structure contradicted the economic foundations. The policies and activities of Stalinist
tyranny not only trampled upon the rights, feelings, and welfare of the masses in
whose interests the revolution was made but injured the development of the Soviet
economy itself, which required democratic administration by the workers to function
most efficiently.
The conflict between Stalin’s one-man rule and workers’ democracy, between the
totalitarian political structure and the economic foundation, was the prime motive
force in Soviet society, however much it was repressed and hushed up. The tension
between these contending social forces could not endure indefinitely. Either the
workers would clean out the bureaucratic usurpers — or the bureaucrats would extrude
a wing which would strike at the last remaining achievements of the revolution and
clear the way for the return of capitalism from within or from abroad.
Trotsky was no defeatist; he did not declare in advance that the worst would
happen. On the contrary, he threw all his forces and resources into the balance to help
the favourable outcome prevail. Now, 20 years after his death, his struggle and foresight
have been vindicated. While imperialism tore itself to pieces for the second time and
was further weakened by the Second World War, the Soviet state survived, despite all
the crimes of Stalinism. After revealing its powers of resistance in the war against
Hitlerism, it has displayed amazing capacities for recuperation and swift growth in the
postwar years. The socialist revolution itself broke through to new ground, extending
into Eastern Europe and Asia and scuttling Stalin’s theory of “socialism in one country”
as a by-product.
These international and national developments have elevated the Soviet working
class to a higher cultural and material level and impelled the most progressive elements
in Soviet society to press hard upon the bureaucrats to relax their dictatorship and
grant concessions. The drive for de-Stalinisation breaks through with such irresistible
force that — up to a certain limited point — it has even carried along elements among
the bureaucracy. Its momentum testifies to the growing powers and impatience of the
socialist elements in Soviet society and confirms Trotsky’s analysis of its main motive
226 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
individuals placed in similar settings and faced with similar problems behave alike.
The so-called faculty psychologists of the 19th century split up the human
personality and psyche into different factors such as instinct, will, intuition,
consciousness, the unconscious, etc., elevating one or another of these elements of
human behaviour into predominance. Trotsky viewed all these various functions as
interpenetrating aspects of a unified physiological-psychological process, materially
conditioned and subject to development and change.
Inspiration and intuition are usually regarded as the special province of idealists
and mystics. However, Trotsky did not hesitate to come to grips even with these
obscure and elusive phases of psychic activity. He noted that the conscious and
unconscious coexist in the historical process just as they do within the individuals
who compose it. He gave an incomparable definition of their interaction in My Life:
Marxism considers itself the conscious expression of the unconscious historical
process. But the “unconscious” process, in the historico-philosophical sense of the
term — not in the psychological — coincides with its conscious expression only at its
highest point, when the masses, by sheer elemental pressure, break through the social
routine and give victorious expression to the deepest needs of historical development.
And at such moments the highest theoretical consciousness of the epoch merges with
the immediate action of those oppressed masses who are farthest away from theory.
The creative union of the conscious with the unconscious is what one usually calls
“inspiration”. Revolution is the inspired frenzy of history.
Every real writer knows creative moments, when something stronger than himself
is guiding his hand; every real orator experiences moments when someone stronger
than the self of his everyday existence speaks through him. This is “inspiration”. It
derives from the highest creative effort of all one’s forces. The unconscious rises from
its deep well and bends the conscious mind to its will, merging it with itself in some
greater synthesis.
The utmost spiritual vigour likewise infuses at times all personal activity connected
with the movement of the masses. This was true for the leaders in the October days.
The hidden strength of the organism, its most deeply rooted instincts, its power of
scent inherited from animal forebears — all these rose and broke through the psychic
routine to join forces with the higher historico-philosophical abstractions in the service
of the revolution. Both these processes, affecting the individual and the mass, were
based on the union of the conscious with the unconscious: the union of instinct — the
mainspring of the will — with the higher theories of thought.24
Trotsky had absorbed the materialist attitude into every fibre of his being; it
permeated all his thought and action from his outlook upon human life to his appraisals
228 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
of the individuals around him. As a consistent materialist he was a proud and avowed
atheist. He would not permit himself to be degraded or humanity to be subjugated to
any of its own fictitious creations issuing from the barbarous past.
His humanistic profession of faith was frankly stated in the testament he set down
a few months before his assassination: “For 43 years of my conscious life I have
remained a revolutionist; for 42 of them I have fought under the banner of Marxism …
I shall die a proletarian revolutionist, a Marxist, a dialectical materialist, and,
consequently, an irreconcilable atheist.”25
He felt no need for the fictitious consolations of personal life after death. Cramped
and contaminated though it was by class society, life on earth was enough because of
the potential for human enjoyment and fulfilment latent within it. “I can see the bright
green strip of grass beneath the wall, and the clear blue sky above the wall, and
sunlight everywhere. Life is beautiful. Let the future generations cleanse it of all evil,
oppression, and violence and enjoy it to the full.” A few days later he added: “Whatever
may be the circumstances of my death I shall die with unshaken faith in the communist
future. This faith in man and in his future gives me even now such power of resistance
as cannot be given by any religion.”26
Such was the final testimony of the most gifted exponent of the 2500-year-old
materialist philosophy in our time.
ALIENATION
that people feel the economic and political forces governing their fate as alien powers.
Although the social soil is different, similar sentiments are widespread in the
anticapitalist countries dominated by the bureaucratic caste. Despite the great advances
in science, technology, industry, public health and other fields made possible by their
revolutions, workers and peasants, students and intellectuals keenly resent their lack
of control over the government and the administration of the economy. Freedom of
thought, expression and organisation are denied them. Despite the official propaganda
that they have at least become masters of their own destinies, the people know that
the powers of decision in the most vital affairs are exercised, not by them, but by
bureaucratic caliphs. The cardinal duty of the masses in the Communist Party, the
unions, the factories and collective farms, the educational institutions and publishing
houses is still to obey the dictates from above.
That now discarded handbook of falsifications of history and Marxism edited by
Stalin, The History of the Communist Party of the Soviet Union, closes with the
admonition that the “Bolsheviks” will be strong and invincible only so long as “they
maintain connection with their mother, the masses, who gave birth to them, suckled
them and reared them”. Khrushchev has told how Stalin in his later years never
visited the factories or farms and was totally insulated from the lives of ordinary folk.
But Stalin’s successor has lifted only a corner of the veil hiding the profound
estrangement of the Soviet masses from the “boss men”, as they are called.
Many thoughtful members of the Communist Party have been impelled by the
revelations at the 20th Congress and by the Polish and Hungarian events of 1956 to
reconsider their former views. Some of them seek an explanation for the crimes of the
Soviet leaders and the Stalinist perversions of socialism in the Marxist outlook itself.
This search has led them back to the young Marx. They believe that they have
found in the early works, which mark his transition from Hegelianism through humanism
to dialectical materialism, the clue to the falsifications of Marxism and the distortions
of socialism which have run rampant in the Soviet Union and the communist parties.
In these observations of Marx on the alienation of mankind under class society, in
particular, they see the basis for a salutary regeneration of the tarnished socialist
ideal.
and a more sensitive concern for the “concrete, whole, living man”. Monstrous forms
of totalitarianism are produced by subservience to such “abstractions” as the Forces
of Production, the Economic Foundations and the Cultural Superstructure, they say.
Such an immoral and inhuman materialism leads to the reappearance, behind socialist
phrases, of the rule of things over men imposed by capitalism.
The same message was proclaimed over a decade ago in the United States by
Dwight MacDonald, then editor of Politics, and by the Johnson-Forest sect. It is a
favourite theme of the social-democratic and ex-Trotskyist writers of the magazine
Dissent, It is now becoming the creed of some former Communist Party intellectuals
grouped around The New Reasoner in England.
E.P. Thompson, one of the two editors of The New Reasoner, wrote in a
programmatic pronouncement in the first issue (Summer, 1957): “The ideologies of
capitalism and Stalinism are both forms of ‘self-alienation’; men stumble in their minds
and lose themselves in abstractions; capitalism sees human labour as a commodity
and the satisfaction of his ‘needs’ as the production and distribution of commodities;
Stalinism sees labour as an economic-physical act in satisfying economic-physical
needs. Socialist humanism declares: liberate men from slavery to things, to the pursuit
of profit or servitude to ‘economic necessity’. Liberate man, as a creative being — and
he will create, not only new values, but things in scope and abundance.”
Despite their up-to-date reasoning, the “new thoughts” brought forward by such
socialist humanists against dialectical materialism are hardly original. The essence of
their viewpoint is to be found in the schools of petty-bourgeois socialism which
flourished in Germany before the revolution of 1848. Scientific socialism was created
in struggle against these doctrines, as anyone familiar with the ideological birth process
of Marxism knows.
The “true socialism” of Moses Hess and Karl Grün sought to base the socialist
movement, not upon the necessary historical development of economic conditions
and the struggles of class forces, but upon abstract principles and ethical precepts
regarding the need for mankind, divided against itself, to recover its wholeness and
universality. In the section on “true socialism” in The Communist Manifesto, Marx
and Engels ridiculed these phrasemongers who talked about the “alienation of the
essence of mankind” instead of undertaking a scientific investigation of money and
its functions.
In their justified revulsion from Stalinism, the new “humane” socialists have not
gone forward to genuine Marxism, as they mistakenly believe; they have landed
behind it. They have unwittingly relapsed into a stage of theoretical development that
socialism and its materialist philosophy surmounted over a century ago. What is
232 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
worse, in taking this backward leap to a prescientific socialism of the most mawkish
variety, they discard both the materialist principles and the dialectical method which
constitute the heart of Marxism.
The attempts of these disoriented intellectuals to insert abstract moralistic
foundations under Marxism are retrogressive. Yet it must be admitted that the theory
of alienation is by no means foreign to Marxism. It did play an influential part in the
genesis and formative period of scientific socialism. Indeed, in the history of the
concept we find a striking example of how the founders of Marxism divested Hegel’s
central conceptions of their “idealist trappings” and placed them on solid materialist
supports, transforming both their form and substance in the process. It is worthwhile
to ascertain what the Marxist attitude toward alienation really is. This will be the best
corrective to the wanderings of those upset socialists who are fumbling for a new
equilibrium.
HEGEL’S CONTRIBUTION
Marx took the concept of alienation from Hegel. In this instance, as in so many
others, Hegelianism was the ideological source and starting point of Marxian thought.
Alienation and estrangement are key categories in Hegel’s idealist philosophy.
These are the most extreme expressions of difference or “otherness”. In the process
of change everything necessarily has a divided and antithetical nature, for it is both
itself and, at the same time, becoming something else, its “other”.
But viewed as a whole, the “other” is simply a development of the “itself”; the
implicit becomes explicit; the possible, actual. This process is a dual one. It involves
estrangement from the original form and the realisation of the essence in a higher form
of existence.
In his system Hegel applied this dialectical logic to the evolution of the “Absolute”,
his synonym for the whole of reality. The Absolute first exists as mere Logical Idea,
self-enclosed like a bud. It breaks out of itself by way of an inner revolution (just how
and why is not clear) to a completely alienated condition — Nature. Hegel saw Nature
as a lifeless dispersed mode of existence in contradiction to the lively perpetual
movement and universal interconnection inherent in the Absolute.
This contradiction drives the Idea forward through a prolonged course of
development until it emerges from its material casing and appears as Mind. Mind in
turn passes through a series of stages from crude sensation to its highest peak in
philosophy, and above all in Hegel’s own idealist outlook.
Throughout this complex process alienation plays the most positive role. It is the
expression of the Negative at work. The Negative, forever destroying existing forms
Alienation 233
itself; it was merely a concealed and mysterious embodiment of the Absolute Idea.
However, Marx, following Feuerbach, pointed out that this Absolute Idea was itself
nothing but “a thing of thought”, a generalised expression for the thinking process of
real individuals dependent on nature.
Marx pays tribute to Feuerbach for exposing the religious essence of Hegel’s
system and thereby reestablishing the materialist truth that Nature, instead of being
an expression of the Idea, is the real basis for thought and the ultimate source of all
ideas.
Hegel, Marx said, discovered “the abstract, logical and speculative expression for
the movement of history”. What Marx sought to do was to uncover the real motive
forces in history (comprising both nature and society in their development, as he was
to emphasise in The German Ideology) which preceded all theorising and provided
both the materials and the motives for the operations of thought.
Moreover, Hegel had mistakenly identified all externalisation of man’s vital powers
in nature and society with alienation because it represented an inferior grade of the
Idea’s existence. Actually, the objectification of his capacities is normal and necessary
to the human being and is the mainspring of all progress. It is perverted into alienation
only under certain historical conditions which are not eternal.
Many brilliant thoughts are to be found in the pages of The Economic and
Philosophic Manuscripts. For example, Marx brings out the differences between the
animal and human senses in a way that counterposes his historical materialism to
vulgar materialism. Sensation is the basis for human knowledge as well as for the
materialist theory of knowledge. Although the human sensory equipment is animal in
origin, it develops beyond that. Human senses pass through an historical, social and
cultural development which endow us with far more discriminating modes of sensation
than any known in the animal state. “The cultivation of the five senses is the work of
the whole history of the world to date”, he concludes.
Capitalism is to be condemned because it blunts sensitivity instead of sharpening
it. The dealer in gems who sees only their market value, and not the beauty and unique
character of minerals, “has no mineralogical sensitivity”, he writes; he is little different
from an animal grubbing for food. The task of civilisation is to develop a specifically
human sensitivity “for the whole wealth of human and natural essence”.
An entire school of contemporary American sociologists, headed by David
Reisman, has based its analysis of the condition of men in “the mass society” on the
fact that the average person is bored and depressed by the drudgery of his work in
factory or office and finds satisfaction for his individuals needs only in leisure hours.
The split between labour and leisure under capitalism was long ago noted by Marx in
238 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
these manuscripts where he pointed out: “Labour is external to the worker, i.e., it does
not belong to his essential being. Therefore he does not affirm himself in his work but
denies himself. He does not feel contented but dissatisfied. He does not develop
freely his physical and spiritual energy but mortifies his body and ruins his mind. The
worker therefore only feels himself to be himself outside his work, and in his work he
feels outside himself. He is at home when he is not working, and when he is working,
he is not at home.”
But civilised man’s growing control over nature was attended by a loss of control
over the basic conditions of his economic activity. So long as production remained
simple but collective, as in primitive tribal life, the producers had control over their
process of production and the disposition of their product. With the extension of the
social division of labour, more and more goods became converted into commodities
and entered exchange in the market.
The producers thereby lost control over their product as it became subject to the
laws of the commodity market. In turn, these laws came to rule the producers to such
an extent that in time men themselves became commodities to be bought and sold.
Slavery was the first organised system of alienated labour; wage labour will be the
last.
Wage labour is a special type of alienated labour. In this mode of production the
labourer becomes the victim of the world market, a slave to the law of supply and
demand, to such a degree that he can stand idle and his dependents starve when there
is no demand for his labour power as a commodity.
The historical groundwork for the alienation suffered by the working class is
private property in the means of production. This enables the owners to appropriate
the surplus product of the labourers. There is nothing mysterious about the material
origin of alienation in class society. It comes about as a consequence of the separation
of the producers from the conditions of production and thereby from what they
produce. When the labourers lose control of the material means of production, they
forfeit control over their lives, their liberties and their means of development.
Hegel pointed this out when he wrote in the Philosophy of Right: “By alienating
the whole of my time, as crystallised in my work, and everything I produced, I would
be making another’s property the substance of my being, my universal activity and
actuality, my personality.”
This second kind of alienation reaches its apex under capitalism, where every
individual involved in the network of production and exchange is ruled by the laws of
the world market. These function as coercive external powers over which even the
masters of capital have no control, as the fluctuations of the business cycle
demonstrate.
The influence of the earlier type of alienation, on the other hand, based upon lack
of command over the forces of nature, lessens as technology and science expand with
the growth of the productive forces from one stage of civilisation to the next. As Marx
wrote: “The miracles of God become superfluous because of the miracles of industry.”
Today, when man’s conquest of nature is conclusive, though far from completed, the
influence of unconquered nature as a factor in producing alienation is small compared
Alienation 241
displaced religion as the major source of alienation, just as it has displaced the deity
as the major object of adoration and attraction. The money form of wealth stands like
a whimsical tyrant between the needs of men and their fulfilment. The possessor of
money can satisfy the most exorbitant desires while the penniless individual cannot
take care of the most elementary needs of food, clothing and shelter.
Money has the magical power of turning things into their opposites. “Gold! Yellow,
glittering, precious gold”, can, as Shakespeare said, “make black, white; foul, fair;
wrong, right; base, noble; old, young; coward, valiant.” The person without artistic
taste can buy and hang pictures in his mansion, or put them in a safety vault, while the
creator and the genuine appreciator cannot view or enjoy them. The meanest scoundrel
can purchase admiration from sycophants while worthy individuals go scorned and
unnoticed.
Under capitalism, where everything enters the field of exchange and becomes the
object of buying and selling, a man’s worth comes to be estimated, not by his really
praiseworthy abilities or actions, but by his bank account. A man is “worth” what he
owns and a millionaire is “worth” incomparably more than a pauper. A Rothschild is
esteemed where a Marx is hated. In this cesspool of universal venality all genuine
human values and standards are distorted and desecrated.
Later, in the first chapter of Capital, Marx unveiled the secrets of these magical
powers of money by tracing them to the forms of value acquired by the commodity in
the course of its evolution. The fetishistic character of money is derived from the
fetishistic character of the commodity form of value which expresses the relations
between independent producers through the medium of things. The fetish of capital
which commands men’s lives and labour is the ultimate expression of this fetishism of
commodities.
If money in the form of capital is the supreme fetish of bourgeois society, the state
which enforces the economic conditions of capitalist exploitation comes a close second.
State compulsion is most harshly manifested in its penal powers, its tax powers and in
its power to conscript for military service. The identity of the ordinary citizen has to be
validated by documents stamped by government officials. He needs a certificate to
vouch for his birth and to prove that he graduated from school, that he is married or
divorced, that he may travel to other countries.
The tyranny of money and the state over the lives of people is reducible in the last
analysis to the relative poverty of the social order.
themselves in a myriad ways in other parts of the social structure. They are crystallised
in the opposition between the state and the members of society. The unity of US
capitalism, for example, is embodied in a state organisation which is dominated and
directed by representatives of the ruling monopolists.
The alienation of this government from the people in our dollar democracy is the
main theme of a study of the rulers and the ruled in the United States recently, made by
Professor C. Wright Mills in The Power Elite. Its opening paragraph reads: “The
powers of ordinary men are circumscribed by the everyday worlds in which they live,
yet even in these rounds of job, family and neighbourhood, they often seem driven by
forces they can neither understand nor govern. ‘Great changes’ are beyond their
control, but affect their conduct and outlook none the less. The very framework of
modern society confines them to projects not their own, but from every side, such
changes now press upon the men and women of the mass society, who accordingly
feel that they are without purpose in an epoch in which they are without power.”
Mills sums up the extreme polarisation of power in our society by declaring that
the big business men, statesmen and brass hats composing the power elite appear to
the impotent mass as “all that we are not”. To be sure, even under the current conformity,
the population is not so stultified and inert as Mills and his fellow academic sociologists
make out. The Negro struggle for equality and the periodic strikes among the industrial
workers indicate that much is stirring below the surface.
But it cannot be denied that the power of labour is largely untapped, unorganised,
and so misdirected that its potential remains hidden even from its possessors. The
policies of the union leaders help the spokesmen for “the power elite” to keep the
people from envisioning the immense political strength they could wield for their own
cause. They thereby keep the working class alienated from its rightful place in American
political life as leader and organiser of the whole nation. This role is handed over by
default to the capitalist parties.
However, the dispossession of the working class from its historical functions will
not be maintained forever. Sooner or later, the labour movement will be obliged to tear
loose from its subordination to alien class political organisations and form its
independent political party. This will be the beginning of a process of political self-
realisation, an ascent to the position of supremacy now held by the capitalist minority.
If today the plutocracy is, to the masses “all that we are not”, the struggle for socialism
can bring about the Great Reversal when “we who have been naught, shall be all”.
Alienation 245
— without success — for an effective political solution. Some speak of “their collective
guilt”, although they are the victims and not the guilty ones. The responsibility for
their intolerable predicament rests entirely upon the ruling imperialists who have
thrust them into this alienated condition.
This diagnosis indicates the only way in which they can overcome that alienation.
That is to join with those forces which are opposed to the imperialists and obliged to
fight them.
Nothing less will do the job than “simultaneous changes in the spheres of industrial
and political organisation, of spiritual and psychological orientation, of character
structure and of cultural activities”. His practical program for curing the ills of modern
society rejects the conquest of power by the workers and the nationalisation of
industry and planned economy. That is the way to totalitarian regimentation, in his
opinion.
He proposes the establishment of small agricultural and industrial “communities
of work” as hothouses in which the laboratory conditions will be created for the
cultivation of the good life. Capitalist society is to be reconstructed and humanity
regenerated through utopian colonies like those advocated by Owen, Fourier, Proudhon
and Kropotkin, which were tried and found wanting over a century ago in the United
States.
Thus the “communitarian socialism” of this humanist turns out to be a faded copy
of the utopian fantasies of the last century. It is a form of flight from the real facts of
modern technology which demand large-scale production on a universal scale to
sustain and elevate the expanding population of the globe. It is also an evasion of the
pressing tasks involved in eliminating the evils of capitalist reaction and Stalinism,
because it alienates itself in theory and in practice from revolutionary Marxism. This
is the only social movement, class power and political program that can effectively
abolish the rule of monopoly capitalism, uproot Stalinism, and create the material
setting for a free and equal social system.
IS ALIENATION EVERLASTING?
Are the alienations from which man suffers incurable? This is the contention of
the Catholic Church, pessimistic Protestant theologians like Reinhold Niebuhr,
existentialist followers of Kierkegaard, and some interpreters of Freud. They picture
man as eternally torn and tormented by irreconcilable aims and impulses, doomed to
despair and disappointment in the unending war between his deepest spiritual
aspirations and his insuperable limitations as an earthbound mortal.
The historical materialists squarely oppose all such preachers of original sin.
Mankind does not have eternal insurmountable failings which have to be compensated
for by the fictitious consolations of the church, the mystical intuitions of idealist
philosophers, or the infinitely repeated but ever defeated efforts at self-transcendence
of the existentialists. The real alienations which cripple and warp humanity have
ascertainable historical roots and material causes. Far from being eternal, they have,
as has been indicated, already shifted their axis in the course of social development
from the contest between society and nature to the conflicts within the social structure.
248 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
These internal social antagonisms are not everlasting. They do not spring from
any intrinsic and inescapable evil in the nature of mankind as a species. They were
generated by specific historico-social conditions which have been uncovered and
can be explained.
Now that mankind has acquired superiority over nature through triumphs of
technology and science, the next great step is to gain collective control over the blind
forces of society. There is only one conscious agency in present-day life strong
enough and strategically placed to shoulder and carry through this imperative task,
says Marxism. That is the force of alienated labour incorporated in the industrial
working class.
The material means for liberating mankind can be brought into existence only
through the world socialist revolution which will concentrate political and economic
power in the hands of the working people. Planned economy of a socialist type on an
international scale will not only enable mankind to regain mastery over the means of
life; it will immeasurably enhance that collective control. The reconstruction of social
relations will complete the mastery of nature for social purposes initiated under class
society, and thereby abolish the conditions which in the past permitted, and even
necessitated, the subjugation of man to man, the rule of the many by the few.
Once everyone’s primary needs are capable of satisfaction, abundance reigns,
and the labour time required to produce the necessities of life is reduced to the
minimum, then the stage will be set for the abolition of all forms of alienation and for
the rounded development of all persons, not at the expense of one another, but in
fraternal relation.
The abolition of private property must be followed by the wiping out of national
barriers. The resultant increase in the productive capacities of society will prepare the
way for the elimination of the traditional antagonisms between physical and intellectual
workers, between the inhabitants of the city and the country, between the advanced
and the undeveloped nations.
These are the indispensable prerequisites for building a harmonious, integrated,
inwardly stable and constantly developing system of social relations. When all
compulsory inequalities in social status, in conditions of life and labour, and in access
to the means of self-development are done away with, then the manifestations of
these material inequalities in the alienation of one section of society from another will
wither away. This in turn will foster the conditions for the formation of harmonious
individuals no longer at war with each other — or within themselves.
Such are the radiant prospects held out by the socialist revolution and its
reorganisation of society as projected by the masters of Marxism.
Alienation 249
Thompson and his fellow humanists, however, dismayed by the filthy features of
Stalinism suddenly bared to their vision, proceed quite differently. They carelessly
toss out the historical generalisations, which condense within themselves an immense
wealth of experience and analysis of social development, along with their disfigured
expressions in real life. This is not the first time that well-intentioned radicals, thrown
off balance by the contradiction between the standards of what a workers’ state
should be and its political degeneration under the Stalinist regime, have rejected both
the theoretical norm and the existing reality. After having been cradled so long in
illusions, they cannot face the objective historical facts of the Soviet structure.
Marxist sociology, however, demands that the facts as they are be taken as the
starting point for theory and action. What are these facts?
In June 1957 Khrushchev swore over TV that there are no contradictions in Soviet
society. This was no more credible than his assertion that all was well with the new
“collective leadership” — shortly before Molotov, Malenkov, Kaganovitch and other
dignitaries were cashiered. The more prudent Mao Tse-tung admitted that certain
types of contradiction can exist between the government and the people in the workers’
states but that those in China, and by inference the Soviet Union, are exclusively of
the non-antagonistic, nonviolent kind.
The divergences between the bureaucrats and the masses in the Soviet Union
which have produced the all-powerful states give the lie to these theoretical
pretensions of the leaders in Moscow and Peking. How is this estrangement between
the rulers and the ruled to be explained?
The taking of power by the workers and public ownership of the means of
production, especially in backward countries, cannot in and of itself and all at once
usher in socialism. These achievements simply lay down the political and legal
conditions for the construction of the new society, In order to arrive at socialism, the
productive forces have to be promoted to the point where consumer goods are cheaper
and more plentiful than under the most beneficent capitalism.
This cannot be attained within the confines of a single country, as the orthodox
Stalinists claim, or by adding up separated national units, each following “its own
road to socialism”, as the dissident Stalinists maintain. The poverty in consumer
goods arising from the inferior productivity of the economy divorced from world
resources is the material source for the growth and maintenance of malignant
bureaucratic tumours within the most “liberal” of the workers’ states.
In principle, in essence, the prime causes of the alienation of labour under
capitalism — private property in the means of production and the anarchy of the
profit system — have been eradicated in the Soviet countries. Thanks to nationalisation
Alienation 251
of basic industry, control of foreign trade and planned economy, the working people
there are no longer separated from the material means of production but are reunited
with them in a new and higher form.
However, these anticapitalist measures and methods do not dispose of the problems
of Soviet economy. Far from it. To uproot the social alienations inherited from the
barbarous past, the workers’ states require not only a powerful heavy industry but
also a well-proportioned economy that can provide the necessities and comforts of
life in increasing volume to all sections of the people.
Not one of the existing postcapitalist states has raised its economy anywhere
near that point. These states have not yet even approached the productivity in the
sphere of subsistence and the means of culture attained by the most advanced
capitalist countries. The prevailing scarcities have resulted in tense struggles among
the various sectors of their population over the division of the restricted national
income. In these struggles the bureaucratic caste which has cornered all the
instruments of political power plays the commanding role. The rulers decide who gets
what and how much. They never forget to place themselves at the head of the table.
There is no exploitation of labour as in capitalist society. But there are sharp
distinctions between the haves, who make up a small minority, and the have-nots, the
majority of the working population. The manifest inequalities in the distribution of
available goods and amenities erode the ties of solidarity between various parts of the
population and dig deep-going differences in their living standards, even where these
are somewhat improved. In this sense, the product of their labour still escapes the
control of the producers themselves. When it enters the domain of distribution, their
production passes under the control of the uncontrolled bureaucracy. In this way
their own production, concentrated in the hands of omnipotent administrators, once
again confronts the masses as an alien and opposing force.
Herein is the principal source, the material basis, of the alienation of rulers and
ruled in the degenerated and deformed workers’ states of the Soviet zone. Their
antagonisms express the growth of two opposing tendencies in the economic structure:
one carried over from the bourgeois past, the other preparing the socialist future. The
socialist foundations of nationalised industry and planned economy in the field of
production are yoked to bureaucratically administered bourgeois standards which
determine the maldistribution of the inadequate supplies of consumer goods.
The development of these two contradictory tendencies is responsible for the
friction which threatens to flare up into explosive conflicts.
252 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
ORGANISATION OF INDUSTRY
Lenin envisaged, and the program of the Bolsheviks stated, that the workers
would control and manage industry through their elected representatives. Instead,
the division of economic functions which excludes the workers under capitalism from
exercising their initiative, intelligence and will has been recreated in new forms under
the bureaucratic maladministration of the Soviet economy.
“The universal brain” which supervises production is no longer the capitalists —
but it is also not yet the workers as it should be under a genuine Soviet democracy.
The hierarchy of bureaucrats arrogated all major powers of decision to themselves
under the successive five-year plans. Orders were issued from the single centralised
command post in Moscow, even on matters of detail. All science and judgment were
vested in appointed officials. Khrushchev’s recent decentralisation of industrial
Alienation 253
behind the uprising of Hungarian and Polish intellectuals and youth. It is also one of
the main themes of the newly awakened, critical-minded generation of Soviet writers.
They are articulating as best they can the rankling protest against regimentation of
cultural, scientific and artistic activities; against the suffocating atmosphere of double-
talking and double-dealing; against official impostures that not only stifle creative
work but make even normalised existence difficult.
In the “People’s Democracies” of Eastern Europe, in the Baltic countries, the
Ukraine and other oppressed nations within the Soviet Union itself there is another
source of resentment: the grievance against a Great Russian regime which governs
heedless of the special demands, traditions, autonomy and interests of the oppressed
nationality.
The real power must be exercised through councils freely elected by the manual
and intellectual workers of city and country. Their democratic rights should include
freedom of organisation and propaganda by all parties which recognise and abide by
the gains of the revolution; freedom of the press; all public functionaries to be under
the control of the electorate with the right of recall of representatives on all levels.
There must be such political reforms as the restoration of democracy within the
workers’ parties with control of the leadership and policies by their members; the
restriction of the income of officials to that of the most skilled workers; the drawing of
the people into the administration of public functions; the abolition of the secret
police, internal passports, labour camps for political dissenters and other abominations.
In the economic domain the workers must have control over national planning
and its execution on all levels and at all stages so that timely reviews can be made of
results in the light of actual experience. Wage standards and other means of distribution
must be revised so that inequalities can be reduced to the minimum. The trade unions
should have the right to strike in order to safeguard the workers against mistakes and
abuses of their government.
All nationalities should have the right to be independent or to federate, if desired,
in a fraternal and equal association of states.
Such measures would add up to a revolutionary change in the structure and
operation of the existing workers’ states, a salutary change from bureaucratic autocracy
to workers’ democracy.
How is such a transformation to be accomplished’ Not by concessions doled out
from above by “enlightened absolutism” or a frightened officialdom but through
direct action by the working people themselves. They will have to take by revolutionary
means the rights of rulership which belong to them, which were promised by the
Marxist program, and which were denied them by the bureaucratic usurpers.
and must remain so up to the advent of future communism. The less productive a
society is and the poorer in the means of subsistence and culture, the harsher these
forms of constraint must be. The mass of mankind must labour under this lash until
they raise the powers of production to the point where everyone’s needs can be taken
care of in a work week of 10 hours or less.
This reduction of necessary labour will free people from the traditional social load
that has weighed them down and enable them to devote most of their time to general
social welfare activity and personal pursuits and pastimes. Recent developments in
science, technology and industry from nuclear energy to automation place such a
goal within sight. But our society is still quite a distance from this promised land.
The means for such freedom cannot be provided under capitalism. They have not
yet been created in the transitional societies that have passed beyond capitalism.
So long as the workers have to toil long hours daily to acquire the bare necessities of
existence and compete with one another for them, they cannot administer the general
affairs of society or properly develop their creative capacities as free human beings.
Such social functions as government, the management of industry, the practice of
science and the arts will continue to be vested in specialists. Taking advantage of
their posts of command, these specialists have raised themselves above the masses
and come to dominate them.
It is out of these economic and social conditions that the ultra-bureaucratic police
regimes of the workers’ states have arisen. There, as under capitalism, though in
different forms, the privileged minority prospers at the expense of the labours of the
majority.
The evils of Stalinism do not come from recognising the material limitations of
production or acting in accord with them. Even the healthiest workers’ regime would
have to take these into account. The crimes of Stalinism consist in placing the interests
and demands of favoured functionaries before the welfare of the people and above
the needs of development towards socialism; in fostering inequalities instead of
consciously and consistently diminishing them; in concealing both the privileges of
aristocrats and the deprivations of plebeians; in stripping the workers of their
democratic rights — and trying to pass off these abominations as “socialism”.
The task of eradicating the scourge of bureaucratism in the anticapitalist states is
inseparable from the task of abolishing bourgeois rule in capitalist countries. The role
of the Kremlin hierarchy has been no less pernicious in foreign affairs than at home. If
the menace of imperialist intervention has helped the bureaucracy to maintain its
power, its international policies in turn have been a prime political factor in saving
capitalist rule from being overthrown by the workers.
258 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
reasons.
If people suffer today from the tyranny of money or from the tyranny of the state,
it is because their productive systems, regardless of its property forms, cannot at their
present state of development take care of all their physical and cultural needs. In order
to throw off these forms of social coercion, it is necessary to raise the powers of social
production — and, in order to raise these powers, it is necessary to get rid of the
reactionary social forces which hold them back.
Scientific socialists can agree with the new humanists that it is necessary to live
up to the highest moral standards. They recognise that the desires for justice, tolerance,
equality and self-respect have become as much a part of civilised life as the needs for
food, clothing and shelter. Marxism would not be fit to serve as the philosophical
guide of the most enlightened people of our time if it failed to take these demands into
account.
But that is only one side of the problem. Until their basic material requirements are
actually assured for everyone, the higher activities are stunted and social relations
must remain un-humanised. The forces of reaction, whose codes and conduct are
governed by the will to defend their power, property, and privileges at any price,
determine the moral climate far more than their opponents who have more elevated
aims and ideals.
It would be more “humane” for the Western imperialists to withdraw quietly from
their colonial domains, instead of fighting to hold them. But the actions of the French
in Algeria again prove that ruthless terror, not peaceful reason, is more likely to
prevail.
From the economic, cultural and ethical standpoints, it would be preferable if the
monied magnates would recognise that their usefulness is finished and consent to
yield their possessions and power to the socialist workers movement by mutual
agreement between the contending classes. So far history has not provided any such
sensible and straightforward solution to the transition from capitalism to socialism.
The principal task before the Soviet people is to get rid of the archaic monstrosity
of their totalitarian political structure. It would be best if the Stalinist leaders would
give up their functions as an oppressive ruling caste, grant independence to their
satellites, and return complete power to their own people. But the case of Hungary
indicates that they are unlikely to cede their commanding positions gracefully, gradually
or easily,
“Humane” and “reasonable” solutions to the fundamental social problems of our
time are blocked by these bulwarks of reaction. That is why the anticapitalist revolutions
in the advanced countries, the anti-imperialist movements in the colonies, and the
260 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
species it has the potential of becoming. Men will recreate their natural environment,
their organisms and their mutual relations as they wish them to be. To human beings
of that happier time the welfare of their fellows will be the first law of their own
existence.
production grow, the closer the workers come to the hour of their release from servitude
to labour. When the production of all the material necessities of life and means of
culture will be taken over by automatic methods and mechanisms, requiring the
minimum of superintendence, humanity will be freed to develop its distinctively human
capacities and relations to the full.
The prehistory of humanity will end and its development on a truly human basis
begin, when wealth of all kinds flows as freely as water and is as abundant as air and
compulsory labour is supplanted by free time. Then free time enjoyed by all will be the
measure of wealth, the guarantee of equality and harmony, the source of unrestricted
progress and the annihilator of alienation. This is the goal of socialism, the promise of
communism.
APPENDIX
EXISTENTIALISM AND MARXISM
By Doug Lorimer
Doug Lorimer is a member of the National Executive of the Democratic Socialist Party.
264 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
SARTREAN EXISTENTIALISM
In his early theoretical writings, culminating in Being and Nothingness (1943)
Sartre summed up existentialism’s deeply pessimistic view of life in the phrases “life is
hell” and “hell is other people”. By 1947, however, Sartre had begun to evolve away
from the gloom and despair this view implied. He now argued that while the world was
“hell” it was human beings who created the world. This implied a move away from
passive self-contemplation toward an active striving for freedom, in which human
action could overcome both “hells”. However, this shift was still confined to a
subjectivist and individualistic framework — a demand for absolute personal freedom.
From the late 1950s on, Sartre tried to marry his existentialist philosophy with the
revolutionary doctrine of Marxism. In his 1960 philosophical treatise The Critique of
Existentialism and Marxism 265
Dialectical Reason, for example, Sartre declared that existentialism was a subordinate
branch of Marxism which aspired to “renew” and “enrich” it.
But this “enriching” involved discarding the materialist, sociohistorical outlook
of Marxism in favour of a subjectivist, individualistic approach to philosophy, sociology,
morality and politics.
The whole of Sartre’s philosophy revolved around the absolute primacy of the
individual subject over everything objective, whether natural or social. The truth and
value of human existence are to be sought exclusively within the existence of the
isolated individual. “If we refuse to see the original dialectical movement in the individual
and in his enterprise of producing his life, of objectifying himself, then we shall have
to give up dialectic or else make of it the immanent law of history”, Sartre wrote in the
lengthy preface to his Critique.1 That is, Sartre located dialectical development
exclusively within human practice. Moreover, he considered that the dialectical
development of society proceeds from the actions of the isolated individual, rather
from the objective realities, laws and necessities of social life.
Marxism takes a diametrically opposite point of view: The thoughts and actions of
the individual are determined by the dialectical development of society. The isolated
individual — so central to existentialism’s world view — is an abstraction. As Marx
himself observed in his “Theses on Feuerbach” (1845): “The human essence is no
abstraction inherent in each single individual. In its reality it is the ensemble of the
social relations.”2 That is, the individual, with his or her own particular personality, is
the product of society. Everything distinctive about humans, from tool-making, speech
and abstract thinking, to the latest products of art and technology, is the result of
millions of years of social practice. Human social practice in turn is an historical
outgrowth of the dialectical development of nature; the organic developing out of the
inorganic; the human from the animal.
Nature, humanity, social life and labour are inseparably interconnected. What
separated humanity from the rest of animal life was the practice of labour — the
regular, collective production of means of subsistence through the use and fashioning
of tools. Through labour prehuman primates began to transform their natural
environment to serve their needs, and in the process they transformed themselves
and their descendants into a qualitatively new species.
Fundamental changes in the organisation of the labour process are the basis for
the dialectical development of society. Subjective components of this development
— individual psychology, for example —are integral and subordinate elements of this
objective historical process. Thus society is more than the sum of its individuals
because it is a product of collective activity. It is only in and through society that we
266 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY
develop as individuals.
Existentialism, on the other hand, pictures the individual as essentially divorced
from other people, confronted by an inert, irrational and hostile social environment. It
champions the spontaneity of the individual against any established institution or
organised movement. It is equally hostile to the social institutions of bourgeois society
and to the working class’s collective struggle against them. Rather than being a guide
to revolutionary action, it is a philosophy that justifies the individualistic non-
conformism of middle-class intellectuals.
ALTHUSSERIAN STRUCTURALISM
In a series of essays written in the mid-1960s, French philosophy professor Louis
Althusser attacked the views of the “Marxist” existentialists. However, Althusser did
not defend orthodox Marxism against the later existentialists’ subjective dialectics and
individualistic humanism. Rather, he substituted an interpretation of Marxism that was
heavily influenced by the antidialectical structuralist school of bourgeois sociology.
Whereas the “Marxist” existentialists were fixated with individual human subjects
to the exclusion of social structures, Althusser produced, as Perry Anderson has
noted, “a version of Marxism in which subjects were abolished altogether, save as the
illusory effects of ideological structures”.3 In contrast to the former, who sought to
“Hegelianise” Marxism by purging it of its materialist outlook, Althusser sought to
“de-Hegelianise” Marxism, i.e., to purge it of dialectics.
“For Hegel’s ‘pure’ principle of consciousness”, Althusser argued, orthodox
Marxists, “have substituted another simple principle, its opposite: material life, the
economy …”4 In opposition to Marx’s materialist approach to social life — his
recognition that the “mode of production of material life conditions the social, political,
and intellectual life process in general”5 — Althusser substituted an eclectic approach
in which each aspect of a given social formation was regarded as a separate structure
undetermined by any other. Instead of Marx’s dialectical method of analysing the
interconnections between social phenomena, and uncovering the underlying laws of
development (contradictions) governing the origin and evolution of a given social
formation, Althusser adopted the structuralist approach of analysing social phenomena
in a purely synchronic and static manner.
While travelling a somewhat different road, Althusser thus arrived at the same
destination as the “Marxist” existentialists he sought to combat: adoption of the
liberal-pragmatist view that there are no determining laws of historical development;
that there is only historical particularity produced by the accidental conjuncture of
multiple and separate events.
Existentialism and Marxism 267
NOTES
IS NATURE DIALECTICAL?
1 The stenograph of this debate was published as Marxisme et Existentialisme (Libraire Plon:
Paris, 1962).
8 Trotsky, “Radio, Science, Technology and Society”, Problems of Everyday Life (Pathfinder
Press: New York, 1973), pp. 252-253.
9 Trotsky, My Life (Pathfinder Press: New York, 1970), p. 122.
10 Trotsky, The Permanent Revolution & Results and Prospects (Pathfinder Press: New
York, 1969), p. 64.
11 Ibid., p. 65.
12 Ibid., p. 63.
13 Trotsky, Marxism in Our Time (Pathfinder Press: New York, 1970), pp. 8-9.
14 Ibid., p. 13.
15 In Defence of Marxism, p. 129.
16 Ibid., pp. 118-119.
17 Ibid., p. 119.
18 Trotsky, The History of the Russian Revolution (Monad Press: New York, 1980), Vol. 1, p.
52.
19 Trotsky, “What Is National Socialism?”, The Struggle Against Fascism in Germany
(Pathfinder Press: New York, 1971), p. 399.
20 The History of the Russian Revolution, Vol. 1, p. 52.
21 Ibid., p. 95.
22 Trotsky, The Case of Leon Trotsky (Merit Publishers: New York, 1968), p. 581.
23 Trotsky, The History of the Russian Revolution, Vol. 1, p. 93.
24 Trotsky, My Life, pp. 334-335.
25 Trotsky, “Testament”, Writings of Leon Trotsky (1939-40) (Pathfinder Press: New York,
1973), pp. 158-159.
26 Ibid., p. 159.
www.resistancebooks.com
272 MARXIST WRITINGS ON HISTORY & PHILOSOPHY